]> pere.pagekite.me Git - text-free-culture-lessig.git/blob - freeculture.xml
Translate a bit more.
[text-free-culture-lessig.git] / freeculture.xml
1 <?xml version='1.0' encoding='UTF-8' ?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href="docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type="text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012 with input from Martin Borg. -->
5 <!--
6 TODO
7 * indexterm primary
8 -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC "-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
11 [
12 <!ENTITY copy "©">
13 <!ENTITY translationblock "">
14 ]>
15 <book id="index" lang="en">
16 <bookinfo>
17 <title>Free Culture</title>
18
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
20
21 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
22 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY</subtitle>
23
24 <pubdate>2004-03-25</pubdate>
25
26 <releaseinfo>Version 2004-02-10</releaseinfo>
27
28 <authorgroup>
29 <author>
30 <firstname>Lawrence</firstname>
31 <surname>Lessig</surname>
32 </author>
33 </authorgroup>
34
35 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
36 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
37 -->
38 <subjectset scheme="libraryofcongress">
39 <subject>
40 <subjectterm>Intellectual property&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
41 </subject>
42 <subject>
43 <subjectterm>Mass media&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
44 </subject>
45 <subject>
46 <subjectterm>Technological innovations&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
47 </subject>
48 <subject>
49 <subjectterm>Art&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
50 </subject>
51 </subjectset>
52
53
54 <publisher>
55 <publishername>The Penguin Press</publishername>
56 <address><city>New York</city></address>
57 </publisher>
58
59 <copyright>
60 <year>2004</year>
61 <holder>Lawrence Lessig</holder>
62 </copyright>
63 <legalnotice>
64 <para>
65 <inlinemediaobject>
66 <imageobject>
67 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.png" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
68 </imageobject>
69 <imageobject>
70 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.svg" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
71 </imageobject>
72 <textobject>
73 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved</phrase>
74 </textobject>
75 </inlinemediaobject>
76 </para>
77
78 <para>
79 This version of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is licensed under
80 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
81 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
82 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
83 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/</ulink>
84 </para>
85 </legalnotice>
86
87 <abstract>
88 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR</title>
89 <para>
90 LAWRENCE LESSIG
91 (<ulink url="http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org</ulink>),
92 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
93 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
94 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
95 (<ulink url="http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org</ulink>).
96 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) and Code: And
97 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), Lessig is a member of
98 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
99 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
100 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
101 twice listed in BusinessWeek's <quote>e.biz 25,</quote> and named one of Scientific
102 American's <quote>50 visionaries.</quote> A graduate of the University of
103 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
104 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
105 Appeals.
106 </para>
107 </abstract>
108
109 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
110 <mediaobject role="cover">
111 <imageobject remap="lrg" role="front-large">
112 <imagedata fileref="images/cover.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
113 </imageobject>
114 <!--
115 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
116 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
117 </imageobject>
118 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
119 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
120 </imageobject>
121 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
122 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
123 </imageobject>
124 -->
125 </mediaobject>
126
127 <biblioid class="isbn">1-59420-006-8</biblioid>
128
129 <!-- LCCN from
130 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
131 -->
132 <biblioid class="libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
133
134 </bookinfo>
135 <!--PAGE BREAK 1-->
136 <dedication id="salespoints">
137 <title></title>
138 <para>
139 You can buy a copy of this book by clicking on one of the links below:
140 </para>
141 <itemizedlist mark="number" spacing="compact">
142 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.amazon.com/">Amazon</ulink></para></listitem>
143 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.barnesandnoble.com/">B&amp;N</ulink></para></listitem>
144 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.penguin.com/">Penguin</ulink></para></listitem>
145 <!-- <ulink url="">Local Bookstore</ulink> -->
146 </itemizedlist>
147 </dedication>
148 <!-- PAGE BREAK 2 -->
149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
150 <dedication id="alsobylessig">
151 <title></title>
152 <para>
153 ALSO BY LAWRENCE LESSIG
154 </para>
155 <para>
156 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
157 </para>
158 <para>
159 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
160 </para>
161 </dedication>
162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
163 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
164 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
165 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
166 <dedication><title></title>
167 <para>
168 To Eric Eldred&mdash;whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
169 it continues still.
170 </para>
171 </dedication>
172
173 <toc id="toc"></toc>
174
175 <lot>
176 <title>List of figures</title>
177 </lot>
178
179 <!--
180 c PREFACE xiii
181 c INTRODUCTION
182 c "PIRACY"
183 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
184 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
185 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
186 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
187 2 Film
188 2 Recorded Music
189 2 Radio
190 2 Cable TV
191 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
192 2 Piracy I
193 2 Piracy II
194 c "PROPERTY"
195 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
196 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
197 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
198 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
199 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
200 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
201 2 Beginnings
202 2 Law: Duration
203 2 Law: Scope
204 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
205 2 Architecture and Law: Force
206 2 Market: Concentration
207 2 Together
208 c PUZZLES
209 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
210 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
211 2 Constraining Creators
212 2 Constraining Innovators
213 2 Corrupting Citizens
214 c BALANCES
215 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
216 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
217 c CONCLUSION
218 c AFTERWORD
219 1 Us, Now
220 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
221 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
222 1 Them, Soon
223 2 1. More Formalities
224 3 Registration and Renewal
225 3 Marking
226 2 2. Shorter Terms
227 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
228 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
229 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
230 c NOTES
231 c ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
232 c INDEX
233 -->
234
235 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
236
237 <preface id="preface">
238 <title>PREFACE</title>
239 <indexterm id='idxpoguedavid' class='startofrange'><primary>Pogue, David</primary></indexterm>
240 <para>
241 <emphasis role="bold">At the end</emphasis> of his review of my first
242 book, <citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle>, David
243 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
244 computer-related texts, wrote this:
245 </para>
246 <blockquote>
247 <para>
248 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
249 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
250 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
251 system, you can always flip off the modem.<footnote id="preface01"><para>
252 David Pogue, <quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 30 January 2000.
253 </para></footnote>
254 </para>
255 </blockquote>
256 <para>
257 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book&mdash;that
258 software, or <quote>code,</quote> functioned as a kind of law&mdash;and his review
259 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
260 could always <quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome</quote>-like simply flip a
261 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
262 any troubles that exist in <emphasis>that</emphasis> space wouldn't
263 <quote>affect</quote> us anymore.
264 </para>
265 <para>
266 Pogue might have been right in 1999&mdash;I'm skeptical, but maybe.
267 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
268 <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
269 causes even after the modem is turned
270 <!--PAGE BREAK 12-->
271 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
272 on-line have fundamentally affected <quote>people who aren't online.</quote> There
273 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
274 </para>
275 <indexterm startref='idxpoguedavid' class='endofrange'/>
276 <para>
277 But unlike <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
278 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
279 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
280 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
281 important.
282 </para>
283 <para>
284 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
285 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of <quote>free culture</quote>&mdash;not
286 <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free beer</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
287 free software movement<footnote>
288 <para>
289 Richard M. Stallman, <citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed. 2002).
290 </para></footnote>), but <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free speech,</quote> <quote>free markets,</quote>
291 <quote>free trade,</quote> <quote>free enterprise,</quote> <quote>free will,</quote> and <quote>free elections.</quote> A
292 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
293 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
294 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
295 follow-on creators and innovators remain <emphasis>as free as
296 possible</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
297 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
298 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
299 <quote>permission culture</quote>&mdash;a culture in which creators get to create
300 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
301 past.
302 </para>
303 <para>
304 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not <quote>we</quote>
305 on the Left or <quote>you</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
306 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
307 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
308 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
309 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
310 culture deem fundamental.
311 </para>
312 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
313 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
314 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
315 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted</primary></indexterm>
316 <para>
317 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
318 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
319 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
320 generated more than 700,000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
321 As William Safire described marching <quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
322 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
323 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,</quote> he formulated perhaps
324 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
325 he asked,
326 </para>
327 <blockquote>
328 <para>
329 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
330 power&mdash;political, corporate, media, cultural&mdash;should be anathema to
331 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
332 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
333 the greatest expression of democracy.<footnote><para> William Safire,
334 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 May 2003.
335 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
336 </para></footnote>
337 </para>
338 </blockquote>
339 <para>
340 This idea is an element of the argument of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle>, though my
341 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
342 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
343 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
344 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
345 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
346 you&mdash;whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
347 Safire's left or on his right.
348 </para>
349 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'/>
350 <para>
351 <emphasis role="strong">The inspiration</emphasis> for the title and for
352 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
353 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
354 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in <citetitle>Free Software, Free
355 Society</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
356 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
357 that this work is <quote>merely</quote> derivative.
358 </para>
359 <para>
360 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
361 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
362 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
363 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
364 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
365 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
366 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
367 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
368
369 <!--PAGE BREAK 14-->
370 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
371 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
372 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
373 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
374 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
375 what I advance here.
376 </para>
377 <para>
378 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
379 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
380 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
381 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
382 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
383 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
384 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
385 book is written.
386 </para>
387
388 </preface>
389 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
390
391 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
392 <chapter label="0" id="c-introduction">
393 <title>INTRODUCTION</title>
394 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
395 <para>
396 <emphasis role="strong">On December 17</emphasis>, 1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
397 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
398 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
399 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
400 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
401 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
402 </para>
403 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.</primary></indexterm>
404 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
405 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
406 <para>
407 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
408 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
409 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
410 and all the space above, to <quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.</quote><footnote><para>
411 St. George Tucker, <citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
412 Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18.
413 </para></footnote>
414 For many
415 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
416 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
417 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
418 </para>
419 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
420 <para>
421 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
422 law&mdash;deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
423 by the most important legal thinkers of our past&mdash;mattered. If
424 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
425 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
426 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
427 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
428 </para>
429 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
430 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
431 <para>
432 In 1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
433 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
434 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
435 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
436 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
437 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
438 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to <quote>an indefinite
439 extent, upwards,</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
440 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
441 </para>
442 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
443 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
444 <indexterm id='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='startofrange'><primary>Douglas, William O.</primary></indexterm>
445 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on airspace vs. land rights</secondary></indexterm>
446 <para>
447 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
448 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
449 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
450 <quote>taking</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
451 that <quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
452 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.</quote> But Justice Douglas
453 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
454 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
455 </para>
456 <blockquote>
457 <para>
458 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
459 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
460 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
461 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
462 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
463 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
464 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
465 the public has a just claim.<footnote>
466 <para>
467 United States v. Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. The Court did find
468 that there could be a <quote>taking</quote> if the government's use of its land
469 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
470 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, <quote>(Intellectual)
471 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
472 Authorship,</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review</citetitle> 48 (1996): 1293, 1333. See also Paul
473 Goldstein, <citetitle>Real Property</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press, 1984),
474 1112&ndash;13.
475 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
476 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
477 </para></footnote>
478 </para>
479 </blockquote>
480 <para>
481 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.</quote>
482 </para>
483 <indexterm startref='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='endofrange'/>
484 <para>
485 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
486 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
487 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
488 <!--PAGE BREAK 18-->
489 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: <quote>Common sense revolts
490 at the idea.</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
491 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
492 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
493 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
494 </para>
495 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
496 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
497 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
498 <para>
499 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
500 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
501 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
502 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
503 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
504 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
505 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
506 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
507 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by <quote>what
508 seemed reasonable</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
509 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
510 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
511 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
512 end, the force of what seems <quote>obvious</quote> to everyone else&mdash;the power of
513 <quote>common sense</quote>&mdash;would prevail. Their <quote>private interest</quote> would not be
514 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
515 </para>
516 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'/>
517 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'/>
518 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'/>
519 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='endofrange'/>
520 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
521 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham</primary></indexterm>
522 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
523 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael</primary></indexterm>
524 <indexterm id='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
525 <para>
526 <emphasis role='strong'>Edwin Howard Armstrong</emphasis> is one of
527 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
528 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
529 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
530 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
531 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
532 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in 1831. But
533 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
534 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
535 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
536 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
537 </para>
538 <para>
539 On the day after Christmas, 1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
540 for his most significant invention&mdash;FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
541 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
542 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
543 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
544 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
545 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
546 much less transmitter power and static.
547 </para>
548 <para>
549 On November 5, 1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
550 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
551 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
552 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
553 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
554 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
555 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
556 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
557 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.</quote>
558 </para>
559 <para>
560 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
561 </para>
562 <blockquote>
563 <para>
564 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
565 sounded like a glass of water being poured. &hellip; A paper was crumpled
566 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
567 fire. &hellip; Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
568 and guitar number were performed. &hellip; The music was projected with a
569 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio <quote>music
570 box.</quote><footnote><para>
571 Lawrence Lessing, <citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong</citetitle>
572 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209.
573 </para></footnote>
574 </para>
575 </blockquote>
576 <indexterm id='idxrca' class='startofrange'><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
577 <indexterm id='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
578 <para>
579 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
580 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
581 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
582 AM radio market. By 1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
583 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
584 a handful of networks.
585 <!--PAGE BREAK 20-->
586 </para>
587 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
588 <para>
589 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
590 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
591 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
592 that removed static from <quote>radio.</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
593 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
594 </para>
595 <blockquote>
596 <para>
597 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
598 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
599 revolution&mdash; start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
600 RCA.<footnote><para> See <quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
601 Electronic Era,</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
602 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
603
604 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #1</ulink>.
605 </para></footnote>
606 </para>
607 </blockquote>
608 <indexterm id='idxfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
609 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
610 <para>
611 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
612 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
613 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
614 described,
615 </para>
616 <indexterm id='idxlessinglawrence' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessing, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
617 <blockquote>
618 <para>
619 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
620 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
621 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
622 unrestrained, posed &hellip; a complete reordering of radio power
623 &hellip; and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
624 on which RCA had grown to power.<footnote><para>Lessing, 226.
625 </para></footnote>
626 </para>
627 </blockquote>
628 <indexterm id='idxfcconfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FCC</primary><secondary>on FM radio</secondary></indexterm>
629 <para>
630 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
631 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
632 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
633 FM radio's deployment generally. In 1936, RCA hired the former head
634 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
635 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM&mdash;principally by moving FM
636 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
637 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
638 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
639 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
640 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
641 </para>
642 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
643 <blockquote>
644 <para>
645 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
646 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
647 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
648 deviousness.<footnote><para>
649 Lessing, 256.
650 </para></footnote>
651 </para>
652 </blockquote>
653 <indexterm startref='idxlessinglawrence' class='endofrange'/>
654 <indexterm><primary>AT&amp;T</primary></indexterm>
655 <para>
656 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
657 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
658 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
659 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
660 (This change was strongly supported by AT&amp;T, because the loss of
661 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
662 wired links from AT&amp;T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
663 least temporarily.
664 </para>
665 <indexterm startref='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='endofrange'/>
666 <indexterm startref='idxfcconfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
667 <para>
668 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
669 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
670 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
671 invalid&mdash;baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
672 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
673 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
674 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
675 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
676 now broke, in 1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
677 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
678 </para>
679 <indexterm startref='idxfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
680 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'/>
681 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
682 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
683 <para>
684 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
685 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
686 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
687 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
688 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
689 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
690 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
691 course always public spirited; the reality is something
692 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
693 to themselves, would crumble in
694 <!--PAGE BREAK 22-->
695 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
696 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
697 effect of technological change.
698 </para>
699 <indexterm startref='idxrca' class='endofrange'/>
700 <indexterm startref='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='endofrange'/>
701 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
702 <para>
703 <emphasis role="strong">There's no</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
704 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
705 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
706 Internet and American Life Project, 58 percent of Americans had access
707 to the Internet in 2002, up from 49 percent two years
708 before.<footnote><para>
709 Amanda Lenhart, <quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
710 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,</quote> Pew Internet and American
711 Life Project, 15 April 2003: 6, available at
712 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #2</ulink>.
713 </para></footnote>
714 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
715 of 2004.
716 </para>
717 <para>
718 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
719 changed things. Some of these changes are technical&mdash;the Internet has
720 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
721 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
722 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
723 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
724 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
725 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
726 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
727 </para>
728 <para>
729 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
730 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
731 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
732 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
733 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
734 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
735 has introduced.
736 </para>
737 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
738 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel</primary></indexterm>
739 <indexterm id='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='startofrange'><primary>culture</primary><secondary>commercial vs. noncommercial</secondary></indexterm>
740 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah</primary></indexterm>
741 <para>
742 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
743 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
744 regulation of each. By <quote>commercial culture</quote> I mean that part of our
745 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
746 <quote>noncommercial culture</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
747 parks or on
748 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
749 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
750 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his <quote>Reader,</quote> or
751 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
752 </para>
753 <para>
754 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
755 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
756 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
757 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
758 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
759 left this culture <quote>free.</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
760 individuals shared and transformed their culture&mdash;telling
761 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
762 clubs, sharing music, making tapes&mdash;were left alone by the law.
763 </para>
764 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>commercial creativity as primary purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
765 <para>
766 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
767 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
768 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
769 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
770 marketplace.<footnote>
771 <para>
772 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
773 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
774 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
775 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
776 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
777 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
778 D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote> Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193,
779 198&ndash;200.
780 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
781 </para></footnote>
782 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
783 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
784 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
785 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
786 </para>
787 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
788 <indexterm><primary>permission culture</primary><secondary> free culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
789 <para>
790 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
791 been erased.<footnote><para>
792 See Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
793 2001), ch. 13.
794 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
795 </para></footnote>
796 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
797 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
798 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
799 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
800 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
801 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
802 the balance of our history&mdash;between uses of our culture that were
803 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission&mdash;has
804 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
805 culture, more and more a permission culture.
806 </para>
807 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
808 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
809 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
810 <indexterm><primary>protection of artists vs. business interests</primary></indexterm>
811 <para>
812 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
813 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
814 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
815 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
816 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
817 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
818 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
819 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
820 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
821 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
822 Causbys.
823 </para>
824 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='endofrange'/>
825 <para>
826 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
827 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
828 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
829 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
830 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
831 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
832 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
833 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
834 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
835 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
836 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
837 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
838 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
839 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
840 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
841 than creators do today&mdash;all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
842 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
843 </para>
844 <para>
845 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
846 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
847 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
848 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
849 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
850 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
851 remakes them.
852 </para>
853 <indexterm startref='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='endofrange'/>
854 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary> on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
855 <para>
856 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
857 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
858 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
859 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions&mdash;whether <quote>piracy</quote> will
860 be permitted, and whether <quote>property</quote> will be protected. The <quote>war</quote> that
861 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet&mdash;what
862 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
863 calls his <quote>own terrorist war</quote><footnote><para>
864 Amy Harmon, <quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
865 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,</quote> <citetitle>New York
866 Times</citetitle>, 17 January 2002.
867 </para></footnote>&mdash;has been framed as a battle about the
868 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
869 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
870 against it.
871 </para>
872 <para>
873 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
874 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
875 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
876 <quote>creative property.</quote> I believe that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that the
877 law, properly tuned, should punish <quote>piracy,</quote> whether on or off the
878 Internet.
879 </para>
880 <para>
881 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
882 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
883 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet <quote>pirates</quote> will also rid our
884 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
885 </para>
886 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
887 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
888 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
889 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
890 <para>
891 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first 180 years of
892 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
893 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
894 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
895 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,<footnote>
896 <para>
897 Neil W. Netanel, <quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
898 Journal</citetitle> 106 (1996): 283.
899 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
900 </para></footnote>
901 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
902 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
903 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
904 could cultivate and extend our culture.
905 </para>
906 <para>
907 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
908 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
909 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
910 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist&ndash;like,
911 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
912 granted&mdash;but it is not often granted to the critical or the
913 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
914 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
915 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
916 </para>
917 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Should "Is it" be "It is" ? -->
918 <para>
919 The story that follows is about this war. Is it not about the
920 <quote>centrality of technology</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
921 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
922 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
923 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
924 against an industry.
925 </para>
926 <para>
927 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
928 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
929 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
930 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
931 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
932 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
933 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
934 </para>
935 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
936 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
937 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary></indexterm>
938 <para>
939 <emphasis role="strong">Like the Causbys'</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about <quote>property.</quote> The
940 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
941 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
942 this <quote>property</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
943 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
944 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
945 of <quote>intellectual property</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
946 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
947 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
948 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
949 <quote>trespassing</quote> upon legitimate claims of <quote>property.</quote> It is as plain to
950 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
951 trespass.
952 </para>
953 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
954 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
955 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
956 <para>
957 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
958 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
959 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
960 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
961 war. Unlike
962 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
963 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
964 on its side.
965 </para>
966 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
967 <para>
968 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
969 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
970 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
971 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
972 our <quote>culture</quote> was as <quote>owned</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
973 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
974 <emphasis>uses</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
975 accepted as it is now.
976 </para>
977 <para>
978 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
979 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
980 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
981 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
982 </para>
983 <para>
984 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
985 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
986 </para>
987 <para>
988 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
989 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
990 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
991 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
992 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
993 </para>
994 <para>
995 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
996 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
997 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
998 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
999 view?
1000 </para>
1001 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1002 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1003 <para>
1004 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1005 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1006 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1007 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of <quote>intellectual
1008 property.</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1009 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1010 this silliness will be much more profound.
1011 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1012 </para>
1013 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='endofrange'/>
1014 <para>
1015 <emphasis role="strong">The struggle</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas: <quote>piracy</quote> and
1016 <quote>property.</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1017 ideas.
1018 </para>
1019 <para>
1020 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1021 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1022 obscure French theorists&mdash;however natural that is for the weird
1023 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1024 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1025 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1026 </para>
1027 <para>
1028 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1029 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1030 government, pushed by big media to respond to this <quote>something new,</quote> is
1031 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1032 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let <quote>common
1033 sense</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1034 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1035 law&mdash;and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1036 fundamental about who we have always been.
1037 </para>
1038 <para>
1039 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1040 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1041 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1042 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1043 of one more consequence of this form of corruption&mdash;a consequence
1044 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1045 </para>
1046 </chapter>
1047 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1048 <part id="c-piracy">
1049 <title><quote>PIRACY</quote></title>
1050 <partintro>
1051 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1052 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
1053 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
1054 <indexterm><primary>music publishing</primary></indexterm>
1055 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
1056 <para>
1057 <emphasis role="strong">Since the inception</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1058 been a war against <quote>piracy.</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1059 <quote>piracy,</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1060 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1061 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1062 </para>
1063 <blockquote>
1064 <para>
1065 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1066 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1067 of them for his own use.<footnote><para>
1068 <!-- f1 -->
1069 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield).
1070 </para></footnote>
1071 </para>
1072 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='endofrange'/>
1073 </blockquote>
1074 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary> efficient content distribution on</secondary></indexterm>
1075 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='startofrange'><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>efficiency of</secondary></indexterm>
1076 <para>
1077 Today we are in the middle of another <quote>war</quote> against <quote>piracy.</quote> The
1078 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1079 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1080 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1081 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1082 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1083 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1084 </para>
1085 <para>
1086 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1087 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1088 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1089 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1090 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will <quote>rob the author of the
1091 profit.</quote>
1092 </para>
1093 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='endofrange'/>
1094 <para>
1095 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1096 increasingly to technology to defend their <quote>property</quote> against this
1097 <quote>piracy.</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1098 raised to believe that <quote>property</quote> should be <quote>free.</quote> Forget tattoos,
1099 never mind body piercing&mdash;our kids are becoming
1100 <emphasis>thieves</emphasis>!
1101 </para>
1102 <para>
1103 There's no doubt that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1104 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1105 notion of <quote>piracy</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1106 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1107 </para>
1108 <para>
1109 The idea goes something like this:
1110 </para>
1111 <blockquote>
1112 <para>
1113 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1114 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1115 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1116 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1117 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1118 piracy.
1119 </para>
1120 </blockquote>
1121 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP</primary></indexterm>
1122 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle</primary></indexterm>
1123 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts</primary></indexterm>
1124 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory of</secondary></indexterm>
1125 <indexterm id='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
1126 <para>
1127 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1128 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1129 theory of creative property<footnote><para>
1130 <!-- f2 -->
1131 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, <quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1132 in the Pepsi Generation,</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review</citetitle> 65 (1990): 397.
1133 </para></footnote>
1134 &mdash;if there is value, then someone must have a
1135 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1136 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1137 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.<footnote><para>
1138 <!-- f3 -->
1139 Lisa Bannon, <quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1140 Up,</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 21 August 1996, available at
1141 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #3</ulink>; Jonathan
1142 Zittrain, <quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1143 Speech, No One Wins,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 24 November 2002.
1144 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
1145 </para></footnote>
1146 There was <quote>value</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1147 <quote>right</quote>&mdash;even against the Girl Scouts.
1148 </para>
1149 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='endofrange'/>
1150 <para>
1151 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1152 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1153 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1154 of law protecting creative property. But the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1155 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1156 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1157 </para>
1158 <indexterm startref='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='endofrange'/>
1159 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
1160 <indexterm id='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>legal restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
1161 <para>
1162 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1163 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1164 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1165 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1166 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1167 </para>
1168 <para>
1169 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1170 takes care to draw&mdash;the distinction between republishing someone's
1171 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1172 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1173 copyright law today regulates both.
1174 </para>
1175 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='endofrange'/>
1176 <para>
1177 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1178 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1179 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1180 entities could bear the burden of the law&mdash;even the burden of the
1181 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1182 more expense of doing business.
1183 </para>
1184 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>creativity impeded by</secondary></indexterm>
1185 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1186 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1187 <para>
1188 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1189 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1190 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1191 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1192 <quote>copying,</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1193 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1194 outweighs any original benefit&mdash;certainly as it affects
1195 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1196 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1197 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1198 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1199 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1200 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1201 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1202 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1203 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1204 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the <quote>Rise of the Creative
1205 Class.</quote><footnote>
1206 <para>
1207 <!-- f4 -->
1208 In <citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class</citetitle> (New York:
1209 Basic Books, 2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1210 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1211 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1212 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1213 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1214 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1215
1216 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1217 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1218 </para></footnote>
1219 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1220 this creative class.
1221 </para>
1222 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='endofrange'/>
1223 <para>
1224 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1225 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1226 context the current battles about behavior labeled <quote>piracy.</quote>
1227 </para>
1228 </partintro>
1229
1230 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1231 <chapter label="1" id="creators">
1232 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators</title>
1233 <indexterm id='idxanimatedcartoons' class='startofrange'><primary>animated cartoons</primary></indexterm>
1234 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'><primary>cartoon films</primary></indexterm>
1235 <indexterm id='idxfilmsanimated' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>animated</secondary></indexterm>
1236 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatwillie' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Willie</primary></indexterm>
1237 <indexterm id='idxmickeymouse' class='startofrange'><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
1238 <para>
1239 <emphasis role="strong">In 1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1240 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called <citetitle>Plane Crazy</citetitle>.
1241 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1242 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle> brought
1243 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1244 </para>
1245 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1246 <para>
1247 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1248 movie <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1249 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1250 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1251 Disney ran a test in the summer of 1928, the results were unambiguous.
1252 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1253 </para>
1254 <blockquote>
1255 <para>
1256 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1257 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1258 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1259 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1260 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1261 </para>
1262 <para>
1263 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1264 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1265 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1266 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1267 synchronization was pretty close.
1268 </para>
1269 <para>
1270 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1271 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1272 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1273 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1274 it was something new!<footnote><para>
1275 <!-- f1 -->
1276 Leonard Maltin, <citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1277 Cartoons</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34&ndash;35.
1278 </para></footnote>
1279 </para>
1280 </blockquote>
1281 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub</primary></indexterm>
1282 <para>
1283 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1284 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: <quote>I have never been so thrilled
1285 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.</quote>
1286 </para>
1287 <para>
1288 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1289 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1290 rarely&mdash;except in Disney's hands&mdash;been anything more than
1291 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1292 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1293 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1294 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1295 </para>
1296 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt' class='endofrange'/>
1297 <indexterm id='idxkeatonbuster' class='startofrange'><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1298 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1299 <para>
1300 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that 1928 also marks
1301 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1302 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1303 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>.
1304 </para>
1305 <para>
1306 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in 1895. In the era of silent
1307 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1308 uncontrollable laughter from his audience. <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1309 Jr</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1310 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton&mdash;wildly popular
1311 and among the best of its genre.
1312 </para>
1313 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1314 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1315 <para>
1316 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1317 Willie.
1318 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1319 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1320 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,<footnote><para>
1321 <!-- f2 -->
1322 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1323 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #4</ulink>.
1324 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1325 use the music for five songs in <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>: <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote> <quote>The
1326 Simpleton</quote> (Delille), <quote>Mischief Makers</quote> (Carbonara), <quote>Joyful Hurry No. 1</quote>
1327 (Baron), and <quote>Gawky Rube</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song, <quote>The Turkey in the
1328 Straw,</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1329 Harry Surden, 10 July 2003, on file with author.
1330 </para></footnote>
1331 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1332 the invention of synchronized sound in <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle> that we
1333 get <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1334 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote>
1335 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1336 Mouse.
1337 </para>
1338 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatwillie' class='endofrange'/>
1339 <indexterm startref='idxmickeymouse' class='endofrange'/>
1340 <indexterm startref='idxkeatonbuster' class='endofrange'/>
1341 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='endofrange'/>
1342 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1343 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
1344 <para>
1345 This <quote>borrowing</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1346 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1347 films of his day.<footnote><para>
1348 <!-- f3 -->
1349 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, <quote>The Mouse
1350 that Ate the Public Domain,</quote> Findlaw, 5 March 2002, at
1351 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #5</ulink>.
1352 </para></footnote>
1353 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1354 knockoffs&mdash;slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1355 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1356 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1357 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1358 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1359 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1360 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1361 old.
1362 </para>
1363 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1364 <para>
1365 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1366 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1367 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1368 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1369 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1370 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1371 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1372 </para>
1373 <para>
1374 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1375 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1376 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1377 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1378 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1379 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1380 work of others is astonishing when set together: <citetitle>Snow White</citetitle>
1381 (1937), <citetitle>Fantasia</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Pinocchio</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Dumbo</citetitle>
1382 (1941), <citetitle>Bambi</citetitle> (1942), <citetitle>Song of the South</citetitle> (1946),
1383 <citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle> (1950), <citetitle>Alice in Wonderland</citetitle> (1951), <citetitle>Robin
1384 Hood</citetitle> (1952), <citetitle>Peter Pan</citetitle> (1953), <citetitle>Lady and the Tramp</citetitle>
1385 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1386 (1955), <citetitle>Mulan</citetitle> (1998), <citetitle>Sleeping Beauty</citetitle> (1959), <citetitle>101
1387 Dalmatians</citetitle> (1961), <citetitle>The Sword in the Stone</citetitle> (1963), and
1388 <citetitle>The Jungle Book</citetitle> (1967)&mdash;not to mention a recent example
1389 that we should perhaps quickly forget, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>
1390 (2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1391 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1392 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1393 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1394 </para>
1395 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales' class='endofrange'/>
1396 <para>
1397 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1398 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1399 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1400 its importance. We could call this <quote>Disney creativity,</quote> though that
1401 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, <quote>Walt Disney
1402 creativity</quote>&mdash;a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1403 culture around us and makes it something different.
1404 </para>
1405 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='endofrange'/>
1406 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='endofrange'/>
1407 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='endofrange'/>
1408 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
1409 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>defined</secondary></indexterm>
1410 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>traditional term for conversion to</secondary></indexterm>
1411 <para> In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1412 relatively fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was
1413 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1414 thirty years&mdash;for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1415 copyrighted.<footnote><para>
1416 <!-- f4 -->
1417 Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1418 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the <quote>average</quote> term by
1419 determining
1420 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1421 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in year
1422 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the
1423 average
1424 term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1425 Web site associated with this book, available at
1426 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #6</ulink>.
1427 </para></footnote>
1428 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1429 copyright holders of a creative work had an <quote>exclusive right</quote> to control
1430 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1431 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1432 </para>
1433 <para>
1434 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1435 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1436 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a <quote>lawyer-free
1437 zone.</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1438 for Disney to use and build upon in 1928. It was free for
1439 anyone&mdash; whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1440 approved or not&mdash;to use and build upon.
1441 </para>
1442 <indexterm startref='idxanimatedcartoons' class='endofrange'/>
1443 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsanimated' class='endofrange'/>
1444 <para>
1445 This is the ways things always were&mdash;until quite recently. For most
1446 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1447 until 1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1448 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1449
1450 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1451 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1452 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s
1453 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1454 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1455 content from before the Great Depression.
1456 </para>
1457 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'/>
1458 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc' class='endofrange'/>
1459 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='endofrange'/>
1460 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='endofrange'/>
1461 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='endofrange'/>
1462 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1463 <para>
1464 <emphasis role="strong">Of course</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on <quote>Walt Disney creativity.</quote>
1465 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1466 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1467 universal.
1468 </para>
1469 <indexterm id='idxcomicsjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1470 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1471 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1472 <indexterm id='idxmanga' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1473 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1474 <para>
1475 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1476 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: <citetitle>manga</citetitle>, or
1477 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of
1478 publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives
1479 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1480 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1481 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1482 </para>
1483 <para>
1484 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1485 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1486 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1487 the stories that these <quote>graphic novels</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1488 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are <quote>men in tights.</quote>
1489 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1490 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1491 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1492 interestingly different way.
1493 </para>
1494 <para>
1495 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1496 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1497 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1498 </para>
1499 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1500 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1501 <para>
1502 This is the phenomenon of <citetitle>doujinshi</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1503 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1504 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is <emphasis>just</emphasis> a
1505 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1506 transforming it either subtly or
1507 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1508 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1509 develop it differently&mdash;with a different story line. Or the comic can
1510 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1511 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently <quote>different.</quote> But they
1512 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1513 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1514 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1515 </para>
1516 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1517 <para>
1518 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1519 huge. More than 33,000 <quote>circles</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1520 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come
1521 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1522 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1523 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1524 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1525 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1526 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1527 </para>
1528 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1529 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1530 <para>
1531 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1532 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1533 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1534 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1535 one. Doujinshi are plainly <quote>derivative works.</quote> There is no general
1536 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1537 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1538 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1539 Jr</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that <quote>taking</quote> without
1540 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1541 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1542 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1543 </para>
1544 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt2' class='endofrange'/>
1545 <indexterm id='idxwinickjudd' class='startofrange'><primary>Winick, Judd</primary></indexterm>
1546 <para>
1547 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1548 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1549 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, <quote>The
1550 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1551 in Japan now. &hellip; American comics were born out of copying each
1552 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1553 other. &hellip; That's how [the artists] learn to draw&mdash;by going into comic
1554 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them</quote>
1555 and building from them.<footnote><para>
1556 <!-- f5 -->
1557 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, <citetitle>Reinventing Comics</citetitle> (New
1558 York: Perennial, 2000).
1559 </para></footnote>
1560 </para>
1561 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1562 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics</primary></indexterm>
1563 <para>
1564 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1565 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1566 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, <quote>there are these rules
1567 and you have to stick to them.</quote> There are things Superman <quote>cannot</quote>
1568 do. <quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1569 which are fifty years old.</quote>
1570 </para>
1571 <indexterm startref='idxwinickjudd' class='endofrange'/>
1572 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1573 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1574 <indexterm id='idxmehrasalil' class='startofrange'><primary>Mehra, Salil</primary></indexterm>
1575 <para>
1576 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1577 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1578 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1579 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1580 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1581 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1582 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.<footnote><para>
1583 <!-- f6 -->
1584 See Salil K. Mehra, <quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1585 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1586 Review</citetitle> 55 (2002): 155, 182. <quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1587 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1588 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1589 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1590 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1591 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.</quote>
1592 </para></footnote>
1593 </para>
1594 <indexterm startref='idxcomicsjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1595 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics' class='endofrange'/>
1596 <indexterm startref='idxmanga' class='endofrange'/>
1597 <para>
1598 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1599 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1600 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1601 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1602 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1603 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1604 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1605 a more general pattern of blocking this <quote>free taking</quote> by the doujinshi
1606 culture?
1607 </para>
1608 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='endofrange'/>
1609 <indexterm startref='idxmehrasalil' class='endofrange'/>
1610 <para>
1611 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1612 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1613 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. <quote>We don't have enough
1614 lawyers,</quote> he told me one afternoon. There <quote>just aren't enough resources
1615 to prosecute cases like this.</quote>
1616 </para>
1617 <para>
1618 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1619 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1620 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1621 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1623 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1624 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1625 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1626 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1627 their clients or hurt them?
1628 </para>
1629 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics' class='endofrange'/>
1630 <para>
1631 <emphasis role='strong'>Let's pause</emphasis> for a moment.
1632 </para>
1633 <para>
1634 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1635 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1636 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1637 </para>
1638 <para>
1639 We live in a world that celebrates <quote>property.</quote> I am one of those
1640 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1641 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1642 <quote>intellectual property.</quote><footnote><para>
1643 <!-- f7 -->
1644 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
1645 The term <citetitle>intellectual property</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1646 Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 11 (New York: New York
1647 University Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
1648 (New York: Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately
1649 describes a set of <quote>property</quote> rights&mdash;copyright, patents,
1650 trademark, and trade-secret&mdash;but the nature of those rights is
1651 very different.
1652 </para></footnote>
1653 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1654 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1655 property.
1656 </para>
1657 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt3' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1658 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1659 <indexterm><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1660 <para>
1661 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1662 plenty of value out there that <quote>property</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1663 mean <quote>money can't buy you love,</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1664 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1665 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1666 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1667 condemning that taking as wrong&mdash; even though trivial, even if
1668 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1669 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1670 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1671 Disney's use would have been considered <quote>fair.</quote> There was nothing
1672 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1673 the public domain.
1674 </para>
1675 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>derivative works based on</secondary></indexterm>
1676 <para>
1677 Thus, even though the things that Disney took&mdash;or more generally,
1678 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity&mdash;are
1679 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1680
1681 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1682 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1683 freedom is good.
1684 </para>
1685 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='endofrange'/>
1686 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1687 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1688 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1689 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1690 <indexterm id='idxmanga2' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1691 <para>
1692 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1693 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1694 work&mdash;or even one copy&mdash;without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1695 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1696 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1697 form, whether large or small.
1698 </para>
1699 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='endofrange'/>
1700 <para>
1701 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1702 say that the copycat comic artists are <quote>stealing.</quote> This form of Walt
1703 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1704 particular find it hard to say why.
1705 </para>
1706 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1707 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1708 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='endofrange'/>
1709 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1710 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1711 <indexterm startref='idxmanga2' class='endofrange'/>
1712 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
1713 <para>
1714 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1715 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1716 without asking or paying for the privilege. (<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1717 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1718 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?</quote>) Acting companies
1719 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1720 permission from anyone. (Does <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> believe
1721 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1722 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1723 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1724 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s;
1725 two volcano disaster films in 1997.
1726 </para>
1727 <para>
1728 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1729 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1730 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1731 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1732 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1733 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1734 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking&mdash;free
1735 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1736 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1737 </para>
1738 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt3' class='endofrange'/>
1739 <para>
1740 The hard question is therefore not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> a
1741 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1742 question instead is <quote><emphasis>How</emphasis> free is this culture?</quote>
1743 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1744 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1745 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1746 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1747 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1748 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1749 a studio or not?
1750 </para>
1751 <para>
1752 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1753 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1754 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1755 </para>
1756 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='endofrange'/>
1757
1758 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1759 </chapter>
1760 <chapter label="2" id="mere-copyists">
1761 <title>CHAPTER TWO: <quote>Mere Copyists</quote></title>
1762 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis</primary></indexterm>
1763 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1764 <indexterm id='idxphotography' class='startofrange'><primary>photography</primary></indexterm>
1765 <para>
1766 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1767 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1768 <quote>photographs.</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1769 <quote>daguerreotypes.</quote> The process was complicated and
1770 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1771 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1772 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1773 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1774 </para>
1775 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William</primary></indexterm>
1776 <para>
1777 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1778 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1779 <quote>automatic pictures.</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1780 making <quote>negatives.</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1781 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1782 the 1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1783 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1784 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1785 amateurs.
1786 </para>
1787 <indexterm id='idxeastmangeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Eastman, George</primary></indexterm>
1788 <para>
1789 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1790 didn't happen until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1791 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1792 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1793 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1794 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1795 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1796 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1797 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1798 population of photographers.
1799 </para>
1800 <indexterm id='idxkodakcameras' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1801 <indexterm id='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)</primary></indexterm>
1802 <para>
1803 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1804 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1805 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. <quote>You press the button and we
1806 do the rest.</quote><footnote><para>
1807 <!-- f1 -->
1808 Reese V. Jenkins, <citetitle>Images and Enterprise</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975), 112.
1809 </para></footnote> As he described in <citetitle>The Kodak Primer</citetitle>:
1810 </para>
1811 <blockquote>
1812 <para>
1813 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1814 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1815 that only an expert can do. &hellip; We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1816 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1817 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1818 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1819 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1820 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1821 chemicals.<footnote>
1822 <para>
1823 <!-- f2 -->
1824 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1825 Brian Coe, <citetitle>The Birth of Photography</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1826 1977), 53.
1827 </para></footnote>
1828 </para>
1829 </blockquote>
1830 <indexterm startref='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='endofrange'/>
1831 <para>
1832 For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1833 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1834 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1835 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1836 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1837 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in 1888; one
1838 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1839 From 1888 through 1909, while industrial production was rising by 4.7
1840 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by 11
1841 percent.<footnote><para>
1842 <!-- f3 -->
1843 Jenkins, 177.
1844 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1845 an average annual increase of over 17 percent.<footnote><para>
1846 <!-- f4 -->
1847 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p. 178.
1848 </para></footnote>
1849 </para>
1850 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1851 <para>
1852
1853 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1854 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1855 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1856 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1857 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1858 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, <quote>For the
1859 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1860 permanent record of his family and its activities. &hellip; For the first
1861 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1862 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1863 interpretation or bias.</quote><footnote><para>
1864 <!-- f5 -->
1865 Coe, 58.
1866 </para></footnote>
1867 </para>
1868 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
1869 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
1870 <para>
1871 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1872 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1873 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1874 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1875 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1876 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its <quote>quality</quote>;
1877 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1878 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1879 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1880 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1881 have before.
1882 </para>
1883 <indexterm startref='idxkodakcameras' class='endofrange'/>
1884 <indexterm id='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>permissions</primary><secondary>photography exempted from</secondary></indexterm>
1885 <para>
1886 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1887 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1888 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1889 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1890 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1891 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1892 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1893 he wanted. Their answer was no.<footnote><para>
1894 <!-- f6 -->
1895 For illustrative cases, see, for example, <citetitle>Pavesich</citetitle>
1896 v. <citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co</citetitle>., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905);
1897 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Chinn</citetitle>, 123090 S.W. 364, 366
1898 (Ky. 1909); <citetitle>Corliss</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Walker</citetitle>, 64 F. 280 (Mass.
1899 Dist. Ct. 1894).
1900 </para></footnote>
1901 </para>
1902 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology' class='endofrange'/>
1903 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt4' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1904 <indexterm id='idximagesownershipof' class='startofrange'><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
1905 <para>
1906 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1907 familiar. The photographer was <quote>taking</quote> something from the person or
1908 building whose photograph he shot&mdash;pirating something of
1909 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1910 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1911 draw
1912 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1913 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1914 that they thought valuable.
1915 </para>
1916 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1917 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1918 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology2' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1919 <para>
1920 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1921 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1922 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1923 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1924 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.<footnote>
1925 <para>
1926 <!-- f7 -->
1927 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote>
1928 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review</citetitle> 4 (1890): 193.
1929 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1930 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.</primary></indexterm>
1931 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1932 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1933 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1934 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1935 </para>
1936 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt4' class='endofrange'/>
1937 <para>
1938 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1939 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1940 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1941 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1942 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1943 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1944 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1945 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1946 clearing the rights to do the capturing.<footnote><para>
1947 <!-- f8 -->
1948 See Melville B. Nimmer, <quote>The Right of Publicity,</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
1949 Problems</citetitle> 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, <quote>Privacy,</quote> <citetitle>California Law
1950 Review</citetitle> 48 (1960) 398&ndash;407; <citetitle>White</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
1951 Inc</citetitle>., 971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951
1952 (1993).
1953 </para></footnote>)
1954 </para>
1955 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1956 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
1957 <para>
1958 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1959 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1960 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1961 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1962 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1963 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1964 Kodak would be benefiting from the <quote>theft</quote> committed by the
1965 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1966 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1967 from the <quote>image-right</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
1968 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1969 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1970 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1971 </para>
1972 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology2' class='endofrange'/>
1973 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology3' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1974 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
1975 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
1976 <para>
1977
1978 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
1979 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
1980 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
1981 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
1982 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
1983 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
1984 technology as they did&mdash;since professionals could have more
1985 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
1986 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
1987 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
1988 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
1989 realized.
1990 </para>
1991 <indexterm startref='idxphotography' class='endofrange'/>
1992 <indexterm startref='idxeastmangeorge' class='endofrange'/>
1993 <indexterm startref='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
1994 <indexterm startref='idximagesownershipof' class='endofrange'/>
1995 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
1996 <indexterm id='idxjustthink' class='startofrange'><primary>Just Think!</primary></indexterm>
1997 <para>
1998 <emphasis role='strong'>If you drive</emphasis> through San
1999 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
2000 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
2001 <quote>Just Think!</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
2002 there's little that's <quote>just</quote> cerebral in the projects
2003 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
2004 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
2005 the film of your VCR. Rather the <quote>film</quote> of digital
2006 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
2007 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
2008 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
2009 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
2010 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
2011 think. By tinkering, they learn.
2012 </para>
2013 <indexterm id='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>education</primary><secondary>in media literacy</secondary></indexterm>
2014 <indexterm id='idxmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>media literacy</primary></indexterm>
2015 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>media literacy and</secondary></indexterm>
2016 <para>
2017 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
2018 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
2019 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, <quote>Five years ago, a good
2020 real-time digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get
2021 professional quality for $595.</quote><footnote><para>
2022 <!-- f9 -->
2023 H. Edward Goldberg, <quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
2024 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,</quote>
2025 cadalyst, February 2002, available at
2026 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #7</ulink>.
2027 </para></footnote>
2028 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
2029 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
2030 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
2031 learning more and more of something teachers call <quote>media literacy.</quote>
2032 </para>
2033 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2034 <para>
2035 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
2036 <quote>Media literacy,</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
2037 Think!, puts it, <quote>is the ability &hellip; to understand, analyze, and
2038 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2039 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2040 the way people access it.</quote>
2041 </para>
2042 <indexterm startref='idxjustthink' class='endofrange'/>
2043 <para>
2044 This may seem like an odd way to think about <quote>literacy.</quote> For most
2045 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2046 and noticing split infinitives are the things that <quote>literate</quote> people know
2047 about.
2048 </para>
2049 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2050 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
2051 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
2052 <para>
2053 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of
2054 television commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000
2055 commercials generally,<footnote><para>
2056 <!-- f10 -->
2057 Judith Van Evra, <citetitle>Television and Child Development</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2058 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990); <quote>Findings on Family and TV
2059 Study,</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post</citetitle>, 25 May 1997, B6.
2060 </para></footnote>
2061 it is increasingly important to understand the <quote>grammar</quote> of media. For
2062 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2063 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2064 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2065 (at least at first) terrible media.
2066 </para>
2067 <para>
2068 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2069 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2070 has written understands how difficult writing is&mdash;how difficult
2071 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2072 language to be understandable&mdash;few of us have any real sense of
2073 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2074 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2075 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2076 </para>
2077 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology3' class='endofrange'/>
2078 <para>
2079 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2080 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2081 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2082 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2083 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2084 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2085 </para>
2086 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2087 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael</primary></indexterm>
2088 <para>
2089 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2090 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2091 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2092
2093 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2094 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2095 about <quote>the placement of objects, color, &hellip; rhythm, pacing, and
2096 texture.</quote><footnote>
2097 <para>
2098 <!-- f11 -->
2099 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish, 13 December
2100 2002.
2101 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2102 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2103 </para></footnote>
2104 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2105 <quote>played</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2106 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2107 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2108 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2109 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2110 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2111 to a wildly successful author.<footnote><para>
2112 <!-- f12 -->
2113 See Scott Steinberg, <quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,</quote> E!online, 4
2114 November 2000, available at
2115 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #8</ulink>; <quote>Timeline,</quote> 22 November 2000,
2116 available at
2117 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #9</ulink>.
2118 </para></footnote>
2119 </para>
2120 <indexterm><primary>computer games</primary></indexterm>
2121 <para>
2122 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2123 describes, <quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2124 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2125 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2126 led.</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2127 </para>
2128 <para>
2129 Yet the push for an expanded literacy&mdash;one that goes beyond text
2130 to include audio and visual elements&mdash;is not about making better
2131 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2132 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2133 </para>
2134 <blockquote>
2135 <para>
2136 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2137 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2138 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2139 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2140 being read-only.
2141 </para>
2142 </blockquote>
2143 <para>
2144 <quote>Read-only.</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2145 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2146 twentieth century.
2147 </para>
2148 <para>
2149 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2150 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2151 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2152 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2153 literacy,
2154 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2155 and this literacy in particular, is to <quote>empower people to choose the
2156 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2157 express.</quote><footnote>
2158 <para>
2159 <!-- f13 -->
2160 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2161 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2162 </para></footnote> It is to enable students <quote>to communicate in the
2163 language of the twenty-first century.</quote><footnote><para>
2164 <!-- f14 -->
2165 Ibid.
2166 </para></footnote>
2167 </para>
2168 <indexterm id='idxbarishstephanie' class='startofrange'><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2169 <para>
2170 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2171 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2172 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2173 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2174 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2175 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2176 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2177 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2178 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2179 students know something about&mdash;gun violence.
2180 </para>
2181 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='endofrange'/>
2182 <para>
2183 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2184 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2185 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2186 away. The <quote>kids were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night,</quote>
2187 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2188 what education should be about&mdash;learning how to express themselves.
2189 </para>
2190 <para>
2191 Using whatever <quote>free web stuff they could find,</quote> and relatively simple
2192 tools to enable the kids to mix <quote>image, sound, and text,</quote> Barish said
2193 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2194 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2195 close to the lives of these students. The project <quote>gave them a tool
2196 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2197 it,</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2198 expression&mdash;far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2199 been created using only text. <quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2200 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2201 gone and done something else,</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2202 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2203 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2204 <emphasis>these</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2205 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2206 </para>
2207 <indexterm startref='idxbarishstephanie' class='endofrange'/>
2208 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2209 <para>
2210
2211 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2212 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?</quote> I asked. In part,
2213 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2214 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of <quote>constructing
2215 meaning.</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2216 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2217 part&mdash;and increasingly, not the most powerful part&mdash;of
2218 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2219 our interview,
2220 </para>
2221 <blockquote>
2222 <para>
2223 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2224 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2225 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2226 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2227 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2228 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2229 you say, <quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.</quote>
2230 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2231 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2232 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, <quote>Well, with all these things that you
2233 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2234 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2235 for me something that reflects that.</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2236 camera and &hellip; saying, <quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2237 make a little movie.</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2238 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2239 about the topic.&hellip;
2240 </para>
2241 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2242 <para>
2243 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2244 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2245 bump up against the fact, <quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2246 to write something.</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2247 they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 times, till they got it right.
2248 </para>
2249 <para>
2250 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2251 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2252 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2253 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2254 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2255 had a lot of power with this language.
2256 </para>
2257 <!-- FIXME removed a " from the end of the previous paragraph that did
2258 not match with any start quote. -->
2259 </blockquote>
2260 <indexterm startref='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2261 <indexterm startref='idxmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2262 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='endofrange'/>
2263 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='endofrange'/>
2264 <indexterm id='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='startofrange'><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2265 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center</primary></indexterm>
2266 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
2267 <para>
2268 <emphasis role='strong'>When two planes</emphasis> crashed into the
2269 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2270 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2271 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2272 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2273 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2274 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2275 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2276 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2277 watching.
2278 </para>
2279 <para>
2280 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2281 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2282 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was <quote>balance,</quote>
2283 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2284 increasingly come to expect it, <quote>news as entertainment,</quote> even if the
2285 entertainment is tragedy.
2286 </para>
2287 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
2288 <indexterm><primary>CBS</primary></indexterm>
2289 <para>
2290 But in addition to this produced news about the <quote>tragedy of September
2291 11,</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2292 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2293 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2294 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2295 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2296 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2297 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2298 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2299 the term in his book <citetitle>Cyber Rights</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2300 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2301 was also the Internet.
2302 </para>
2303 <indexterm startref='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='endofrange'/>
2304 <para>
2305 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet&mdash;though I do think the
2306 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2307 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2308 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2309 movie
2310 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2311 by a student on the <quote>Just Think!</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2312 with sound or text.
2313 </para>
2314 <para>
2315 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2316 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2317 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2318 tradition&mdash;not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2319 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2320 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2321 spread practically instantaneously.
2322 </para>
2323 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2324 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2325 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2326 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2327 <para>
2328 September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2329 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2330 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2331 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2332 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2333 cultures, it records private facts in a public way&mdash;it's a kind
2334 of electronic <citetitle>Jerry Springer</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2335 </para>
2336 <indexterm><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2337 <indexterm id='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>public discourse conducted on</secondary></indexterm>
2338 <para>
2339 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2340 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2341 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2342 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2343 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2344 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2345 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2346 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2347 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2348 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2349 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2350 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2351 </para>
2352 <indexterm id='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
2353 <indexterm id='idxelections' class='startofrange'><primary>elections</primary></indexterm>
2354 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
2355 <para>
2356 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2357 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2358 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2359 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2360 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2361 people vote
2362 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2363 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2364 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2365 </para>
2366 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2367 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson' class='endofrange'/>
2368 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2369 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de</primary></indexterm>
2370 <indexterm id='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>public discourse in</secondary></indexterm>
2371 <indexterm><primary>jury system</primary></indexterm>
2372 <para>
2373 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2374 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2375 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2376 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2377 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2378 most important account of early <quote>Democracy in America.</quote> It wasn't
2379 popular elections that fascinated him&mdash;it was the jury, an
2380 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2381 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2382 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2383 deliberated. Members argued about the <quote>right</quote> result; they tried to
2384 persuade each other of the <quote>right</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2385 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2386 come to an end.<footnote><para>
2387 <!-- f15 -->
2388 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, <citetitle>Democracy in America</citetitle>,
2389 bk. 1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16.
2390 </para></footnote>
2391 </para>
2392 <indexterm startref='idxelections' class='endofrange'/>
2393 <para>
2394 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2395 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2396 are pushing to create just such an institution.<footnote><para>
2397 <!-- f16 -->
2398 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, <quote>Deliberation Day,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2399 Political Philosophy</citetitle> 10 (2) (2002): 129.
2400 </para></footnote>
2401 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2402 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2403 place for <quote>democratic deliberation</quote> to occur.
2404 </para>
2405 <indexterm id='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='startofrange'><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2406 <para>
2407 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2408 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2409 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2410 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2411 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2412 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.<footnote><para>
2413 <!-- f17 -->
2414 Cass Sunstein, <citetitle>Republic.com</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001),
2415 65&ndash;80, 175, 182, 183, 192.
2416 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2417 little beyond what our friends say.
2418 </para>
2419 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2420 <indexterm><primary>e-mail</primary></indexterm>
2421 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2422 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2423 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='endofrange'/>
2424 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='endofrange'/>
2425 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='endofrange'/>
2426 <para>
2427 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2428 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2429 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2430 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2431 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2432
2433 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2434 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2435 place.
2436 </para>
2437 <para>
2438 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2439 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2440 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2441 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2442 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2443 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2444 </para>
2445 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard</primary></indexterm>
2446 <para>
2447 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2448 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race
2449 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2450 is having an effect.
2451 </para>
2452 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent</primary></indexterm>
2453 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom</primary></indexterm>
2454 <indexterm id='idxmediablogpressureon' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>blog pressure on</secondary></indexterm>
2455 <indexterm id='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>news events on</secondary></indexterm>
2456 <para>
2457 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2458 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2459 <quote>misspoke</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2460 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2461 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2462 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2463 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2464 more instances of the same <quote>misspeaking</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2465 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2466 resign as senate majority leader.<footnote><para>
2467 <!-- f18 -->
2468 Noah Shachtman, <quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,</quote> New
2469 York Times, 16 January 2003, G5.
2470 </para></footnote>
2471 </para>
2472 <indexterm id='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2473 <para>
2474 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2475 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2476 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2477 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2478 on.
2479 </para>
2480 <indexterm startref='idxmediablogpressureon' class='endofrange'/>
2481 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>peer-generated rankings on</secondary></indexterm>
2482 <para>
2483 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2484 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2485 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2486 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2487 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2488 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2489 peer-generated rankings.
2490 </para>
2491 <indexterm startref='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='endofrange'/>
2492 <indexterm id='idxjournalism' class='startofrange'><primary>journalism</primary></indexterm>
2493 <indexterm id='idxwinerdave' class='startofrange'><primary>Winer, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2494 <para>
2495 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2496 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2497 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2498 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2499 difference is the absence of a financial <quote>conflict of interest.</quote> <quote>I think you
2500 have to take the conflict of interest</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2501 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2502 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2503 get it out of the way.</quote>
2504 </para>
2505 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2506 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2507 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2508 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
2509 <para>
2510 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2511 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2512 from the public than an unconcentrated media can&mdash;as CNN admitted
2513 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2514 its own employees.<footnote><para>
2515 <!-- f19 -->
2516 Telephone interview with David Winer, 16 April 2003.
2517 </para></footnote>
2518 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2519 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2520 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2521 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2522 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2523 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2524 told her that <emphasis>they</emphasis> were writing <quote>the story.</quote>)
2525 </para>
2526 <indexterm startref='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='endofrange'/>
2527 <para>
2528 Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2529 debate&mdash;<quote>amateur</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced,
2530 but in the sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to
2531 give their reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a
2532 story, as reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds
2533 from across the southwest United States turned to the Internet to
2534 retell what they had seen.<footnote><para>
2535 <!-- f20 -->
2536 John Schwartz, <quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2537 Information Online,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci
2538 D. Kramer, <quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,</quote>
2539 Online Journalism Review, 2 February 2003, available at
2540 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #10</ulink>.
2541 </para></footnote>
2542 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2543 <quote>triangulate,</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2544 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2545 out of it</quote>&mdash;with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2546 </para>
2547 <para>
2548 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2549 with blogs. <quote>It's going to become an essential skill,</quote> Winer predicts,
2550 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2551 not clear that <quote>journalism</quote> is happy about this&mdash;some journalists
2552 have been told to curtail their blogging.<footnote>
2553 <para>
2554 <!-- f21 -->
2555 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2556 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2557 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve</primary></indexterm>
2558 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2559 See Michael Falcone, <quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?</quote> <citetitle>New
2560 York Times</citetitle>, 29 September 2003, C4. (<quote>Not all news organizations have
2561 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2562 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2563 war on March 9, stopped posting 12 days later at his bosses'
2564 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a <citetitle>Houston Chronicle</citetitle> reporter, was
2565 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2566 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.</quote>)
2567 </para></footnote>
2568 But it is clear that we are still in transition. <quote>A
2569
2570 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2571 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,</quote> Winer told me.
2572 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2573 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2574 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, <quote>we will
2575 be the last thing that gets shut down.</quote>
2576 </para>
2577 <indexterm startref='idxjournalism' class='endofrange'/>
2578 <para>
2579 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because <quote>you
2580 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.</quote>
2581 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2582 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2583 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2584 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2585 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2586 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2587 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2588 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2589 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2590 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2591 extraordinary to report.
2592 </para>
2593 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage' class='endofrange'/>
2594 <indexterm startref='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='endofrange'/>
2595 <indexterm startref='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='endofrange'/>
2596 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2597 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson2' class='endofrange'/>
2598 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2599 <indexterm startref='idxwinerdave' class='endofrange'/>
2600 <indexterm id='idxbrownjohnseely' class='startofrange'><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
2601 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2602 <para>
2603 <emphasis role='strong'>John Seely Brown</emphasis> is the chief
2604 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2605 describes it, is <quote>human learning and &hellip; the creation of
2606 knowledge ecologies for creating &hellip; innovation.</quote>
2607 </para>
2608 <para>
2609 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2610 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2611 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2612 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2613 affect learning.
2614 </para>
2615 <para>
2616 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When <quote>a lot of us grew up,</quote>
2617 he explains, that tinkering was done <quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2618 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.</quote> But digital technologies
2619 enable a different kind of tinkering&mdash;with abstract ideas though
2620 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2621 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2623 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2624 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2625 or <quote>free collage,</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2626 the tinkering of many others.
2627 </para>
2628 <para>
2629 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2630 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2631 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2632 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2633 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2634 </para>
2635 <para>
2636 This opportunity creates a <quote>completely new kind of learning platform,</quote>
2637 as Brown describes. <quote>As soon as you start doing that, you &hellip;
2638 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2639 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2640 if they can improve it.</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2641 apprenticeship. <quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.</quote>
2642 </para>
2643 <para>
2644 In this process, <quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2645 They are code.</quote> Kids are <quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2646 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2647 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2648 platform. &hellip; You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2649 you tinker the more you improve.</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2650 learn.
2651 </para>
2652 <para>
2653 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2654 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2655 it, <quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2656 intelligence.</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2657 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2658 text. <quote>The Web &hellip; says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2659 you are visual, if you are interested in film &hellip; [then] there is a
2660 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2661 these multiple forms of intelligence.</quote>
2662 </para>
2663 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'/>
2664 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2665 <para>
2666 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2667 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2668
2669 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2670 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2671 kind of recognition.
2672 </para>
2673 <para>
2674 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2675 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2676 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2677 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2678 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2679 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2680 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2681 </para>
2682 <para>
2683 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2684 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2685 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>)
2686 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the <quote>right to
2687 tinker</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2688 general.<footnote><para>
2689 <!-- f22 -->
2690 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, <quote>Technological Access
2691 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2692 of the Association for Computer Machinery</citetitle> 43 (2000): 9.
2693 </para></footnote>
2694 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2695 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2696 </para>
2697 <para>
2698 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,</quote> Brown
2699 explains. We need to <quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2700 and want to learn.</quote>
2701 </para>
2702 <para>
2703 <quote>Yet,</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2704 evince, <quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2705 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. &hellip; We're building an
2706 architecture that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2707 system that closes down that part of the brain.</quote>
2708 </para>
2709 <indexterm startref='idxbrownjohnseely' class='endofrange'/>
2710 <para>
2711 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2712 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2713 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2714 the law to close down that technology.
2715 </para>
2716 <para>
2717 <quote>No way to run a culture,</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2718 chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="collectors"/>,
2719 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2720 </para>
2721 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2722 </chapter>
2723 <chapter label="3" id="catalogs">
2724 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs</title>
2725 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2726 <indexterm><primary>RPI</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</see></indexterm>
2727 <indexterm id='idxrensselaer' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary></indexterm>
2728 <indexterm id='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary><secondary>computer network search engine of</secondary></indexterm>
2729 <indexterm id='idxsearchengines' class='startofrange'><primary>search engines</primary></indexterm>
2730 <indexterm id='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='startofrange'><primary>university computer networks, p2p sharing on</primary></indexterm>
2731 <indexterm id='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>search engines used on</secondary></indexterm>
2732 <para>
2733 <emphasis role='strong'>In the fall</emphasis> of 2002, Jesse Jordan
2734 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2735 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2736 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2737 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2738 was available on the RPI network.
2739 </para>
2740 <para>
2741 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2742 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2743 to information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand
2744 undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school
2745 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2746 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2747 </para>
2748 <para>
2749 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2750 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2751 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2752 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2753 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2754 </para>
2755 <indexterm id='idxgoogle' class='startofrange'><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2756 <para>
2757 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2758 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2759 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2760 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2761 engines can do this even better. The idea of <quote>intranet</quote> search
2762 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2763 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2764 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2765 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2766 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2767 </para>
2768 <indexterm startref='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='endofrange'/>
2769 <indexterm id='idxjordanjesse' class='startofrange'><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2770 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>network file system of</secondary></indexterm>
2771 <para>
2772 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2773 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2774 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2775 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2776 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2777 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2778 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2779 </para>
2780 <indexterm startref='idxgoogle' class='endofrange'/>
2781 <para>
2782 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2783 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2784 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2785 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2786 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2787 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2788 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2789 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2790 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2791 on-line.
2792 </para>
2793 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='endofrange'/>
2794 <para>
2795 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2796 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2797 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2798 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2799 be on users' computers.
2800 </para>
2801 <indexterm startref='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='endofrange'/>
2802 <para>
2803 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2804 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2805 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2806 might have created; university brochures&mdash;basically anything that
2807 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2808 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2809 computer.
2810 </para>
2811 <indexterm><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2812 <indexterm><primary>education</primary><secondary>tinkering as means of</secondary></indexterm>
2813 <para>
2814 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2815 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2816 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and&mdash;so that this
2817 point is absolutely clear&mdash;Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2818 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2819 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2820 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2821 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2822 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2823 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2824 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2825 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2826 supposed to do.
2827 </para>
2828 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
2829 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>against student file sharing</secondary></indexterm>
2830 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
2831 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
2832 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='endofrange'/>
2833 <para>
2834 On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2835 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2836 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2837 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2838 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2839 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2840 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2841 </para>
2842 <para>
2843 <quote>It was absurd,</quote> he told me. <quote>I don't think I did anything
2844 wrong. &hellip; I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2845 engine that I ran or &hellip; what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2846 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2847 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2848 easier to use</quote>&mdash;again, a <emphasis>search engine</emphasis>,
2849 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2850 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2851 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2852 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2853 with music.
2854 </para>
2855 <indexterm startref='idxsearchengines' class='endofrange'/>
2856 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
2857 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>statutory damages of</secondary></indexterm>
2858 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>individual defendants intimidated by</secondary></indexterm>
2859 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages</primary></indexterm>
2860 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>intimidation tactics of</secondary></indexterm>
2861 <para>
2862 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2863 network and had therefore <quote>willfully</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2864 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2865 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2866 <quote>willful infringement,</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2867 call <quote>statutory damages.</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2868 claim $150,000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2869 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2870 Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000.
2871 </para>
2872 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University</primary></indexterm>
2873 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University</primary></indexterm>
2874 <para>
2875 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2876 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2877 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2878 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2879 huge demands for <quote>damages</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2880 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2881 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $100
2882 <emphasis>billion</emphasis>&mdash;six times the
2883 <emphasis>total</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2884 2001.<footnote><para>
2885
2886 <!-- f1 -->
2887 Tim Goral, <quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks:
2888 Suit Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages,</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC</citetitle> 6
2889 (2003): 5, available at 2003 WL 55179443.
2890 </para></footnote>
2891 </para>
2892 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaer' class='endofrange'/>
2893 <para>
2894 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2895 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2896 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2897 $12,000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2898 $12,000 to dismiss the case.
2899 </para>
2900 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt</primary></indexterm>
2901 <para>
2902 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2903 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2904 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2905 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2906 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2907 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2908 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, <quote>You don't want to pay another
2909 visit to a dentist like me.</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2910 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2911 </para>
2912 <indexterm><primary>legal system, attorney costs in</primary></indexterm>
2913 <para>
2914 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2915 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2916 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2917 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2918 at least $250,000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2919 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2920 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2921 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2922 </para>
2923 <para>
2924 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $250,000 and a chance at winning,
2925 or $12,000 and a settlement.
2926 </para>
2927 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
2928 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
2929 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
2930 <para>
2931 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2932 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2933 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2934 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2935 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $1 million a year.
2936 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2937 artist makes $45,900.<footnote><para>
2938 <!-- f2 -->
2939 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001)
2940 (27&ndash;2042&mdash;Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2941 the Arts, <citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon</citetitle> (2000).
2942 </para></footnote>
2943 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2944 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2945 student for running a search engine?<footnote><para>
2946 <!-- f3 -->
2947 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in <quote>KaZaA and Punishment,</quote>
2948 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, A24.
2949 </para></footnote>
2950 </para>
2951 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='endofrange'/>
2952 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='endofrange'/>
2953 <para>
2954 On June 23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2955 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2956 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $15 million lawsuit became an
2957 activist:
2958 </para>
2959 <blockquote>
2960 <para>
2961 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2962 an activist. &hellip; [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2963 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2964 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2965 </para>
2966 </blockquote>
2967 <para>
2968 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2969 his father told me, Jesse <quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
2970 I. &hellip; He's not a tree hugger. &hellip; I think it's bizarre that they would
2971 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2972 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.</quote>
2973 </para>
2974 <indexterm startref='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='endofrange'/>
2975 <indexterm startref='idxjordanjesse' class='endofrange'/>
2976 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
2977 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='endofrange'/>
2978 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='endofrange'/>
2979 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='endofrange'/>
2980 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
2981 </chapter>
2982 <chapter label="4" id="pirates">
2983 <title>CHAPTER FOUR: <quote>Pirates</quote></title>
2984 <indexterm id='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in development of content industry</secondary></indexterm>
2985 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
2986 <para>
2987 <emphasis role='strong'>If <quote>piracy</quote> means</emphasis>
2988 using the creative property of others without their
2989 permission&mdash;if <quote>if value, then right</quote> is
2990 true&mdash;then the history of the content industry is a history of
2991 piracy. Every important sector of <quote>big media</quote>
2992 today&mdash;film, records, radio, and cable TV&mdash;was born of a
2993 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
2994 generation's pirates join this generation's country club&mdash;until
2995 now.
2996 </para>
2997 <section id="film">
2998 <title>Film</title>
2999 <para>
3000 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.<footnote><para>
3001 <!-- f1 -->
3002 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
3003 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
3004 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 87&ndash;93,
3005 which details Edison's <quote>adventures</quote> with copyright and patent.
3006 </para></footnote>
3007 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
3008 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
3009 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
3010 exercised through a monopoly <quote>trust,</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
3011 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
3012 property&mdash;patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
3013 this creative property
3014 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
3015 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
3016 </para>
3017 <para>
3018 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
3019 </para>
3020 <blockquote>
3021 <para>
3022 A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
3023 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
3024 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
3025 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
3026 summer of 1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
3027 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
3028 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
3029 </para>
3030 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William</primary></indexterm>
3031 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company</primary></indexterm>
3032 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3033 <para>
3034 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
3035 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
3036 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
3037 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
3038 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
3039 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
3040 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
3041 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
3042 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
3043 license was revoked.<footnote><para>
3044 <!-- f2 -->
3045 J. A. Aberdeen, <citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
3046 Picture Producers</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts
3047 posted at <quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
3048 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,</quote> available at
3049 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #11</ulink>. For a
3050 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
3051 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, <quote>From
3052 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
3053 the Propertization of Copyright</quote> (September 2002), University of
3054 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
3055 Working Paper No. 159.
3056 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
3057 </para></footnote>
3058 </para>
3059 </blockquote>
3060 <para>
3061 The Napsters of those days, the <quote>independents,</quote> were companies like
3062 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
3063 resisted. <quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
3064 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
3065 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.</quote><footnote><para>
3066 <!-- f3 -->
3067 Marc Wanamaker, <quote>The First Studios,</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority</citetitle>, archived at
3068 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #12</ulink>.
3069 </para></footnote>
3070 That led the independents to flee the East
3071 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
3072 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
3073 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
3074 did just that.
3075 </para>
3076 <para>
3077 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
3078 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
3079 patent holder a truly <quote>limited</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
3080
3081 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
3082 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
3083 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
3084 Edison's creative property.
3085 </para>
3086 </section>
3087 <section id="recordedmusic">
3088 <title>Recorded Music</title>
3089 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
3090 <para>
3091 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
3092 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
3093 </para>
3094 <indexterm id='idxfourneauxhenri' class='startofrange'><primary>Fourneaux, Henri</primary></indexterm>
3095 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil</primary></indexterm>
3096 <para>
3097 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
3098 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
3099 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
3100 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
3101 their music. In other words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
3102 1899 hit <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
3103 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
3104 right to perform it publicly.
3105 </para>
3106 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3107 <para>
3108 But what if I wanted to record <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> using Edison's phonograph
3109 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
3110 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
3111 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
3112 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
3113 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
3114 <quote>public performance</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
3115 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
3116 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
3117 brain are not&mdash;yet&mdash; regulated by copyright law). So if I
3118 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
3119 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
3120 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
3121 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
3122 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
3123 its composer anything.
3124 </para>
3125 <indexterm startref='idxfourneauxhenri' class='endofrange'/>
3126 <para>
3127 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
3128 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
3129 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
3130 put it,
3131 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3132 </para>
3133 <blockquote>
3134 <para>
3135 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3136 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3137 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3138 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3139 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3140 rights.<footnote><para>
3141 <!-- f4 -->
3142 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3143 S. 6330 and H.R. 19853 Before the (Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th
3144 Cong. 59, 1st sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3145 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in <citetitle>Legislative History of the
3146 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3147 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3148 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3149 </para></footnote>
3150 </para>
3151 </blockquote>
3152 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip</primary></indexterm>
3153 <para>
3154 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3155 people's works were <quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3156 genius of American composers,</quote><footnote><para>
3157 <!-- f5 -->
3158 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223
3159 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3160 </para></footnote>
3161 and the <quote>music publishing industry</quote>
3162 was thereby <quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.</quote><footnote><para>
3163 <!-- f6 -->
3164 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226
3165 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3166 </para></footnote>
3167 As John Philip
3168 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, <quote>When they make money
3169 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.</quote><footnote><para>
3170 <!-- f7 -->
3171 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23
3172 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3173 </para></footnote>
3174 </para>
3175 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company</primary></indexterm>
3176 <indexterm><primary>player pianos</primary></indexterm>
3177 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
3178 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
3179 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
3180 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
3181 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>statutory license system in</secondary></indexterm>
3182 <para>
3183 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3184 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3185 player piano argued that <quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3186 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3187 of anything he had before their introduction.</quote> Rather, the machines
3188 increased the sales of sheet music.<footnote><para>
3189 <!-- f8 -->
3190
3191 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283&ndash;84
3192 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3193 Perforating Company of New York).
3194 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3195 Congress was <quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3196 they represent, and whose servants they are.</quote> <quote>All talk about
3197 `theft,'</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3198 wrote, <quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3199 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3200 statute.</quote><footnote><para>
3201 <!-- f9 -->
3202 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared
3203 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3204 Graphophone Company Association).
3205 </para></footnote>
3206 </para>
3207 <indexterm><primary>cover songs</primary></indexterm>
3208 <para>
3209 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3210 <emphasis>and</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3211 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the <quote>mechanical
3212 reproductions</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3213 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3214 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3215 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3216 recorded once. This is the part of
3217
3218 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3219 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3220 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3221 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3222 </para>
3223 <indexterm id='idxcompulsorylicense' class='startofrange'><primary>compulsory license</primary></indexterm>
3224 <indexterm id='idxstatutorylicenses' class='startofrange'><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
3225 <para>
3226 American law ordinarily calls this a <quote>compulsory license,</quote> but I will
3227 refer to it as a <quote>statutory license.</quote> A statutory license is a license
3228 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3229 Copyright Act in 1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3230 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3231 the fee set by the statute.
3232 </para>
3233 <indexterm id='idxgrishamjohn' class='startofrange'><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
3234 <para>
3235 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3236 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3237 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3238 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3239 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3240 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3241 Grisham.
3242 </para>
3243 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='endofrange'/>
3244 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3245 <para>
3246 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3247 thus, in effect, the law <emphasis>subsidizes</emphasis> the recording
3248 industry through a kind of piracy&mdash;by giving recording artists a
3249 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3250 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3251 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3252 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3253 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3254 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3255 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3256 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3257 creativity.<footnote><para>
3258
3259 <!-- f10 -->
3260 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and
3261 H.R. 11794 Before the (Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st
3262 sess., 217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3263 in <citetitle>Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3264 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3265 </para></footnote>
3266 </para>
3267 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='endofrange'/>
3268 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3269 <indexterm startref='idxgrishamjohn' class='endofrange'/>
3270 <para>
3271 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3272 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3273 records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3274 relates,
3275 </para>
3276 <blockquote>
3277 <para>
3278 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3279 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3280 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3281 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3282 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3283 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3284 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3285 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3286 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before 1909 and
3287 the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3288 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3289 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3290 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3291 choice.<footnote><para>
3292 <!-- f11 -->
3293 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee
3294 on the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8
3295 March 1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3296 this report.</para></footnote>
3297 </para>
3298 </blockquote>
3299 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='endofrange'/>
3300 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='endofrange'/>
3301 <indexterm startref='idxcompulsorylicense' class='endofrange'/>
3302 <indexterm startref='idxstatutorylicenses' class='endofrange'/>
3303 <para>
3304 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3305 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3306 </para>
3307 </section>
3308 <section id="radio">
3309 <title>Radio</title>
3310 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
3311 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
3312 <para>
3313 Radio was also born of piracy.
3314 </para>
3315 <para>
3316 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3317 <quote>public performance</quote> of the composer's work.<footnote><para>
3318 <!-- f12 -->
3319 See 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning,
3320 record companies printed <quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast</quote> and other
3321 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3322 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3323 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3324 station. See <citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Whiteman</citetitle>, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd
3325 Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3326 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3327 Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 281.
3328 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned</primary></indexterm>
3329 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3330 </para></footnote>
3331 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3332 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3333 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3334 </para>
3335 <para>
3336 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3337 copy of the <emphasis>composer's</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3338 also performing a copy of the <emphasis>recording artist's</emphasis>
3339 work. It's one thing to have <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> sung on the radio by the
3340 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3341 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3342 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3343 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3344 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3345 music for his work.
3346 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
3347
3348 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3349 </para>
3350 <para>
3351 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3352 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3353 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3354 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3355 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3356 of playing the song.
3357 </para>
3358 <indexterm id='idxmadonna' class='startofrange'><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3359 <para>
3360 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3361 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3362 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3363 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3364 </para>
3365 <para>
3366 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3367 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3368 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3369 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3370 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3371 <quote>protected</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3372 <emphasis>pirate</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3373 her anything.
3374 </para>
3375 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='endofrange'/>
3376 <indexterm startref='idxmadonna' class='endofrange'/>
3377 <para>
3378 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3379 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3380 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3381 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3382 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3383 to take something for nothing.
3384 </para>
3385 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='endofrange'/>
3386 </section>
3387 <section id="cabletv">
3388 <title>Cable TV</title>
3389 <indexterm id='idxcabletelevision' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
3390 <para>
3391 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3392 </para>
3393 <para>
3394 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3395 television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3396 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3397 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3398 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3399 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3400 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3401 did&mdash; Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3402 give away.
3403 </para>
3404 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas</primary></indexterm>
3405 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin</primary></indexterm>
3406 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3407 <para>
3408 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3409 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3410 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.</quote><footnote><para>
3411 <!-- f13 -->
3412 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the
3413 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3414 Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966)
3415 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3416 Commission).
3417 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3418 </para></footnote>
3419 There may have been a <quote>public interest</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3420 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3421 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, <quote>Does public
3422 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?</quote><footnote><para>
3423 <!-- f14 -->
3424 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3425 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3426 </para></footnote>
3427 As another broadcaster put it,
3428 </para>
3429 <blockquote>
3430 <para>
3431 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3432 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3433 paid for.<footnote><para>
3434 <!-- f15 -->
3435 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3436 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3437 </para></footnote>
3438 </para>
3439 </blockquote>
3440 <para>
3441 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3442 </para>
3443 <blockquote>
3444 <para>
3445 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3446 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3447 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3448 think there are harsher words which would fit it.<footnote><para>
3449 <!-- f16 -->
3450 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3451 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3452 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3453 </para></footnote>
3454 </para>
3455 </blockquote>
3456 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3457 <para>
3458 These were <quote>free-ride[rs],</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3459 Heston said, who were <quote>depriving actors of
3460 compensation.</quote><footnote><para>
3461 <!-- f17 -->
3462 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3463 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3464 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3465 </para>
3466 </footnote>
3467 </para>
3468 <para>
3469 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3470 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3471 </para>
3472 <blockquote>
3473 <para>
3474 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3475 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3476 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3477 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. &hellip; The
3478
3479 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3480 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3481 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.<footnote><para>
3482 <!-- f18 -->
3483 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M.
3484 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3485 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3486 </para></footnote>
3487 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3488 </para>
3489 </blockquote>
3490 <para>
3491 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3492 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3493 </para>
3494 <para>
3495 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3496 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they <quote>pirated.</quote>
3497 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3498 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3499 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3500 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3501 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3502 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3503 companies thus built their empire in part upon a <quote>piracy</quote> of the value
3504 created by broadcasters' content.
3505 </para>
3506 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3507 <indexterm startref='idxcabletelevision' class='endofrange'/>
3508 <para>
3509 <emphasis role='strong'>These separate stories</emphasis> sing a
3510 common theme. If <quote>piracy</quote> means using value from someone
3511 else's creative property without permission from that creator&mdash;as
3512 it is increasingly described today<footnote><para>
3513 <!-- f19 -->
3514 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, <citetitle>The Engine
3515 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet&mdash;The Myth of Free
3516 Information</citetitle>, available at
3517 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #13</ulink>. <quote>The
3518 threat of piracy&mdash;the use of someone else's creative work without
3519 permission or compensation&mdash;has grown with the Internet.</quote>
3520 </para></footnote>
3521 &mdash; then <emphasis>every</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3522 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3523 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV. &hellip; The list is long and
3524 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3525 last. Every generation&mdash;until now.
3526 </para>
3527 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3528 </section>
3529 </chapter>
3530 <chapter label="5" id="piracy">
3531 <title>CHAPTER FIVE: <quote>Piracy</quote></title>
3532 <para>
3533 <emphasis role='strong'>There is piracy</emphasis> of copyrighted
3534 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3535 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3536 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3537 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3538 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3539 </para>
3540 <para>
3541 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of <quote>taking</quote>
3542 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3543 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3544 taking <quote>piracy,</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3545 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3546 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3547 has so often done in the past.
3548 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3549 </para>
3550 <section id="piracy-i">
3551 <title>Piracy I</title>
3552 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3553 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3554 <para>
3555 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3556 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3557 content, copy it, and sell it&mdash;all without the permission of a copyright
3558 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion
3559 every year to physical piracy<footnote><para>
3560 <!-- f1 -->
3561 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), <citetitle>The
3562 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003</citetitle>, July 2003, available
3563 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #14</ulink>. See
3564 also Ben Hunt, <quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3565 Times</citetitle>, 14 February 2003, 11.
3566 </para></footnote>
3567 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3568 estimates that it loses $3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3569 </para>
3570 <para>
3571 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3572 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3573 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3574 This piracy is wrong.
3575 </para>
3576 <para>
3577 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3578 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3579 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3580 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3581 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3582 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3583 of our existence, treated as right.
3584 </para>
3585 <para>
3586 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3587 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3588 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3589 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3590 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3591 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3592 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3593 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3594 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3595 </para>
3596 <para>
3597 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3598 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3599 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3600 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3601 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3602 similar childhood.
3603 </para>
3604 <para>
3605 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3606 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3607 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3608 of intellectual property law.<footnote><para>
3609 <!-- f2 -->
3610 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3611 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The
3612 New Press, 2003), 10&ndash;13, 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3613 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3614 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3615 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3616 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3617 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3618 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3619 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3620 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3621 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3622 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3623 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3624 TRIPS framework.
3625 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents</primary></indexterm>
3626 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
3627 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3628 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3629 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3630 is wrong.
3631 </para>
3632 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3633 <para>
3634 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3635 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3636 to American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3637 bought those American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any
3638 less money than they otherwise would have had.<footnote><para>
3639 <!-- f3 -->
3640 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3641 Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002),
3642 144&ndash;90. <quote>In some instances &hellip; the impact of piracy on the
3643 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3644 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3645 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3646 pirating were not an option.</quote> Ibid., 149.
3647 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3648 </para></footnote>
3649 </para>
3650 <para>
3651 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3652 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3653 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3654 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3655 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes &amp; Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3656 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?</quote>
3657 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes &amp;
3658 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3659 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3660 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3661 piracy of the tangible.
3662 </para>
3663 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'/>
3664 <para>
3665 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3666 property right of a very special sort, it <emphasis>is</emphasis> a
3667 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3668 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3669 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3670 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3671 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3672 give people the right to <quote>take</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3673 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3674
3675 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3676 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3677 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3678 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3679 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3680 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what <quote>property</quote> means.
3681 </para>
3682 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3683 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
3684 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
3685 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3686 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3687 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of</secondary></indexterm>
3688 <indexterm><primary>Windows</primary></indexterm>
3689 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>international software piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3690 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of</secondary></indexterm>
3691 <para>
3692 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3693 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese <quote>steal</quote>
3694 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3695 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3696 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3697 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3698 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3699 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3700 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3701 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3702 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3703 </para>
3704 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
3705 <para>
3706 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3707 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3708 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3709 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3710 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3711 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3712 </para>
3713 <indexterm><primary>Netscape</primary></indexterm>
3714 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer</primary></indexterm>
3715 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3716 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3717 <para>
3718 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3719 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3720 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3721 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3722 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3723 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3724 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3725 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3726 what&mdash;at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3727 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3728 violating the law is still wrong.
3729 </para>
3730 <para>
3731 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3732 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3733 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3734 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3735 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3736 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3737 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3738 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3739 is flat out wrong.
3740 </para>
3741 <para>
3742 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3743 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is. Or
3744 at least, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3745 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of <quote>piracy</quote> are useful
3746 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3747 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3748 <quote>piracy</quote> in that sense of the term.
3749 </para>
3750 <para>
3751 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3752 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3753 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3754 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3755 </para>
3756 <para>
3757 For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3758 controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it
3759 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable
3760 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3761 </para>
3762 <para>
3763 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3764 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3765 sharing to survive.
3766 </para>
3767 </section>
3768 <section id="piracy-ii">
3769 <title>Piracy II</title>
3770 <para>
3771 The key to the <quote>piracy</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that <quote>rob[s]
3772 the author of [his] profit.</quote><footnote><para>
3773 <!-- f4 -->
3774 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777).
3775 </para></footnote>
3776 This means we must determine whether
3777 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3778 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3779 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3780 author of his profit.
3781 </para>
3782 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3783 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn</primary></indexterm>
3784 <para>
3785 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3786 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3787 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3788 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well<footnote><para>
3789 <!-- f5 -->
3790 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3791 See Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3792 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle> (New York:
3793 HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3794 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3795 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3796 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3797 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3798 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 89&ndash;92, 139.
3799
3800 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
3801 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3802 put together components that had been developed independently.
3803 </para>
3804 <para>
3805 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999,
3806 Napster amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After
3807 eighteen months, there were close to 80 million registered users of the
3808 system.<footnote><para>
3809 <!-- f6 -->
3810 See Carolyn Lochhead, <quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,</quote> <citetitle>San
3811 Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24 September 2002, A1; <quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,</quote>
3812 <citetitle>New Scientist</citetitle>, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Napster Names CEO,
3813 Secures New Financing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 23 May 2003, C1;
3814 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton,
3815 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet</quote> (London) <citetitle>Times</citetitle>, 26 July 2002, 18.
3816 </para></footnote>
3817 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3818 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3819 boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3820 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3821 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3822 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend&mdash;
3823 or your 20,000 best friends.
3824 </para>
3825 <para>
3826 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3827 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3828 September 2002 estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded
3829 music&mdash;28 percent of Americans older than 12.<footnote><para>
3830
3831 <!-- f7 -->
3832 See Ipsos-Insight, <citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution</citetitle>
3833 (September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3834 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have
3835 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3836 </para></footnote>
3837 A survey by the NPD group quoted in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>
3838 estimated that 43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3839 exchange content in May 2003.<footnote><para>
3840 <!-- f8 -->
3841 Amy Harmon, <quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,</quote> <citetitle>New
3842 York Times</citetitle>, 6 June 2003, A1.
3843 </para></footnote>
3844 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3845 massive quantity of content is being <quote>taken</quote> on these networks. The
3846 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3847 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3848 </para>
3849 <para>
3850 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3851 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3852 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3853 complicated than one might think. So consider&mdash;a bit more
3854 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3855 do&mdash;the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3856 of harm it entails.
3857 </para>
3858 <para>
3859 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3860 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3861 different kinds into four types.
3862 </para>
3863 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
3864 <listitem>
3865 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3866 <para>
3867 <!-- A. -->
3868 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3869 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3870 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3871 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3872 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3873 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3874 users who download instead of purchasing.
3875 </para></listitem>
3876 <listitem><para>
3877 <!-- B. -->
3878 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3879 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3880 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3881 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3882 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3883 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3884 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3885 music purchased.
3886 </para></listitem>
3887 <listitem><para>
3888 <!-- C. -->
3889 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3890 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3891 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3892 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3893 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3894 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3895 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend <quote>recalling</quote> old
3896 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3897 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3898 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3899 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero&mdash;the same
3900 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to
3901 a local collector.
3902 </para></listitem>
3903 <listitem><para>
3904 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3905 <!-- D. -->
3906 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3907 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3908 wants to give away.
3909 </para></listitem>
3910 </orderedlist>
3911 <para>
3912 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3913 </para>
3914 <para>
3915 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3916 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3917 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3918 harmful.<footnote><para>
3919 <!-- f9 -->
3920 See Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle>, 148&ndash;49.
3921 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3922 </para></footnote>
3923 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3924 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3925 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3926 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3927 answer&mdash;and certainly much more difficult than the current
3928 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3929 </para>
3930 <para>
3931 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3932 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3933 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3934 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3935 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of <quote>theft</quote> that is
3936 <quote>devastating</quote> the industry.
3937 </para>
3938 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
3939 <para>
3940 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3941 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3942 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3943 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3944 &amp; Young put it, <quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3945 technology, the labels fought it.</quote><footnote><para>
3946 <!-- f10 -->
3947 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary></indexterm>
3948 See Cap Gemini Ernst &amp; Young, <citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
3949 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis</citetitle> (2003), 3. This report
3950 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3951 practice of cassette taping in the 1970s, including an advertising
3952 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption <quote>Home taping
3953 is killing music.</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3954 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3955 behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3956 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3957 Assessment, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law</citetitle>,
3958 OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3959 October 1989), 145&ndash;56. </para></footnote>
3960 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3961 when record sales fell by 11.4 percent in 1981, the industry claimed
3962 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3963 regulating technology was the answer.
3964 </para>
3965 <indexterm><primary>MTV</primary></indexterm>
3966 <para>
3967 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3968 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3969 turnaround. <quote>In the end,</quote> Cap Gemini concludes, <quote>the `crisis' &hellip; was
3970 not the fault of the tapers&mdash;who did not [stop after MTV came into
3971 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
3972 being]&mdash;but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
3973 innovation at the major labels.</quote><footnote><para>
3974 <!-- f11 -->
3975 U.S. Congress, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying</citetitle>, 4.
3976 </para></footnote>
3977 </para>
3978 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'/>
3979 <para>
3980 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
3981 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
3982 the industry in particular, and society in general&mdash;or at least
3983 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
3984 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
3985 VCR&mdash;the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
3986 harmful. The question is also <emphasis>how</emphasis> harmful type A
3987 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
3988 </para>
3989 <para>
3990 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
3991 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
3992 The <quote>net harm</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
3993 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
3994 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
3995 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
3996 therefore have little <emphasis>static</emphasis> reason to resist
3997 them.
3998
3999 </para>
4000 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>sales levels of</secondary></indexterm>
4001 <para>
4002 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
4003 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
4004 actually suggest it might be close.
4005 </para>
4006 <para>
4007 In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9 percent,
4008 from 882 million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7
4009 percent.<footnote><para>
4010 <!-- f12 -->
4011 See Recording Industry Association of America, <citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics</citetitle>,
4012 available at
4013 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #15</ulink>. A later
4014 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
4015 Association of America, <citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy</citetitle>, 25 June 2003,
4016 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
4017 #16</ulink>: <quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
4018 have fallen by 26 percent from 1.16 billion units in to 860 million
4019 units in 2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
4020 of sales, revenues are down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in to $12.6
4021 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
4022 industry worldwide has gone from a $39 billion industry in 2000 down
4023 to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
4024 shipments).</quote>
4025 </para></footnote>
4026 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
4027 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
4028 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
4029 than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That no
4030 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
4031 account for at least some of the loss. <quote>From 1999 to 2001, the average
4032 price of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19.</quote><footnote>
4033 <!-- f13 -->
4034 <para>
4035 Jane Black, <quote>Big Music's Broken Record,</quote> BusinessWeek online, 13
4036 February 2003, available at
4037 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #17</ulink>.
4038 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane</primary></indexterm>
4039 </para>
4040 </footnote>
4041 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
4042 the decline. As Jane Black of <citetitle>BusinessWeek</citetitle> notes, <quote>The
4043 soundtrack to the film <citetitle>High Fidelity</citetitle> has a list price of
4044 $18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
4045 $19.99.</quote><footnote><para>
4046 <!-- f14 -->
4047 Ibid.
4048 </para></footnote>
4049 </para>
4050 <para>
4051
4052 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
4053 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
4054 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
4055 that the RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
4056 estimates that 2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
4057 although 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4058 free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 percent.
4059 </para>
4060 <para>
4061 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
4062 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
4063 The recording industry constantly asks, <quote>What's the difference between
4064 downloading a song and stealing a CD?</quote>&mdash;but their own numbers
4065 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
4066 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
4067 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
4068 downloads. If every download were a lost sale&mdash;if every use of
4069 Kazaa <quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit</quote>&mdash;then the industry
4070 would have suffered a 100 percent drop in sales last year, not a 7
4071 percent drop. If 2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4072 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, then there is
4073 a huge difference between <quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.</quote>
4074 </para>
4075 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'/>
4076 <para>
4077 These are the harms&mdash;alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
4078 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
4079 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
4080 these costs?
4081 </para>
4082 <para>
4083 One benefit is type C sharing&mdash;making available content that
4084 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
4085 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
4086 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
4087 available.<footnote><para>
4088 <!-- f15 -->
4089 By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels
4090 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
4091 Law&mdash;Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
4092 Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April
4093 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
4094 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #18</ulink>.
4095 </para></footnote>
4096 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
4097 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
4098 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
4099 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
4100 sense <emphasis>to the company</emphasis> to make it available.
4101 </para>
4102 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4103 <para>
4104 In real space&mdash;long before the Internet&mdash;the market had a simple
4105 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
4106 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
4107 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
4108 today.<footnote><para>
4109 <!-- f16 -->
4110 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4111 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
4112 in existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the
4113 United States, an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter
4114 Press, <citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
4115 Market</citetitle> (2002), available at
4116 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #19</ulink>. Used
4117 records accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See National
4118 Association of Recording Merchandisers, <quote>2002 Annual Survey
4119 Results,</quote> available at
4120 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #20</ulink>.
4121 </para></footnote>
4122 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
4123 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
4124 content, <emphasis>even if the content is still under
4125 copyright</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
4126 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
4127 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
4128 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
4129 the content they sell.
4130 </para>
4131 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
4132 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard</primary></indexterm>
4133 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
4134 <para>
4135 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
4136 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
4137 the content available isn't making money from making the content
4138 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
4139 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
4140 when someone shares my 1949 recording of Bernstein's <quote>Two Love Songs,</quote>
4141 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
4142 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
4143 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
4144 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
4145 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
4146 </para>
4147 <para>
4148 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
4149 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
4150 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
4151 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
4152 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
4153 shut as well?
4154 </para>
4155 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
4156 <indexterm><primary>Doctorow, Cory</primary></indexterm>
4157 <indexterm><primary>Down and Out in the Magic Kingdom (Doctorow)</primary></indexterm>
4158 <para>
4159 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4160 type D sharing to occur&mdash;the sharing of content that copyright owners
4161 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4162 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4163 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
4164 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4165
4166 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4167 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4168 would be a great advertisement for the <quote>real</quote> book. People would read
4169 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4170 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4171 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4172 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4173 great book!)
4174 </para>
4175 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'/>
4176 <para>
4177 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4178 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4179 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4180 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4181 </para>
4182 <para>
4183 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4184 understandably says, <quote>This is how much we've lost,</quote> we must also ask,
4185 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4186 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4187 unavailable?</quote>
4188 </para>
4189 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson' class='endofrange'/>
4190 <para>
4191 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4192 chapter, much of the <quote>piracy</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4193 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4194 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="pirates"/>, much of
4195 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4196 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4197 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4198 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4199 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4200 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4201 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4202 found only with time.
4203 </para>
4204 <para>
4205 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4206 just what you call type A sharing?</quote>
4207 </para>
4208 <para>
4209 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The
4210 effect
4211 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4212 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4213 Napster
4214 case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4215 developed
4216 a technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of identified
4217 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4218 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4
4219 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4220 <quote>down to zero.</quote><footnote><para>
4221 <!-- f17 -->
4222 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34-
4223 35 (N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183
4224 MHP, available at
4225
4226 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #21</ulink>. For an
4227 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4228 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster</citetitle> (New
4229 York: Crown Business, 2003), 269&ndash;82.
4230 </para></footnote>
4231 </para>
4232 <para>
4233 If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4234 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4235 assure that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance
4236 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of
4237 VCRs or 100 percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns
4238 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4239 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4240 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4241 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4242 </para>
4243 <para>
4244 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4245 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4246 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4247 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4248 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4249 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4250 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4251 </para>
4252 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
4253 <indexterm><primary>composers, copyright protections of</primary></indexterm>
4254 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4255 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
4256 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
4257 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
4258 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>music recordings played on</secondary></indexterm>
4259 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
4260 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright protections in</secondary></indexterm>
4261 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
4262 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
4263 <indexterm><primary>composer's rights vs. producers' rights in</primary></indexterm>
4264 <para>
4265 So, as we've seen, when <quote>mechanical reproduction</quote> threatened the
4266 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4267 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4268 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4269 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4270 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4271 complained to Congress that their <quote>creative property</quote> was not being
4272 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4273 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4274 benefit was enough.
4275 </para>
4276 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
4277 <para>
4278 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4279 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4280 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4281 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4282 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4283 price.
4284 </para>
4285 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='endofrange'/>
4286 <para>
4287
4288 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4289 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4290 pianos, served two important goals&mdash;indeed, the two central goals
4291 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4292 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4293 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4294 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4295 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4296 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4297 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4298 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4299 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4300 Congress chose a path that would assure
4301 <emphasis>compensation</emphasis> without giving the past
4302 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4303 </para>
4304 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='endofrange'/>
4305 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='endofrange'/>
4306 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'/>
4307 <indexterm><primary>Betamax</primary></indexterm>
4308 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
4309 <para>
4310 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4311 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4312 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4313 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4314 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4315 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4316 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4317 <quote>record</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4318 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4319 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4320 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4321 </para>
4322 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='endofrange'/>
4323 <para>
4324 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4325 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4326 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4327 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4328 machine to copy only if there were a special <quote>copy me</quote> signal on the
4329 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4330 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4331 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4332 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4333 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4334 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4335 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4336 for the architecture it chose.
4337 </para>
4338 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4339 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on VCR technology</secondary></indexterm>
4340 <para>
4341 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4342 champion. Valenti called VCRs <quote>tapeworms.</quote> He warned, <quote>When there are
4343 20, 30, 40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4344 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4345 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4346 copyright.</quote><footnote><para>
4347 <!-- f18 -->
4348 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4349 S. 1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st
4350 and 2nd sess., 459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4351 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4352 </para></footnote>
4353 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4354 creative judgment,</quote> he told Congress, <quote>to understand the devastation
4355 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4356 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4357 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4358 and plain common sense.</quote><footnote><para>
4359 <!-- f19 -->
4360 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475.
4361 </para></footnote>
4362 Indeed, as surveys would later show, 45
4363 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more<footnote><para>
4364 <!-- f20 -->
4365 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 480 F. Supp. 429,
4366 (C.D. Cal., 1979).
4367 </para></footnote>
4368 &mdash; a use the Court would later hold was not <quote>fair.</quote> By
4369 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4370 copyright infringement without creating a mechanism to compensate
4371 copyright owners,</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would <quote>take from the
4372 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4373 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4374 profit from its reproduction.</quote><footnote><para>
4375 <!-- f21 -->
4376 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony
4377 of Jack Valenti).
4378 </para></footnote>
4379 </para>
4380 <para>
4381 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4382 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4383 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction&mdash;leading Judge Alex
4384 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the <quote>Hollywood
4385 Circuit</quote>&mdash;held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4386 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4387 rule, this totally familiar technology&mdash;which Jack Valenti had
4388 called <quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry</quote> (worse
4389 yet, it was a <emphasis>Japanese</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4390 American film industry)&mdash;was an illegal
4391 technology.<footnote><para>
4392 <!-- f22 -->
4393 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th Cir.
4394 1981).
4395 </para></footnote>
4396 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex</primary></indexterm>
4397 </para>
4398 <para>
4399 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4400
4401 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4402 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4403 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4404 Court wrote,
4405 </para>
4406 <blockquote>
4407 <para>
4408 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4409 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4410 market
4411 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4412 authority
4413 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4414 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4415 implicated
4416 by such new technology.<footnote><para>
4417 <!-- f23 -->
4418 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417, 431 (1984).
4419 </para></footnote>
4420 </para>
4421 </blockquote>
4422 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='endofrange'/>
4423 <para>
4424 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4425 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4426 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4427 enough, this <quote>taking</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4428 together, a pattern is clear:
4429 </para>
4430
4431 <informaltable id="t1">
4432 <tgroup cols="4" align="left">
4433 <thead>
4434 <row>
4435 <entry>CASE</entry>
4436 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS <quote>PIRATED</quote></entry>
4437 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS</entry>
4438 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS</entry>
4439 </row>
4440 </thead>
4441 <tbody>
4442 <row>
4443 <entry>Recordings</entry>
4444 <entry>Composers</entry>
4445 <entry>No protection</entry>
4446 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4447 </row>
4448 <row>
4449 <entry>Radio</entry>
4450 <entry>Recording artists</entry>
4451 <entry>N/A</entry>
4452 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4453 </row>
4454 <row>
4455 <entry>Cable TV</entry>
4456 <entry>Broadcasters</entry>
4457 <entry>No protection</entry>
4458 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4459 </row>
4460 <row>
4461 <entry>VCR</entry>
4462 <entry>Film creators</entry>
4463 <entry>No protection</entry>
4464 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4465 </row>
4466 </tbody>
4467 </tgroup>
4468 </informaltable>
4469 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'/>
4470 <para>
4471 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4472 way content was distributed.<footnote><para>
4473 <!-- f24 -->
4474 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4475 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4476 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4477 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4478 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4479 1992 (Title 17 of the <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat.
4480 4237, codified at 17 U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4481 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4482 Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 71. See also Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,</quote>
4483 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 293&ndash;96.
4484 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
4485 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
4486 </para></footnote>
4487 In each case, throughout our history,
4488 that change meant that someone got a <quote>free ride</quote> on someone else's
4489 work.
4490 </para>
4491 <para>
4492 In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4493 Congress eliminate all free riding. In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of
4494 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4495 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4496 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of <quote>piracy.</quote>
4497 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4498 the behavior of the <quote>pirates.</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4499 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4500 interests at stake.
4501 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4502 </para>
4503 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
4504 <para>
4505 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4506 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4507 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4508 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4509 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4510 regulated?
4511 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4512 to $15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4513 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4514 permission to record a song?
4515 </para>
4516 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on balance of interests in copyright law</secondary></indexterm>
4517 <para>
4518 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4519 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4520 copyright <quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4521 over all possible uses of his work.</quote><footnote><para>
4522 <!-- f25 -->
4523 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
4524 (1984).
4525 </para></footnote>
4526 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4527 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4528 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4529 balancing has historically been done <emphasis>after</emphasis> a
4530 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4531 facilitate the distribution of content.
4532 </para>
4533 <para>
4534 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4535 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4536 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4537 should not become a tool for <quote>stealing</quote> from artists. But neither
4538 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4539 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4540 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4541 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4542 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4543 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4544 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4545 public interest that innovation continue.
4546 </para>
4547 <para>
4548
4549 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4550 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4551 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4552 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4553 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4554 efficient. Yet these <quote>potential public benefits,</quote> as John Schwartz
4555 writes in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, <quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4556 fight.</quote><footnote><para>
4557 <!-- f26 -->
4558 John Schwartz, <quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4559 Echoes Past Efforts,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 September 2003, C3.
4560 </para></footnote>
4561 </para>
4562 <para>
4563 <emphasis role='strong'>Yet when anyone</emphasis> begins to talk
4564 about <quote>balance,</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4565 argument. <quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4566 incentives,</quote> they say, <quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4567 content,</quote> the warriors insist, <quote>is our
4568 <emphasis>property</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4569 `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4570 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4571 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether
4572 the car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?</quote>
4573 </para>
4574 <para>
4575 <quote>It is <emphasis>our property</emphasis>,</quote> the warriors
4576 insist. <quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4577 is protected.</quote>
4578 </para>
4579 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4580 </section>
4581 </chapter>
4582 </part>
4583 <part id="c-property">
4584 <title><quote>PROPERTY</quote></title>
4585 <partintro>
4586 <para>
4587
4588 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4589 <emphasis role='strong'>The copyright warriors</emphasis> are right: A
4590 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4591 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4592 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4593 that partially determine the price she can get.
4594 </para>
4595 <para>
4596 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a <quote>property</quote> right is a
4597 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4598 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4599 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4600 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4601 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4602 when I take the good <emphasis>idea</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4603 table in the backyard&mdash;by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4604 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4605 then?
4606 </para>
4607 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
4608 <para>
4609 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4610 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4611 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4612 in the ordinary case&mdash;indeed, in practically every case except for a
4613 narrow
4614 range of exceptions&mdash;ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4615 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress&mdash;though I
4616 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4617 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4618 when I copy the way someone else dresses), <quote>He who receives an idea
4619 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4620 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.</quote><footnote><para>
4621 <!-- f1 -->
4622 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in
4623 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson</citetitle>, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4624 Ellery Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333&ndash;34.
4625 </para></footnote>
4626 </para>
4627 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>intangibility of</secondary></indexterm>
4628 <para>
4629 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4630 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4631 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4632 expression
4633 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4634 property.
4635 </para>
4636 <para>
4637 But how, and to what extent, and in what form&mdash;the details,
4638 in other words&mdash;matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4639 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4640 <quote>property</quote> in its proper context.<footnote><para>
4641 <!-- f2 -->
4642 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4643 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4644 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4645 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4646 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4647 Adam Mossoff, <quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,</quote>
4648 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review</citetitle> 45 (2003): 373, 429 n. 241.
4649 </para></footnote>
4650 </para>
4651 <para>
4652 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4653 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4654 <quote>copyright material is property</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4655 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4656 these stories, the significance of this true
4657 statement&mdash;<quote>copyright material is property</quote>&mdash; will be a bit
4658 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4659 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4660 </para>
4661 </partintro>
4662
4663 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4664 <chapter label="6" id="founders">
4665 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders</title>
4666 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for</secondary></indexterm>
4667 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
4668 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
4669 <indexterm id='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='startofrange'><primary>England, copyright laws developed in</primary></indexterm>
4670 <indexterm id='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='startofrange'><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>history of copyright law in</secondary></indexterm>
4671 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4672 <indexterm><primary>Henry V</primary></indexterm>
4673 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4674 <indexterm id='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='startofrange'><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4675 <para>
4676 <emphasis role='strong'>William Shakespeare</emphasis> wrote
4677 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> in 1595. The play was first
4678 published in 1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4679 written. He would continue to write plays through 1613, and the plays
4680 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4681 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4682 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4683 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4684 Henry V: <quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4685 clichés.</quote>
4686 </para>
4687 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4688 <indexterm id='idxtonsonjacob' class='startofrange'><primary>Tonson, Jacob</primary></indexterm>
4689 <para>
4690 In 1774, almost 180 years after <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> was written, the
4691 <quote>copy-right</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4692 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.<footnote><para>
4693 <!-- f1 -->
4694 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben</primary></indexterm>
4695 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John</primary></indexterm>
4696 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4697 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4698 handsome <quote>definitive editions</quote> of classic works. In addition to <citetitle>Romeo and
4699 Juliet</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4700 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4701 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, <quote>Jacob Tonson,
4702 Bookseller,</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar</citetitle> 61:3 (1992): 424&ndash;31.
4703 </para></footnote>
4704 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4705 the Conger<footnote><para>
4706 <!-- f2 -->
4707 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle> (Nashville:
4708 Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 151&ndash;52.
4709 </para></footnote>
4710 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4711 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the <quote>copy</quote> of
4712 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4713 that no
4714 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4715 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4716 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4717 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4718 </para>
4719 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4720 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4721 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
4722 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4723 <para>
4724 Now, there's something puzzling about the year 1774 to anyone who
4725 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4726 history of copyright is 1710, the year that the British Parliament
4727 adopted the first <quote>copyright</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4728 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4729 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4730 works already published by 1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4731 additional years.<footnote><para>
4732 <!-- f3 -->
4733 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4734 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4735 <quote>copyright law.</quote> See Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 40.
4736 </para></footnote> Under this law, <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> should have been
4737 free in 1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4738 Tonson's control in 1774?
4739 </para>
4740 <indexterm startref='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='endofrange'/>
4741 <indexterm startref='idxtonsonjacob' class='endofrange'/>
4742 <indexterm id='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
4743 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
4744 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (1662)</primary></indexterm>
4745 <para>
4746 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a <quote>copyright</quote>
4747 was&mdash;indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4748 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4749 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of 1662, had
4750 expired in 1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4751 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4752 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4753 that the publishers, or <quote>Stationers,</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4754 books.
4755 </para>
4756 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='endofrange'/>
4757 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
4758 <para>
4759 There was no <emphasis>positive</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4760 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4761 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4762 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4763 from legislatures <quote>positive law.</quote> We call the words from judges
4764 <quote>common law.</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4765 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4766 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4767 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4768 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4769 </para>
4770 <indexterm startref='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='endofrange'/>
4771 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4772 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4773 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
4774 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4775 <para>
4776 This question was important to the publishers, or <quote>booksellers,</quote> as
4777 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4778 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4779 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4780
4781 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4782 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4783 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4784 ultimately
4785 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4786 </para>
4787 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>as narrow monopoly right</secondary></indexterm>
4788 <para>
4789 The Statute of Anne granted the author or <quote>proprietor</quote> of a book an
4790 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4791 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4792 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4793 copyright <quote>expired,</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4794 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4795 believed.
4796 </para>
4797 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne' class='endofrange'/>
4798 <para>
4799 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4800 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4801 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4802 <emphasis>at all?</emphasis>
4803 </para>
4804 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'/>
4805 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4806 <indexterm><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4807 <para>
4808 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4809 strong claim. Take <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> as an example: That play
4810 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4811 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4812 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4813 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4814 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4815 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4816 reason is there to allow someone else to <quote>steal</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4817 </para>
4818 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4819 <para>
4820 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4821 about the notion of <quote>copyright</quote> that existed at the time of the
4822 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4823 <quote>booksellers.</quote>
4824 </para>
4825 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
4826 <para>
4827 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4828 to apply the concept of <quote>copyright</quote> ever more broadly. But in 1710, it
4829 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4830 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4831 others from reprinting a book. In 1710, the <quote>copy-right</quote> was a right
4832 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4833 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4834 generally how
4835 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4836 a work could be <emphasis>used</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4837 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4838 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4839 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4840 </para>
4841 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4842 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4843 <para>
4844 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4845 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4846 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4847 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4848 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4849 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4850 allowed to make his films. The <quote>copy-right</quote> was only an exclusive
4851 right to print&mdash;no less, of course, but also no more.
4852 </para>
4853 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England</primary></indexterm>
4854 <indexterm id='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='startofrange'><primary>monopoly, copyright as</primary></indexterm>
4855 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (1656)</primary></indexterm>
4856 <para>
4857 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4858 They had had a long and ugly experience with <quote>exclusive rights,</quote>
4859 especially <quote>exclusive rights</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4860 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4861 monopolies&mdash;especially monopolies for works that already
4862 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4863 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4864 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In 1656, it passed the
4865 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4866 inventions. And by 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4867 monopoly in publishing.
4868 </para>
4869 <para>
4870 Thus the <quote>copy-right,</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4871 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4872 claim that <quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,</quote> try
4873 sounding convincing when uttering, <quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4874 have it forever.</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4875 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4876 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4877 </para>
4878 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
4879 <indexterm id='idxbooksellersenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>booksellers, English</primary></indexterm>
4880 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4881 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4882 <para>
4883 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4884 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4885 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4886 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4887 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4888
4889 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4890 kind&mdash;tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4891 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4892 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as <quote>old patentees
4893 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling</quote>; they were <quote>men who do
4894 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4895 indetted.</quote><footnote><para>
4896
4897 <!-- f4 -->
4898 Philip Wittenberg, <citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4899 Property</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31.
4900 </para></footnote>
4901 </para>
4902 <indexterm><primary>Enlightenment</primary></indexterm>
4903 <indexterm><primary>knowledge, freedom of</primary></indexterm>
4904 <para>
4905 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4906 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4907 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4908 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4909 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4910 with that idea.
4911 </para>
4912 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament2' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4913 <para>
4914 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4915 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4916 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4917 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4918 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4919 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4920 compromise
4921 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4922 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4923 construction and spread of culture.
4924 </para>
4925 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne2' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)
4926 </primary></indexterm>
4927 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
4928 <para>
4929 When 1731 (1710 + 21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4930 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4931 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4932 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4933 to control publication. But in 1735 and 1737, they tried to persuade
4934 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4935 they said; they needed more time.
4936 </para>
4937 <para>
4938 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4939 words that echo today,
4940 </para>
4941 <blockquote>
4942 <para>
4943 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4944 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4945 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4946 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4947 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4948 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4949 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4950 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4951 Booksellers.<footnote><para>
4952 <!-- f5 -->
4953 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4954 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4955 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4956 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4957 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4958 mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4959 al., 8, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618).
4960 </para></footnote>
4961 </para>
4962 </blockquote>
4963 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne2' class='endofrange'/>
4964 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='endofrange'/>
4965 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
4966 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
4967 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
4968 <para>
4969 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4970 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4971 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
4972 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
4973 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
4974 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
4975 creative <quote>property</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
4976 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
4977 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
4978 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
4979 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
4980 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
4981 way to protect authors.
4982 </para>
4983 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament2' class='endofrange'/>
4984 <para>
4985 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
4986 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
4987 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
4988 <quote>The publishers &hellip; had as much concern for authors as a cattle
4989 rancher has for cattle.</quote><footnote><para>
4990 <!-- f6 -->
4991 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
4992 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4993 Lyman Ray Patterson, <quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
4994 Law Review</citetitle> 40 (1987): 28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
4995 Vaidhyanathan, 37&ndash;48.
4996 </para></footnote>
4997 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
4998 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
4999 </para>
5000 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5001 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5002 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5003 <para>
5004 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
5005 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
5006 Donaldson.<footnote><para>
5007 <!-- f7 -->
5008 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, <citetitle>Authorship and Copyright</citetitle>
5009 (London: Routledge, 1992), 62&ndash;69.
5010 </para></footnote>
5011 </para>
5012 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne3' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
5013 <indexterm id='idxconger' class='startofrange'><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
5014 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James</primary></indexterm>
5015 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew</primary></indexterm>
5016 <para>
5017 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
5018 career in Edinburgh in 1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
5019 reprints <quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,</quote> at least
5020 under the Statute of Anne.<footnote><para>
5021 <!-- f8 -->
5022 Mark Rose, <citetitle>Authors and Owners</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
5023 1993), 92.
5024 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
5025 </para></footnote>
5026 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
5027 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
5028 and became <quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.</quote> <quote>[A]mong
5029 them,</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was <quote>the young James Boswell
5030 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
5031 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.</quote><footnote><para>
5032 <!-- f9 -->
5033 Ibid., 93.
5034 </para></footnote>
5035 </para>
5036 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5037 <para>
5038 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
5039 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
5040 inexpensive editions <quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
5041 of the supposed common law right of Literary
5042 Property.</quote><footnote><para>
5043 <!-- f10 -->
5044 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5045 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle>, 167 (quoting
5046 Borwell).
5047 </para></footnote>
5048 His books undercut the Conger prices by 30 to 50 percent, and he
5049 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
5050 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
5051 </para>
5052 <indexterm startref='idxconger' class='endofrange'/>
5053 <indexterm id='idxmillarvtaylor' class='startofrange'><primary>Millar v. Taylor</primary></indexterm>
5054 <para>
5055 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block <quote>piracy</quote> like
5056 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the <quote>pirates,</quote>
5057 the most important early victory being <citetitle>Millar</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Taylor</citetitle>.
5058 </para>
5059 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='endofrange'/>
5060 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers' class='endofrange'/>
5061 <indexterm id='idxthomsonjames' class='startofrange'><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5062 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5063 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)</primary></indexterm>
5064 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert</primary></indexterm>
5065 <para>
5066 Millar was a bookseller who in 1729 had purchased the rights to James
5067 Thomson's poem <quote>The Seasons.</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
5068 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
5069 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
5070 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
5071 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.<footnote><para>
5072 <!-- f11 -->
5073 Howard B. Abrams, <quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
5074 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review</citetitle> 29
5075 (1983): 1152.
5076 </para></footnote>
5077 </para>
5078 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
5079 <para>
5080 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
5081 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
5082 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
5083 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
5084 law would protect the author against subsequent <quote>pirates.</quote>
5085 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
5086 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
5087 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
5088 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
5089 </para>
5090 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw' class='endofrange'/>
5091 <indexterm startref='idxthomsonjames' class='endofrange'/>
5092 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='endofrange'/>
5093 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament3' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5094 <para>
5095 Considered as a matter of abstract justice&mdash;reasoning as if
5096 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
5097 principles&mdash;Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
5098 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
5099 with in 1710: How best to limit
5100 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
5101 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
5102 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in 1710, but
5103 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
5104 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
5105 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
5106 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
5107 </para>
5108 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='endofrange'/>
5109 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5110 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers2' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5111 <para>
5112 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
5113 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
5114 </para>
5115 <indexterm><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5116 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
5117 <indexterm id='idxhouseoflords' class='startofrange'><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5118 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>House of Lords vs.</secondary></indexterm>
5119 <para>
5120 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
5121 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
5122 Thomas Beckett.<footnote><para>
5123 <!-- f12 -->
5124 Ibid., 1156.
5125 </para></footnote>
5126 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
5127 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in <citetitle>Millar</citetitle>,
5128 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
5129 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
5130 Court. In February of 1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
5131 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
5132 </para>
5133 <indexterm startref='idxmillarvtaylor' class='endofrange'/>
5134 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament3' class='endofrange'/>
5135 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson v. Beckett</primary></indexterm>
5136 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5137 <para>
5138 As few legal cases ever do, <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle> drew an
5139 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
5140 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
5141 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
5142 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
5143 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
5144 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
5145 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
5146 </para>
5147 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne3' class='endofrange'/>
5148 <para>
5149 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
5150 presented to the House and voted upon first by the <quote>law lords,</quote>
5151 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
5152 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
5153 House of Lords generally voted.
5154 </para>
5155 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='endofrange'/>
5156 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5157 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5158 <para>
5159 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
5160 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
5161 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
5162 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
5163 (22 to 11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
5164 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
5165 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
5166 passed into the public domain.
5167 </para>
5168 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis</primary></indexterm>
5169 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John</primary></indexterm>
5170 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel</primary></indexterm>
5171 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
5172 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
5173 <para>
5174 <quote>The public domain.</quote> Before the case of <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle>
5175 v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
5176 England. Before 1774, there was a strong argument that common law
5177 copyrights were perpetual. After 1774, the public domain was
5178 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
5179 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
5180 history&mdash;including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
5181 and Bunyan&mdash;were free of legal restraint.
5182 </para>
5183 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='endofrange'/>
5184 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers2' class='endofrange'/>
5185 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw2' class='endofrange'/>
5186 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='endofrange'/>
5187 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5188 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5189 <para>
5190 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
5191 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
5192 where most of the <quote>pirate publishers</quote> did their work, people
5193 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the <citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser</citetitle>
5194 reported, <quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
5195 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
5196 decision of which so many individuals were interested.</quote> <quote>Great
5197 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
5198 and illuminations.</quote><footnote><para>
5199 <!-- f13 -->
5200 Rose, 97.
5201 </para></footnote>
5202 </para>
5203 <indexterm startref='idxhouseoflords' class='endofrange'/>
5204 <para>
5205 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
5206 equally strong in the opposite direction. The <citetitle>Morning Chronicle</citetitle>
5207 reported:
5208 </para>
5209 <blockquote>
5210 <para>
5211 By the above decision &hellip; near 200,000 pounds worth of what was
5212 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
5213 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
5214 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
5215 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
5216 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
5217 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
5218 successors.<footnote><para>
5219 <!-- f14 -->
5220 Ibid.
5221 </para></footnote>
5222 </para>
5223 </blockquote>
5224 <indexterm><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5225 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5226 <para>
5227 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
5228 <quote>Ruined</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
5229 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
5230 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
5231 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
5232 <emphasis>free</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
5233 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
5234 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
5235 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
5236 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
5237 book from someone. But <emphasis>free</emphasis> in the sense that the
5238 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
5239 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
5240 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
5241 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
5242 develop&mdash; chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
5243 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a <emphasis>competitive
5244 context</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
5245 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
5246 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
5247 </para>
5248 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellersenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5249 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5250 <para>
5251 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
5252 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
5253 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
5254 protected.
5255 </para>
5256 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='endofrange'/>
5257 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5258 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5259 <indexterm startref='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='endofrange'/>
5260 <indexterm startref='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='endofrange'/>
5261 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='endofrange'/>
5262 <indexterm startref='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='endofrange'/>
5263 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='endofrange'/>
5264 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='endofrange'/>
5265 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
5266 </chapter>
5267 <chapter label="7" id="recorders">
5268 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders</title>
5269 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
5270 <indexterm id='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>documentary film</primary></indexterm>
5271 <indexterm id='idxelsejon' class='startofrange'><primary>Else, Jon</primary></indexterm>
5272 <indexterm id='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>in documentary film</secondary></indexterm>
5273 <indexterm id='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>fair use of copyrighted material in</secondary></indexterm>
5274 <para>
5275 <emphasis role='strong'>Jon Else</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5276 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5277 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5278 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5279 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5280 </para>
5281 <para>
5282 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5283 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5284 today.
5285 </para>
5286 <indexterm id='idxwagnerrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5287 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5288 <para>
5289 In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5290 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5291 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5292 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5293 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5294 stage.
5295 </para>
5296 <indexterm id='idxsimpsonsthe' class='startofrange'><primary>Simpsons, The</primary></indexterm>
5297 <para>
5298 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5299 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5300 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5301 and the opera company played Wagner, was <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. As Else judged
5302 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5303 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5304 about the scene.
5305 </para>
5306 <indexterm startref='idxwagnerrichard' class='endofrange'/>
5307 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>multiple copyrights associated with</secondary></indexterm>
5308 <para>
5309 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5310 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>.
5311 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5312 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5313 unless <quote>fair use</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5314 </para>
5315 <indexterm id='idxgraciefilms' class='startofrange'><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5316 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt' class='startofrange'><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5317 <para>
5318 Else called <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5319 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5320 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5321 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5322 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5323 </para>
5324 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5325 <para>
5326 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5327 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5328 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5329 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5330 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5331 </para>
5332 <indexterm startref='idxgraciefilms' class='endofrange'/>
5333 <para>
5334 Then, as Else told me, <quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5335 &hellip; that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation&mdash;or at
5336 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.</quote>
5337 And second, Fox <quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5338 to use this four-point-five seconds of &hellip; entirely unsolicited
5339 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.</quote>
5340 </para>
5341 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt' class='endofrange'/>
5342 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='endofrange'/>
5343 <indexterm id='idxherrerarebecca' class='startofrange'><primary>Herrera, Rebecca</primary></indexterm>
5344 <para>
5345 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5346 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5347 explained to her, <quote>There must be some mistake here. &hellip; We're
5348 asking for your educational rate on this.</quote> That was the educational
5349 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5350 confirm what he had been told.
5351 </para>
5352 <indexterm><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5353 <para>
5354 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,</quote> he told me. <quote>Yes, you
5355 have your facts straight,</quote> she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the
5356 clip of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5357 about
5358
5359 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5360 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, <quote>And
5361 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.</quote> As an assistant
5362 to Herrera told Else later on, <quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5363 the money.</quote>
5364 </para>
5365 <indexterm startref='idxherrerarebecca' class='endofrange'/>
5366 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5367 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The</primary></indexterm>
5368 <para>
5369 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5370 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5371 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5372 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5373 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5374 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5375 </para>
5376 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5377 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt2' class='startofrange'><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5378 <para>
5379 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5380 copyright to <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5381 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5382 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5383 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5384 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5385 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5386 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5387 says the owner gets to control.
5388 </para>
5389 <para>
5390 For example, <quote>public performance</quote> is a use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> that the
5391 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5392 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see <quote>My
5393 Favorite <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>,</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5394 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5395 whatever she wants&mdash;$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set
5396 by the law.
5397 </para>
5398 <para>
5399 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5400 thought is <quote>fair use.</quote><footnote><para>
5401 <!-- f1 -->
5402 For an excellent argument that such use is <quote>fair use,</quote> but that
5403 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is <quote>fair use,</quote> see Richard
5404 A. Posner with William F. Patry, <quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5405 Wake of <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5406 Law School, 5 August 2003.
5407 </para></footnote>
5408 Else's use of just 4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>
5409 episode is clearly a fair use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>&mdash;and fair use does
5410 not require the permission of anyone.
5411 </para>
5412 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='endofrange'/>
5413 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt2' class='endofrange'/>
5414 <para>
5415 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5416 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon <quote>fair use.</quote> Here's his reply:
5417 </para>
5418 <blockquote>
5419 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
5420 <para>
5421 The <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5422 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5423 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5424 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was <quote>clearly
5425 fair use</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5426 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5427 </para>
5428 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
5429 <listitem>
5430 <indexterm><primary>Errors and Omissions insurance</primary></indexterm>
5431 <para>
5432 <!-- 1. -->
5433 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5434 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5435 <quote>visual cue sheet</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5436 shot in the film. They take a dim view of <quote>fair use,</quote> and a claim of
5437 <quote>fair use</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5438 </para></listitem>
5439 <listitem>
5440 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5441 <indexterm><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5442 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George</primary></indexterm>
5443 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5444 <para>
5445 <!-- 2. -->
5446 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5447 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5448 tracking down and stopping unlicensed <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> usage, just as George
5449 Lucas had a very high profile litigating <citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5450 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5451 license to four seconds of <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5452 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5453 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5454 principle.
5455 </para></listitem>
5456 <listitem><para>
5457 <!-- 3. -->
5458 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5459 School &hellip; who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5460 that Fox would <quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5461 life,</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5462 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5463 pockets, me or them.
5464 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5465 </para>
5466 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='endofrange'/>
5467 </listitem>
5468 <listitem><para>
5469 <!-- 4. -->
5470 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5471 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5472 money.
5473 </para></listitem>
5474 </orderedlist>
5475 </blockquote>
5476 <indexterm startref='idxsimpsonsthe' class='endofrange'/>
5477 <para>
5478 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5479 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5480 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5481 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5482 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5483 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5484 </para>
5485 <para>
5486 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5487 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5488 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5489 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5490 not.
5491 </para>
5492 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='endofrange'/>
5493 <indexterm startref='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5494 <indexterm startref='idxelsejon' class='endofrange'/>
5495 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5496 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='endofrange'/>
5497 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='endofrange'/>
5498 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5499 </chapter>
5500 <chapter label="8" id="transformers">
5501 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers</title>
5502 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul</primary></indexterm>
5503 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5504 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary></indexterm>
5505 <para>
5506 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5507 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5508 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5509 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5510 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5511 anticipation of the power of networks.
5512 </para>
5513 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on</secondary></indexterm>
5514 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in</primary></indexterm>
5515 <para>
5516 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5517 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology&mdash;not to distribute
5518 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5519 difficult. In 1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5520 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5521 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5522 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5523 important to his career.
5524 </para>
5525 <para>
5526 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5527 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5528 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5529 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5530 </para>
5531 <para>
5532 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5533 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5534 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5535 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5536 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5537 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5538 </para>
5539 <para>
5540 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. <quote>Our
5541 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5542 Eastwood's films,</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5543 arose. <quote>No one had ever really done this before,</quote> Alben explained. <quote>No
5544 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5545 actor's career.</quote>
5546 </para>
5547 <para>
5548 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5549 Slade asked, <quote>Well, what will it take?</quote>
5550 </para>
5551 <para>
5552 Alben replied, <quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5553 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5554 else that we want to use in these film clips.</quote> Slade said, <quote>Great! Go
5555 for it.</quote><footnote>
5556 <para>
5557 <!-- f1 -->
5558 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5559 publicity&mdash;rights an artist has to control the commercial
5560 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden <quote>Rip, Mix,
5561 Burn</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5562 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of</secondary></indexterm>
5563 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5564 </para></footnote>
5565 </para>
5566 <para>
5567 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5568 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5569 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5570 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5571 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5572 </para>
5573 <para>
5574 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5575 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5576 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5577 </para>
5578 <blockquote>
5579 <para>
5580 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5581 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include&mdash;of
5582 course we were going to use the <quote>Make my day</quote> clip from <citetitle>Dirty
5583 Harry</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5584 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5585 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5586 </para>
5587 <para>
5588 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5589 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5590 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5591 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5592 rate at the time was about $600. So we had to identify the
5593 people&mdash;some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5594 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5595 glass&mdash;is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5596 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5597 started calling people.
5598 </para>
5599 </blockquote>
5600 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald</primary></indexterm>
5601 <para>
5602 Some actors were glad to help&mdash;Donald Sutherland, for example,
5603 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5604 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5605 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5606 know, $1,200?</quote> And they would say, <quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5607 to get $1,200.</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5608 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5609 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5610 career.
5611 </para>
5612 <para>
5613 It was one <emphasis>year</emphasis> later&mdash;<quote>and even then we
5614 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.</quote>
5615 </para>
5616 <para>
5617 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5618 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5619 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5620 </para>
5621 <blockquote>
5622 <para>
5623 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5624 hands and said, <quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5625 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5626 actors.</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5627 constituent parts and said, <quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5628 directors, &hellip; this many musicians,</quote> and we just went at it very
5629 systematically and cleared the rights.
5630 </para>
5631 </blockquote>
5632 <para>
5633
5634 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5635 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5636 loved it, and it sold very well.
5637 </para>
5638 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter</primary></indexterm>
5639 <para>
5640 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5641 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5642 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, <quote>There is
5643 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5644 at all.</quote><footnote><para>
5645 <!-- f2 -->
5646 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, <citetitle>Seven
5647 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition</citetitle>, available at
5648 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #22</ulink>.
5649 </para></footnote>
5650 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5651 has to be made?
5652 </para>
5653 <para>
5654 For, as he acknowledged, <quote>very few &hellip; have the time and resources,
5655 and the will to do this,</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5656 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5657 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5658 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5659 </para>
5660 <blockquote>
5661 <para>
5662 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5663 he or she gets paid very well. &hellip; And then when 30 seconds of
5664 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5665 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person &hellip; should be
5666 compensated for that.
5667 </para>
5668 </blockquote>
5669 <para>
5670 Or at least, is this <emphasis>how</emphasis> the artist should be
5671 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5672 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5673 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5674 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5675 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5676 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5677 made to be more clean?
5678 </para>
5679 <blockquote>
5680 <para>
5681 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5682 mechanism&mdash;where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5683 subject to estranged former spouses&mdash;you'd see a lot more of this
5684 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5685 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5686 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5687 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5688 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5689 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5690 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5691 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5692 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5693 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5694 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, <quote>Oh, I
5695 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5696 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5697 money,</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5698 </para>
5699 </blockquote>
5700 <para>
5701 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5702 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5703 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5704 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5705 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5706 </para>
5707 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'/>
5708 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'/>
5709 <para>
5710 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5711 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5712 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5713 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5714 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5715 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5716 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5717 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5718 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5719 <quote>Does this still make sense?</quote>
5720 </para>
5721 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'/>
5722 <para>
5723 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5724 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5725 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5726 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5727
5728 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5729 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5730 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5731 </para>
5732 <para>
5733 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5734 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode.
5735 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5736 judges loved every minute of it.
5737 </para>
5738 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David</primary></indexterm>
5739 <para>
5740 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5741 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5742 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5743 room of over 250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5744 began his talk with a question: <quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5745 were just violated in this room?</quote>
5746 </para>
5747 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David</primary></indexterm>
5748 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5749 <para>
5750 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5751 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5752 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5753 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5754 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle
5755 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5756 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5757 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5758 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5759 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5760 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5761 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5762 couldn't easily do them legally.
5763 </para>
5764 <para>
5765 We live in a <quote>cut and paste</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5766 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5767 and paste architecture of the Internet created&mdash;in a second you can
5768 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5769 planted in your presentation.
5770 </para>
5771 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos</primary></indexterm>
5772 <para>
5773 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5774 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5775 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5776 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5777 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5778 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5779 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5780 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5781 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5782 </para>
5783 <para>
5784 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5785 wanted to be <quote>legal,</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5786 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5787 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5788 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5789 </para>
5790 <para>
5791 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5792 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5793 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5794 necessarily requiring that the <quote>free</quote> use be free as in <quote>free beer.</quote>
5795 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5796 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5797 along: a rule, for example, that says <quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5798 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5799 will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5800 copyright owner.</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5801 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5802 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5803 registers the work.
5804 </para>
5805 <para>
5806 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5807 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5808 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5809 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5810 </para>
5811 <para>
5812 <emphasis role='strong'>In February 2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5813 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5814 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live</citetitle> and
5815 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5816 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5817 would work together to form a <quote>unique filmmaking pact.</quote> Under the
5818 agreement, DreamWorks <quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5819 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and&mdash;with the use
5820 of stateof-the-art digital technology&mdash;insert Myers and other
5821 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5822 entertainment.</quote>
5823 </para>
5824 <para>
5825 The announcement called this <quote>film sampling.</quote> As Myers explained,
5826 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5827 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5828 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5829 to take that same concept and apply it to film.</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5830 quoted as saying, <quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5831 new audiences, it is Mike.</quote>
5832 </para>
5833 <para>
5834 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5835 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5836 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5837 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5838 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5839 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5840 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5841 privilege reserved for the funny and famous&mdash;and presumably rich.
5842 </para>
5843 <para>
5844 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5845 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of <quote>fair use.</quote>
5846 Much of <quote>sampling</quote> should be considered <quote>fair use.</quote> But few would
5847 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5848 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5849 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5850 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5851 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5852 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5853 process is a process of paying lawyers&mdash;again a privilege, or perhaps a
5854 curse, reserved for the few.
5855 </para>
5856 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5857 </chapter>
5858 <chapter label="9" id="collectors">
5859 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors</title>
5860 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
5861 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
5862 <para>
5863 <emphasis role='strong'>In April 1996</emphasis>, millions of
5864 <quote>bots</quote>&mdash;computer codes designed to
5865 <quote>spider,</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5866 content&mdash;began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5867 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5868 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5869 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5870 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5871 Internet and stored them.
5872 </para>
5873 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5874 <para>
5875 By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5876 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5877 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5878 the world. Using a technology called <quote>the Way Back Machine,</quote> you could
5879 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to 1996, as
5880 well as when those pages changed.
5881 </para>
5882 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Orwell, George</primary></indexterm>
5883 <para>
5884 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5885 appreciated. In the dystopia described in <citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5886 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5887 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5888 reports.
5889 </para>
5890 <para>
5891 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5892 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5893 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5894 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5895 </para>
5896 <para>
5897 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5898 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5899 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5900 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5901 library&mdash;constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5902 </para>
5903 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'/>
5904 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5905 <para>
5906 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5907 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5908 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5909 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5910 what others might prefer you forget.<footnote><para>
5911 <!-- f1 -->
5912 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
5913 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases</primary></indexterm>
5914 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5915 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003,
5916 press release stated, <quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.</quote> That was
5917 later changed, without notice, to <quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5918 Have Ended.</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003.
5919 </para></footnote>
5920 </para>
5921 <indexterm><primary>history, records of</primary></indexterm>
5922 <para>
5923 <emphasis role='strong'>We take it</emphasis> for granted that we can
5924 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5925 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5926 race riots in Watts in 1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in 1963,
5927 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5928 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5929 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
5930 remember&mdash;not just what it is convenient to remember, but
5931 remember something close to the truth.
5932 </para>
5933 <para>
5934 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5935 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We <emphasis>all</emphasis>
5936 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
5937 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
5938 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
5939 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
5940 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
5941 </para>
5942 <para>
5943 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5944 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5945 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5946 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5947 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5948 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5949 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5950 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet&mdash;the
5951 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5952 </para>
5953 <para>
5954 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5955 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5956 researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5957 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5958 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5959 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5960 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10
5961 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5962 </para>
5963 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
5964 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive</primary></indexterm>
5965 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University</primary></indexterm>
5966 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5967 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>archival function of</secondary></indexterm>
5968 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage2' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
5969 <para>
5970 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
5971 human history. At the end of 2002, it held <quote>two hundred and thirty
5972 terabytes of material</quote>&mdash;and was <quote>ten times larger than the
5973 Library of Congress.</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
5974 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
5975 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
5976 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
5977 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
5978 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
5979 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University&mdash;thanks to a
5980 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
5981 is available to scholars for a very low fee. <quote>But other than that,
5982 [television] is almost unavailable,</quote> Kahle told me. <quote>If you were
5983 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
5984 just a graduate student?</quote> As Kahle put it,
5985 </para>
5986 <blockquote>
5987 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan</primary></indexterm>
5988 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes</primary></indexterm>
5989 <para>
5990 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
5991 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
5992 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
5993 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
5994 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
5995
5996 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
5997 <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode that came out after it &hellip; it would be almost
5998 impossible. &hellip; Those materials are almost unfindable. &hellip;
5999 </para>
6000 </blockquote>
6001 <indexterm><primary>newspapers</primary><secondary>archives of</secondary></indexterm>
6002 <para>
6003 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
6004 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
6005 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
6006 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
6007 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
6008 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
6009 </para>
6010 <para>
6011 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
6012 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
6013 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
6014 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
6015 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
6016 work.
6017 </para>
6018 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
6019 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6020 <para>
6021 These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library
6022 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
6023 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
6024 borrow back the deposits&mdash;for an unlimited time at no cost. In
6025 1915 alone, there were more than 5,475 films deposited and <quote>borrowed
6026 back.</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
6027 held by any library. The copy exists&mdash;if it exists at
6028 all&mdash;in the library archive of the film company.<footnote><para>
6029 <!-- f2 -->
6030 Doug Herrick, <quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
6031 the Library of Congress,</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly</citetitle> 13 nos. 2&ndash;3
6032 (1980): 5; Anthony Slide, <citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
6033 Preservation in the United States</citetitle> (Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland &amp;
6034 Co., 1992), 36.
6035 </para></footnote>
6036 </para>
6037 <para>
6038 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
6039 were originally not copyrighted&mdash;there was no way to capture the
6040 broadcasts, so there was no fear of <quote>theft.</quote> But as technology enabled
6041 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
6042 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
6043 <quote>copyrighted.</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
6044 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
6045 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
6046 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
6047 </para>
6048 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
6049 <para>
6050 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and
6051 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
6052 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
6053 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
6054 September 11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
6055 stations from around the world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made
6056 their coverage during the week of September 11 available free on-line.
6057 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
6058 events of that day.
6059 </para>
6060 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive</primary></indexterm>
6061 <indexterm><primary>archive.org</primary><seealso>Internet Archive</seealso></indexterm>
6062 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage2' class='endofrange'/>
6063 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6064 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive</primary></indexterm>
6065 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film</primary></indexterm>
6066 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films</primary></indexterm>
6067 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick</primary></indexterm>
6068 <para>
6069 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
6070 archive of film includes close to 45,000 <quote>ephemeral films</quote> (meaning
6071 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
6072 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
6073 1,300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
6074 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
6075 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
6076 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
6077 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
6078 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
6079 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
6080 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
6081 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the <quote>Duck and Cover</quote> film
6082 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
6083 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
6084 few minutes&mdash;for free.
6085 </para>
6086 <para>
6087 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
6088 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
6089 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
6090 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
6091 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
6092 to find them.
6093 </para>
6094 <para>
6095 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
6096 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
6097 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
6098 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
6099 property, but during a second life that all creative property
6100 has&mdash;a noncommercial life.
6101 </para>
6102 <para>
6103 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
6104 of creative property goes through different <quote>lives.</quote> In its first
6105 life, if the
6106
6107 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
6108 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
6109 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
6110 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
6111 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
6112 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
6113 </para>
6114 <para>
6115 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
6116 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
6117 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
6118 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
6119 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
6120 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
6121 longer sold.
6122 </para>
6123 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6124 <para>
6125 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
6126 very quickly (the average today is after about a year<footnote><para>
6127 <!-- f3 -->
6128 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6129 Dave Barns, <quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
6130 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>,
6131 5 September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927
6132 and 1946, only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese,
6133 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,</quote> <citetitle>Boston
6134 College Law Review</citetitle> 44 (2003): 593 n. 51.
6135 </para></footnote>). After
6136 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
6137 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
6138 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
6139 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
6140 important to the spread and stability of culture.
6141 </para>
6142 <para>
6143 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
6144 creative property does not hold true with the most important
6145 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
6146 centuries. For these&mdash;television, movies, music, radio, the
6147 Internet&mdash;there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
6148 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes &amp;
6149 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
6150 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
6151 disappears.
6152 </para>
6153 <para>
6154 <emphasis role='strong'>For most of</emphasis> the twentieth century,
6155 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
6156 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
6157 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
6158 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
6159 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
6160 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
6161 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
6162 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
6163 little practical effect.
6164 </para>
6165 <para>
6166 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
6167 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
6168 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
6169 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
6170 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
6171 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
6172 </para>
6173 <para>
6174 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
6175 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
6176 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
6177 Kahle describes,
6178 </para>
6179 <blockquote>
6180 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>total number of</secondary></indexterm>
6181 <para>
6182 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
6183 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
6184 movies, &hellip; and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
6185 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
6186 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
6187 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
6188 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
6189 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
6190 &hellip; thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
6191 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
6192 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
6193 </para>
6194 </blockquote>
6195 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
6196 <para>
6197 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
6198 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
6199 libraries or archives could be. <emphasis>When</emphasis> the
6200 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
6201 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
6202 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
6203 will draw upon it to understand it;
6204 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
6205 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
6206 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
6207 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past&mdash;a
6208 future <emphasis>for</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
6209 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
6210 </para>
6211 <para>
6212 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
6213 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
6214 call these <quote>archives,</quote> as warm as the idea of a <quote>library</quote> might seem,
6215 the <quote>content</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
6216 someone's <quote>property.</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
6217 that Kahle and others would exercise.
6218 </para>
6219 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'/>
6220 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
6221 </chapter>
6222 <chapter label="10" id="property-i">
6223 <title>CHAPTER TEN: <quote>Property</quote></title>
6224 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon</primary></indexterm>
6225 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
6226 <para>
6227 <emphasis role='strong'>Jack Valenti</emphasis> has been the president
6228 of the Motion Picture Association of America since 1966. He first came
6229 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
6230 administration&mdash;literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
6231 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
6232 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
6233 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
6234 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
6235 </para>
6236 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
6237 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment</primary></indexterm>
6238 <indexterm><primary>MGM</primary></indexterm>
6239 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6240 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox</primary></indexterm>
6241 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6242 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
6243 <para>
6244 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
6245 Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal
6246 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
6247 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
6248 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
6249 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
6250 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
6251 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
6252 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
6253 Warner Brothers.
6254 </para>
6255 <para>
6256 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
6257 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
6258 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
6259 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
6260 political skill of a Southerner&mdash;the ability to appear simple and
6261 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
6262 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
6263 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
6264 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
6265 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
6266 Washingtonian way.
6267 </para>
6268 <para>
6269 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
6270 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
6271 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
6272 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
6273 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
6274 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
6275 redefine the meaning of <quote>creative property.</quote>
6276 </para>
6277 <para>
6278 In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
6279 perfectly:
6280 </para>
6281 <blockquote>
6282 <para>
6283 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
6284 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
6285 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
6286 theme which animates this entire debate: <emphasis>Creative property
6287 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
6288 other property owners in the nation</emphasis>. That is the issue.
6289 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
6290 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.<footnote><para>
6291 <!-- f1 -->
6292 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R.
6293 4794, H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the
6294 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
6295 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
6296 Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack
6297 Valenti).
6298 </para></footnote>
6299 </para>
6300 </blockquote>
6301 <para>
6302 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
6303 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
6304 <quote>central theme</quote> to which <quote>reasonable men and women</quote> will return is
6305 this:
6306 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6307 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6308 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.</quote>
6309 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6310 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6311 </para>
6312 <para>
6313 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6314 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6315 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6316 extreme a claim made by <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> who is serious in
6317 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6318 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6319 it comes to the nature and scope of <quote>creative property.</quote> His views
6320 have <emphasis>no</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6321 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6322 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6323 </para>
6324 <para>
6325 While <quote>creative property</quote> is certainly <quote>property</quote> in a nerdy and
6326 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,<footnote><para>
6327 <!-- f2 -->
6328 Lawyers speak of <quote>property</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6329 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6330 object. Thus, my <quote>property right</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6331 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For
6332 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of <quote>property</quote> to
6333 <quote>lawyer talk,</quote> see Bruce Ackerman, <citetitle>Private Property and the
6334 Constitution</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 26&ndash;27.
6335 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6336 <quote>creative property owners</quote> have been <quote>accorded the same rights and
6337 protection resident in all other property owners.</quote> Indeed, if creative
6338 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6339 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6340 in our tradition.
6341 </para>
6342 <para>
6343 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6344 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6345 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6346 overturned in 1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6347 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6348 culture would develop.
6349 </para>
6350 <para>
6351 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6352 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6353 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6354 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6355 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6356 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6357 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6358 the same would be to
6359
6360 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6361 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6362 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6363 perfect control.
6364 </para>
6365 <para>
6366 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6367 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6368 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6369 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6370 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6371 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6372 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6373 </para>
6374 <para>
6375 <emphasis role='strong'>To get</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6376 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6377 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6378 </para>
6379 <para>
6380 The framers of our Constitution loved <quote>property.</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6381 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6382 important requirement. If the government takes your property&mdash;if
6383 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6384 farm&mdash;it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's <quote>Takings
6385 Clause,</quote> to pay you <quote>just compensation</quote> for that taking. The
6386 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6387 sacred. It cannot <emphasis>ever</emphasis> be taken from the property
6388 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6389 </para>
6390 <para>
6391 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6392 Valenti calls <quote>creative property.</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6393 power to create <quote>creative property,</quote> the Constitution
6394 <emphasis>requires</emphasis> that after a <quote>limited time,</quote> Congress
6395 take back the rights that it has granted and set the <quote>creative
6396 property</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6397 the expiration of a copyright term <quote>takes</quote> your copyright and turns it
6398 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6399 pay <quote>just compensation</quote> for this <quote>taking.</quote> Instead, the same
6400 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6401 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6402 requires that you lose your <quote>creative property</quote> right without any
6403 compensation at all.
6404 </para>
6405 <para>
6406 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6407 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6408 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6409 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6410 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6411 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6412 itself.
6413 </para>
6414 <indexterm id='idxjeffersonthomas' class='startofrange'><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
6415 <para>
6416 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6417 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6418 The Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6419 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6420 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6421 president (as it did in 1800). The framers were no doubt
6422 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6423 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6424 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6425 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6426 </para>
6427 <para>
6428 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6429 least try to understand <emphasis>why</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6430 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6431 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6432 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6433 domain?
6434 </para>
6435 <indexterm startref='idxjeffersonthomas' class='endofrange'/>
6436
6437 <para>
6438 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6439 history of these <quote>creative property</quote> rights, and the control that they
6440 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6441 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6442 should be at the core of this war: Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis>
6443 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6444 <emphasis>whether</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6445 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6446 ought to be. Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6447 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6448 also control how culture develops.
6449 </para>
6450 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>four modalities of constraint on</secondary></indexterm>
6451 <indexterm id='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>four modalities of</secondary></indexterm>
6452 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as ex post regulation modality</secondary></indexterm>
6453 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6454 <para>
6455
6456 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6457 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6458 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6459 than the narrow language of the law allows. In <citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6460 Cyberspace</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6461 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6462 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6463 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6464 </para>
6465 <figure id="fig-1331">
6466 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.</title>
6467 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6468 </figure>
6469 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6470 <para>
6471 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6472 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6473 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6474 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6475 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6476 be regulated&mdash; either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6477 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6478 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6479 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6480 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6481 Web, you can be punished
6482 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6483 with a $150,000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6484 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6485 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6486 </para>
6487 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6488 <para>
6489 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6490 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6491 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6492 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6493 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6494 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6495 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6496 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6497 the source of the enforcement.
6498 </para>
6499 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6500 <para>
6501 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6502 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6503 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6504 norms&mdash;it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6505 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6506 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6507 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6508 individual or group might behave.
6509 </para>
6510 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6511 <para>
6512 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6513 <quote>architecture</quote>&mdash;the physical world as one finds it&mdash;is a
6514 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6515 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6516 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6517 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6518 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6519 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6520 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6521 theft, but by nature, by <quote>architecture.</quote> If a 500-pound boulder
6522 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6523 constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6524 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6525 </para>
6526 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6527 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6528 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints' class='endofrange'/>
6529 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6530 <para>
6531
6532 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6533 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6534 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6535 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6536 undermined by another.
6537 </para>
6538 <para>
6539 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6540 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6541 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6542 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6543 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6544 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6545 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6546 </para>
6547 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6548 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6549 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6550 <indexterm id='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>driving speed, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6551 <indexterm id='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>speeding, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6552 <para>
6553 So, for example, consider the <quote>freedom</quote> to drive a car at a high
6554 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6555 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6556 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6557 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6558 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6559 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6560 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6561 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6562 the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own
6563 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6564 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6565 </para>
6566 <para>
6567 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6568 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6569 special role in affecting the three.<footnote><para>
6570 <!-- f3 -->
6571 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6572 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6573 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6574 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6575 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Code: And
6576 Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90&ndash;95;
6577 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>The New Chicago School,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies</citetitle>,
6578 June 1998.
6579 </para></footnote>
6580 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6581 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6582 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6583 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6584 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6585 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6586 used to require that other laws be more
6587 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6588 strict&mdash;a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6589 limit, for example&mdash;so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6590 driving.
6591 </para>
6592 <indexterm startref='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6593 <indexterm startref='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6594 <figure id="fig-1361">
6595 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.</title>
6596 <graphic fileref="images/1361.png"></graphic>
6597 </figure>
6598 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6599 <para>
6600 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6601 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6602 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6603 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6604 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6605 another.<footnote>
6606 <para>
6607 <!-- f4 -->
6608 Some people object to this way of talking about <quote>liberty.</quote> They object
6609 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6610 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6611 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6612 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6613 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6614 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6615 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6616 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6617 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6618 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6619 of liberty. As I argued in <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, we come from a
6620 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6621 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6622 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6623 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6624 <citetitle>On Liberty</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6625 1978), 19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6626 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons, <quote>The
6627 Right to Work,</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6628 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays</citetitle> (London:
6629 Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6630 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6631 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6632 places easier; 42 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
6633 12101 (2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6634 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6635 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6636 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6637 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (1990)</primary></indexterm>
6638 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.</primary></indexterm>
6639 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6640 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6641 </para></footnote>
6642 </para>
6643 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='endofrange'/>
6644 <section id="hollywood">
6645 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right</title>
6646 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
6647 <para>
6648 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6649 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6650 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6651 rallying makes sense.
6652 </para>
6653 <para>
6654 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6655 Internet:
6656 </para>
6657 <figure id="fig-1371">
6658 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6659 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6660 </figure>
6661 <indexterm id='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='startofrange'><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6662 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6663 <indexterm id='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='startofrange'><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6664 <para>
6665 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6666 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6667 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6668 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6669 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6670 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6671 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6672 recognize&mdash;kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6673 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6674 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6675 this form of infringement.
6676 </para>
6677 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright regulatory balance lost with</secondary></indexterm>
6678 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>regulatory balance lost in</secondary></indexterm>
6679 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6680 <indexterm><primary>MP3s</primary></indexterm>
6681 <para>
6682 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6683 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6684 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6685 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6686 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6687 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6688 </para>
6689 <indexterm startref='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='endofrange'/>
6690 <indexterm startref='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='endofrange'/>
6691 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>established industries threatened by changes in</secondary></indexterm>
6692 <para>
6693 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6694 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6695 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6696 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6697 Iraq
6698 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6699 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6700 looting that results.
6701 </para>
6702 <figure id="fig-1381">
6703 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.</title>
6704 <graphic fileref="images/1381.png"></graphic>
6705 </figure>
6706 <indexterm><primary>Commerce, U.S. Department of</primary></indexterm>
6707 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
6708 <para>
6709 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6710 warriors. Indeed, in a <quote>White Paper</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6711 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995,
6712 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6713 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6714 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should
6715 strengthen intellectual property law, (2) businesses should adopt
6716 innovative marketing techniques, (3) technologists should push to
6717 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (4) educators should
6718 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6719 </para>
6720 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='endofrange'/>
6721 <indexterm startref='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='endofrange'/>
6722 <indexterm><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6723 <indexterm><primary>steel industry</primary></indexterm>
6724 <para>
6725 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed&mdash;if it was to
6726 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6727 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6728 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6729 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6730 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6731 life. Homeowners living in a
6732
6733 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6734 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6735 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6736 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6737 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6738 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6739 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6740 </para>
6741 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='endofrange'/>
6742 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='endofrange'/>
6743 <indexterm><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
6744 <para>
6745 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6746 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6747 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6748 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6749 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6750 Brown describes it, its <quote>architecture of revenue.</quote>
6751 </para>
6752 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
6753 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
6754 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
6755 <indexterm><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
6756 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
6757 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
6758 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry</primary></indexterm>
6759 <indexterm><primary>remote channel changers</primary></indexterm>
6760 <para>
6761 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6762 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6763 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6764 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6765 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20
6766 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6767 of digital cameras.<footnote><para>
6768 <!-- f5 -->
6769 See Geoffrey Smith, <quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?</quote>
6770 BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at
6771 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #23</ulink>. For a more
6772 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6773 R. Schoenberger, <quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?</quote> Forbes.com, 6
6774 October 2003, available at
6775 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #24</ulink>.
6776 </para></footnote>
6777
6778 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6779 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6780 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6781 <emphasis>for the purpose of</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6782 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6783 weakened the <quote>stickiness</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6784 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf), and it
6785 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6786 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6787 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6788 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6789 </para>
6790 <indexterm id='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='startofrange'><primary>free market, technological changes in</primary></indexterm>
6791 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
6792 <indexterm><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
6793 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
6794 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
6795 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
6796 <indexterm><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
6797 <para>
6798 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6799 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6800 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6801 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6802 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6803 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6804 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6805 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, <quote>established companies
6806 have an interest in excluding future competitors.</quote><footnote><para>
6807 <!-- f6 -->
6808 Fred Warshofsky, <citetitle>The Patent Wars</citetitle> (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170&ndash;71.
6809 </para></footnote>
6810 And relative to a
6811 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6812 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6813 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6814 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6815 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6816 Brezhnev.
6817 </para>
6818 <para>
6819 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6820 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6821 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6822 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6823 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6824 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6825 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6826 opportunities for innovation and change.
6827 </para>
6828 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
6829 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
6830 <indexterm><primary>speech, freedom of</primary><secondary>constitutional guarantee of</secondary></indexterm>
6831 <para>
6832 In the context of laws regulating speech&mdash;which include,
6833 obviously, copyright law&mdash;that duty is even stronger. When the
6834 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6835 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6836 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6837 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6838 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6839 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: <quote>Congress
6840 shall make no law &hellip; abridging the freedom of speech.</quote> So when
6841 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would <quote>abridge</quote> the freedom
6842 of speech, it should ask&mdash; carefully&mdash;whether such
6843 regulation is justified.
6844 </para>
6845 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='endofrange'/>
6846 <indexterm startref='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='endofrange'/>
6847 <para>
6848 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6849 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6850 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6851 <quote>justified.</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6852 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6853 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6854 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6855 </para>
6856 <para>
6857 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6858 </para>
6859 <indexterm id='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='startofrange'><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann</primary></indexterm>
6860 <indexterm id='idxddt' class='startofrange'><primary>DDT</primary></indexterm>
6861 <indexterm id='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='startofrange'><primary>insecticide, environmental consequences of</primary></indexterm>
6862 <indexterm id='idxfarming' class='startofrange'><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6863 <para>
6864 In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss
6865 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6866 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the
6867 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6868 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6869 </para>
6870 <para>
6871 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6872 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6873 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6874 </para>
6875 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6876 <indexterm><primary>Silent Spring (Carson)</primary></indexterm>
6877 <indexterm id='idxenvironmentalism' class='startofrange'><primary>environmentalism</primary></indexterm>
6878 <para>
6879 But in 1962, Rachel Carson published <citetitle>Silent Spring</citetitle>, which argued that
6880 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6881 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6882 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6883 </para>
6884 <para>
6885 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6886 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6887 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6888 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6889 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6890 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6891 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6892 </para>
6893 <indexterm startref='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='endofrange'/>
6894 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James</primary></indexterm>
6895 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovative freedom balanced with fair compensation in</secondary></indexterm>
6896 <para>
6897 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6898 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an <quote>environmentalism</quote> for
6899 culture.<footnote><para>
6900 <!-- f7 -->
6901 See, for example, James Boyle, <quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6902 Environmentalism for the Net?</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal</citetitle> 47 (1997): 87.
6903 </para></footnote>
6904 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6905 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6906 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6907 <quote>for free.</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6908 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6909 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6910 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6911 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6912 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6913 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6914 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6915 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6916 </para>
6917 <indexterm startref='idxfarming' class='endofrange'/>
6918 <para>
6919 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6920 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6921 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6922 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6923 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6924 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6925 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6926 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6927 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6928 </para>
6929 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='endofrange'/>
6930 <para>
6931 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6932 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6933 be lost.
6934 </para>
6935 <indexterm startref='idxddt' class='endofrange'/>
6936 <indexterm startref='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='endofrange'/>
6937 <indexterm startref='idxenvironmentalism' class='endofrange'/>
6938 </section>
6939 <section id="beginnings">
6940 <title>Beginnings</title>
6941 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>on creative property</secondary></indexterm>
6942 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
6943 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
6944 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
6945 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
6946 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>constitutional tradition on</secondary></indexterm>
6947 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
6948 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
6949 <para>
6950 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6951 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of <quote>creative
6952 property</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6953 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6954 </para>
6955 <indexterm id='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>in constitutional Progress Clause</secondary></indexterm>
6956 <para>
6957 The power to establish <quote>creative property</quote> rights is granted to
6958 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6959 odd. Article I, section 8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that:
6960 </para>
6961 <para>
6962 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6963 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6964 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
6965
6966 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
6967 We can call this the <quote>Progress Clause,</quote> for notice what this clause
6968 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
6969 <quote>creative property rights.</quote> It says that Congress has the power
6970 <emphasis>to promote progress</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
6971 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
6972 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
6973 </para>
6974 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
6975 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
6976 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>history of American</secondary></indexterm>
6977 <para>
6978 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
6979 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="founders"/>,
6980 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
6981 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
6982 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
6983 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
6984 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
6985 copyrights extend <quote>to Authors</quote> only.
6986 </para>
6987 <indexterm><primary>Senate, U.S.</primary></indexterm>
6988 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>structural checks and balances of</secondary></indexterm>
6989 <indexterm><primary>electoral college</primary></indexterm>
6990 <para>
6991 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
6992 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
6993 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
6994 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
6995 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
6996 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
6997 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
6998 to reinforce the power of the states&mdash;including the Senate, whose
6999 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
7000 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
7001 case, a <emphasis>structure</emphasis> built checks and balances into
7002 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
7003 concentrations of power.
7004 </para>
7005 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='endofrange'/>
7006 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
7007 <para>
7008 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call <quote>copyright</quote>
7009 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
7010 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
7011 <quote>copyright</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210
7012 years since they first struck its design.
7013 </para>
7014 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='endofrange'/>
7015 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='endofrange'/>
7016 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='endofrange'/>
7017 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
7018 <para>
7019 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
7020 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
7021 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
7022 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
7023 started here:
7024 </para>
7025 <figure id="fig-1441">
7026 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
7027 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
7028 </figure>
7029 <para>
7030 We will end here:
7031 </para>
7032 <figure id="fig-1442">
7033 <title><quote>Copyright</quote> today.</title>
7034 <graphic fileref="images/1442.png"></graphic>
7035 </figure>
7036 <para>
7037 Let me explain how.
7038 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
7039 </para>
7040 </section>
7041 <section id="lawduration">
7042 <title>Law: Duration</title>
7043 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
7044 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7045 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7046 <indexterm><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>common law protections of</secondary></indexterm>
7047 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>balance of U.S. content in</secondary></indexterm>
7048 <para>
7049 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
7050 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
7051 the English had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws
7052 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
7053 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
7054 authorship.<footnote>
7055 <para>
7056 <!-- f8 -->
7057 William W. Crosskey, <citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
7058 the United States</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press, 1953), vol. 1,
7059 485&ndash;86: <quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
7060 Law of the Land,' <emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
7061 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law</emphasis></quote>
7062 (emphasis added).
7063 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.</primary></indexterm>
7064 </para></footnote>
7065 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
7066 States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
7067 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
7068 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
7069 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
7070 domain to reprint and distribute works.
7071 </para>
7072 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
7073 <indexterm id='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>federal vs. state</secondary></indexterm>
7074 <para>
7075 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
7076 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
7077 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
7078 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
7079 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
7080 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
7081 </para>
7082 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
7083 <para>
7084 In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
7085 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
7086 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
7087 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
7088 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
7089 </para>
7090 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='endofrange'/>
7091 <para>
7092 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
7093 ten years of the Republic, only 5 percent of the works were actually
7094 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
7095 in the United States both before 1790 and from 1790 through 1800, 95
7096 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
7097 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
7098 likely within fourteen years.<footnote><para>
7099 <!-- f9 -->
7100 Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790
7101 to 1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, <citetitle>A
7102 History of Book Publishing in the United States</citetitle>, vol. 1, <citetitle>The Creation
7103 of an Industry, 1630&ndash;1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000
7104 imprints recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
7105 1790 act; William J. Maher, <citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
7106 and the Copyright Law of 1790 in Historical Context</citetitle>, 7&ndash;10 (2002),
7107 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
7108 #25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
7109 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
7110 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
7111 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
7112 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
7113 Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124. </para></footnote>
7114 </para>
7115 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact' class='endofrange'/>
7116 <indexterm startref='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='endofrange'/>
7117 <para>
7118 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
7119 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
7120 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
7121 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
7122 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
7123 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
7124 copyright, either.
7125 </para>
7126 <para>
7127 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
7128 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
7129 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
7130 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
7131 domain.<footnote><para>
7132 <!-- f10 -->
7133 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
7134 instance, of the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were
7135 renewed in 1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
7136 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, <quote>Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright,</quote>
7137 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright</citetitle>, vol. 1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
7138 1963), 618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
7139 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote>
7140 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 471, 498&ndash;501, and
7141 accompanying figures. </para></footnote>
7142 </para>
7143 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='endofrange'/>
7144 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
7145 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
7146 <para>
7147 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
7148 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
7149 out of print after one year.<footnote><para>
7150 <!-- f11 -->
7151 See Ringer, ch. 9, n. 2. </para></footnote> When that happens, the
7152 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
7153 no longer <emphasis>effectively</emphasis> controlled by
7154 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
7155 is to sell the books as used books; that use&mdash;because it does not
7156 involve publication&mdash;is effectively free.
7157 </para>
7158 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7159 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
7160 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
7161 <para>
7162 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
7163 changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28
7164 years to a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
7165 from 14 years to 28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
7166 the term increased once again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal
7167 term of 14 years to 28 years, setting a maximum term of 56 years.
7168 </para>
7169 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7170 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
7171 <para>
7172 Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
7173 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
7174 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
7175 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
7176 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
7177 In 1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
7178 And in 1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
7179 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
7180 </para>
7181 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
7182 <para>
7183 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
7184 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
7185 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
7186 years, or 70 percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years
7187
7188 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
7189 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
7190 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
7191 of the expiration of a copyright term.
7192 </para>
7193 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='endofrange'/>
7194 <para>
7195 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
7196 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
7197 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
7198 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
7199 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
7200 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
7201 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
7202 value.
7203 </para>
7204 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7205 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>of natural authors vs. corporations</secondary></indexterm>
7206 <indexterm><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>copyright terms for</secondary></indexterm>
7207 <para>
7208 The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For
7209 all works created after 1978, there was only one copyright term&mdash;the
7210 maximum term. For <quote>natural</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
7211 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992,
7212 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
7213 before 1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
7214 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
7215 was ninety-five years.
7216 </para>
7217 <para>
7218 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
7219 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
7220 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
7221 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
7222 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
7223 that terms be <quote>limited,</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
7224 them.
7225 </para>
7226 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='endofrange'/>
7227 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
7228 <para>
7229 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
7230 dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to
7231 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
7232 in 1973 was just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
7233 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
7234 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95
7235 years.<footnote><para>
7236 <!-- f12 -->
7237 These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the
7238 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
7239 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
7240 Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote> loc. cit.
7241 </para></footnote>
7242 </para>
7243 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='endofrange'/>
7244 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='endofrange'/>
7245 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='endofrange'/>
7246 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='endofrange'/>
7247 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='endofrange'/>
7248 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
7249 </section>
7250 <section id="lawscope">
7251 <title>Law: Scope</title>
7252 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7253 <para>
7254 The <quote>scope</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
7255 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
7256 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
7257 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
7258 </para>
7259 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7260 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>historical shift in copyright coverage of</secondary></indexterm>
7261 <para>
7262 In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only <quote>maps,
7263 charts, and books.</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
7264 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
7265 the author the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> copyrighted works. That
7266 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
7267 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
7268 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
7269 did not extend to what lawyers call <quote>derivative works.</quote> It would not,
7270 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
7271 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
7272 (such as a drama based on a published book).
7273 </para>
7274 <para>
7275 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
7276 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
7277 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
7278 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
7279 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
7280 work not only the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> the work, but also the
7281 exclusive right of control over any <quote>copies</quote> of that work. And most
7282 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
7283 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
7284 <quote>derivative work</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
7285 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
7286 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
7287 on the initial creative work.
7288 </para>
7289 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>marking of</secondary></indexterm>
7290 <indexterm id='idxformalities' class='startofrange'><primary>formalities</primary></indexterm>
7291 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>registration requirement of</secondary></indexterm>
7292 <para>
7293 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
7294 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
7295 complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition
7296 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
7297 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
7298 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
7299 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
7300 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
7301 famous &copy; or the word <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>. And for most
7302 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
7303 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
7304 secured.
7305 </para>
7306 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='endofrange'/>
7307 <para>
7308 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
7309 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
7310 in the first ten years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible
7311 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
7312 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
7313 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
7314 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
7315 copyrighted&mdash;that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
7316 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
7317 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
7318 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
7319 original author.
7320 </para>
7321 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>European</secondary></indexterm>
7322 <para>
7323 All of these <quote>formalities</quote> were abolished in the American system when
7324 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
7325 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
7326 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
7327 a &copy;; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
7328 copy available for others to copy.
7329 </para>
7330 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='endofrange'/>
7331 <indexterm startref='idxformalities' class='endofrange'/>
7332 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='endofrange'/>
7333 <para>
7334 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
7335 differences.
7336 </para>
7337 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact2' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7338 <para>
7339 If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who
7340 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
7341 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
7342 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
7343 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were
7344 174 publishers in the United States.<footnote><para>
7345 <!-- f13 -->
7346 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, <quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
7347 Creation of American Literature,</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
7348 International Law and Politics</citetitle> 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
7349 Federal Copyright Records, 1790&ndash;1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987).
7350
7351 </para></footnote>
7352 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
7353 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
7354 the United States&mdash;publishers.
7355 </para>
7356 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7357 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7358 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7359 <para>
7360 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
7361 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
7362 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
7363 was totally unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and made
7364 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
7365 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
7366 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
7367 were restrained.
7368 </para>
7369 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact2' class='endofrange'/>
7370 <para>
7371 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
7372 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
7373 every note to your spouse, every doodle, <emphasis>every</emphasis>
7374 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form&mdash;all of this is
7375 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
7376 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
7377 protect it.
7378 </para>
7379 <para>
7380 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
7381 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
7382 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
7383 </para>
7384 <para>
7385 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
7386 control
7387 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
7388 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of <quote>derivative
7389 rights.</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
7390 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
7391 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
7392 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
7393 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
7394 exclusive
7395 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
7396 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
7397 </para>
7398 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7399 <para>
7400 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
7401 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
7402 expansion
7403 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
7404 copyright.
7405 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
7406 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
7407 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
7408 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
7409 </para>
7410 <para>
7411 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
7412 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
7413 within a free culture&mdash;at least, it's astonishing when you
7414 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
7415 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
7416 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
7417 <emphasis>that</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
7418 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
7419 all&mdash;they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
7420 not protect derivative rights at all.<footnote><para>
7421 <!-- f14 -->
7422 Jonathan Zittrain, <quote>The Copyright Cage,</quote> <citetitle>Legal
7423 Affairs</citetitle>, July/August 2003, available at
7424 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #26</ulink>.
7425 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
7426 </para></footnote>
7427 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
7428 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7429 the wrong of direct piracy.
7430 </para>
7431 <para>
7432 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7433 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7434 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7435 of my book.<footnote><para>
7436 <!-- f15 -->
7437 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7438 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7439 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere <quote>copies</quote> and
7440 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld, <quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7441 Copyright's Constitutionality,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7442 Journal</citetitle> 112 (2002): 1&ndash;60 (see especially
7443 pp. 53&ndash;59).
7444 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb</primary></indexterm>
7445 </para></footnote>
7446 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7447 </para>
7448 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7449 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
7450 <indexterm><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
7451 <para>
7452 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7453 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7454 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7455 called <quote>Mickey Mouse,</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7456 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7457 created?
7458 </para>
7459 <para>
7460 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7461 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7462 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7463 the rights originally granted.
7464 </para>
7465 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7466 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='endofrange'/>
7467 </section>
7468 <section id="lawreach">
7469 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach</title>
7470 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7471 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7472 <para>
7473 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7474 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7475 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7476 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.<footnote><para>
7477 <!-- f16 -->
7478 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7479 certainly regulates more than <quote>copies</quote>&mdash;a public performance of a
7480 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7481 per se doesn't make a copy; 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7482 106(4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a <quote>copy</quote>; 17
7483 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section 112(a). But the presumption under the
7484 existing law (which regulates <quote>copies;</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7485 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7486 </para></footnote>
7487 </para>
7488 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
7489 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>other property rights vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7490 <para>
7491 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7492 <quote>Copies.</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7493 <emphasis>copy</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7494 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that <quote>creative
7495 property</quote> deserves the <quote>same rights</quote> as all other property, it is the
7496 <emphasis>obvious</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7497 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7498 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7499 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7500 copies should <emphasis>not</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7501 law. More precisely, they should not <emphasis>always</emphasis> be
7502 the trigger for copyright law.
7503 </para>
7504 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='endofrange'/>
7505 <para>
7506 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7507 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7508 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7509 the law of copyright automatically applies,<footnote><para>
7510 <!-- f17 -->
7511 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7512 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7513 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7514 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7515 technology.
7516 </para></footnote>
7517 because it is clear that the
7518 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7519 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7520 </para>
7521 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7522 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='endofrange'/>
7523 <para>
7524 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7525 empty circle.
7526 </para>
7527 <figure id="fig-1521">
7528 <title>All potential uses of a book.</title>
7529 <graphic fileref="images/1521.png"></graphic>
7530 </figure>
7531 <indexterm id='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>three types of uses of</secondary></indexterm>
7532 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7533 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright applicability altered by technology of</secondary></indexterm>
7534 <indexterm id='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='startofrange'><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright intent altered by</secondary></indexterm>
7535 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7536 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7537 <para>
7538 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7539 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7540 all its potential <emphasis>uses</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7541 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7542 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7543 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7544 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7545 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7546 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7547 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7548 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7549 acts do not make a copy.
7550 </para>
7551 <figure id="fig-1531">
7552 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.</title>
7553 <graphic fileref="images/1531.png"></graphic>
7554 </figure>
7555 <para>
7556 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7557 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7558 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7559 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7560 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see first
7561 diagram on next page).
7562 </para>
7563 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7564 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7565 <indexterm id='idxfairuse' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary></indexterm>
7566 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7567 <para>
7568 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7569 that remain unregulated because the law considers these <quote>fair uses.</quote>
7570 </para>
7571 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7572 <figure id="fig-1541">
7573 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.</title>
7574 <graphic fileref="images/1541.png"></graphic>
7575 </figure>
7576 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
7577 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
7578 <para>
7579 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7580 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7581 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7582 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7583 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7584 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7585 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such <quote>fair uses</quote>
7586 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7587 </para>
7588 <figure id="fig-1542">
7589 <title>Unregulated copying considered <quote>fair uses.</quote></title>
7590 <graphic fileref="images/1542.png"></graphic>
7591 </figure>
7592 <para> </para>
7593 <figure id="fig-1551">
7594 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.</title>
7595 <graphic fileref="images/1551.png"></graphic>
7596 </figure>
7597 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7598 <para>
7599 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7600 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7601 sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that
7602 are nonetheless deemed <quote>fair</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7603 </para>
7604 <indexterm startref='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='endofrange'/>
7605 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7606 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
7607 <indexterm><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7608 <para>
7609 Enter the Internet&mdash;a distributed, digital network where every use
7610 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.<footnote><para>
7611 <!-- f18 -->
7612 I don't mean <quote>nature</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7613 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7614 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7615 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7616 of copies remain.
7617 </para></footnote>
7618 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7619 digital network, the scope of category 1 changes dramatically. Uses
7620 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7621 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7622 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7623 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7624 a copy&mdash;category 1 gets sucked into category 2. And those who
7625 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7626 exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7627 shift.
7628 </para>
7629 <indexterm startref='idxfairuse' class='endofrange'/>
7630 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='endofrange'/>
7631 <para>
7632 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7633 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7634 be no plausible <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>-related argument that
7635 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7636 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7637 the book once, ten times, or every
7638 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7639 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7640 use&mdash;reading&mdash; could be regulated by copyright law because
7641 none of those uses produced a copy.
7642 </para>
7643 <indexterm id='idxebooks' class='startofrange'><primary>e-books</primary></indexterm>
7644 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>technological developments and</secondary></indexterm>
7645 <para>
7646 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7647 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7648 only once or only once a month, then <emphasis>copyright
7649 law</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7650 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7651 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7652 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7653 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7654 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7655 copyright owner's wish.
7656 </para>
7657 <para>
7658 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7659 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7660 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7661 points also become clear:
7662 </para>
7663 <para>
7664 First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7665 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7666 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7667 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7668 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7669 part of free culture before the Internet.
7670 </para>
7671 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7672 <para>
7673 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7674 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7675 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7676 <emphasis>any</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7677 using a machine. <quote>Copy and paste</quote> and <quote>cut and paste</quote> become
7678 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7679 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7680 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7681 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7682 creative work.
7683 </para>
7684 <indexterm id='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7685 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7686 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>fair use vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7687 <para>
7688 Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary
7689
7690 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7691 burden on category 3 (<quote>fair use</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7692 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7693 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7694 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7695 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7696 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7697 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7698 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7699 regulated.
7700 </para>
7701 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='endofrange'/>
7702 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='endofrange'/>
7703 <indexterm startref='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='endofrange'/>
7704 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='endofrange'/>
7705 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='endofrange'/>
7706 <para>
7707 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7708 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7709 depend upon fair use&mdash;never even addressing the earlier question
7710 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7711 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7712 <emphasis>unregulated</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7713 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7714 enough.
7715 </para>
7716 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='endofrange'/>
7717 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'/>
7718 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson2' class='endofrange'/>
7719 <indexterm startref='idxebooks' class='endofrange'/>
7720 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='endofrange'/>
7721 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='endofrange'/>
7722 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='endofrange'/>
7723 <indexterm id='idxvideopipeline' class='startofrange'><primary>Video Pipeline</primary></indexterm>
7724 <indexterm id='idxadvertising' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
7725 <indexterm id='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='startofrange'><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>trailer advertisements of</secondary></indexterm>
7726 <para>
7727 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7728 in the business of making <quote>trailer</quote> advertisements for movies available
7729 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7730 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7731 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7732 </para>
7733 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7734 <para>
7735 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it began
7736 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7737 previews. The idea was to expand their <quote>selling by sampling</quote>
7738 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7739 <quote>browsing.</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7740 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7741 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7742 </para>
7743 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
7744 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7745 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7746 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
7747 <para>
7748 In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7749 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7750 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7751 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7752 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7753 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter&mdash;he had built a
7754 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7755 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7756 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7757 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7758 <quote>fair use</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7759 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7760 their rights.
7761 </para>
7762 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising' class='endofrange'/>
7763 <indexterm startref='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='endofrange'/>
7764 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7765 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>willful infringement findings in</secondary></indexterm>
7766 <indexterm><primary>willful infringement</primary></indexterm>
7767 <para>
7768 Disney countersued&mdash;for $100 million in damages. Those damages
7769 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had <quote>willfully
7770 infringed</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7771 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7772 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7773 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7774 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7775 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $100 million.
7776 </para>
7777 <para>
7778 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7779 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7780 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7781 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7782 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7783 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7784 Disney's permission.
7785 </para>
7786 <indexterm><primary>first-sale doctrine</primary></indexterm>
7787 <para>
7788 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7789 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7790 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7791 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7792 was in the marketplace, the <quote>first-sale doctrine</quote> would free the
7793 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7794 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7795 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7796 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7797 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7798 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7799 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7800 </para>
7801 <indexterm startref='idxvideopipeline' class='endofrange'/>
7802 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc2' class='endofrange'/>
7803 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='endofrange'/>
7804 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='endofrange'/>
7805 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='endofrange'/>
7806 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='endofrange'/>
7807 <indexterm><primary>Barnes &amp; Noble</primary></indexterm>
7808 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7809 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
7810 <para>
7811 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7812 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7813 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes &amp; Noble has the
7814 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7815 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7816 abuse. If Barnes &amp; Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7817 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7818 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7819 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7820 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7821 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7822 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7823 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7824 happening are quite slight.
7825 </para>
7826 <para>
7827 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7828 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7829 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7830 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7831 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7832 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7833 </para>
7834 </section>
7835 <section id="lawforce">
7836 <title>Architecture and Law: Force</title>
7837 <para>
7838 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7839 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7840 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7841 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7842 </para>
7843 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>technology as automatic enforcer of</secondary></indexterm>
7844 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright enforcement controlled by</secondary></indexterm>
7845 <para>
7846 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7847 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7848 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7849 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7850 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7851 your freedom.
7852 </para>
7853 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca</primary></indexterm>
7854 <indexterm id='idxmarxbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7855 <indexterm id='idxwarnerbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7856 <para>
7857 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7858 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7859 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7860 <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7861 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7862 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7863 plan.<footnote><para>
7864 <!-- f19 -->
7865 See David Lange, <quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7866 Contemporary Problems</citetitle> 44 (1981): 172&ndash;73.
7867 </para></footnote>
7868 </para>
7869 <para>
7870 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7871 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers <quote>were brothers long before
7872 you were.</quote><footnote><para>
7873 <!-- f20 -->
7874 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
7875 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and
7876 Copywrongs</citetitle>, 1&ndash;3.
7877 </para></footnote>
7878 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7879 <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7880 trying to control <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>, then the Marx
7881 Brothers would insist on control over <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>.
7882 </para>
7883 <para>
7884 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7885 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7886 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7887 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7888 </para>
7889 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7890 <para>
7891 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7892 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7893 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7894 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7895 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7896 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7897 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7898 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7899 </para>
7900 <indexterm startref='idxwarnerbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7901 <indexterm startref='idxmarxbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7902
7903 <indexterm id='idxadobeebookreader' class='startofrange'><primary>Adobe eBook Reader</primary></indexterm>
7904 <para>
7905 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7906 </para>
7907 <para>
7908 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7909 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7910 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7911 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7912 technology.
7913 </para>
7914 <para>
7915 On the next page is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook
7916 Reader.
7917 </para>
7918 <para>
7919 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7920 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7921 public domain: <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, for example, is in
7922 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7923 public domain: My own book <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
7924 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7925 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7926 copy of
7927 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7928 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7929 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
7930 </para>
7931 <figure id="fig-1611">
7932 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader</title>
7933 <graphic fileref="images/1611.png"></graphic>
7934 </figure>
7935 <para>
7936 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7937 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7938 </para>
7939 <figure id="fig-1612">
7940 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.</title>
7941 <graphic fileref="images/1612.png"></graphic>
7942 </figure>
7943 <para>
7944 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7945 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
7946 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
7947 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
7948 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
7949 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>
7950 read aloud through the computer.
7951 </para>
7952 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle</primary></indexterm>
7953 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics</citetitle>, (Aristotle)</primary></indexterm>
7954 <para>
7955 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7956 translation): Aristotle's <citetitle>Politics</citetitle>.
7957 </para>
7958 <figure id="fig-1621">
7959 <title>E-book of Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote></title>
7960 <graphic fileref="images/1621.png"></graphic>
7961 </figure>
7962 <para>
7963 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7964 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
7965 the book.
7966 </para>
7967 <figure id="fig-1622">
7968 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote>.</title>
7969 <graphic fileref="images/1622.png"></graphic>
7970 </figure>
7971 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
7972 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
7973 <para>
7974 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
7975 original e-book version of my last book, <citetitle>The Future of
7976 Ideas</citetitle>:
7977 </para>
7978 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
7979 <figure id="fig-1631">
7980 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>The Future of Ideas</quote>.</title>
7981 <graphic fileref="images/1631.png"></graphic>
7982 </figure>
7983 <para>
7984 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
7985 </para>
7986 <para>
7987 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
7988 <quote>permissions</quote>&mdash; as if the publisher has the power to control how
7989 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
7990 certainly does have the power&mdash;up to the limits of the copyright
7991 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
7992 power.<footnote><para>
7993 <!-- f21 -->
7994 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
7995 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
7996 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
7997 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
7998 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
7999 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
8000 subsequently acquired the book.
8001 </para></footnote>
8002 When my e-book of <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> says I have the
8003 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
8004 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
8005 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
8006 control that the law would enable.
8007 </para>
8008 <para>
8009 The control comes instead from the code&mdash;from the technology
8010 within which the e-book <quote>lives.</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
8011 permissions, they are not the sort of <quote>permissions</quote> that most of us
8012 deal with. When a teenager gets <quote>permission</quote> to stay out till
8013 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
8014 till 2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
8015 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
8016 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
8017 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
8018 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
8019 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
8020 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
8021 aloud&mdash;it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
8022 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
8023 won't read aloud.
8024 </para>
8025 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8026 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8027 <para>
8028 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
8029 These are <emphasis>controls</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
8030 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
8031 you tried to type <quote>Warner Brothers,</quote> erased <quote>Brothers</quote> from the
8032 sentence.
8033 </para>
8034 <para>
8035 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
8036 <emphasis>law</emphasis> as copyright <emphasis>code</emphasis>. The
8037 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
8038 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
8039 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
8040 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
8041 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
8042 </para>
8043 <para>
8044 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
8045 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
8046 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
8047 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
8048 to defeat these protections as well?
8049 </para>
8050 <para>
8051 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
8052 eBook Reader.
8053 </para>
8054 <indexterm id='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='startofrange'><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)</primary></indexterm>
8055 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>e-book restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
8056 <para>
8057 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
8058 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
8059 on the Adobe site was a copy of <citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
8060 Wonderland</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
8061 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
8062 following report:
8063 </para>
8064 <figure id="fig-1641">
8065 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>Alice's Adventures in
8066 Wonderland</quote>.</title>
8067 <graphic fileref="images/1641.png"></graphic>
8068 </figure>
8069 <!-- PAGE BREAK 164-->
8070 <para>
8071 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
8072 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
8073 <quote>permissions</quote> indicated, not allowed to <quote>read aloud</quote>!
8074 </para>
8075 <para>
8076 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
8077 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
8078 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
8079 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
8080 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
8081 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
8082 </para>
8083 <para>
8084 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
8085 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
8086 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
8087 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
8088 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
8089 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
8090 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
8091 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
8092 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
8093 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
8094 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
8095 </para>
8096 <indexterm startref='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='endofrange'/>
8097 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='endofrange'/>
8098 <para>
8099 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
8100 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
8101 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
8102 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
8103 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
8104 often crazy.
8105 </para>
8106 <indexterm startref='idxadobeebookreader' class='endofrange'/>
8107 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet2' class='endofrange'/>
8108 <para>
8109 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
8110 story of mine that makes the same point.
8111 </para>
8112 <indexterm id='idxaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8113 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog1' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8114 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8115 <para>
8116 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named <quote>Aibo.</quote> The Aibo
8117 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
8118 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
8119 </para>
8120 <para>
8121 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
8122 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
8123 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
8124 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
8125 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
8126 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
8127 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
8128 </para>
8129 <para>
8130 <quote>Teach</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
8131 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
8132 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
8133 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
8134 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
8135 their computer <quote>dog</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
8136 </para>
8137 <indexterm><primary>hacks</primary></indexterm>
8138 <para>
8139 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
8140 <citetitle>hack</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
8141 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
8142 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
8143 them, <citetitle>hack</citetitle> is a much more positive
8144 term. <citetitle>Hack</citetitle> just means code that enables the
8145 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
8146 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
8147 old computer doesn't run, or <quote>drive,</quote> the printer. If you discovered
8148 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
8149 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
8150 you just bought.
8151 </para>
8152 <para>
8153 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
8154 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
8155 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
8156 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
8157 ethically.
8158 </para>
8159 <para>
8160 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
8161 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
8162 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
8163 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
8164 than Sony had built.
8165 </para>
8166 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8167 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog1' class='endofrange'/>
8168 <indexterm startref='idxaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8169 <para>
8170 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
8171 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
8172 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
8173 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
8174 the
8175
8176 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
8177 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
8178 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
8179 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
8180 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
8181 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
8182 thought, <emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
8183 a robot dog to dance?</emphasis>
8184 </para>
8185 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>government case against</secondary></indexterm>
8186 <para>
8187 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show&mdash;
8188 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
8189 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
8190 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
8191 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
8192 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
8193 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
8194 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
8195 into being silent about something he knew very well.
8196 </para>
8197 <para>
8198 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.<footnote><para>
8199 <!-- f22 -->
8200 See Pamela Samuelson, <quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,</quote>
8201 <citetitle>Science</citetitle> 293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, <quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
8202 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect</citetitle>,
8203 January 2002; <quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
8204 DMCA,</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter</citetitle>, 11 December 2001; Bill
8205 Holland, <quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,</quote> <citetitle>Billboard</citetitle>,
8206 May 2001; Janelle Brown, <quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?</quote> Salon.com,
8207 April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, <quote>Frequently Asked
8208 Questions about <citetitle>Felten and USENIX</citetitle> v. <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> Legal Case,</quote> available at
8209 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #27</ulink>.
8210 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
8211 </para></footnote>
8212 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
8213 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
8214 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
8215 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
8216 </para>
8217 <para>
8218 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
8219 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
8220 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
8221 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
8222 <quote>this music cannot be copied,</quote> and have a computer respect that
8223 command. The technology was to be part of a <quote>trusted system</quote> of
8224 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
8225 Internet much more.
8226 </para>
8227 <para>
8228 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
8229 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
8230 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
8231 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
8232 </para>
8233 <para>
8234 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
8235 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
8236 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
8237 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
8238 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
8239 </para>
8240 <para>
8241 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
8242 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
8243 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
8244 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
8245 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
8246 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
8247 </para>
8248 <para>
8249 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
8250 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
8251 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
8252 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
8253 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
8254 constituted, succeed.
8255 </para>
8256 <indexterm id='idxaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8257 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog2' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8258 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8259 <para>
8260 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
8261 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
8262 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
8263 wrote:
8264 </para>
8265 <blockquote>
8266 <para>
8267 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
8268 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
8269 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
8270 </para>
8271 </blockquote>
8272 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8273 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog2' class='endofrange'/>
8274 <indexterm startref='idxaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8275 <para>
8276 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
8277 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
8278 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
8279 </para>
8280 <blockquote>
8281 <para>
8282 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
8283 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
8284 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
8285 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
8286 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (<quote>DMCA</quote>).
8287 </para>
8288 </blockquote>
8289 <para>
8290 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
8291 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
8292 spreading such information an offense.
8293 </para>
8294 <para>
8295 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
8296 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
8297 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
8298 These new technologies would be copyright protection
8299 technologies&mdash; technologies to control the replication and
8300 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
8301 <emphasis>code</emphasis> to modify the original
8302 <emphasis>code</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
8303 protection for copyright owners.
8304 </para>
8305 <para>
8306 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
8307 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
8308 <emphasis>legal code</emphasis> intended to buttress
8309 <emphasis>software code</emphasis> which itself was intended to
8310 support the <emphasis>legal code of copyright</emphasis>.
8311 </para>
8312 <para>
8313 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
8314 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
8315 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
8316 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
8317 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
8318 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
8319 have been a copyright violation.
8320 </para>
8321 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8322 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8323 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8324 <para>
8325 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
8326 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
8327 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
8328 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
8329 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
8330 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
8331 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
8332 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
8333 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
8334 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
8335 </para>
8336 <para>
8337 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
8338 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
8339 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
8340 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
8341 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
8342 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
8343 </para>
8344 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8345 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8346 <para>
8347 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
8348 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
8349 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
8350 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
8351 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
8352 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka <quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers</citetitle>,</quote>
8353 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
8354 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
8355 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8356 </para>
8357 <blockquote>
8358 <para>
8359 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
8360 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
8361 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
8362 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
8363 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
8364 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the <quote>Neighborhood</quote>
8365 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
8366 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
8367 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
8368 broadcasting has always been <quote>You are an important person just the way
8369 you are. You can make healthy decisions.</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
8370 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
8371 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
8372 important.<footnote><para>
8373 <!-- f23 -->
8374 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8375 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
8376 455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
8377 James Lardner, <citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
8378 the VCR</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270&ndash;71.
8379 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8380 </para></footnote>
8381 </para>
8382 </blockquote>
8383 <para>
8384 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
8385 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
8386 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
8387 the VCR responsible.
8388 </para>
8389 <para>
8390 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
8391 the DMCA.
8392 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8393 </para>
8394 <para>
8395 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
8396 </para>
8397 <para>
8398 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
8399 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
8400 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
8401 pirating of copyrighted material&mdash;a bad end. Or they can be used
8402 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
8403 would be considered fair use&mdash;a good end.
8404 </para>
8405 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'><primary>handguns</primary></indexterm>
8406 <para>
8407 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
8408 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
8409 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
8410 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
8411 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
8412 and bad uses.
8413 </para>
8414 <figure id="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig">
8415 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.</title>
8416 <graphic fileref="images/1711.png"></graphic>
8417 </figure>
8418 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8419 <para>
8420 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
8421 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
8422 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: <emphasis>No one ever
8423 died from copyright circumvention</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
8424 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
8425 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
8426 </para>
8427 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'/>
8428 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'/>
8429 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8430 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8431 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8432 <para>
8433 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
8434 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
8435 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
8436 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
8437 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
8438 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
8439 </para>
8440 <para>
8441 This is how <emphasis>code</emphasis> becomes
8442 <emphasis>law</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
8443 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
8444 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
8445 law&mdash;increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
8446 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
8447 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
8448 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect&mdash;at
8449 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
8450 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
8451 </para>
8452 <para>
8453 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
8454 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
8455 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
8456 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
8457 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
8458 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
8459 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
8460 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
8461 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
8462 </para>
8463 <para>
8464
8465 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
8466 For example, imagine you were part of a <citetitle>Star Trek</citetitle> fan club. You
8467 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
8468 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
8469 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
8470 simply continue it.<footnote><para>
8471 <!-- f24 -->
8472 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, <quote>Legal Fictions,
8473 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
8474 Entertainment Law Journal</citetitle> 17 (1997): 651.
8475 </para></footnote>
8476 </para>
8477 <para>
8478 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
8479 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
8480 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
8481 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
8482 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
8483 </para>
8484 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
8485 <para>
8486 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
8487 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
8488 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
8489 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
8490 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
8491 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
8492 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
8493 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
8494 </para>
8495 <para>
8496 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
8497 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
8498 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
8499 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8500 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8501 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8502 </para>
8503 </section>
8504 <section id="marketconcentration">
8505 <title>Market: Concentration</title>
8506 <para>
8507 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically&mdash;tripled in
8508 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8509 well&mdash;from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8510 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8511 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8512 find better ways
8513 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8514 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8515 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8516 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8517 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8518 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8519 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8520 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8521 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8522 control.
8523 </para>
8524 <para>
8525 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8526 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8527 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8528 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8529 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8530 </para>
8531 <para>
8532 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8533 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8534 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8535 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8536 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8537 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8538 announced in June 2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8539 live in a world where just three companies control more than percent
8540 of the media.
8541 </para>
8542 <para>
8543 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8544 nature.
8545 </para>
8546 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8547 <indexterm><primary>BMG</primary></indexterm>
8548 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
8549 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John</primary></indexterm>
8550 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8551 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8552 <para>
8553 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8554 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8555 ownership, <quote>five companies control 85 percent of our media sources.</quote><footnote><para>
8556 <!-- f25 -->
8557 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8558 Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003)
8559 (statement of Senator John McCain). </para></footnote>
8560 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8561 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 percent of the
8562 U.S. music market.<footnote><para>
8563 <!-- f26 -->
8564 Lynette Holloway, <quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8565 Slide,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 23 December 2002.
8566 </para></footnote>
8567 The <quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8568 programming to 74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.</quote><footnote><para>
8569 <!-- f27 -->
8570 Molly Ivins, <quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette</citetitle>,
8571 31 May 2003.
8572 </para></footnote>
8573 </para>
8574 <para>
8575 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8576 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8577 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8578 seventy-five stations. Today <emphasis>one</emphasis> company owns
8579 more than 1,200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8580 total number of radio owners dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most
8581 markets, the two largest broadcasters control 74 percent of that
8582 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control 90 percent of
8583 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8584 </para>
8585 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8586 <para>
8587 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8588 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8589 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8590 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8591 the United States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all
8592 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent
8593 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8594 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8595 protected&mdash; by the market.
8596 </para>
8597 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8598 <para>
8599 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8600 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8601 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8602 </para>
8603 <blockquote>
8604 <para>
8605 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8606 unmatched in its integration. They supply content&mdash;Fox movies
8607 &hellip; Fox TV shows &hellip; Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8608 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8609 advertisers&mdash;in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8610 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8611 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8612 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8613 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8614 the same function in the United States.<footnote><para>
8615 <!-- f28 -->
8616 James Fallows, <quote>The Age of Murdoch,</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly</citetitle> (September
8617 2003): 89.
8618 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8619 </para></footnote>
8620 </para>
8621 </blockquote>
8622 <para>
8623 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8624 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8625 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8626 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8627 </para>
8628 <figure id="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership">
8629 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.</title>
8630 <graphic fileref="images/1761.png"></graphic>
8631 </figure>
8632 <para>
8633 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8634 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8635 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8636 distribute content?
8637 </para>
8638 <para>
8639 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8640 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8641 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8642 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8643 </para>
8644 <para>
8645 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8646 integration may matter.
8647 </para>
8648 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman</primary></indexterm>
8649 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8650 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8651 <para>
8652 In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle>. He took
8653 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8654 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8655 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8656 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8657 </para>
8658 <para>
8659 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8660 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8661 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8662 control.<footnote><para>
8663 <!-- f29 -->
8664 Leonard Hill, <quote>The Axis of Access,</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8665 Forum, <quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,</quote> St. Louis,
8666 Missouri, 3 April 2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8667 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #28</ulink>;
8668 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8669 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #29</ulink>).
8670 </para></footnote>
8671 </para>
8672 <para>
8673
8674 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8675 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8676 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8677 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8678 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992,
8679 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8680 television&mdash;75 percent of it&mdash;was <quote>independent</quote> of the
8681 networks.
8682 </para>
8683 <para>
8684 In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8685 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985,
8686 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8687 2002, only five independent television studios remained. <quote>In 1992,
8688 only 15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8689 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8690 controlled companies more than quintupled to 77 percent.</quote> <quote>In 1992, 16
8691 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8692 year there was one.</quote><footnote><para>
8693 <!-- f30 -->
8694 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8695 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st
8696 sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8697 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8698 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8699 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8700 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February
8701 2003.
8702 </para></footnote>
8703 In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8704 that ran it. <quote>In the ten-year period between 1992 and 2002, the number
8705 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8706 increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8707 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8708 63%.</quote><footnote><para>
8709 <!-- f31 -->
8710 Ibid.
8711 </para></footnote>
8712 </para>
8713 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8714 <para>
8715 Today, another Norman Lear with another <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle> would
8716 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8717 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8718 owned by the network.
8719 </para>
8720 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry</primary></indexterm>
8721 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill</primary></indexterm>
8722 <para>
8723 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8724 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8725 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8726 </para>
8727 <blockquote>
8728 <para>
8729 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8730 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8731 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8732 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8733 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8734 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8735 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8736 handful.<footnote><para>
8737 <!-- f32 -->
8738 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers</citetitle>, Bill
8739 Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at
8740 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #31</ulink>.
8741 </para></footnote>
8742 </para>
8743 </blockquote>
8744 <para>
8745 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8746 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8747 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8748 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8749 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8750 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8751 question without risk of consequence&mdash;not necessarily banishment
8752 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8753 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8754 democracy.
8755 </para>
8756 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.</primary></indexterm>
8757 <para>
8758 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8759 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the <quote>Innovator's
8760 Dilemma</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8761 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8762 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8763 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.<footnote><para>
8764 <!-- f33 -->
8765 Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8766 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle>
8767 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press, 1997). Christensen
8768 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8769 Kim B. Clark, <quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8770 Concepts in Technological Evolution,</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy</citetitle> 14 (1985):
8771 235&ndash;51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8772 Kaplan, <citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8773 Underperform the Market&mdash;and How to Successfully Transform Them</citetitle>
8774 (New York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001). </para></footnote>
8775
8776 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8777 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8778 sprinting.
8779 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
8780 </para>
8781 <para>
8782 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8783 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8784 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8785 measure.
8786 </para>
8787 <para>
8788 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8789 suggest the concern.
8790 </para>
8791 <para>
8792 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8793 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8794 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8795 </para>
8796 <para>
8797 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8798 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8799 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8800
8801 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8802 wrecked by drugs&mdash;though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8803 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8804 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8805 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8806 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8807 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8808 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8809 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8810 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8811 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8812 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8813 outweigh these costs.
8814 </para>
8815 <para>
8816 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8817 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8818 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8819 these issues.
8820 </para>
8821 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8822 <para>
8823 Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8824 a media campaign as part of the <quote>war on drugs.</quote> The campaign produced
8825 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8826 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8827 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8828 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8829 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8830 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8831 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8832 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8833 </para>
8834 <para>
8835 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8836 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8837 </para>
8838 <para>
8839 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8840 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8841 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8842 war. Can you do it?
8843 </para>
8844 <para>
8845 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8846 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8847 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8848 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8849 message will be heard then?
8850 </para>
8851 <para>
8852 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8853 <quote>controversial</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8854 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8855 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8856 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8857 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8858 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8859 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8860 rights of the stations to be this biased.<footnote><para>
8861 <!-- f34 -->
8862 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8863 <indexterm><primary>Comcast</primary></indexterm>
8864 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project</primary></indexterm>
8865 <indexterm><primary>NBC</primary></indexterm>
8866 <indexterm><primary>WJOA</primary></indexterm>
8867 <indexterm><primary>WRC</primary></indexterm>
8868 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8869 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads
8870 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8871 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as <quote>against
8872 [their] policy.</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8873 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8874 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8875 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8876 Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8877 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, <quote>On the Issue of
8878 an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV Networks,</quote> <citetitle>New
8879 York Times</citetitle>, 13 March 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time
8880 there is very little that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to
8881 even the playing field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, <quote>Ad
8882 Hoc Access: The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8883 Radio,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review</citetitle> 6 (1988): 449&ndash;79, and for a
8884 more recent summary of the stance of the FCC and the courts, see
8885 <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors Association</citetitle> v. <citetitle>FCC</citetitle>, 184 F. 3d 872
8886 (D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8887 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8888 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8889 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, <quote>Antidiesel Group Fuming
8890 After Muni Rejects Ad,</quote> SFGate.com, 16 June 2003, available at
8891 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #32</ulink>. The ground
8892 was that the criticism was <quote>too controversial.</quote>
8893 </para></footnote>
8894 </para>
8895 <para>
8896 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well&mdash;if we lived
8897 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8898 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8899 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8900 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8901 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8902 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8903 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8904 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8905 </para>
8906 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'/>
8907 </section>
8908 <section id="together">
8909 <title>Together</title>
8910 <para>
8911 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8912 copyright warriors that the government should <quote>protect my property.</quote>
8913 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8914 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8915 </para>
8916 <para>
8917 But when we see how dramatically this <quote>property</quote> has changed&mdash;
8918 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8919 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8920 cultivate our culture is dramatically different&mdash;the claim begins
8921 to seem
8922
8923 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8924 less innocent and obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to
8925 supplement the law's control, and (2) the power of concentrated
8926 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8927 the massively expanded <quote>property</quote> rights granted by copyright
8928 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8929 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8930 be redefined.
8931 </para>
8932 <para>
8933 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8934 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8935 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8936 our culture today.
8937 </para>
8938 <para>
8939 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8940 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8941 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8942 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8943 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8944 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8945 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8946 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8947 traditionally defined copyright's regulation&mdash;a weakening of that
8948 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
8949 </para>
8950 <para>
8951 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
8952 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
8953 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
8954 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
8955 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
8956 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
8957 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
8958 future. And these changes have to be <emphasis>reductions</emphasis>
8959 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
8960 in control that technology and the market enable.
8961 </para>
8962 <para>
8963 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
8964 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
8965 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
8966 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
8967 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
8968 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
8969 more of the development of our culture than now</emphasis>.
8970 </para>
8971 <para>
8972 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
8973 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
8974 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
8975 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
8976 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
8977 were independent of the networks. <emphasis>Never</emphasis> has
8978 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
8979 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
8980 regulation&mdash;a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
8981 energy of a nation at the founding&mdash;is now a massive regulation
8982 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
8983 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
8984 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
8985 known.<footnote><para>
8986 <!-- f35 -->
8987 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
8988 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his <quote>four surrenders</quote> of
8989 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan, 159&ndash;60.
8990 </para></footnote>
8991 </para>
8992 <para>
8993 <emphasis role='strong'>This has been</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
8994 point can now be briefly stated.
8995 </para>
8996 <para>
8997 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
8998 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
8999 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
9000 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
9001 that copyright law has undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this:
9002 </para>
9003
9004 <informaltable id="t2">
9005 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9006 <thead>
9007 <row>
9008 <entry></entry>
9009 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9010 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9011 </row>
9012 </thead>
9013 <tbody>
9014 <row>
9015 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9016 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9017 <entry>Free</entry>
9018 </row>
9019 <row>
9020 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9021 <entry>Free</entry>
9022 <entry>Free</entry>
9023 </row>
9024 </tbody>
9025 </tgroup>
9026 </informaltable>
9027
9028 <para>
9029 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
9030 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
9031 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
9032
9033 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
9034 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
9035 noncommercial work was also free.
9036 </para>
9037 <para>
9038 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
9039 </para>
9040
9041 <informaltable id="t3">
9042 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9043 <thead>
9044 <row>
9045 <entry></entry>
9046 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9047 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9048 </row>
9049 </thead>
9050 <tbody>
9051 <row>
9052 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9053 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9054 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9055 </row>
9056 <row>
9057 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9058 <entry>Free</entry>
9059 <entry>Free</entry>
9060 </row>
9061 </tbody>
9062 </tgroup>
9063 </informaltable>
9064
9065 <para>
9066 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law&mdash;if
9067 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
9068 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
9069 transformation were still essentially free.
9070 </para>
9071 <para>
9072 In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
9073 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
9074 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
9075 expanded. Thus by 1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
9076 we could say the law began to look like this:
9077 </para>
9078
9079 <informaltable id="t4">
9080 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9081 <thead>
9082 <row>
9083 <entry></entry>
9084 <entry>COPY</entry>
9085 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9086 </row>
9087 </thead>
9088 <tbody>
9089 <row>
9090 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9091 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9092 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9093 </row>
9094 <row>
9095 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9096 <entry>&copy;/Free</entry>
9097 <entry>Free</entry>
9098 </row>
9099 </tbody>
9100 </tgroup>
9101 </informaltable>
9102
9103 <para>
9104 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
9105 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
9106 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
9107 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
9108 that the law now looks like this:
9109 </para>
9110
9111 <informaltable id="t5">
9112 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9113 <thead>
9114 <row>
9115 <entry></entry>
9116 <entry>COPY</entry>
9117 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9118 </row>
9119 </thead>
9120 <tbody>
9121 <row>
9122 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9123 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9124 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9125 </row>
9126 <row>
9127 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9128 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9129 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9130 </row>
9131 </tbody>
9132 </tgroup>
9133 </informaltable>
9134
9135 <para>
9136 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
9137 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
9138 creativity&mdash;
9139 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
9140 commercial or not, transformative or not&mdash;with the same rules
9141 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
9142 </para>
9143 <para>
9144 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
9145 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
9146 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
9147 these domains actually does any good.
9148 </para>
9149 <para>
9150 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
9151 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
9152 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
9153 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
9154 reasons sketched especially in chapters
9155 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/> and
9156 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>, one
9157 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
9158 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
9159 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
9160 </para>
9161 <para>
9162 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
9163 course copyright is a kind of <quote>property,</quote> and of course, as with any
9164 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
9165 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
9166 property rights<footnote><para>
9167 <!-- f36 -->
9168 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement</primary></indexterm>
9169 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
9170 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
9171 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, <quote>The
9172 Disintegration of Property,</quote> in <citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property</citetitle>, J. Roland
9173 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
9174 Press, 1980).
9175 </para></footnote>)
9176 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
9177 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
9178 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
9179 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the <quote>copyright</quote>
9180 did not control <emphasis>at all</emphasis> the freedom of others to
9181 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
9182 free, and for almost 180 years our country consistently protected a
9183 vibrant and rich free culture.
9184 </para>
9185 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
9186 <para>
9187 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
9188 limits on the scope of the interests protected by <quote>property.</quote> The very
9189 birth of <quote>copyright</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
9190 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
9191 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9192 linkend="founders"/>). The tradition of <quote>fair use</quote> is
9193 animated by a similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the
9194 costs of exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the
9195 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9196 linkend="recorders"/>). Adding
9197 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
9198 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
9199 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter <xref
9200 xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>). And
9201 granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect, claims of
9202 property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing the soul
9203 of a culture (chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9204 linkend="collectors"/>). Free cultures, like free markets, are built
9205 with property. But the nature of the property that builds a free
9206 culture is very different from the extremist vision that dominates the
9207 debate today.
9208 </para>
9209 <para>
9210 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
9211 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
9212 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
9213 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
9214 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
9215 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
9216 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
9217 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
9218 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
9219 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
9220 lawyer.
9221 </para>
9222 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
9223 </section>
9224 </chapter>
9225 </part>
9226 <part id="c-puzzles">
9227 <title>PUZZLES</title>
9228
9229 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
9230 <chapter label="11" id="chimera">
9231 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera</title>
9232 <indexterm id='idxchimera' class='startofrange'><primary>chimeras</primary></indexterm>
9233 <indexterm id='idxwells' class='startofrange'><primary>Wells, H. G.</primary></indexterm>
9234 <indexterm id='idxtcotb' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The</quote> (Wells)</primary></indexterm>
9235
9236 <para>
9237 <emphasis role='strong'>In a well-known</emphasis> short story by
9238 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
9239 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
9240 Andes.<footnote><para>
9241 <!-- f1. -->
9242 H. G. Wells, <quote>The Country of the Blind</quote> (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells,
9243 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
9244 York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
9245 </para></footnote>
9246 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with <quote>sweet water, pasture,
9247 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
9248 that bore an excellent fruit.</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
9249 takes this as an opportunity. <quote>In the Country of the Blind,</quote> he tells
9250 himself, <quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.</quote> So he resolves to live with the
9251 villagers to explore life as a king.
9252 </para>
9253 <para>
9254 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
9255 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
9256 <quote>blind.</quote> They don't have the word <citetitle>blind</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
9257 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
9258 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
9259 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. <quote>`You
9260 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
9261 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
9262 alone!'</quote>
9263 </para>
9264 <para>
9265 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
9266 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
9267 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
9268 affection, a young woman who to him seems <quote>the most beautiful thing in
9269 the whole of creation,</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
9270 description of what he sees <quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
9271 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
9272 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
9273 indulgence.</quote> <quote>She did not believe,</quote> Wells tells us, and <quote>she could
9274 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.</quote>
9275 </para>
9276 <para>
9277 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his <quote>mysteriously delighted</quote>
9278 love, the father and the village object. <quote>You see, my dear,</quote> her
9279 father instructs, <quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
9280 anything right.</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
9281 </para>
9282 <para>
9283 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. <quote>His brain
9284 is affected,</quote> he reports.
9285 </para>
9286 <para>
9287 <quote>What affects it?</quote> the father asks. <quote>Those queer things that are
9288 called the eyes &hellip; are diseased &hellip; in such a way as to affect
9289 his brain.</quote>
9290 </para>
9291 <para>
9292 The doctor continues: <quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
9293 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
9294 simple and easy surgical operation&mdash;namely, to remove these
9295 irritant bodies [the eyes].</quote>
9296 </para>
9297 <para>
9298 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
9299 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
9300 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
9301 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
9302 </para>
9303 <para>
9304 <emphasis role='strong'>It sometimes</emphasis> happens that the eggs
9305 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
9306 <quote>chimera.</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
9307 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
9308 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
9309
9310 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
9311 plot for murder mysteries. <quote>But the DNA shows with 100 percent
9312 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
9313 scene. &hellip;</quote>
9314 </para>
9315 <indexterm startref='idxtcotb' class='endofrange'/>
9316 <indexterm startref='idxwells' class="endofrange"/>
9317 <para>
9318 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
9319 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
9320 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
9321 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
9322 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
9323 understanding of a <quote>person</quote> should reflect this reality.
9324 </para>
9325 <para>
9326 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
9327 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
9328 unfairly enough, <quote>the copyright wars,</quote> the more I think we're dealing
9329 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question <quote>What is
9330 p2p file sharing?</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
9331 wrong. One side says, <quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
9332 others' records&mdash;the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
9333 thirty years without any question at all.</quote> That's true, at least in
9334 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
9335 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
9336 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
9337 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
9338 </para>
9339 <para>
9340 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
9341 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
9342 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
9343 <quote>friends</quote> beyond recognition to say <quote>my ten thousand best friends</quote> can
9344 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
9345 what <quote>we have always been allowed to do,</quote> we have not always been
9346 allowed to share music with <quote>our ten thousand best friends.</quote>
9347 </para>
9348 <para>
9349 Likewise, when the other side says, <quote>File sharing is just like walking
9350 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
9351 with it,</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
9352 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
9353 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
9354 from Tower.
9355 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9356 </para>
9357 <para>
9358
9359 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
9360 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
9361 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
9362 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
9363 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
9364 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
9365 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
9366 $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
9367 CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.)
9368 </para>
9369 <para>
9370 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
9371 that it is both&mdash;both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
9372 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
9373 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
9374 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
9375 </para>
9376 <para>
9377 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
9378 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
9379 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
9380 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
9381 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
9382 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
9383 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
9384 implemented.<footnote><para>
9385 <!-- f2. -->
9386 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9387 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
9388 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
9389 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003,
9390 available at
9391 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9392 #33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
9393 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
9394 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
9395 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, <quote>House Bill Aims to Up
9396 Stakes on Piracy,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 17 July 2003, available at
9397 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #34</ulink>. Civil
9398 penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied song. For a recent
9399 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
9400 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 songs
9401 through a family computer, see <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
9402 re. Verizon Internet Services)</citetitle>, 240 F. Supp. 2d 24
9403 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $90
9404 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
9405 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
9406 $12,000 to $17,500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
9407 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $98
9408 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
9409 Elizabeth Young, <quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,</quote> redandblack.com,
9410 August 2003, available at
9411 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #35</ulink>. For an
9412 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
9413 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
9414 identities, see James Collins, <quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
9415 Name Students,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 8 August 2003, D3, available at
9416 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #36</ulink>.
9417 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
9418 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
9419 </para></footnote>
9420
9421 </para>
9422 <indexterm startref='idxchimera' class='endofrange'/>
9423 <para>
9424 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
9425 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
9426 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
9427 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
9428 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
9429 </para>
9430 <para>
9431 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
9432 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
9433 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
9434 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
9435 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
9436 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe <emphasis>either</emphasis> extreme
9437 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
9438 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
9439 </para>
9440 <para>
9441
9442 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
9443 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
9444 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
9445 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
9446 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
9447 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
9448 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
9449 </para>
9450 <para>
9451 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to <quote>steal</quote> music. My
9452 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
9453 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
9454 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
9455 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
9456 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
9457 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
9458 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
9459 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
9460 protection for copyrighted material,
9461 </para>
9462 <blockquote>
9463 <para>
9464 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
9465 material, and we want to protect those rights.
9466 </para>
9467 <para>
9468 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
9469 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
9470 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
9471 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
9472 produce a totally different industry model.
9473 </para>
9474 <para>
9475 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
9476 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
9477 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
9478 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
9479 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
9480 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
9481 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
9482 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
9483 interests.<footnote><para>
9484 <!-- f3. -->
9485 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
9486 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
9487 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
9488 House Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement of Peter
9489 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
9490 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
9491 Congressional Testimony File. </para></footnote>
9492 </para>
9493 </blockquote>
9494 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
9495 <para>
9496 In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
9497 one of <quote>the major labels.</quote> Its position on these matters has now
9498 changed.
9499 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9500 </para>
9501 <para>
9502 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
9503 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9504 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9505 </para>
9506
9507 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9508 </chapter>
9509 <chapter label="12" id="harms">
9510 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms</title>
9511 <para>
9512 <emphasis role='strong'>To fight</emphasis> <quote>piracy,</quote> to
9513 protect <quote>property,</quote> the content industry has launched a
9514 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9515 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9516 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9517 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9518 </para>
9519 <para>
9520 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9521 particular, the consequences for <quote>free culture.</quote> But my aim now is to
9522 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9523 justified?
9524 </para>
9525 <para>
9526 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9527 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9528 power of the property called <quote>intellectual property</quote> is at its greatest in
9529 our history.
9530 </para>
9531 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
9532 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
9533 <para>
9534 Yet <quote>common sense</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9535 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9536 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9537 rejection of <quote>piracy</quote> still has play.
9538 </para>
9539 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9540 <para>
9541 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9542 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9543 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9544 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9545 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9546 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9547 </para>
9548 <section id="constrain">
9549 <title>Constraining Creators</title>
9550 <para>
9551 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9552 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9553 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9554 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9555 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9556 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9557 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9558 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9559 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9560 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9561 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9562 weave together a string&mdash;a mash-up&mdash; of songs from your
9563 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9564 </para>
9565 <para>
9566 This digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> is in part an extension of the
9567 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9568 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9569 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9570 of digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9571 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9572 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9573 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9574 the culture all around.
9575 </para>
9576 <para>
9577 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9578 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9579
9580 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9581
9582 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9583 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9584 storytelling extended across the globe.
9585 </para>
9586 <para>
9587 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9588 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9589 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9590 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9591 that catalog cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9592 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9593 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9594 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9595 work is presumptively illegal.
9596 </para>
9597 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom</primary></indexterm>
9598 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9599 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9600 <indexterm><primary>doctors malpractice claims against</primary></indexterm>
9601 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
9602 <para>
9603 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9604 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9605 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9606 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9607 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9608 by the RIAA (Jesse Jordan of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9609 labelnumber" linkend="catalogs"/> was just one) were threatened with a
9610 $98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted songs
9611 to be copied. Yet World-Com&mdash;which defrauded investors of $11
9612 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization of
9613 over $200 billion&mdash;received a fine of a mere $750
9614 million.<footnote><para>
9615 <!-- f1. -->
9616 See Lynne W. Jeter, <citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom</citetitle>
9617 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley &amp; Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of
9618 the settlement, see MCI press release, <quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9619 Approval for SEC Settlement</quote> (7 July 2003), available at
9620 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #37</ulink>.
9621 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom</primary></indexterm>
9622 </para></footnote>
9623 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9624 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9625 no more than $250,000 in damages for pain and
9626 suffering.<footnote>
9627 <para>
9628 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9629 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For
9630 an overview, see Tanya Albert, <quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9631 Say Tort Reformers,</quote> amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at
9632 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #38</ulink>,
9633 and <quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,</quote> CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003,
9634 available at
9635 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9636 recent months.
9637 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.</primary></indexterm>
9638 </para></footnote>
9639 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9640 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9641 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9642 </para>
9643 <indexterm><primary>art, underground</primary></indexterm>
9644 <para>
9645 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9646 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9647 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9648 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9649 Disneys <quote>pirates.</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9650 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9651 designed to
9652
9653 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9654 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9655 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9656 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9657 we will begin to see a world of underground art&mdash;not because the
9658 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9659 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9660 fraught. Already, exhibits of <quote>illegal art</quote> tour the United
9661 States.<footnote><para>
9662 <!-- f3. -->
9663
9664 See Danit Lidor, <quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,</quote> <citetitle>Wired</citetitle>, 7 July
9665 2003, available at
9666 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9667 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #41</ulink>.
9668 </para></footnote>
9669 In what does their <quote>illegality</quote> consist?
9670 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9671 critical or reflective.
9672 </para>
9673 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9674 <para>
9675 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9676 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9677 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. But an
9678 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9679 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9680 discovered in 2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9681 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9682 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9683 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9684 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9685 </para>
9686 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
9687 <para>
9688 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9689 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9690 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9691 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9692 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9693 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9694 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9695 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9696 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9697 </para>
9698 <para>
9699 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9700 described in chapter
9701 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/>, in
9702 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9703 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9704 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9705 use.
9706 </para>
9707 <para>
9708
9709 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9710 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9711 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9712 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad&mdash;in
9713 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9714 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9715 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9716 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9717 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9718 </para>
9719 <para>
9720 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9721 <quote>breathing room</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9722 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9723 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9724 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9725 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9726 journalists&mdash; these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9727 these rules have little relationship to the <quote>law</quote> with which judges
9728 comfort themselves.
9729 </para>
9730 <para>
9731 For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful
9732 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9733 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9734 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9735 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak&mdash;in that
9736 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9737 <quote>copyright</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9738 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9739 culture that is free.
9740 </para>
9741 <para>
9742 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9743 </para>
9744 <blockquote>
9745 <para>
9746 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9747 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9748 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9749 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made &hellip; you're not
9750 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9751 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9752 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, <quote>This has been
9753 cleared.</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9754 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9755 </para>
9756 </blockquote>
9757 </section>
9758 <section id="innovators">
9759 <title>Constraining Innovators</title>
9760 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovation hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
9761 <indexterm id='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>innovation</primary><secondary>industry establishment opposed to</secondary></indexterm>
9762 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
9763 <para>
9764 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9765 story&mdash;creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9766 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9767 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9768 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9769 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9770 </para>
9771 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints2' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9772 <para>
9773 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9774 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9775 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9776 one at that, <xref xrefstyle="select: pagenumber"
9777 linkend="innovators"/> pages into a book like this), then you
9778 can see this other aspect by substituting <quote>free market</quote>
9779 every place I've spoken of <quote>free culture.</quote> The point is
9780 the same, even if the interests affecting culture are more
9781 fundamental.
9782 </para>
9783 <para>
9784 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9785 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9786 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary&mdash;at
9787 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9788 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9789 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9790 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9791 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9792 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9793 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9794 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9795 </para>
9796 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints2' class='endofrange'/>
9797 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9798 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
9799 <para>
9800 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9801 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9802 strategy that I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9803 labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9804 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9805 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9806 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9807 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9808 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9809 lesson. That lesson&mdash;what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9810 <quote>nuclear pall</quote> that has fallen over the Valley&mdash;has been learned.
9811 </para>
9812 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
9813 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
9814 <para>
9815 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9816 I told in <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9817 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9818 </para>
9819 <indexterm id='idxmpcom' class='startofrange'><primary>MP3.com</primary></indexterm>
9820 <indexterm id='idxmympcom' class='startofrange'><primary>my.mp3.com</primary></indexterm>
9821 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael</primary></indexterm>
9822 <para>
9823 In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9824 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9825 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9826 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9827 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9828 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9829 </para>
9830 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9831 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>preference data on</secondary></indexterm>
9832 <para>
9833 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9834 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9835 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9836 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9837 Raitt. And so on.
9838 </para>
9839 <para>
9840 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9841 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9842 preference data. In January 2000, the company launched a service
9843 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9844 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9845 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9846 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9847 wherever you were&mdash;at work or at home&mdash;you could get access
9848 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9849 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9850 </para>
9851 <para>
9852 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9853 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9854
9855 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9856 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9857 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9858 the kind of content the users liked.
9859 </para>
9860 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'/>
9861 <para>
9862 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000
9863 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9864 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9865 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9866 therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9867 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9868 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9869 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was 50,000
9870 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers something
9871 they had already bought.
9872 </para>
9873 <indexterm id='idxvivendiuniversal' class='startofrange'><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9874 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
9875 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9876 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9877 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
9878 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
9879 <indexterm><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>outsize penalties of</secondary></indexterm>
9880 <para>
9881 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9882 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9883 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9884 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9885 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9886 MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9887 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $54 million. Vivendi
9888 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9889 </para>
9890 <para>
9891 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9892 </para>
9893 <para>
9894 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9895 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9896 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9897 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9898 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9899 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9900 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9901 demanded.
9902 </para>
9903 <indexterm startref='idxvivendiuniversal' class='endofrange'/>
9904 <para>
9905 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9906 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9907 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9908 clients in this
9909 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9910 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9911 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9912 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9913 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9914 </para>
9915 <indexterm startref='idxmpcom' class='endofrange'/>
9916 <indexterm startref='idxmympcom' class='endofrange'/>
9917 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='endofrange'/>
9918 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9919 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
9920 <indexterm id='idxbmw' class='startofrange'><primary>BMW</primary></indexterm>
9921 <indexterm id='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='startofrange'><primary>cars, MP3 sound systems in</primary></indexterm>
9922 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
9923 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John</primary></indexterm>
9924 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9925 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad</primary></indexterm>
9926 <indexterm><primary>MP3 players</primary></indexterm>
9927 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>venture capital for</secondary></indexterm>
9928 <indexterm id='idxneedlemanrafe' class='startofrange'><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
9929 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
9930 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
9931 <para>
9932 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003,
9933 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9934 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9935 its development, its cofounder (John Hummer), and general partner
9936 (Hank Barry).<footnote><para>
9937 <!-- f4. -->
9938 See Joseph Menn, <quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9939 Times</citetitle>, 23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9940 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, <quote>The Music
9941 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,</quote> Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available
9942 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #42</ulink>.
9943 See also Jon Healey, <quote>Online Music Services Besieged,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9944 Times</citetitle>, 28 May 2001.
9945 </para></footnote>
9946 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
9947 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
9948 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
9949 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
9950 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
9951 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
9952 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
9953 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
9954 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
9955 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
9956 <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
9957 discussion with BMW:
9958 </para>
9959 <blockquote>
9960 <para>
9961 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
9962 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
9963 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
9964 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
9965 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
9966 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
9967 United States with bona fide MP3 players. &hellip; <footnote>
9968 <para>
9969 <!-- f5. -->
9970 Rafe Needleman, <quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,</quote> <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, 16 June
9971 2003, available at
9972 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #43</ulink>. I am grateful
9973 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
9974 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
9975 </para></footnote>
9976 </para>
9977 </blockquote>
9978 <indexterm startref='idxbmw' class='endofrange'/>
9979 <indexterm startref='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='endofrange'/>
9980 <indexterm startref='idxneedlemanrafe' class='endofrange'/>
9981 <para>
9982 This is the world of the mafia&mdash;filled with <quote>your money or your
9983 life</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
9984 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
9985 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
9986 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
9987 constantly threatened by litigation.
9988 </para>
9989 <para>
9990
9991 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
9992 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
9993 enterprises. The point is the definition of <quote>illegal.</quote> The law is a
9994 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
9995 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
9996 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
9997 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
9998 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
9999 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
10000 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
10001 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
10002 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
10003 much less creativity.
10004 </para>
10005 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
10006 <para>
10007 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
10008 use. Whatever the <quote>real</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
10009 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
10010 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
10011 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
10012 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
10013 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
10014 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
10015 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
10016 produce an overregulatedregulated market.
10017 </para>
10018 <para>
10019 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
10020 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
10021 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
10022 culture&mdash;a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
10023 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
10024 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
10025 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
10026 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
10027 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
10028 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
10029 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
10030 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
10031 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
10032 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
10033 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
10034 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
10035 result.
10036 </para>
10037 <para>
10038 <emphasis role='strong'>The uncertainty</emphasis> of the law is one
10039 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
10040 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
10041 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
10042 better protects their content.
10043 </para>
10044 <para>
10045 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
10046 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
10047 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
10048 this feature is a <quote>bug.</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
10049 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
10050 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
10051 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables <quote>piracy,</quote> then,
10052 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
10053 </para>
10054 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10055 <para>
10056 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
10057 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
10058 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
10059 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.<footnote><para>
10060 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> GartnerG2 and
10061 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
10062 (2003), 33&ndash;35, available at
10063 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10064 </para></footnote>
10065 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
10066 <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
10067 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
10068 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
10069 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
10070 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
10071 copyright violators and disable their machines.<footnote><para>
10072 <!-- f7. -->
10073 GartnerG2, 26&ndash;27.
10074 </para></footnote>
10075 </para>
10076 <para>
10077 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
10078 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
10079 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
10080 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
10081 and costs on
10082 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
10083 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
10084 those requirements.
10085 </para>
10086 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
10087 <para>
10088 In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
10089 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
10090 would impose.<footnote><para>
10091 <!-- f8. -->
10092 See David McGuire, <quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,</quote> Newsbytes,
10093 February 2002 (Entertainment).
10094 </para></footnote>
10095 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
10096 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
10097 harm than good.
10098 </para>
10099 <para>
10100 <emphasis role='strong'>There is one</emphasis> more obvious way in
10101 which this war has harmed innovation&mdash;again, a story that will be
10102 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
10103 </para>
10104 <para>
10105 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
10106 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
10107 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
10108 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
10109 </para>
10110 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
10111 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
10112 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
10113 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
10114 <para>
10115 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10116 linkend="property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
10117 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
10118 Jessica Litman in her book <citetitle>Digital
10119 Copyright</citetitle>,<footnote><para>
10120 <!-- f9. -->
10121 Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (Amherst,
10122 N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 2001).
10123 <indexterm><primary>Digital Copyright (Litman)</primary></indexterm>
10124 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
10125 </para></footnote>
10126 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter
10127 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/> details,
10128 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
10129 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
10130 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
10131 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
10132 </para>
10133 <para>
10134 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
10135 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
10136 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
10137 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
10138 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
10139 </para>
10140 <indexterm id='idxinternetradioon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>radio on</secondary></indexterm>
10141 <indexterm id='idxradiooninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
10142 <para>
10143 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.<footnote><para>
10144 <!-- f10. -->
10145 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.</primary></indexterm>
10146 The only circuit court exception is found in <citetitle>Recording Industry
10147 Association of America (RIAA)</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems</citetitle>, 180 F. 3d
10148 1072 (9th Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
10149 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
10150 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
10151 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
10152 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
10153 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
10154 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Grokster, Ltd</citetitle>., 259 F. Supp. 2d
10155 1029 (C.D. Cal., 2003), where the court found the link between the
10156 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
10157 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
10158 liability.
10159 </para></footnote>
10160 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
10161 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
10162 here.<footnote><para>
10163 <!-- f11. -->
10164 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy</primary></indexterm>
10165 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
10166 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz</primary></indexterm>
10167 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10168 For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
10169 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize
10170 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
10171 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
10172 August 2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
10173 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
10174 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that
10175 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
10176 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
10177 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
10178 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, <quote>Copyright and
10179 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003, 33&ndash;34,
10180 available at
10181 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10182 </para></footnote>
10183 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
10184 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
10185 </para>
10186 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10187 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
10188 <para>
10189
10190 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
10191 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10192 linkend="pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
10193 artist doesn't get paid for that <quote>radio performance</quote> unless he or she
10194 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
10195 version of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote>&mdash;to memorialize her famous
10196 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden&mdash;
10197 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
10198 copyright owners of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> would get some money, whereas
10199 Marilyn Monroe would not.
10200 </para>
10201 <para>
10202 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
10203 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
10204 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
10205 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
10206 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
10207 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
10208 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
10209 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
10210 recording artists.
10211 </para>
10212 <para>
10213 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
10214 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
10215 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
10216 spectrum. Thus, I can <quote>tune in</quote> to an Internet radio station in
10217 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
10218 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
10219 metropolitan area.
10220 </para>
10221 <para>
10222 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
10223 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
10224 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
10225 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
10226 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
10227 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
10228 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
10229 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
10230 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
10231 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
10232 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
10233 </para>
10234 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
10235 <para>
10236
10237 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
10238 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
10239 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
10240 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
10241 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
10242 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
10243 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
10244 FM radio,
10245 </para>
10246 <blockquote>
10247 <para>
10248 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
10249 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
10250 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
10251 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
10252 than by technical restrictions. &hellip; Armstrong likened the situation
10253 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
10254 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
10255 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
10256 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
10257 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
10258 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
10259 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
10260 shackles.<footnote><para>
10261 <!-- f12. -->
10262 Lessing, 239.
10263 </para></footnote>
10264 </para>
10265 </blockquote>
10266 <para>
10267 This potential for FM radio was never realized&mdash;not
10268 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
10269 underestimated the power of <quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
10270 legislation</quote><footnote><para>
10271 <!-- f13. -->
10272 Ibid., 229.
10273 </para></footnote>
10274 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
10275 </para>
10276 <para>
10277 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
10278 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
10279 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
10280 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
10281 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
10282 radio?
10283 </para>
10284 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10285 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
10286 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on radio</secondary></indexterm>
10287 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
10288 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10289 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
10290 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>Internet radio hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
10291 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10292 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
10293 <para>
10294 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
10295 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
10296
10297 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
10298 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
10299 of Internet radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
10300 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
10301 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
10302 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
10303 of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> on the air, <emphasis>Internet radio
10304 does</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
10305 radio&mdash;the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
10306 burdens terrestrial radio.
10307 </para>
10308 <para>
10309 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
10310 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
10311 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
10312 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
10313 over $1 million a year.<footnote>
10314 <para>
10315 <!-- f14. -->
10316 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
10317 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
10318 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
10319 iLaw (Stanford), 3 July 2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
10320 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
10321 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
10322 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP
10323 DTRA 1 and 2, available at
10324 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #45</ulink>.
10325 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
10326 C. Picker, <quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
10327 Distribution,</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin</citetitle> (Summer/Fall 2002): 461: <quote>This was
10328 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
10329 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
10330 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
10331 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
10332 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.</quote>
10333 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)</primary></indexterm>
10334 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
10335 </para></footnote>
10336 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
10337 equivalent fee.
10338 </para>
10339 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='endofrange'/>
10340 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='endofrange'/>
10341 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='endofrange'/>
10342 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='endofrange'/>
10343 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='endofrange'/>
10344 <para>
10345 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
10346 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
10347 station) would have to collect the following data from <emphasis>every
10348 listening transaction</emphasis>:
10349 </para>
10350 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
10351 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
10352 <listitem><para>
10353 name of the service;
10354 </para></listitem>
10355 <listitem><para>
10356 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
10357 </para></listitem>
10358 <listitem><para>
10359 type of program (archived/looped/live);
10360 </para></listitem>
10361 <listitem><para>
10362 date of transmission;
10363 </para></listitem>
10364 <listitem><para>
10365 time of transmission;
10366 </para></listitem>
10367 <listitem><para>
10368 time zone of origination of transmission;
10369 </para></listitem>
10370 <listitem><para>
10371 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
10372 </para></listitem>
10373 <listitem><para>
10374 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
10375 </para></listitem>
10376 <listitem><para>
10377 sound recording title;
10378 </para></listitem>
10379 <listitem><para>
10380 ISRC code of the recording;
10381 </para></listitem>
10382 <listitem><para>
10383 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
10384 </para></listitem>
10385 <listitem><para>
10386 featured recording artist;
10387 </para></listitem>
10388 <listitem><para>
10389 retail album title;
10390 </para></listitem>
10391 <listitem><para>
10392 recording label;
10393 </para></listitem>
10394 <listitem><para>
10395 UPC code of the retail album;
10396 </para></listitem>
10397 <listitem><para>
10398 catalog number;
10399 </para></listitem>
10400 <listitem><para>
10401 copyright owner information;
10402 </para></listitem>
10403 <listitem><para>
10404 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
10405 </para></listitem>
10406 <listitem><para>
10407 name of the service or entity;
10408 </para></listitem>
10409 <listitem><para>
10410 channel or program;
10411 </para></listitem>
10412 <listitem><para>
10413 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
10414 </para></listitem>
10415 <listitem><para>
10416 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
10417 </para></listitem>
10418 <listitem><para>
10419 time zone where the signal was received (user);
10420 </para></listitem>
10421 <listitem><para>
10422 unique user identifier;
10423 </para></listitem>
10424 <listitem><para>
10425 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
10426 </para></listitem>
10427 </orderedlist>
10428 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
10429 <para>
10430 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
10431 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
10432 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
10433 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
10434 Internet radio has to pay a <emphasis>type of copyright fee</emphasis>
10435 that terrestrial radio does not.
10436 </para>
10437 <para>
10438 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
10439 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
10440 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
10441 </para>
10442 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
10443 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
10444 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10445 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10446 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10447 <para>
10448 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
10449 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
10450 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
10451 </para>
10452 <blockquote>
10453 <para>
10454 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
10455 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
10456 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
10457 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
10458 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
10459 webcasters asked the RIAA, &hellip; <quote>How do you come up with a
10460
10461 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
10462 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
10463 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
10464 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
10465 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
10466 business. &hellip;</quote>
10467 </para>
10468 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10469 <para>
10470 And the RIAA experts said, <quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
10471 industry with thousands of webcasters, <emphasis>we think it should be
10472 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
10473 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market</emphasis>.</quote> (Emphasis
10474 added.)
10475 </para>
10476 </blockquote>
10477 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'/>
10478 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='endofrange'/>
10479 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='endofrange'/>
10480 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='endofrange'/>
10481 <para>
10482 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
10483 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
10484 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
10485 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
10486 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
10487 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
10488 effective to prevent it.
10489 </para>
10490 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10491 <indexterm startref='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='endofrange'/>
10492 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='endofrange'/>
10493 <indexterm startref='idxinternetradioon' class='endofrange'/>
10494 <indexterm startref='idxradiooninternet' class='endofrange'/>
10495 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10496 </section>
10497 <section id="corruptingcitizens">
10498 <title>Corrupting Citizens</title>
10499 <para>
10500 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
10501 dinosaurs
10502 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
10503 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
10504 </para>
10505 <para>
10506 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
10507 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
10508 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
10509 </para>
10510 <para>
10511 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
10512 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
10513 large number of citizens. According to <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, 43 million
10514 Americans downloaded music in May 2002.<footnote><para>
10515 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, <quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,</quote> Pew
10516 Internet and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at
10517 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #46</ulink>.
10518 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that 37 million
10519 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early 2001.
10520 </para></footnote>
10521 According to the RIAA,
10522 the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
10523 set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As the
10524
10525 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
10526 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
10527 the world, but against students building search engines, and
10528 increasingly
10529 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
10530 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
10531 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
10532 extreme
10533 response by the other.
10534 </para>
10535 <para>
10536 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
10537 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
10538 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
10539 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
10540 ($15,000,000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
10541 paying all the money in the world in damages ($250,000 in legal fees)
10542 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
10543 ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
10544 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September 2003, the RIAA
10545 sued 261 individuals&mdash;including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
10546 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
10547 was.<footnote><para>
10548 <!-- f16. -->
10549 Alex Pham, <quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,</quote> <citetitle>Los
10550 Angeles Times</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, Business.
10551 </para></footnote>
10552 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
10553 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
10554 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000
10555 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
10556 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
10557 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
10558 they oppose.
10559 </para>
10560 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition</primary></indexterm>
10561 <para>
10562 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
10563 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
10564 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
10565 consumption of alcohol was 1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
10566 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just 30 percent
10567 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10568 consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition
10569 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10570 number were criminals.<footnote><para>
10571 <!-- f17. -->
10572 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, <quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10573 Prohibition,</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review</citetitle> 81, no. 2 (1991): 242.
10574 </para></footnote>
10575 We have
10576 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10577 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10578 narcotics that 7 percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.<footnote><para>
10579 <!-- f18. -->
10580 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10581 Reform Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of
10582 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10583 </para></footnote>
10584 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of
10585 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10586 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10587 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10588 cheat.<footnote><para>
10589 <!-- f19. -->
10590 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, <quote>Tax
10591 Compliance,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature</citetitle> 36 (1998): 818 (survey of
10592 compliance literature).
10593 </para></footnote>
10594 We pride ourselves on our <quote>free society,</quote> but an endless array of
10595 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10596 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10597 </para>
10598 <indexterm><primary>law schools</primary></indexterm>
10599 <para>
10600 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10601 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10602 students about the importance of <quote>ethics.</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10603 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10604 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10605 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10606 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10607 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10608 teach them how to behave ethically&mdash;how to say no to bribes, or
10609 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10610 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10611 Americans&mdash;more significantly in some parts of America than in
10612 others, but still, everywhere in America today&mdash;can't live their
10613 lives both normally and legally, since <quote>normally</quote> entails a certain
10614 degree of illegality.
10615 </para>
10616 <para>
10617 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10618 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10619 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10620 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10621 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10622 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10623 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10624 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10625 to consider the alternative.
10626 </para>
10627 <para>
10628
10629 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10630 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10631 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10632 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10633 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10634 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10635 </para>
10636 <para>
10637 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10638 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10639 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10640 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10641 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10642 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10643 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10644 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10645 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10646 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10647 introduced this different idea of <quote>sharing.</quote> We need to be able to
10648 call these twenty million Americans <quote>citizens,</quote> not <quote>felons.</quote>
10649 </para>
10650 <para>
10651 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10652 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10653 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10654 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10655 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10656 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10657 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10658 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10659 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10660 a nation of felons?
10661 </para>
10662 <para>
10663 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10664 </para>
10665 <para>
10666 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10667 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10668 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10669 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10670 used
10671
10672 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10673 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That <quote>use</quote> of the
10674 recordings is free.
10675 </para>
10676 <para>
10677 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10678 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10679 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am <quote>free</quote> to copy,
10680 or <quote>rip,</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10681 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that <quote>freedom</quote> was a
10682 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the <quote>Rip, Mix, Burn</quote>
10683 capacities of digital technologies.
10684 </para>
10685 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda</primary></indexterm>
10686 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>mix technology and</secondary></indexterm>
10687 <para>
10688 This <quote>use</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10689 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10690 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10691 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10692 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10693 Others&mdash;the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10694 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10695 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10696 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10697 </para>
10698 <para>
10699 This use is enabled by unprotected media&mdash;either CDs or records.
10700 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10701 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10702 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10703 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10704 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10705 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10706 on people's machines.
10707 </para>
10708 <para>
10709 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10710 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10711 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10712 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10713 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10714 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10715
10716 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10717 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10718 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10719 plastic or were part of a massively complex <quote>digital rights
10720 management</quote> system.
10721 </para>
10722 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'/>
10723 <para>
10724 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10725 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10726 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10727 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10728 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10729 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10730 freedom to move content easily?
10731 </para>
10732 <para>
10733 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10734 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10735 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10736 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10737 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10738 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10739 alternative&mdash;namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10740 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10741 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10742 </para>
10743 <para>
10744 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10745 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10746 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10747 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10748 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10749 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10750 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10751 </para>
10752 <para>
10753 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10754 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10755 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10756 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10757 </para>
10758 <para>
10759 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10760 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10761
10762 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10763
10764 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10765 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10766 </para>
10767 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
10768 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
10769 <para>
10770 <emphasis role='strong'>There's one more</emphasis> aspect to this
10771 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10772 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10773 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10774 <quote>collateral damage</quote> that <quote>arises whenever you turn
10775 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.</quote> This
10776 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10777 </para>
10778 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10779 <para>
10780 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,</quote> von Lohmann
10781 explains,
10782 </para>
10783 <blockquote>
10784 <para>
10785 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10786 evaporate to one degree or another. &hellip; If you're a copyright
10787 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10788 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10789 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10790 access? &hellip; Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, <quote>Oh, well,
10791 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.</quote> Well, what this campaign
10792 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10793 American Internet-using population into <quote>lawbreakers.</quote>
10794 </para>
10795 </blockquote>
10796 <para>
10797 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10798 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10799 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10800 </para>
10801 <para>
10802 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA
10803 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10804 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10805 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10806 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10807 an Internet user is revealed.
10808 </para>
10809 <para>
10810 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10811 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10812 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10813 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10814 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10815 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10816 the family could be liable for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10817 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10818 Jesse Jordan.<footnote><para>
10819 <!-- f20. -->
10820 See Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10821 Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,</quote>
10822 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, <quote>Worried Parents
10823 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10824 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10825 Being Sued,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson
10826 Graham, <quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 15 September
10827 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, <quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10828 Fan, Either,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 25 September 2003, C1; Margo Varadi, <quote>Is
10829 Brianna a Criminal?</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star</citetitle>, 18 September 2003, P7.
10830 </para></footnote>
10831
10832 </para>
10833 <para>
10834 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10835 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10836 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.<footnote><para>
10837 <!-- f21. -->
10838 See <quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10839 Some Methods Used,</quote> CNN.com, available at
10840 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #47</ulink>.
10841 </para></footnote>
10842 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10843 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10844 one of those MP3s will have the same <quote>fingerprint.</quote>
10845 </para>
10846 <para>
10847 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10848 friend gives a CD to your daughter&mdash;a collection of songs just
10849 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10850 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10851 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10852 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10853 network is <quote>cooperating</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10854 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10855 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10856 as a <quote>criminal.</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10857 to deploy,<footnote><para>
10858 <!-- f22. -->
10859 See Jeff Adler, <quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,</quote>
10860 <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, <quote>Four
10861 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10862 Colleges,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10863 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10864 Monitor</citetitle>, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, <quote>Music
10865 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10866 Lawsuit Possible,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 16 July 2003, 1C; Beth Cox, <quote>RIAA
10867 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,</quote> <citetitle>Internet News</citetitle>, 30 January
10868 2003, available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10869 #48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Download Warning 101: Freshman
10870 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10871 Sharing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 11 August 2003, E11; <quote>Raid, Letters
10872 Are Weapons at Universities,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 26 September 2000, 3D.
10873 </para></footnote>
10874 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10875 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10876 </para>
10877 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'/>
10878 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10879 <para>
10880 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10881 a lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10882 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10883 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10884 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10885 this <quote>contraband</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10886 college students
10887
10888 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10889 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10890 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10891 Says von Lohmann,
10892 </para>
10893 <blockquote>
10894 <para>
10895 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10896 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10897 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10898 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10899 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10900 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10901 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10902 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10903 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10904 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10905 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10906 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10907 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10908 larger number of Americans than drug use. &hellip; If forty to sixty
10909 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10910 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10911 million of them.
10912 </para>
10913 </blockquote>
10914 <para>
10915 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered <quote>criminals</quote> under
10916 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective&mdash;
10917 securing rights to authors&mdash;without these millions being
10918 considered <quote>criminals,</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10919 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10920 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10921 </para>
10922
10923 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10924 </section>
10925 </chapter>
10926 </part>
10927 <part id="c-balances">
10928 <title>BALANCES</title>
10929 <partintro>
10930
10931 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10932 <para>
10933 <emphasis role='strong'>So here's</emphasis> the picture: You're
10934 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
10935 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
10936 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
10937 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10938 </para>
10939 <para>
10940 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10941 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10942 stop&mdash;or before she understands just why she should
10943 stop&mdash;the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10944 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10945 everything around.
10946 </para>
10947 <para>
10948 <emphasis role='strong'>A war</emphasis> about copyright rages all
10949 around&mdash;and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
10950 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
10951 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
10952 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
10953 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
10954 that if let alone would burn itself out.
10955 </para>
10956 <para>
10957 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
10958 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
10959 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
10960 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
10961 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
10962 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
10963 made that is happening all around.
10964 </para>
10965 <para>
10966 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
10967 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
10968 gasoline onto this fire.
10969 </para>
10970 <para>
10971 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
10972 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
10973 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
10974 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
10975 </para>
10976 <para>
10977 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
10978 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
10979 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
10980 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
10981 success will require.
10982 </para>
10983 </partintro>
10984
10985 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
10986 <chapter label="13" id="eldred">
10987 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred</title>
10988 <indexterm id='idxeldrederic' class='startofrange'><primary>Eldred, Eric</primary></indexterm>
10989 <indexterm id='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='startofrange'><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel</primary></indexterm>
10990 <para>
10991 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
10992 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
10993 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
10994 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
10995 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
10996 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
10997 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
10998 </para>
10999 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>of public-domain literature</secondary></indexterm>
11000 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>library of works derived from</secondary></indexterm>
11001 <para>
11002 It didn't work&mdash;at least for his daughters. They didn't find
11003 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
11004 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
11005 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
11006 them available for free.
11007 </para>
11008 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt5' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11009 <indexterm><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
11010 <para>
11011 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
11012 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
11013 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
11014 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
11015 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
11016 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
11017 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
11018 many others, into a form more accessible&mdash;technically
11019 accessible&mdash;today.
11020 </para>
11021 <indexterm><primary>Scarlet Letter, The (Hawthorne)</primary></indexterm>
11022 <para>
11023 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
11024 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's <citetitle>Scarlet Letter</citetitle> had passed into the
11025 public domain in 1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
11026 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
11027 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
11028 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
11029 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
11030 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (<citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle>), sometimes not
11031 (<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame</citetitle>, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>). These are all
11032 commercial publications of public domain works.
11033 </para>
11034 <indexterm startref='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='endofrange'/>
11035 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt5' class='endofrange'/>
11036 <para>
11037 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
11038 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
11039 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
11040 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
11041 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
11042 call the <quote>noncommercial publishing industry,</quote> which before the
11043 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
11044 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
11045 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
11046 generally.<footnote><para>
11047 <!-- f1. -->
11048 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
11049 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
11050 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
11051 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers&mdash;people who
11052 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
11053 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
11054 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
11055 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
11056 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
11057 Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on
11058 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
11059 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
11060 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
11061 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
11062 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
11063 protect noncommercial pornographers.</para></footnote>
11064 </para>
11065 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
11066 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11067 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
11068 <indexterm><primary>Frost, Robert</primary></indexterm>
11069 <indexterm><primary>New Hampshire (Frost)</primary></indexterm>
11070 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
11071 <indexterm id='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
11072 <para>
11073 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's
11074 collection of poems <citetitle>New Hampshire</citetitle> was slated to
11075 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
11076 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
11077 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
11078 linkend="property-i"/>, in 1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
11079 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights&mdash;this time by
11080 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
11081 than 1923 to his collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
11082 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
11083 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
11084 more than 1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
11085 </para>
11086 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='endofrange'/>
11087 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
11088 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11089 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11090 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
11091 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11092 <para>
11093
11094 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
11095 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
11096 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
11097 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
11098 <quote>copyrights should be forever.</quote><footnote><para>
11099 <!-- f2. -->
11100 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11101 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11102 The full text is: <quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
11103 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
11104 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
11105 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
11106 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
11107 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
11108 Congress,</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998).
11109 </para></footnote>
11110 </para>
11111 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
11112 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>felony punishment for infringement of</secondary></indexterm>
11113 <indexterm><primary>NET (No Electronic Theft) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11114 <indexterm><primary>No Electronic Theft (NET) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11115 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>felony punishments for</secondary></indexterm>
11116 <para>
11117 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
11118 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
11119 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
11120 second law passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
11121 of publishing would make Eldred a felon&mdash;whether or not anyone
11122 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
11123 to undertake.
11124 </para>
11125 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='endofrange'/>
11126 <indexterm id='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
11127 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
11128 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause2' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
11129 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11130 <para>
11131 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
11132 constitutional
11133 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
11134 interpretation.
11135 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
11136 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
11137 importantly
11138 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
11139 </para>
11140 <blockquote>
11141 <para>
11142 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science &hellip;
11143 by securing for limited Times to Authors &hellip; exclusive Right to
11144 their &hellip; Writings. &hellip;
11145 </para>
11146 </blockquote>
11147 <indexterm startref='idxeldrederic' class='endofrange'/>
11148 <para>
11149 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
11150 clause of Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
11151 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
11152 something&mdash;for example, to regulate <quote>commerce among the several
11153 states</quote> or <quote>declare War.</quote> But here, the <quote>something</quote> is something quite
11154 specific&mdash;to <quote>promote &hellip; Progress</quote>&mdash;through means that
11155 are also specific&mdash; by <quote>securing</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights</quote> (i.e.,
11156 copyrights) <quote>for limited Times.</quote>
11157 </para>
11158 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='endofrange'/>
11159 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause2' class='endofrange'/>
11160 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='endofrange'/>
11161 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
11162 <para>
11163 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
11164 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
11165 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
11166 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be <quote>limited</quote> will have
11167 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
11168 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
11169 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
11170 what the Constitution plainly forbids&mdash;perpetual terms <quote>on the
11171 installment plan,</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
11172 </para>
11173 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='endofrange'/>
11174 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='endofrange'/>
11175 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11176 <para>
11177 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
11178 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
11179 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
11180 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
11181 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
11182 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
11183 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
11184 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
11185 this gravy train going.
11186 </para>
11187 <para>
11188 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
11189 government. <quote>Corruption</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
11190 bribed. Rather, <quote>corruption</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
11191 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
11192 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
11193 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
11194 do&mdash;and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
11195 </para>
11196 <para>
11197 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
11198 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
11199 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
11200 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry
11201 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
11202 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
11203 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
11204 published by anyone for free.
11205 </para>
11206 <para>
11207 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from
11208 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
11209 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
11210 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
11211 report:
11212 </para>
11213 <para>
11214 <quote>Next year,</quote> the adviser announces, <quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
11215
11216 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
11217 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
11218 receiving the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of
11219 those works.</quote>
11220 </para>
11221 <para>
11222 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,</quote> she continues, <quote>that
11223 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
11224 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
11225 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.</quote>
11226 </para>
11227 <para>
11228 <quote>Hope?</quote> a fellow board member says. <quote>Can't we be doing something
11229 about it?</quote>
11230 </para>
11231 <para>
11232 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>We could contribute
11233 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
11234 they support the bill.</quote>
11235 </para>
11236 <para>
11237 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
11238 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. <quote>How much
11239 would we get if this extension were passed?</quote> you ask the adviser. <quote>How
11240 much is it worth?</quote>
11241 </para>
11242 <para>
11243 <quote>Well,</quote> the adviser says, <quote>if you're confident that you will continue
11244 to get at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
11245 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent),
11246 then this law would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate.</quote>
11247 </para>
11248 <para>
11249 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
11250 correct conclusion:
11251 </para>
11252 <para>
11253 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
11254 $1,000,000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
11255 contributions
11256 would assure that the bill was passed?</quote>
11257 </para>
11258 <para>
11259 <quote>Absolutely,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>It is worth it to you to
11260 contribute
11261 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
11262 copyrights. Which for us means over $1,000,000.</quote>
11263 </para>
11264 <para>
11265 You quickly get the point&mdash;you as the member of the board and, I
11266 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
11267 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
11268 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
11269 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
11270 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
11271 copyrights
11272 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
11273 the copyright term extended.
11274 </para>
11275 <para>
11276 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
11277 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
11278 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
11279 </para>
11280 <para>
11281 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
11282 Copyright
11283 Term Extension Act, this <quote>theory</quote> about incentives was proved
11284 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
11285 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
11286 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
11287 contributions.<footnote><para>
11288 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, <quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
11289 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years,</quote>
11290 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 17 October 1998, 22.
11291 </para></footnote>
11292 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
11293 $1.5 million lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more
11294 than $200,000 in campaign contributions.<footnote><para>
11295 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, <quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
11296 Age,</quote> available at
11297 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #49</ulink>.
11298 </para></footnote>
11299 Disney is estimated to have
11300 contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in the
11301 cycle.<footnote><para>
11302 <!-- f5. -->
11303 Alan K. Ota, <quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,</quote>
11304 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week</citetitle>, 8 August 1990, available at
11305 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #50</ulink>.
11306 </para></footnote>
11307
11308 </para>
11309 <para>
11310 <emphasis role='strong'>Constitutional law</emphasis> is not oblivious
11311 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
11312 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
11313 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
11314 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
11315 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
11316 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
11317 constitutional requirement that terms be <quote>limited.</quote> If
11318 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
11319 again.
11320 </para>
11321 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='endofrange'/>
11322 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='endofrange'/>
11323 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='endofrange'/>
11324 <para>
11325 It was also my judgment that <emphasis>this</emphasis> Supreme Court
11326 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
11327 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
11328 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
11329 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
11330 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
11331 Supreme Court's
11332
11333 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
11334 decision in 1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
11335 guns near schools.
11336 </para>
11337 <para>
11338 Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
11339 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
11340 power to regulate only <quote>commerce among the several states</quote> (aka
11341 <quote>interstate
11342 commerce</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
11343 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
11344 interstate
11345 commerce.
11346 </para>
11347 <para>
11348 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
11349 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
11350 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
11351 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
11352 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
11353 </para>
11354 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
11355 <para>
11356 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
11357 that in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The government had
11358 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
11359 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
11360 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
11361 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
11362 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
11363 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
11364 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
11365 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
11366 position to second-guess Congress.
11367 </para>
11368 <para>
11369 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,</quote>
11370 the Chief Justice wrote.<footnote><para>
11371 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995).
11372 </para></footnote>
11373 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
11374 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
11375 Congress's power. The decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
11376 later in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>.<footnote><para>
11377 <!-- f7. -->
11378 <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>, 529 U.S. 598 (2000).
11379 </para></footnote>
11380 </para>
11381 <para>
11382 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
11383 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.<footnote><para>
11384 <!-- f8. -->
11385 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
11386 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
11387 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
11388 by the government would allow the government unending power to
11389 regulate commerce&mdash;the limitation to interstate commerce
11390 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
11391 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
11392 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights&mdash;the
11393 limitation to <quote>limited times</quote> notwithstanding.
11394 </para></footnote>
11395 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
11396 yield the conclusion that Congress
11397 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
11398 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
11399 term, then there would be no <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power over
11400 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
11401 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
11402 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
11403 term of existing copyrights.
11404 </para>
11405 <para>
11406 <emphasis>If</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
11407 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> stood for
11408 politics&mdash;a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
11409 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
11410 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
11411 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
11412 demonstrating the <quote>fidelity</quote> in such an interpretation of the
11413 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
11414 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
11415 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
11416 were going to be petty politicians.
11417 </para>
11418 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
11419 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
11420 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11421 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11422 <para>
11423 <emphasis role='strong'>Now let's pause</emphasis> for a moment to
11424 make sure we understand what the argument in
11425 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
11426 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
11427 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
11428 piracy&mdash;piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
11429 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
11430 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
11431 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
11432 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
11433 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
11434 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
11435 power&mdash;expressed through the power of lobbyists' money&mdash;to
11436 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
11437 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
11438 piracy that affects us all.
11439 </para>
11440 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association</primary></indexterm>
11441 <para>
11442 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
11443
11444 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
11445 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
11446 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than <quote>legal piracy.</quote><footnote><para>
11447 <!-- f9. -->
11448 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11449 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available
11450 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #51</ulink>.
11451 </para></footnote>
11452 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
11453 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
11454 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
11455 charter.
11456 </para>
11457 <para>
11458 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
11459 copyright
11460 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
11461 influence
11462 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
11463 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
11464 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
11465 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
11466 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
11467 bought to extend them again.
11468 </para>
11469 <para>
11470 <emphasis role='strong'>It is valuable</emphasis> copyrights that are
11471 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
11472 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.</quote> These works are too valuable for
11473 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
11474 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
11475 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
11476 the 1920s and 1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
11477 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
11478 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
11479 and no longer available as a result.
11480 </para>
11481 <para>
11482 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to
11483 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
11484 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
11485 copyright holders for that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
11486 But the law and its effect were not limited to that 2 percent. The law
11487 extended the terms of copyright generally.<footnote><para>
11488 <!-- f10. --> The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
11489 Congressional
11490 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
11491 of Petitioners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 7, available at
11492 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #52</ulink>.
11493 </para></footnote>
11494
11495 </para>
11496 <para>
11497 Think practically about the consequence of this
11498 extension&mdash;practically,
11499 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
11500
11501 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
11502 work. In 1930, 10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those
11503 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
11504 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
11505 remaining
11506 9,873. What would you have to do?
11507 </para>
11508 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11509 <para>
11510 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were
11511 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
11512 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
11513 titles and authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration
11514 and renewal records for works published in 1930. That will produce a
11515 list of books still under copyright.
11516 </para>
11517 <para>
11518 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
11519 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
11520 </para>
11521 <para>
11522 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
11523 owners
11524 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
11525 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
11526 being at least a list?
11527 </para>
11528 <para>
11529 But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in
11530 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
11531 practically
11532 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
11533 thousands
11534 of such records&mdash;especially since the person who registered is
11535 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930!
11536 </para>
11537 <para>
11538 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,</quote> the
11539 apologists for the system respond. <quote>Why should there be a list of
11540 copyright owners?</quote>
11541 </para>
11542 <para>
11543 Well, actually, if you think about it, there <emphasis>are</emphasis>
11544 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
11545 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
11546 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
11547 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
11548 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
11549 what tangible property.
11550 </para>
11551 <para>
11552 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
11553 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
11554 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
11555
11556 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
11557 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
11558 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
11559 happen
11560 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
11561 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
11562 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
11563 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
11564 know quite well who owns what property.
11565 </para>
11566 <para>
11567 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
11568 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
11569 already
11570 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
11571 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
11572 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
11573 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
11574 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
11575 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
11576 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
11577 </para>
11578 <para>
11579 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
11580 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
11581 consequence
11582 for other creative works is much more dire.
11583 </para>
11584 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'><primary>Agee, Michael</primary></indexterm>
11585 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
11586 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films</primary></indexterm>
11587 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The</primary></indexterm>
11588 <para>
11589 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
11590 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
11591 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
11592 made between 1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, <citetitle>The Lucky Dog</citetitle>, is
11593 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923
11594 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
11595 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
11596 money. According to one estimate, <quote>Roach has sold about 60,000
11597 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's silent
11598 films.</quote><footnote><para>
11599 <!-- f11. -->
11600 See David G. Savage, <quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,</quote>
11601 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, <quote>Classic Movies,
11602 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
11603 Down Copyright Extension,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 9 October 2002.
11604 </para></footnote>
11605 </para>
11606 <para>
11607 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
11608 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
11609 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11610 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11611 </para>
11612 <para>
11613 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11614
11615 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11616 any continuing commercial value. The rest&mdash;to the extent it
11617 survives at all&mdash;sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11618 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11619 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11620 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11621 work available for distribution.
11622 </para>
11623 <para>
11624 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11625 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11626 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11627 it cost more than $10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11628 film in 1993, it can now cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of
11629 8 mm film.<footnote><para>
11630 <!-- f12. -->
11631 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11632 Supporting the Petitoners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11633 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01- 618), 12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11634 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11635 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, available at
11636 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #53</ulink>.
11637 </para></footnote>
11638
11639 </para>
11640 <para>
11641 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11642 important.
11643 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11644 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11645 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11646 locate the copyright owner.
11647 </para>
11648 <para>
11649 Or more accurately, <emphasis>owners</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11650 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11651 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11652 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11653 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11654 to these films is exceptionally high.
11655 </para>
11656 <para>
11657 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11658 copyright owner when she shows up?</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11659 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11660 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11661 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11662 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11663 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11664 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11665 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11666 </para>
11667 <para>
11668 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11669
11670 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11671 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11672 benefit
11673 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11674 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11675 the copyright expires.
11676 </para>
11677 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'/>
11678 <para>
11679 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11680 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11681 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11682 canisters
11683 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11684 than dust.
11685 </para>
11686 <para>
11687 <emphasis role='strong'>Of all the</emphasis> creative work produced
11688 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11689 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11690 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11691 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11692 the copyright acts as an <quote>engine of free expression.</quote>
11693 </para>
11694 <para>
11695 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11696 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11697 indicated,
11698 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11699 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11700 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11701 distributors,
11702 the commercial life ends.
11703 </para>
11704 <para>
11705 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11706 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes &amp; Noble, and
11707 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11708 between
11709 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11710 Friday
11711 night watching a 1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11712 of culture is important and valuable&mdash;for entertainment but also, and
11713 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11714 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11715 have, we need to have access to this history.
11716 </para>
11717 <para>
11718 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11719
11720 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11721 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11722 this context do no good.
11723 </para>
11724 <para>
11725 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11726 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11727 <emphasis>copyright-related use</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11728 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11729 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11730 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11731 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11732 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11733 was independent of copyright law.
11734 </para>
11735 <para>
11736 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11737 a film&mdash;the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs&mdash;were
11738 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11739 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11740 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11741 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11742 market didn't have more to offer.
11743 </para>
11744 <para>
11745 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11746 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11747 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11748 would not have interfered with anything.
11749 </para>
11750 <para>
11751 But this situation has now changed.
11752 </para>
11753 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11754 <para>
11755 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11756 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11757 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11758 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11759 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11760 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11761 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11762 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11763 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11764 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11765 </para>
11766 <para>
11767 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11768 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11769 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11770 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11771 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11772 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11773 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11774 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11775 written for a radically different context.
11776 </para>
11777 <para>
11778 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11779 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11780 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11781 <emphasis>copyright</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11782 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11783 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11784 context, copyright is serving no purpose <emphasis>at all</emphasis>
11785 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11786 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11787 </para>
11788 <para>
11789 You may well ask, <quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11790 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11791 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11792 culture widely?</quote>
11793 </para>
11794 <para>
11795 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11796 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes &amp; Noble
11797 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11798 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11799 of a library is to serve what <quote>the market</quote> would demand. But if you
11800 think the role of a library is bigger than this&mdash;if you think its
11801 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11802 particular bit of that culture or not&mdash;then we can't count on the
11803 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11804 </para>
11805 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'/>
11806 <para>
11807 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11808 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11809 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11810 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11811
11812 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11813 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11814 culture, 94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11815 1923 and 1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11816 commercial market, if access is a value, then 6 percent is a failure
11817 to provide that value.<footnote><para>
11818 <!-- f13. -->
11819 Jason Schultz, <quote>The Myth of the 1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,</quote> 20
11820 December 2002, available at
11821 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #54</ulink>.
11822 </para></footnote>
11823
11824 </para>
11825 <para>
11826 <emphasis role='strong'>In January 1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11827 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11828 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11829 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (1)
11830 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11831 <quote>limited Times</quote> requirement, and (2) that extending terms
11832 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11833 </para>
11834 <para>
11835 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11836 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11837 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11838 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11839 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11840 </para>
11841 <para>
11842 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11843 copyrights be for <quote>limited Times</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11844 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11845 <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11846 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11847 terms that are <quote>limited.</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11848 to interpret the term <quote>limited Times</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11849 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11850 power to extend existing terms.
11851 </para>
11852 <para>
11853 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11854 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11855 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11856 whole, where the court will sit <quote>en banc</quote> to hear the case.
11857 </para>
11858 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David</primary></indexterm>
11859 <para>
11860 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11861 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11862
11863 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11864 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11865 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11866 overstepped its bounds.
11867 </para>
11868 <para>
11869 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11870 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11871 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11872 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11873 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11874 </para>
11875 <para>
11876 But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11877 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11878 was set for October of 2002. The summer would be spent writing
11879 briefs and preparing for argument.
11880 </para>
11881 <para>
11882 <emphasis role='strong'>It is over</emphasis> a year later as I write
11883 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
11884 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
11885 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
11886 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
11887 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
11888 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
11889 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
11890 client, Eric Eldred.
11891 </para>
11892 <para>
11893 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11894 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11895 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11896 mistake lost it.
11897 </para>
11898 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11899 <para>
11900 <emphasis role='strong'>The mistake</emphasis> was made early, though
11901 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
11902 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
11903 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
11904 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
11905 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11906 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11907 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11908 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11909 </para>
11910 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11911 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan</primary></indexterm>
11912 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11913 <para>
11914 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11915 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11916 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11917 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11918 told me, if we could make the issue seem <quote>important</quote> to the Supreme
11919 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11920 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against <quote>the
11921 most powerful media companies in the world.</quote>
11922 </para>
11923 <para>
11924 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
11925 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
11926 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
11927 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
11928 <quote>right</quote> as in <quote>true,</quote> I thought, but it is <quote>wrong</quote> as in <quote>it just shouldn't be
11929 that way.</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
11930 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
11931 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
11932 interpretation
11933 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
11934 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
11935 unconstitutional,
11936 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
11937 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
11938 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
11939 Constitution,
11940 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
11941 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
11942 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
11943 </para>
11944 <para>
11945 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
11946 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
11947 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
11948 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
11949 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
11950 why it was unconstitutional.
11951 </para>
11952 <para>
11953 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
11954
11955 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
11956 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
11957 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
11958 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
11959 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
11960 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
11961 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
11962 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
11963 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
11964 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
11965 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
11966 <emphasis>law</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
11967 the widest range of credible critics&mdash;credible not because they
11968 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
11969 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
11970 </para>
11971 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11972 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis</primary></indexterm>
11973 <para>
11974 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
11975 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
11976 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
11977 Congress. In November 1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
11978 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
11979 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
11980 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
11981 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
11982 to get bogged down?</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
11983 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
11984 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
11985 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
11986 </para>
11987 <para>
11988 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
11989 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
11990 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
11991 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
11992 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
11993 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
11994 </para>
11995 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
11996 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
11997 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
11998 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11999 <para>
12000 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
12001 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
12002
12003 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
12004 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/ Linux
12005 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
12006 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
12007 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
12008 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
12009 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
12010 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
12011 </para>
12012 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries</primary></indexterm>
12013 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union</primary></indexterm>
12014 <para>
12015 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
12016 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
12017 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
12018 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
12019 </para>
12020 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
12021 <para>
12022 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
12023 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
12024 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
12025 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
12026 clear.
12027 </para>
12028 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George</primary></indexterm>
12029 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
12030 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James</primary></indexterm>
12031 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12032 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton</primary></indexterm>
12033 <para>
12034 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
12035 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
12036 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
12037 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
12038 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
12039 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
12040 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
12041 nothing more than <quote>rent-seeking</quote>&mdash;the fancy term economists use
12042 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
12043 </para>
12044 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12045 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan</primary></indexterm>
12046 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen</primary></indexterm>
12047 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12048 <para>
12049 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
12050 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
12051 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
12052 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
12053 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
12054 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
12055 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
12056 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
12057
12058 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
12059 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
12060 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
12061 </para>
12062 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12063 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
12064 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Commerce Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
12065 <para>
12066 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
12067 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
12068 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
12069 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
12070 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
12071 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
12072 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
12073 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
12074 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
12075 confidence in our argument.
12076 </para>
12077 <para>
12078 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
12079 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these <quote>friends</quote> included
12080 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
12081 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
12082 copyright holders.
12083 </para>
12084 <para>
12085 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
12086 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either&mdash;they
12087 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
12088 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
12089 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
12090 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
12091 wanted to control.
12092 </para>
12093 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George</primary></indexterm>
12094 <indexterm><primary>Porgy and Bess</primary></indexterm>
12095 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
12096 <para>
12097 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
12098 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
12099 Dr. Seuss's work&mdash; better than allowing it to fall into the
12100 public domain&mdash;because if this creativity were in the public
12101 domain, then people could use it to <quote>glorify drugs or to create
12102 pornography.</quote><footnote><para>
12103 <!-- f14. -->
12104 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
12105 U.S. (2003) (No. 01-618), 19.
12106 </para></footnote>
12107 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
12108 <quote>protection</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
12109 to license <citetitle>Porgy and Bess</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
12110 Americans in the cast.<footnote><para>
12111 <!-- f15. -->
12112 Dinitia Smith, <quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
12113 Mouse Joins the Fray,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 28 March 1998, B7.
12114 </para></footnote>
12115 That's
12116 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
12117 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
12118 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
12119 </para>
12120 <para>
12121 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
12122 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
12123 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
12124 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
12125 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, <quote>Give us twenty years
12126 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
12127 better with them than anyone else.</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
12128 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
12129 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
12130 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
12131 </para>
12132 <para>
12133 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
12134 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
12135 copyrights&mdash;extensions that would further concentrate the market;
12136 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
12137 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
12138 </para>
12139 <para>
12140 <emphasis role='strong'>Between February</emphasis> and October, there
12141 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
12142 I set the strategy.
12143 </para>
12144 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
12145 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12146 <para>
12147 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
12148 called <quote>the Conservatives.</quote> The other we called <quote>the Rest.</quote> The
12149 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
12150 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
12151 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
12152 five who had supported the <citetitle>Lopez/Morrison</citetitle> line
12153 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
12154 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
12155 </para>
12156 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12157 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12158 <para>
12159 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
12160 Congress's power. These four&mdash;Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
12161 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer&mdash;had repeatedly argued that
12162 the Constitution
12163 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
12164 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
12165 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
12166 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
12167 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
12168 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
12169 </para>
12170 <para>
12171 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
12172 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
12173 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
12174 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
12175 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
12176 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
12177 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
12178 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
12179 sense.
12180 </para>
12181 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12182 <para>
12183 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
12184 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
12185 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
12186 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
12187 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
12188 these retrospective extensions.
12189 </para>
12190 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'/>
12191 <para>
12192 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
12193 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
12194 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
12195 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
12196 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
12197 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
12198 </para>
12199 <para>
12200 This analysis of <quote>the Rest</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
12201 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
12202 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
12203 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
12204 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation&mdash;the
12205 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
12206 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
12207 powers have limits.
12208 </para>
12209 <para>
12210 This then was the core of our strategy&mdash;a strategy for which I am
12211 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
12212 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
12213 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
12214 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
12215 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
12216 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
12217 supposed to be <quote>limited.</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
12218 reconcile <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> with
12219 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
12220 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
12221 be limited.
12222 </para>
12223 <para>
12224 <emphasis role='strong'>The argument</emphasis> on the government's
12225 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
12226 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
12227 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
12228 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
12229 that practice is unconstitutional.
12230 </para>
12231 <para>
12232 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
12233 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in 1831
12234 and in 1909. And of course, in 1962, Congress began extending
12235 existing
12236 terms regularly&mdash;eleven times in forty years.
12237 </para>
12238 <para>
12239 But this <quote>consistency</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
12240 extended
12241 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
12242 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
12243 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
12244 existing
12245 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
12246 restraint
12247 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
12248 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
12249 hesitated
12250 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
12251 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
12252 </para>
12253 <para>
12254 <emphasis role='strong'>Oral argument</emphasis> was scheduled for the
12255 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
12256 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
12257 <quote>mooted</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
12258
12259 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
12260 help in the case. Such <quote>moots</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
12261 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
12262 </para>
12263 <para>
12264 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
12265 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
12266 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
12267 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
12268 Congress
12269 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
12270 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
12271 this central idea.
12272 </para>
12273 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12274 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12275 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12276 <para>
12277 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
12278 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
12279 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
12280 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
12281 </para>
12282 <para>
12283 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
12284 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
12285 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
12286 the harm&mdash;passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
12287 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.</quote>
12288 </para>
12289 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12290 <para>
12291 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
12292 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
12293 right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
12294 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
12295 does the right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it is right. As
12296 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
12297 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
12298 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
12299 </para>
12300 <para>
12301 <emphasis role='strong'>The night before</emphasis> the argument, a
12302 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
12303 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
12304 culture. Hundreds stood in line
12305
12306 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
12307 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
12308 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
12309 </para>
12310 <para>
12311 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
12312 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
12313 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
12314 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
12315 congressmen
12316 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
12317 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
12318 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
12319 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
12320 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
12321 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
12322 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
12323 family of the Justices.
12324 </para>
12325 <para>
12326 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
12327 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
12328 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
12329 those enumerated powers had any limit.
12330 </para>
12331 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12332 <para>
12333 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
12334 The history was bothering her.
12335 </para>
12336 <blockquote>
12337 <para>
12338 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
12339 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
12340 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
12341 practice that began with the very first act.
12342 </para>
12343 </blockquote>
12344 <para>
12345 She was quite willing to concede <quote>that this flies directly in the face
12346 of what the framers had in mind.</quote> But my response again and again
12347 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
12348 </para>
12349 <blockquote>
12350 <para>
12351 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
12352 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
12353 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
12354 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
12355 is yes.
12356 </para>
12357 </blockquote>
12358 <para>
12359 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
12360 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
12361 Kennedy, who observed,
12362 </para>
12363 <blockquote>
12364 <para>
12365 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
12366 the '76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
12367 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
12368 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
12369 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
12370 </para>
12371 </blockquote>
12372 <para>
12373 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
12374 student,
12375 I answered,
12376 </para>
12377 <blockquote>
12378 <para>
12379 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
12380 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
12381 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
12382 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
12383 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
12384 </para>
12385 </blockquote>
12386 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12387 <para>
12388 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
12389 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
12390 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
12391 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
12392 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
12393 </para>
12394 <para>
12395 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
12396 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> ruling,
12397 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
12398 </para>
12399 <para>
12400 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
12401 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
12402
12403 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
12404 </para>
12405 <blockquote>
12406 <para>
12407 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
12408 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
12409 </para>
12410 <para>
12411 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
12412 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
12413 domain
12414 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
12415 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
12416 into the Copyright Clause.
12417 </para>
12418 </blockquote>
12419 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.</primary></indexterm>
12420 <para>
12421 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
12422 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
12423 asked Solicitor General Olson,
12424 </para>
12425 <blockquote>
12426 <para>
12427 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12428 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
12429 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
12430 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12431 time.
12432 </para>
12433 </blockquote>
12434 <para>
12435 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
12436 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
12437 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
12438 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
12439 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
12440 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
12441 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
12442 Patent Clause&mdash; indeed, the very first case striking a law of
12443 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
12444 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
12445 Court to my side.
12446 </para>
12447 <para>
12448 <emphasis role='strong'>As I left</emphasis> the court that day, I
12449 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
12450 hundred questions I wished I had
12451
12452 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
12453 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
12454 optimistic.
12455 </para>
12456 <para>
12457 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
12458 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
12459 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
12460 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
12461 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
12462 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
12463 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
12464 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
12465 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
12466 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
12467 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court&mdash;in particular,
12468 the Conservatives&mdash;would feel itself constrained by the rule of
12469 law that it had established elsewhere.
12470 </para>
12471 <para>
12472 <emphasis role='strong'>The morning</emphasis> of January 15, 2003, I
12473 was five minutes late to the office and missed the 7:00 A.M. call from
12474 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
12475 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
12476 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
12477 majority. There were two dissents.
12478 </para>
12479 <para>
12480 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
12481 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
12482 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
12483 </para>
12484 <para>
12485 My <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
12486 money in the world against <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. And here
12487 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
12488 reasoning.
12489 </para>
12490 <para>
12491 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
12492 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
12493 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
12494 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
12495 even appear in the Court's opinion.
12496 </para>
12497 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12498 <para>
12499
12500 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
12501 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
12502 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
12503 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
12504 </para>
12505 <para>
12506 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable&mdash;for her, and for Justice
12507 Souter. Neither believes in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
12508 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
12509 they had worked so hard to defeat.
12510 </para>
12511 <para>
12512 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
12513 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
12514 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
12515 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
12516 reconcile the two simply <emphasis>by not addressing the
12517 argument</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
12518 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
12519 followed from the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
12520 be limited, but in this context it would not.
12521 </para>
12522 <para>
12523 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
12524 they would respect? By what right did they&mdash;the silent
12525 five&mdash;get to select the part of the Constitution they would
12526 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
12527 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
12528 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
12529 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
12530 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
12531 the system we have.
12532 </para>
12533 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12534 <para>
12535 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
12536 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
12537 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
12538 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
12539 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
12540 the Court discounted the parallel&mdash;without explaining how the
12541 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
12542 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
12543 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
12544 </para>
12545 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12546 <para>
12547 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
12548 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
12549 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
12550 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
12551 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8
12552 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
12553 that the actual number was 99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
12554 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
12555 <quote>limited,</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
12556 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
12557 </para>
12558 <para>
12559 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
12560 because neither believed in the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
12561 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
12562 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
12563 Sentelle. It was <citetitle>Hamlet</citetitle> without the Prince.
12564 </para>
12565 <para>
12566 <emphasis role='strong'>Defeat brings depression</emphasis>. They say
12567 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
12568 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
12569 sorts.
12570 </para>
12571 <indexterm><primary>originalism</primary></indexterm>
12572 <para>
12573 It was first anger with the five <quote>Conservatives.</quote> It would have been
12574 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> didn't
12575 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
12576 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
12577 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
12578 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
12579 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is <quote>originalism</quote>&mdash;to
12580 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
12581 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
12582 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> and many other <quote>originalist</quote> rulings. Where was their
12583 <quote>originalism</quote> now?
12584 </para>
12585 <para>
12586 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
12587 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
12588 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
12589 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
12590
12591 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
12592 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
12593 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
12594 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
12595 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
12596 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
12597 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
12598 own principles.
12599 </para>
12600 <para>
12601 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
12602 myself.
12603 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
12604 the law as it is.
12605 </para>
12606 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12607 <para>
12608 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
12609 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
12610 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
12611 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
12612 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
12613 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12614 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12615 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12616 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12617 </para>
12618 <para>
12619 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12620 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12621 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12622 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12623 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12624 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12625 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12626 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12627 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12628 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12629 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12630 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12631 effort to persuade; but I
12632 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12633 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12634 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12635 should decide the issue.
12636 </para>
12637 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12638 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12639 <para>
12640 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12641 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12642 Kathleen Sullivan?
12643 </para>
12644 <para>
12645 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12646 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12647 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12648 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12649 </para>
12650 <para>
12651 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12652 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12653 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12654 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12655 have persuaded.
12656 </para>
12657 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12658 <para>
12659 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12660 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12661 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12662 case was a mistake. <quote>The Court is not ready,</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12663 issue should not be raised until it is.
12664 </para>
12665 <para>
12666 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12667 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12668 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12669 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12670 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12671 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12672 this case&mdash;a decision I had made four years before&mdash;was wrong.
12673 </para>
12674 <para>
12675 <emphasis role='strong'>While the reaction</emphasis> to the Sonny
12676 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12677 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12678 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12679 that battle over ideas. Where
12680
12681 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12682 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12683 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12684 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12685 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12686 harmful law. <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12687 </para>
12688 <blockquote>
12689 <para>
12690 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12691 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12692 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12693 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12694 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12695 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12696 </para>
12697 </blockquote>
12698 <para>
12699 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12700 hilarious images&mdash;of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12701 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced on the next page
12702 (<xref linkend="fig-18"/>). The <quote>powerful and wealthy</quote> line is a bit
12703 unfair. But the punch in the face felt exactly like that.
12704 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12705 </para>
12706 <figure id="fig-18">
12707 <title>Tom the Dancing Bug cartoon</title>
12708 <graphic fileref="images/18.png"></graphic>
12709 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12710 </figure>
12711 <para>
12712 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12713 quote from <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>. That <quote>grand experiment</quote> we call the
12714 <quote>public domain</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think, <quote>Honey,
12715 I shrunk the Constitution.</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12716 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12717 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12718 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12719 </para>
12720 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12721 </chapter>
12722 <chapter label="14" id="eldred-ii">
12723 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II</title>
12724 <para>
12725 <emphasis role='strong'>The day</emphasis>
12726 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12727 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12728 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was denied&mdash;meaning the case was
12729 really finally over&mdash;fate would have it that I was giving a
12730 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12731 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12732 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12733 wrote an op-ed piece.
12734 </para>
12735 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12736 <para>
12737 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12738 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12739 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12740 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12741 Justice Kennedy: <quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12742 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12743 that.</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12744 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12745 </para>
12746 <para>
12747 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12748 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12749 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12750 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12751 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12752 the work passed into the public domain.
12753 </para>
12754 <para>
12755 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12756 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12757 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12758 </para>
12759 <para>
12760 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12761 is either the <quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act</quote> or the <quote>Copyright
12762 Term Deregulation Act.</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12763 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12764 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12765 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $1. But for
12766 everything else, let the content go.
12767 </para>
12768 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12769 <para>
12770 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12771 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12772 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12773 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12774 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12775 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12776 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12777 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12778 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12779 the stupid harm of the present system.
12780 </para>
12781 <para>
12782 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12783 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12784 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12785 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12786 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12787 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12788 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12789 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12790 where copyright owners could be identified.
12791 </para>
12792 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12793 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12794 <para>
12795 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12796 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
12797 linkend="property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12798 removed in 1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12799 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.<footnote><para>
12800 <!-- f1. -->
12801 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law</primary></indexterm>
12802 Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12803 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12804 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12805 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act,
12806 every text of the Convention has provided that <quote>the enjoyment and the
12807 exercise</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention <quote>shall not be subject
12808 to any formality.</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12809 embodied in Article 5(2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12810 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12811 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12812 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12813 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12814 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12815 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12816 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12817 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>International
12818 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12819 Press, 2001), 153&ndash;54. </para></footnote>
12820 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a <quote>natural right.</quote> Natural
12821 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12822 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12823 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12824 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12825 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12826 </para>
12827 <para>
12828 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12829 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12830 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12831 <quote>Walt Disney creativity</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12832 know what's protected and what's not.
12833 </para>
12834 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12835 <para>
12836 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12837 Berlin in 1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12838 Convention in 1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12839 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12840 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12841 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12842 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an <citetitle>i</citetitle> or cross a
12843 <citetitle>t</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12844 </para>
12845 <para>
12846 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12847 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12848 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12849 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12850 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12851 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12852 </para>
12853 <para>
12854 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12855 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12856 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12857 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12858 burden
12859 imposed upon creators.
12860 </para>
12861 <para>
12862 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was
12863 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12864
12865 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12866 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12867 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12868 the government. He has a property right over the table <quote>naturally,</quote>
12869 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12870 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12871 table.
12872 </para>
12873 <para>
12874 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12875 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12876 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12877 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12878 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12879 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12880 spread.
12881 </para>
12882 <para>
12883 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12884 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12885 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12886 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12887 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12888 important reason to secure registration&mdash;both because it makes
12889 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12890 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12891 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12892 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12893 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12894 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12895 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12896 system of protection for property generally.
12897 </para>
12898 <para>
12899 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12900 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12901 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12902 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12903 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12904 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12905 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12906 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12907
12908 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12909 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12910 <emphasis>lawyer</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12911 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
12912 </para>
12913 <para>
12914 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12915 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12916 didn't <quote>get.</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
12917 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
12918 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, <quote>short,</quote> then this
12919 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
12920 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
12921 be presumptively uncontrolled.
12922 </para>
12923 <para>
12924 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
12925 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
12926 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
12927 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
12928 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
12929 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
12930 seen before <emphasis>because there are no formalities</emphasis>.
12931 </para>
12932 <para>
12933 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
12934 it is worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
12935 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
12936 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
12937 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
12938 </para>
12939 <para>
12940 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
12941 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
12942 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
12943 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
12944 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you.
12945 </para>
12946 <para>
12947 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
12948 registering the work mean that the $1 is really misleading? Isn't the
12949 hassle worth more than $1? Isn't that the real problem with
12950 registration?
12951 </para>
12952 <para>
12953 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
12954 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
12955 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
12956
12957 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
12958 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
12959 address the real problem of <emphasis>governments</emphasis> standing
12960 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
12961 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
12962 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
12963 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
12964 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
12965 upon historical data, that system would move up to 98 percent of
12966 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
12967 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
12968 </para>
12969 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12970 <para>
12971 <emphasis role='strong'>When Steve Forbes</emphasis> endorsed the
12972 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
12973 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
12974 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
12975 willing to take the first step.
12976 </para>
12977 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe</primary></indexterm>
12978 <para>
12979 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
12980 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
12981 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
12982 possible. In May 2003, it looked as if the bill would be
12983 introduced. On May 16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, <quote>we are
12984 close.</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
12985 something good might happen here.
12986 </para>
12987 <para>
12988 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
12989 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
12990 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
12991 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
12992 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
12993 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
12994 </para>
12995 <para>
12996 The MPAA argued first that Congress had <quote>firmly rejected the central
12997 concept in the proposed bill</quote>&mdash;that copyrights be renewed. That
12998 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's <quote>firm rejection</quote> had occurred
12999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
13000 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
13001 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
13002 owners&mdash;apparently those who could not afford the $1 fee. Third,
13003 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
13004 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
13005 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
13006 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
13007 off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
13008 argued that the bill would impose <quote>enormous</quote> costs, since a
13009 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
13010 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
13011 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
13012 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
13013 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
13014 film is a valid derivative use.
13015 </para>
13016 <para>
13017 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
13018 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
13019 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
13020 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
13021 or not&mdash;a controversial claim in any case&mdash;unless they know
13022 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
13023 </para>
13024 <para>
13025 <emphasis role='strong'>At the beginning</emphasis> of this book, I
13026 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
13027 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
13028 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
13029 opposition&mdash;the power of the side that fought to defend the
13030 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
13031 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
13032 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
13033 </para>
13034 <para>
13035 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
13036 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
13037 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
13038 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
13039 sense?
13040 </para>
13041 <para>
13042
13043 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
13044 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
13045 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
13046 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
13047 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
13048 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
13049 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
13050 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
13051 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
13052 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
13053 </para>
13054 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin</primary></indexterm>
13055 <para>
13056 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
13057 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
13058 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
13059 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
13060 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
13061 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the <quote>Dark
13062 Content</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
13063 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
13064 </para>
13065 <para>
13066 What does this industry really want?
13067 </para>
13068 <para>
13069 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
13070 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
13071 protecting <emphasis>their</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
13072 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
13073 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
13074 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
13075 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
13076 content that doesn't require <emphasis>their</emphasis> permission
13077 first.
13078 </para>
13079 <para>
13080 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
13081 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
13082 its aim not the protection of <quote>property</quote> but the rejection of a
13083 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
13084 theirs. <emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
13085 theirs</emphasis>.
13086 </para>
13087 <para>
13088 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
13089 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
13090
13091 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
13092 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
13093 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
13094 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
13095 and to share its own creation.
13096 </para>
13097 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13098 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13099 <para>
13100 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
13101 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
13102 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
13103 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
13104 block the progress of others.
13105 </para>
13106 <para>
13107 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
13108 <quote>property</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
13109 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
13110 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing <quote>permission
13111 society.</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
13112 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
13113 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
13114 </para>
13115 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
13116 </chapter>
13117 </part>
13118 <chapter label="15" id="c-conclusion">
13119 <title>CONCLUSION</title>
13120 <indexterm id='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='startofrange'><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in</primary></indexterm>
13121 <indexterm id='idxaidsmedications' class='startofrange'><primary>AIDS medications</primary></indexterm>
13122 <indexterm id='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='startofrange'><primary>antiretroviral drugs</primary></indexterm>
13123 <indexterm id='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>developing countries, foreign patent costs in</primary></indexterm>
13124 <indexterm id='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='startofrange'><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13125 <indexterm id='idxhivaidstherapies' class='startofrange'><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies</primary></indexterm>
13126 <para>
13127 <emphasis role='strong'>There are more</emphasis> than 35 million
13128 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
13129 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
13130 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
13131 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
13132 </para>
13133 <para>
13134 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
13135 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
13136 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
13137 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
13138 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
13139 the disease almost invisible.
13140 </para>
13141 <para>
13142 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
13143 United States, they cost between $10,000 and $15,000 per person per
13144 year. Today, some cost $25,000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
13145 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
13146 population:
13147 $15,000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
13148 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.<footnote><para>
13149 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, <quote>Final Report: Integrating
13150 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy</quote> (London, 2002),
13151 available at
13152 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
13153 release
13154 issued 9 July 2002, only 230,000 of the 6 million who need drugs in
13155 the developing world receive them&mdash;and half of them are in Brazil.
13156 </para></footnote>
13157 </para>
13158 <indexterm id='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13159 <indexterm id='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>pharmaceutical patents</primary></indexterm>
13160 <para>
13161 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
13162 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
13163 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
13164 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
13165 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
13166 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
13167 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
13168 </para>
13169 <para>
13170 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
13171 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
13172 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
13173 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
13174 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
13175 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
13176 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
13177 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
13178 changes.
13179 </para>
13180 <para>
13181 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
13182 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
13183 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
13184 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
13185 costs significantly below the market price.
13186 </para>
13187 <indexterm id='idxinternationallaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>international law</primary></indexterm>
13188 <indexterm id='idxparallelimportation' class='startofrange'><primary>parallel importation</primary></indexterm>
13189 <indexterm id='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='startofrange'><primary>South Africa, Republic of, pharmaceutical imports by</primary></indexterm>
13190 <para>
13191 In 1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
13192 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
13193 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
13194 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
13195 Africa from India. This is called <quote>parallel importation,</quote> and it is
13196 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
13197 permitted within the European Union.<footnote>
13198 <para>
13199 <!-- f2. -->
13200 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
13201 Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37.
13202 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13203 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13204 </para></footnote>
13205 </para>
13206 <indexterm><primary>United States Trade Representative (USTR)</primary></indexterm>
13207 <para>
13208 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
13209 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
13210 characterized it, <quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa &hellip;
13211 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
13212 imports.</quote><footnote><para>
13213 <!-- f3. -->
13214 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13215 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13216 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13217 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 14, available at
13218 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #56</ulink>. For a
13219 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
13220 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
13221 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess.,
13222 Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150&ndash;57 (statement of James
13223 Love).
13224 </para></footnote>
13225 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
13226 government asked South Africa to change the law&mdash;and to add
13227 pressure to that request, in 1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
13228 possible trade sanctions.
13229 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
13230 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
13231 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
13232 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
13233 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
13234 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
13235 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
13236 patent&mdash; pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
13237 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
13238 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
13239 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.<footnote><para>
13240 <!-- f4. -->
13241 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13242 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13243 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13244 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 15. </para></footnote>
13245 </para>
13246 <indexterm startref='idxparallelimportation' class='endofrange'/>
13247 <para>
13248 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
13249 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
13250 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
13251 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
13252 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
13253 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
13254 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
13255 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
13256 </para>
13257 <para>
13258 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
13259 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
13260 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
13261 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
13262 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
13263 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save 15 to 30 million lives.
13264 </para>
13265 <para>
13266 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
13267 profits of United States drug companies&mdash;at least, not substantially. It
13268 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
13269 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
13270 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
13271 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
13272 by U.S. companies.
13273 </para>
13274 <para>
13275 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
13276 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
13277 argument
13278 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
13279 about the sanctity of property.<footnote><para>
13280 <!-- f5. -->
13281 See Sabin Russell, <quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
13282 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24
13283 May 1999, A1, available at
13284 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #57</ulink>
13285 (<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
13286 system of intellectual property protection</quote>); Robert Weissman, <quote>AIDS
13287 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
13288 Medicines,</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus</citetitle> 4:23 (August 1999), available at
13289 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #58</ulink>
13290 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, <quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
13291 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
13292 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
13293 Symposium Journal</citetitle> (Spring 2001): 175.
13294 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
13295 </para></footnote>
13296 It was because <quote>intellectual property</quote> would be violated that these
13297 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
13298 importance of <quote>intellectual property</quote> that led these government actors
13299 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
13300 </para>
13301 <indexterm startref='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='endofrange'/>
13302 <para>
13303 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
13304 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
13305 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
13306 direct cost would be to speed the death of 15 to 30 million Africans,
13307 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the <quote>sanctity</quote> of an
13308 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
13309 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
13310 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
13311 </para>
13312 <indexterm id='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>in pharmaceutical industry</secondary></indexterm>
13313 <para>
13314 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
13315 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
13316 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
13317 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
13318 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system&mdash;
13319 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
13320 </para>
13321 <para>
13322 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
13323 drug companies would love&mdash;they say, and I believe them&mdash;to
13324 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
13325 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
13326 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
13327 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
13328 </para>
13329 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>of drug patents</secondary></indexterm>
13330 <para>
13331 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
13332 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
13333 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, <quote>How
13334 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $1 a pill, but the same
13335 drug would cost an American $1,500?</quote> Because there is no <quote>sound
13336 bite</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
13337 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
13338 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
13339 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
13340 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
13341 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
13342 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal&mdash;the sanctity of an
13343 idea called <quote>intellectual property.</quote>
13344 </para>
13345 <indexterm startref='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='endofrange'/>
13346 <indexterm startref='idxaidsmedications' class='endofrange'/>
13347 <indexterm startref='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='endofrange'/>
13348 <indexterm startref='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='endofrange'/>
13349 <indexterm startref='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='endofrange'/>
13350 <indexterm startref='idxhivaidstherapies' class='endofrange'/>
13351 <indexterm startref='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='endofrange'/>
13352 <para>
13353 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
13354 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
13355 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
13356 What is the argument?
13357 </para>
13358 <para>
13359 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
13360 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
13361 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
13362 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
13363 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
13364 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
13365 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
13366 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
13367 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
13368 were balanced in just this sense.
13369 </para>
13370 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='endofrange'/>
13371 <indexterm startref='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13372 <indexterm startref='idxinternationallaw2' class='endofrange'/>
13373 <para>
13374 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
13375 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
13376 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
13377 our tradition, now reigns in this culture&mdash;bizarrely, and with
13378 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
13379 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
13380 </para>
13381 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13382 <para>
13383 <emphasis role='strong'>A simple idea</emphasis> blinds us, and under
13384 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
13385 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
13386 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
13387 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
13388 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
13389 control of that property removes our
13390 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
13391 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
13392 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
13393 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
13394 this common sense open its eyes.
13395 </para>
13396 <para>
13397 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
13398 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
13399 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
13400 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
13401 to fight <quote>piracy,</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
13402 the idea of <quote>creative property,</quote> while transforming real creators into
13403 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
13404 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
13405 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
13406 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
13407 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
13408 produce the <quote>perfect storm</quote> for free culture.
13409 </para>
13410 <indexterm><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
13411 <indexterm><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13412 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13413 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
13414 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13415 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
13416 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
13417 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>public projects in</secondary></indexterm>
13418 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)</primary></indexterm>
13419 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust</primary></indexterm>
13420 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13421 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web</primary></indexterm>
13422 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System</primary></indexterm>
13423 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
13424 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13425 <para>
13426 <emphasis role='strong'>In August 2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
13427 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
13428 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.<footnote><para>
13429 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>,
13430 August 2003, E1, available at
13431 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #59</ulink>; William New, <quote>Global Group's
13432 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13433 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13434 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #60</ulink>; William New, <quote>U.S. Official
13435 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13436 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13437 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #61</ulink>.
13438 </para></footnote>
13439 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
13440 a meeting to discuss <quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
13441 goods.</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
13442 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
13443 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
13444 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
13445 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
13446 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
13447 that I describe in chapter
13448 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="c-afterword"/>. It
13449 included a project to develop single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs),
13450 which are thought to have great significance in biomedical
13451 research. (That nonprofit project comprised a consortium of the
13452 Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and technological companies,
13453 including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
13454 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
13455 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
13456 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
13457 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
13458 in the early 1980s. And it included <quote>open source and free software.</quote>
13459 </para>
13460 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'/>
13461 <para>
13462 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
13463 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
13464 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
13465 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
13466 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
13467 </para>
13468 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>in international debate on intellectual property</secondary></indexterm>
13469 <para>
13470 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.<footnote><para>
13471 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
13472 meeting.
13473 </para></footnote>
13474 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
13475 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
13476 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
13477 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
13478 property issues.
13479 </para>
13480 <indexterm id='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='startofrange'><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13481 <para>
13482 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
13483 about WIPO. In February 2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
13484 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
13485 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
13486 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
13487 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
13488 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
13489 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
13490 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
13491 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
13492 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
13493 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
13494 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
13495 talk about an <quote>Information Society</quote> unless one also talked about the
13496 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
13497 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
13498 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
13499 stuff of
13500 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
13501 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
13502 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
13503 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
13504 </para>
13505 <para>
13506 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
13507 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
13508 thus the meeting about <quote>open and collaborative projects to create
13509 public goods</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
13510 </para>
13511 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='endofrange'/>
13512 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='endofrange'/>
13513 <indexterm startref='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='endofrange'/>
13514 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
13515 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
13516 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>on free software</secondary></indexterm>
13517 <para>
13518 But there is one project within that list that is highly
13519 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is <quote>open source
13520 and free software.</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
13521 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
13522 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
13523 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
13524 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
13525 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
13526 rather than <quote>proprietary software,</quote> for their own internal uses.
13527 </para>
13528 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft</quote> licenses</primary></indexterm>
13529 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13530 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13531 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13532 <para>
13533 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
13534 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
13535 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
13536 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
13537 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
13538 operating system, the most famous bit of <quote>free software</quote>&mdash;and IBM
13539 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support <quote>open source and
13540 free software</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
13541 to support a mode of software development that is different from
13542 Microsoft's.<footnote><para>
13543 <!-- f8. -->
13544 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
13545 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
13546 <quote>open source</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
13547 principal opposition is to <quote>free software</quote> licensed under a <quote>copyleft</quote>
13548 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
13549 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, <quote>The Future
13550 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
13551 Toward Open Source Software</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
13552 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
13553 Public Policy Research, 2002), 69, available at
13554 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #62</ulink>. See also
13555 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, <citetitle>The Commercial Software
13556 Model</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (3
13557 May 2001), available at
13558 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #63</ulink>.
13559 </para></footnote>
13560 </para>
13561 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='endofrange'/>
13562 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)</primary></indexterm>
13563 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)</primary></indexterm>
13564 <para>
13565 More important for our purposes, to support <quote>open source and free
13566 software</quote> is not to oppose copyright. <quote>Open source and free software</quote>
13567 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
13568 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
13569 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
13570 by
13571 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
13572 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
13573 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
13574 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
13575 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
13576 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
13577 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
13578 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
13579 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
13580 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
13581 </para>
13582 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13583 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13584 <indexterm id='idxkrimjonathan' class='startofrange'><primary>Krim, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
13585 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by</secondary></indexterm>
13586 <para>
13587 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
13588 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
13589 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
13590 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
13591 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
13592 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
13593 States government to veto the meeting.<footnote><para>
13594 <!-- f9. -->
13595 Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> available at <ulink
13596 url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #64</ulink>.
13597 </para></footnote>
13598 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
13599 </para>
13600 <para>
13601 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
13602 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
13603 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
13604 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
13605 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
13606 its lobbying efforts.
13607 </para>
13608 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='endofrange'/>
13609 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13610 <para>
13611 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
13612 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
13613 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
13614 Office, explained that <quote>open-source software runs counter to the
13615 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.</quote>
13616 She is quoted as saying, <quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
13617 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
13618 goals of WIPO.</quote>
13619 </para>
13620 <indexterm startref='idxkrimjonathan' class='endofrange'/>
13621 <para>
13622 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
13623 </para>
13624 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='endofrange'/>
13625 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
13626 <para>
13627 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
13628 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
13629 right called <quote>copyright</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
13630 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it <quote>runs counter</quote> to the mission
13631 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
13632 in understanding&mdash;the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
13633 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
13634 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
13635 </para>
13636 <indexterm><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13637 <indexterm><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13638 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs</primary></indexterm>
13639 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13640 <para>
13641 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to <quote>promote</quote>
13642 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
13643 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
13644 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
13645 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
13646 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
13647 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
13648 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
13649 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
13650 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
13651 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
13652 </para>
13653 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
13654 <para>
13655 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
13656 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
13657 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13658 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13659 <emphasis>their</emphasis> rights. If they want to <quote>waive</quote> or
13660 <quote>disclaim</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13661 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $20 billion to do
13662 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13663 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13664 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13665 to do with <emphasis>their</emphasis> property.
13666 </para>
13667 <indexterm id='idxboland' class='startofrange'><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13668 <para>
13669 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13670 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,</quote> she's
13671 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13672 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13673 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13674 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from <quote>waiving</quote> or
13675 <quote>disclaiming</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13676 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13677 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13678 way possible.
13679 </para>
13680 <indexterm id='idxfeudalsystem' class='startofrange'><primary>feudal system</primary></indexterm>
13681 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>feudal system of</secondary></indexterm>
13682 <para>
13683 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13684 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called <quote>feudalism.</quote> Under
13685 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13686 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13687 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13688 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13689 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13690 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13691 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13692 that control.
13693 </para>
13694 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13695 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13696 <para>
13697 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13698 choice we are now making about intellectual property.<footnote><para>
13699 <!-- f10. -->
13700 See Drahos with Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism</citetitle>, 210&ndash;20.
13701 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13702 </para></footnote>
13703 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13704 choice now is whether that information society will be
13705 <emphasis>free</emphasis> or <emphasis>feudal</emphasis>. The trend is
13706 toward the feudal.
13707 </para>
13708 <indexterm startref='idxfeudalsystem' class='endofrange'/>
13709 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='endofrange'/>
13710 <para>
13711 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13712 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13713 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13714 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13715 </para>
13716 <blockquote>
13717 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='endofrange'/>
13718 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='endofrange'/>
13719 <para>
13720 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13721 it should be (<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13722 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13723 not simply to promote intellectual property rights</quote>), not as it is. If
13724 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13725 say anything wrong. But in the world
13726 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13727 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13728 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13729 </para>
13730 </blockquote>
13731 <para>
13732 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13733 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13734 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13735 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13736 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13737 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13738 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13739 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13740 </para>
13741 <indexterm startref='idxboland' class='endofrange'/>
13742 <para>
13743 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13744 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13745 <quote>goal</quote> of a government should be <quote>to promote the right balance</quote> of
13746 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13747 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. <quote>Typical for
13748 an academic,</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13749 </para>
13750 <para>
13751 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13752 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13753 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13754 our own country's history).
13755 </para>
13756 <para>
13757 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13758 government should be to <quote>seek balance,</quote> then count me with the silly,
13759 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13760 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13761 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13762 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13763 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13764 not lies is just na&iuml;ve, then who have we, the most powerful
13765 democracy in the world, become?
13766 </para>
13767 <para>
13768 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13769 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13770 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13771 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13772 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13773 been part of our tradition for most of our history&mdash;free culture.
13774 </para>
13775 <para>
13776 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13777 </para>
13778 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
13779 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
13780 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted</primary></indexterm>
13781 <para>
13782 <emphasis role='strong'>There are moments</emphasis> of hope in this
13783 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13784 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13785 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13786 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13787 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13788 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13789 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing 700,000 letters were
13790 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13791 </para>
13792 <para>
13793 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13794 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13795 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13796 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13797 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13798 concentration in the media.
13799 </para>
13800 <para>
13801 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13802 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13803 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13804 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13805 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13806 </para>
13807 <para>
13808 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13809 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13810 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13811 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13812 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13813 range of rights&mdash;property rights of a historically extreme
13814 form&mdash;that makes their bigness bad.
13815 </para>
13816 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13817 <para>
13818 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13819 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13820 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13821 Americans have a long history of fighting <quote>big,</quote> wisely or not. That
13822 we could be motivated to fight <quote>big</quote> again is not something new.
13823 </para>
13824 <para>
13825 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13826 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13827 the idea of <quote>intellectual property.</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13828 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13829 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13830 called <quote>property</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13831 </para>
13832 <para>
13833 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13834 of our tragedy.
13835 </para>
13836 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob</primary></indexterm>
13837 <para>
13838 <emphasis role='strong'>As I write</emphasis> these final words, the
13839 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
13840 three hundred individuals.<footnote><para>
13841 <!-- f11. -->
13842 John Borland, <quote>RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers,</quote> CNET News.com, September
13843 2003, available at
13844 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #65</ulink>; Paul
13845 R. La Monica, <quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,</quote> CNN/Money, 8 September
13846 2003, available at
13847 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #66</ulink>; Soni
13848 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, <quote>Sued for a Song,
13849 N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among 261 Cited as Sharers,</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News</citetitle>, 9
13850 September 2003, 3; Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13851 Targets; Single Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13852 Defendants,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13853 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,</quote> <citetitle>Wired News</citetitle>, 10 September 2003,
13854 available at
13855 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #67</ulink>.
13856 </para></footnote>
13857 Eminem has just been sued for <quote>sampling</quote> someone else's
13858 music.<footnote><para>
13859 <!-- f12. -->
13860 Jon Wiederhorn, <quote>Eminem Gets Sued &hellip; by a Little Old Lady,</quote>
13861 mtv.com, 17 September 2003, available at
13862 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #68</ulink>.
13863 </para></footnote>
13864 The story about Bob Dylan <quote>stealing</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13865 finished making the rounds.<footnote><para>
13866 <!-- f13. -->
13867 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, <quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13868 Dylan Songs,</quote> Kansascity.com, 9 July 2003, available at
13869 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #69</ulink>.
13870 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13871 </para></footnote>
13872 An insider from Hollywood&mdash;who insists he must remain
13873 anonymous&mdash;reports <quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13874 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13875 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13876 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13877 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.</quote> Congressmen are
13878 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13879 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13880 kids who use a computer to share content.
13881 </para>
13882 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13883 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13884 <indexterm><primary>BBC</primary></indexterm>
13885 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in</primary></indexterm>
13886 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
13887 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto</primary></indexterm>
13888 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>public creative archive in</secondary></indexterm>
13889 <para>
13890 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13891 that it will build a <quote>Creative Archive,</quote> from which British citizens can
13892 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.<footnote><para>
13893 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,</quote> BBC press release,
13894 24 August 2003, available at
13895 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #70</ulink>.
13896 </para></footnote>
13897 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13898 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13899 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13900 country.<footnote><para>
13901 <!-- f15. -->
13902 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,</quote> Creative Commons Weblog, 6 August 2003,
13903 available at
13904 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #71</ulink>.
13905 </para></footnote>
13906 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13907 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13908 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13909 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13910 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13911 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13912 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13913 day into the Causbys.
13914 </para>
13915 <para>
13916 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
13917 potential is ever to be realized.
13918
13919 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
13920
13921 </para>
13922 </chapter>
13923 <chapter label="16" id="c-afterword">
13924 <title>AFTERWORD</title>
13925 <para>
13926
13927 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
13928 <emphasis role='strong'>At least some</emphasis> who have read this
13929 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
13930 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
13931 </para>
13932 <para>
13933 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
13934 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
13935 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
13936 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
13937 </para>
13938 <para>
13939 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
13940 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
13941 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists&mdash;all to tell this
13942 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
13943 is so important.
13944 </para>
13945 <para>
13946 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
13947 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
13948 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
13949 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
13950 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
13951 </para>
13952 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
13953
13954 <section id="usnow">
13955 <title>US, NOW</title>
13956 <para>
13957 <emphasis role='strong'>Common sense</emphasis> is with the copyright
13958 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
13959 extremes&mdash;as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
13960 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
13961 choice, then the warriors should win.
13962 </para>
13963 <para>
13964 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
13965 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
13966 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright&mdash;<quote>All Rights
13967 Reserved</quote>&mdash; and those who reject copyright&mdash;<quote>No Rights
13968 Reserved.</quote> The <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
13969 permission before you <quote>use</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The <quote>No
13970 Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
13971 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
13972 </para>
13973 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
13974 <indexterm id='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>initial free character of</secondary></indexterm>
13975 <para>
13976 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
13977 tilted in the <quote>no rights reserved</quote> direction. Content could be copied
13978 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
13979 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
13980 the
13981
13982 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
13983 original design of the Internet was <quote>no rights reserved.</quote> Content was
13984 <quote>taken</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
13985 unprotected.
13986 </para>
13987 <para>
13988 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
13989 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
13990 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
13991 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
13992 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
13993 architecture made the effective default <quote>no rights reserved,</quote> the
13994 future architecture will make the effective default <quote>all rights
13995 reserved.</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
13996 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
13997 content requires permission. The <quote>cut and paste</quote> world that defines
13998 the Internet today will become a <quote>get permission to cut and paste</quote>
13999 world that is a creator's nightmare.
14000 </para>
14001 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='endofrange'/>
14002 <indexterm startref='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='endofrange'/>
14003 <para>
14004 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle&mdash;neither
14005 <quote>all rights reserved</quote> nor <quote>no rights reserved</quote> but <quote>some rights
14006 reserved</quote>&mdash; and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
14007 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
14008 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
14009 before.
14010 </para>
14011 <section id="examples">
14012 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples</title>
14013 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>restoration efforts on previous aspects of</secondary></indexterm>
14014 <indexterm id='idxbrowsing' class='startofrange'><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
14015 <indexterm id='idxprivacyrights2' class='startofrange'><primary>privacy rights</primary></indexterm>
14016 <para>
14017 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
14018 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
14019 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
14020 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
14021 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
14022 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
14023 to your neighbors or boss. The <quote>privacy</quote> of your browsing habits was
14024 assured.
14025 </para>
14026 <para>
14027 What made it assured?
14028 </para>
14029 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
14030 <para>
14031 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
14032 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>, your
14033 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
14034 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
14035 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
14036 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
14037 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
14038 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
14039 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
14040 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
14041 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
14042 (there is no law protecting <quote>privacy</quote> in public places), and in many
14043 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
14044 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
14045 </para>
14046 <indexterm id='idxamazon' class='startofrange'><primary>Amazon</primary></indexterm>
14047 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet</primary></indexterm>
14048 <indexterm id='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>privacy protection on</secondary></indexterm>
14049 <para>
14050 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
14051 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
14052 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
14053 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
14054 <quote>recently viewed</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
14055 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
14056 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any <quote>privacy</quote>
14057 protected by the friction disappears, too.
14058 </para>
14059 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>privacy rights in use of</secondary></indexterm>
14060 <para>
14061 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
14062 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
14063 people should have the <quote>right</quote> to browse in a library without the
14064 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
14065 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
14066 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
14067 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
14068 disappears.
14069 </para>
14070 <indexterm startref='idxbrowsing' class='endofrange'/>
14071 <indexterm startref='idxamazon' class='endofrange'/>
14072 <para>
14073 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define <quote>privacy</quote>
14074 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
14075 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
14076 friction did.<footnote><para>
14077 <!-- f1. -->
14078
14079 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, <quote>Fair Information Practices and the
14080 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
14081 Law Review</citetitle> 1 (2001): par. 6&ndash;18, available at
14082
14083 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>
14084 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
14085 also Jeffrey Rosen, <citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
14086 in an Anxious Age</citetitle> (New York: Random House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs
14087 between technology and privacy).</para></footnote>
14088 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
14089 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
14090
14091 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
14092 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
14093 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
14094 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
14095 </para>
14096 <indexterm startref='idxprivacyrights2' class='endofrange'/>
14097 <indexterm startref='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='endofrange'/>
14098 <indexterm><primary>Data General</primary></indexterm>
14099 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
14100 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
14101 <para>
14102 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
14103 movement. When computers with software were first made available
14104 commercially, the software&mdash;both the source code and the
14105 binaries&mdash; was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
14106 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
14107 care much about controlling their software.
14108 </para>
14109 <indexterm id='idxstallmanrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Stallman, Richard</primary></indexterm>
14110 <para>
14111 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
14112 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
14113 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
14114 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
14115 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
14116 people's work.
14117 </para>
14118 <para>
14119 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
14120 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
14121 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
14122 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
14123 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
14124 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
14125 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
14126 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
14127 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
14128 anything else?
14129 </para>
14130 <indexterm id='idxproprietarycode' class='startofrange'><primary>proprietary code</primary></indexterm>
14131 <para>
14132 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
14133 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
14134 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
14135 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
14136 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
14137 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
14138 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
14139 </para>
14140 <para>
14141 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
14142 early 1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
14143 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
14144 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
14145 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
14146 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
14147 fundamentally weakened.
14148 </para>
14149 <indexterm startref='idxproprietarycode' class='endofrange'/>
14150 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus</primary></indexterm>
14151 <para>
14152 Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
14153 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
14154 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's <quote>Linux</quote>
14155 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
14156 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14157 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14158 </para>
14159 <para>
14160 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
14161 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
14162 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
14163 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
14164 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
14165 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
14166 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
14167 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
14168 byproduct.
14169 </para>
14170 <para>
14171 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
14172 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
14173 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
14174 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
14175 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
14176 what before had been passively guaranteed.
14177 </para>
14178 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='endofrange'/>
14179 <indexterm startref='idxstallmanrichard' class='endofrange'/>
14180 <indexterm id='idxacademicjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
14181 <indexterm id='idxscientificjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>scientific journals</primary></indexterm>
14182 <para>
14183 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
14184 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
14185 scientific journals are produced.
14186 </para>
14187 <indexterm id='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>Lexis and Westlaw</primary></indexterm>
14188 <indexterm id='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
14189 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14190 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>access to opinions of</secondary></indexterm>
14191 <para>
14192 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
14193 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
14194 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
14195 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
14196 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
14197 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
14198 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
14199 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
14200 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
14201 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
14202 and Westlaw are also free
14203 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
14204 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
14205 Court opinion through their respective services.
14206 </para>
14207 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>access fees for material in</secondary></indexterm>
14208 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>license system for rebuilding of</secondary></indexterm>
14209 <para>
14210 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
14211 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
14212 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
14213 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
14214 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
14215 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
14216 access to material that is not in the public domain.
14217 </para>
14218 <indexterm startref='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='endofrange'/>
14219 <indexterm startref='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='endofrange'/>
14220 <para>
14221 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
14222 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
14223 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
14224 </para>
14225 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14226 <para>
14227 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
14228 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
14229 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
14230 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
14231 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
14232 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
14233 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
14234 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
14235 the technology of paper journals (architecture)&mdash;namely, that it
14236 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
14237 </para>
14238 <para>
14239 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
14240 that libraries not give the general public access to the
14241 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
14242 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
14243 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
14244 granted before.
14245 </para>
14246 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
14247 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
14248 <para>
14249 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
14250 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
14251 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
14252 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
14253 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
14254 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
14255 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
14256 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
14257 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
14258 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
14259 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
14260 </para>
14261 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='endofrange'/>
14262 <para>
14263 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
14264 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
14265 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
14266 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
14267 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
14268 presumptively a good&mdash;especially when it helps spread knowledge
14269 and science.
14270 </para>
14271 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='endofrange'/>
14272 <indexterm startref='idxacademicjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14273 <indexterm startref='idxscientificjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14274 </section>
14275 <section id="oneidea">
14276 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea</title>
14277 <indexterm id='idxcreativecommons' class='startofrange'><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
14278 <para>
14279 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
14280 increasing control effected through law and technology.
14281 </para>
14282 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University</primary></indexterm>
14283 <para>
14284 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
14285 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
14286 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
14287 <emphasis>reasonable</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
14288 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
14289 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
14290 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
14291 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
14292 make this possible.
14293 </para>
14294 <para>
14295 <emphasis>Simple</emphasis>&mdash;which means without a middleman, or
14296 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
14297 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
14298 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
14299 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
14300 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
14301 shared. These three expressions together&mdash;a legal license, a
14302 human-readable description, and
14303 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
14304 machine-readable tags&mdash;constitute a Creative Commons license. A
14305 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
14306 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
14307 that the person associated with the license believes in something
14308 different than the <quote>All</quote> or <quote>No</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
14309 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
14310 certain freedoms are given.
14311 </para>
14312 <para>
14313 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
14314 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
14315 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
14316 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
14317 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
14318 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (<quote>share and share
14319 alike</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
14320 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
14321 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
14322 </para>
14323 <para>
14324 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
14325 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
14326 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
14327 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
14328 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
14329 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
14330 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
14331 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
14332 a public domain.
14333 </para>
14334 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia</primary></indexterm>
14335 <para>
14336 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
14337 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
14338 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
14339 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
14340 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
14341 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
14342 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
14343 of content (<quote>content conducers,</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
14344 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
14345 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
14346 </para>
14347 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
14348 <para>
14349 The aim is not to fight the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts. The aim is to
14350 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
14351 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
14352 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
14353 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
14354 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
14355 the background of digital technologies. New rules&mdash;with different
14356 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
14357 them&mdash;are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
14358 to begin to build those rules.
14359 </para>
14360 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
14361 <para>
14362 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
14363 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
14364 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
14365 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
14366 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
14367 </para>
14368 <para>
14369 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
14370 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1)
14371 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
14372 and (2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
14373 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (1) will download
14374 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2)
14375 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
14376 them (2)-goods. If there are more (2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the
14377 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
14378 <emphasis>increase</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
14379 </para>
14380 <para>
14381 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
14382 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
14383 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
14384 was a total success.
14385 </para>
14386 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)</primary></indexterm>
14387 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter</primary></indexterm>
14388 <para>
14389 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
14390 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
14391 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
14392 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled <citetitle>Free for All</citetitle>,
14393 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
14394 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
14395 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
14396 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
14397 well.
14398 </para>
14399 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'/>
14400 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy</primary></indexterm>
14401 <indexterm><primary>rap music</primary></indexterm>
14402 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter</primary></indexterm>
14403 <para>
14404 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
14405 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
14406 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
14407 reasons. Many who use the <quote>sampling license</quote> do so because anything
14408 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
14409 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
14410 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
14411 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
14412 art&mdash;they, too, sample from others. Because the
14413 <emphasis>legal</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
14414 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
14415 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not <quote>allow</quote>
14416 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
14417 high<footnote><para>
14418 <!-- f2. -->
14419 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
14420 Culture Wars</citetitle> (2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
14421 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
14422 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>.
14423 </para></footnote>),
14424 these artists release into the creative environment content
14425 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
14426 </para>
14427 <para>
14428 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
14429 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
14430 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
14431 you are effectively saying you believe in the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote>
14432 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
14433 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
14434 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
14435 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
14436 this notion of <quote>Some Rights Reserved,</quote> and gives many the chance to
14437 say it to others.
14438 </para>
14439 <para>
14440 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
14441 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
14442 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
14443 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
14444
14445 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
14446 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
14447 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
14448 </para>
14449 <para>
14450 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
14451 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
14452 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
14453 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
14454 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
14455 steps are possible.
14456 </para>
14457 <para>
14458 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
14459 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
14460 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
14461 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
14462 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
14463 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
14464 creativity to spread more easily.
14465 </para>
14466 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='endofrange'/>
14467 <indexterm startref='idxcreativecommons' class='endofrange'/>
14468 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
14469 </section>
14470 </section>
14471 <section id="themsoon">
14472 <title>THEM, SOON</title>
14473 <para>
14474 <emphasis role='strong'>We will</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
14475 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
14476 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
14477 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
14478 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
14479 </para>
14480 <para>
14481 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
14482 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
14483 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
14484 to our end.
14485 </para>
14486
14487 <section id="formalities">
14488 <title>1. More Formalities</title>
14489 <para>
14490 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
14491 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
14492 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
14493 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
14494 </para>
14495 <para>
14496 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
14497 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
14498 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
14499 protected.
14500 </para>
14501 <para>
14502 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
14503 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
14504 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
14505 default is control, and <quote>formalities</quote> are banished.
14506 </para>
14507 <para>
14508 Why?
14509 </para>
14510 <para>
14511 As I suggested in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
14512 linkend="property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
14513 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
14514 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
14515 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
14516 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
14517 formalities were getting in the way.
14518 </para>
14519 <para>
14520 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
14521 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
14522 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
14523 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
14524 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
14525 trace&mdash; there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
14526 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
14527 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
14528 past. And thus, the <emphasis>lack</emphasis> of formalities forces
14529 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
14530 </para>
14531 <para>
14532 The law should therefore change this requirement<footnote><para>
14533 <!-- f1. -->
14534 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
14535 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
14536 adopted by other countries as well.</para></footnote>&mdash;but it
14537 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
14538 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
14539 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
14540 </para>
14541 <para>
14542 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
14543 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
14544 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
14545 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
14546 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
14547 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
14548 developed by others.
14549 </para>
14550
14551 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
14552
14553 <section id="registration">
14554 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL</title>
14555 <para>
14556 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
14557 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
14558 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
14559 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
14560 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
14561 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
14562 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
14563 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
14564 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
14565 panic&mdash;nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
14566 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
14567 </para>
14568 <para>
14569 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
14570 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
14571 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
14572 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
14573 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
14574 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
14575 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
14576 </para>
14577 <para>
14578 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
14579 There are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world.
14580 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
14581 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
14582 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
14583 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
14584 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
14585 with which registration occurs up.
14586 </para>
14587 <para>
14588 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
14589 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
14590 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
14591 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
14592 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
14593 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
14594 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
14595 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
14596 formality&mdash;while producing a database
14597 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
14598 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
14599 </para>
14600
14601 </section>
14602 <section id="marking">
14603 <title>MARKING</title>
14604 <para>
14605 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
14606 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
14607 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule&mdash;akin to
14608 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
14609 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
14610 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
14611 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
14612 uniformly across all media.
14613 </para>
14614 <para>
14615 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
14616 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
14617 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
14618 use the work.
14619 </para>
14620 <para>
14621 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
14622 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
14623 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
14624 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
14625 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
14626 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
14627 signal from the failure to mark&mdash;not the loss of the copyright, but the
14628 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
14629 </para>
14630 <para>
14631 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
14632 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
14633 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
14634 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
14635 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
14636 doesn't give permission.<footnote><para>
14637 <!-- f2. -->
14638 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
14639 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
14640 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
14641 </para></footnote>
14642 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be <quote>use unless someone
14643 complains.</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
14644 stop using the work in any new
14645 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
14646 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
14647 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
14648 their work.
14649 </para>
14650 <para>
14651 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
14652 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
14653 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
14654 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
14655 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
14656 </para>
14657 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>copyright marking of</secondary></indexterm>
14658 <para>
14659 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
14660 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
14661 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
14662 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
14663 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
14664 <emphasis>solely</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
14665 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
14666 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
14667 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
14668 other important functions.
14669 </para>
14670 <para>
14671 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
14672 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
14673 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
14674 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
14675 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
14676 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
14677 </para>
14678 <para>
14679 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
14680 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
14681 make things unclear.
14682 </para>
14683 <para>
14684 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
14685 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
14686 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
14687 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
14688 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
14689 that assertion at the appropriate time.
14690 </para>
14691
14692 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
14693 </section>
14694 </section>
14695 <section id="shortterms">
14696 <title>2. Shorter Terms</title>
14697 <para>
14698 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14699 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14700 natural authors.
14701 </para>
14702 <para>
14703 In <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14704 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14705 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14706 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14707 radical. <citetitle>The Economist</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14708 copyright term.<footnote><para>
14709
14710 <!-- f3. -->
14711 <quote>A Radical Rethink,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 366:8308 (25 January 2003): 15,
14712 available at
14713 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #74</ulink>.
14714 </para></footnote>
14715 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14716 </para>
14717 <para>
14718 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14719 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14720 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14721 terms.
14722 </para>
14723 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14724 <listitem><para>
14725 <!-- (1) -->
14726 <emphasis>Keep it short:</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14727 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14728 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14729 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14730 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14731 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14732 </para></listitem>
14733 <listitem><para>
14734 <!-- (2) -->
14735 <emphasis>Keep it simple:</emphasis> The line between the public
14736 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14737 fuzziness of <quote>fair use,</quote> and the distinction between <quote>ideas</quote> and
14738 <quote>expression.</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14739 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14740 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14741 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14742 <quote>lawyer-free zone</quote> makes the complexities of <quote>fair use</quote> and
14743 <quote>idea/expression</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14744 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14745 </para></listitem>
14746 <listitem>
14747 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions</primary></indexterm>
14748 <para>
14749 <!-- (3) -->
14750 <emphasis>Keep it alive:</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14751 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14752 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14753 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14754 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14755 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14756 pension.<footnote><para>
14757 <!-- f4. -->
14758 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14759 and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001),
14760 available at
14761 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #75</ulink>.
14762 </para></footnote>
14763 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14764 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14765 single form.
14766 </para></listitem>
14767 <listitem><para>
14768 <!-- (4) -->
14769 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14770 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14771 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14772 in 1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14773 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14774 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in 1923 than we
14775 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14776 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14777 the number of authors who wrote in 1923. Of course, we can increase
14778 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14779 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14780 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14781 creativity in 1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14782 we can do about that now. </para></listitem>
14783 </orderedlist>
14784 <para>
14785 These changes together should produce an <emphasis>average</emphasis>
14786 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until 1976,
14787 the average term was just 32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14788 same.
14789 </para>
14790 <para>
14791 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas <quote>radical.</quote> (After all, I
14792 call them <quote>extremists.</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14793 than the term under Richard Nixon. How <quote>radical</quote> can it be to ask for
14794 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14795 </para>
14796
14797 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14798
14799 </section>
14800 <section id="freefairuse">
14801 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use</title>
14802 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
14803 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
14804 <para>
14805 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14806 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14807 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14808 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14809 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14810 the emergence of that new technology.
14811 </para>
14812 <para>
14813 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors <quote>exclusive
14814 right</quote> to <quote>their writings.</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14815 right to <quote>their writings</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14816 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14817 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14818 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14819 though that movie is not <quote>my writing.</quote>
14820 </para>
14821 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin</primary></indexterm>
14822 <para>
14823 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it
14824 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14825 control translations and dramatizations of a work.<footnote><para>
14826 <!-- f5. -->
14827 Benjamin Kaplan, <citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14828 University Press, 1967), 32.
14829 </para></footnote>
14830 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14831 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14832 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14833 </para>
14834 <blockquote>
14835 <para>
14836 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14837 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14838 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14839 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.<footnote><para>
14840 <!-- f6. --> Ibid., 56.
14841 </para></footnote>
14842 </para>
14843 </blockquote>
14844 <para>
14845 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14846 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14847 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14848 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14849 Consider each limitation in turn.
14850 </para>
14851 <para>
14852 <emphasis>Term:</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14853 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14854 sense to protect John
14855
14856 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14857 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14858 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14859 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14860 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14861 after the creative work is done.
14862 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
14863 </para>
14864 <para>
14865 <emphasis>Scope:</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14866 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14867 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14868 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14869 material. When all <quote>reuse</quote> of creative material was within the control
14870 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14871 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14872 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14873 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14874 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14875 the creative process. Smothers it.
14876 </para>
14877 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
14878 <para>
14879 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14880 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14881 foreseeable derivative rights&mdash;turning a book into a movie, or a
14882 poem into a musical score&mdash;it doesn't make sense to require
14883 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14884 much more sense.
14885 </para>
14886 <para>
14887 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14888 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14889 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14890 Paul Goldstein.<footnote>
14891 <para>
14892 <!-- f7. -->
14893 Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14894 Jukebox</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187&ndash;216.
14895 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul</primary></indexterm>
14896 </para></footnote>
14897 His view is that the law should be written so that
14898 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14899 </para>
14900 <para>
14901 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14902 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14903 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14904 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14905 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14906 </para>
14907 <para>
14908 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14909 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
14910 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
14911 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
14912 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
14913 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
14914 </para>
14915 </section>
14916
14917 <section id="liberatemusic">
14918 <title>4. Liberate the Music&mdash;Again</title>
14919 <para>
14920 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
14921 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
14922 is, to most people, most pressing&mdash;music. There is no other
14923 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
14924 battles around the sharing of music.
14925 </para>
14926 <para>
14927 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
14928 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
14929 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
14930 killer app&mdash;possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
14931 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
14932 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
14933 innovation on the network.
14934 </para>
14935 <para>
14936 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
14937 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
14938 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
14939 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
14940 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
14941 </para>
14942 <para>
14943 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
14944 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
14945 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
14946 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="piracy"/>, they enable
14947 four different kinds of sharing:
14948 </para>
14949 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
14950 <listitem><para>
14951 <!-- A. -->
14952 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
14953 for purchasing CDs.
14954 </para></listitem>
14955 <listitem><para>
14956 <!-- B. -->
14957 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
14958 on the way to purchasing CDs.
14959 </para></listitem>
14960 <listitem><para>
14961 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
14962 <!-- C. -->
14963 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14964 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
14965 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
14966 </para></listitem>
14967 <listitem><para>
14968 <!-- D. -->
14969 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14970 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
14971 owner plainly endorses.
14972 </para></listitem>
14973 </orderedlist>
14974 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
14975 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
14976 <para>
14977 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
14978 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
14979 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
14980 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
14981 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
14982 significantly weakened.
14983 </para>
14984 <para>
14985 As I said in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
14986 linkend="piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
14987 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
14988 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
14989 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
14990 networks.
14991 </para>
14992 <para>
14993 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
14994 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
14995 should respond.
14996 </para>
14997 <para>
14998 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
14999 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
15000 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
15001 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
15002 is cumbersome and slow&mdash;we in the United States are lucky to have
15003 broadband service at 1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
15004 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
15005 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
15006 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
15007 Internet is mainly just an idea.
15008 </para>
15009 <para>
15010 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
15011 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
15012 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
15013 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
15014 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
15015 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
15016 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
15017 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
15018 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
15019 where everywhere you are&mdash;except maybe the desert or the
15020 Rockies&mdash;you can instantaneously be connected to the
15021 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
15022 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
15023 </para>
15024 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over</primary></indexterm>
15025 <para>
15026 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
15027 give you access to content on the fly&mdash;such as Internet radio,
15028 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
15029 then, is the critical point: When it is <emphasis>extremely</emphasis>
15030 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
15031 <emphasis>easier</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
15032 access to content than it will be to download and store content
15033 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
15034 content</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
15035 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
15036 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
15037 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
15038 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
15039 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
15040 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
15041 paying for this content even though <quote>free</quote> content is available in the
15042 form of MP3s across the Web.<footnote><para>
15043 <!-- f8. -->
15044 See, for example, <quote>Music Media Watch,</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3
15045 April 2002, available at
15046 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #76</ulink>.
15047 </para></footnote>
15048
15049 </para>
15050 <para>
15051 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
15052 present: It is emphatically temporary. The <quote>problem</quote> with file
15053 sharing&mdash;to the extent there is a real problem&mdash;is a problem
15054 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
15055 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
15056 makers today to be <quote>solving</quote> this problem in light of a technology
15057 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
15058 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
15059 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
15060 artists get paid, during
15061
15062 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
15063 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
15064 and twenty-first-century technologies.
15065 </para>
15066 <para>
15067 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different <quote>problems</quote>
15068 here to solve. Let's start with type D content&mdash;uncopyrighted
15069 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
15070 <quote>problem</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
15071 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
15072 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
15073 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
15074 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
15075 order to eliminate kidnapping.
15076 </para>
15077 <para>
15078 Type C content raises a different <quote>problem.</quote> This is content that was,
15079 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
15080 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
15081 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
15082 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
15083 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
15084 way that returns something to the artist.
15085 </para>
15086 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
15087 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
15088 <para>
15089 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
15090 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
15091 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
15092 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
15093 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
15094 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
15095 from the author's perspective, this <quote>sharing</quote> of his content without
15096 his being compensated is less than ideal.
15097 </para>
15098 <para>
15099 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
15100 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
15101 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
15102 providers would be free, under this rule, to <quote>share</quote> that content,
15103 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
15104 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
15105 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
15106 </para>
15107 <para>
15108
15109 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
15110 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
15111 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
15112 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
15113 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
15114 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
15115 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
15116 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
15117 trade.
15118 </para>
15119 <para>
15120 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
15121 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
15122 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
15123 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
15124 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
15125 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
15126 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
15127 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
15128 </para>
15129 <para>
15130 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
15131 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
15132 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
15133 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
15134 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
15135 delivering and accessing content.
15136 </para>
15137 <para>
15138 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
15139 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
15140 </para>
15141 <para>
15142 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
15143 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
15144 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
15145 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
15146 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
15147 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
15148 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
15149 harmed the interests of the content industry.
15150 </para>
15151 <para>
15152 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
15153 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
15154 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
15155 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
15156 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
15157 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
15158 way to compensate those who are harmed.
15159 </para>
15160 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15161 <para>
15162 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
15163 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.<footnote>
15164 <para>
15165 <!-- f9. -->
15166 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15167 William Fisher, <citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities</citetitle> (last
15168 revised: 10 October 2000), available at
15169 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #77</ulink>; William
15170 Fisher, <citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
15171 Entertainment</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
15172 2004), ch. 6, available at
15173 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #78</ulink>. Professor
15174 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
15175 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
15176 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, <quote>Impose a
15177 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,</quote> available at
15178 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Who's Holding Back
15179 Broadband?</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
15180 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
15181 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, 26 February 2002,
15182 available at
15183 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, <citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
15184 Use Fee (IPUF)</citetitle>, 3 March 2002, available at
15185 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
15186 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 13 May
15187 2002, available at
15188 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, <quote>Getting Copyright Right,</quote>
15189 IEEE Spectrum Online, 1 July 2002, available at
15190 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #83</ulink>; Declan
15191 McCullagh, <quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,</quote> CNET News.com, 27 August
15192 2002, available at
15193 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #84</ulink>.
15194 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
15195 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
15196 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
15197 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
15198 debate by about a decade. See
15199 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #85</ulink>.
15200 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William</primary></indexterm>
15201 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
15202 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15203 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'/>
15204 </para></footnote>
15205 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
15206 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
15207 would (1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
15208 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
15209 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
15210 develop (2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
15211 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (3) artists would be
15212 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (4) an appropriate
15213 tax.
15214 </para>
15215 <para>
15216 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
15217 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
15218 <citetitle>Promises to Keep</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
15219 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
15220 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
15221 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
15222 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
15223 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
15224 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
15225 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
15226 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
15227 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
15228 controlling access.
15229 </para>
15230 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'/>
15231 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15232 <para>
15233 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
15234 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
15235 the system supports the widest range of <quote>semiotic democracy</quote>
15236 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
15237 other changes I described were accomplished&mdash;in particular, the
15238 limits on derivative
15239
15240 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
15241 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
15242 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
15243 allowed to do with the content itself.
15244 </para>
15245 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
15246 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore</primary></indexterm>
15247 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
15248 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>prices of</secondary></indexterm>
15249 <para>
15250 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
15251 <quote>harm</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
15252 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
15253 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
15254 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
15255 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat <quote>free</quote> by being
15256 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
15257 of songs at even the very high price of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents,
15258 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
15259 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
15260 Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a song. And no doubt
15261 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
15262 on-line.
15263 </para>
15264 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
15265 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast</secondary></indexterm>
15266 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
15267 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
15268 <indexterm><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in</secondary></indexterm>
15269 <para>
15270 This competition has already occurred against the background of <quote>free</quote>
15271 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
15272 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
15273 that, there is nothing impossible at all about <quote>competing with free.</quote>
15274 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
15275 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
15276 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
15277 theaters are often luxurious&mdash;with <quote>first class</quote> seats, and meals
15278 served while you watch a movie&mdash;as they struggle and succeed in
15279 finding ways to compete with <quote>free.</quote>
15280 </para>
15281 <para>
15282 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
15283 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
15284 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
15285 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
15286 innovators&mdash;ones who would have a right to the content, and would
15287 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
15288 the law.
15289 </para>
15290 <para>
15291 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
15292 </para>
15293 <para>
15294
15295 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
15296 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
15297 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
15298 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
15299 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
15300 create.
15301 </para>
15302 <para>
15303 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
15304 by
15305 </para>
15306 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
15307 <listitem><para>
15308 <!-- 1. -->
15309 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
15310 </para></listitem>
15311 <listitem><para>
15312 <!-- 2. -->
15313 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
15314 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
15315 statute;
15316 </para></listitem>
15317 <listitem><para>
15318 <!-- 3. -->
15319 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
15320 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
15321 </para></listitem>
15322 </orderedlist>
15323 <para>
15324 But what if <quote>piracy</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
15325 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
15326 consumers continue to <quote>take</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
15327 something then?
15328 </para>
15329 <para>
15330 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
15331 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
15332 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
15333 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
15334 technology that is 95 percent secure and produces a market of size <citetitle>x</citetitle>,
15335 or (b) to have a technology that is 50 percent secure but produces a
15336 market of five times <citetitle>x</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
15337 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
15338 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
15339 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
15340 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
15341 pirates.
15342 </para>
15343 <para>
15344 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
15345 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
15346 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
15347
15348 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
15349 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
15350 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
15351 </para>
15352 </section>
15353
15354 <section id="firelawyers">
15355 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers</title>
15356 <para>
15357 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
15358 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
15359 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
15360 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
15361 </para>
15362 <para>
15363 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
15364 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
15365 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
15366 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
15367 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
15368 strong view queers the law.
15369 </para>
15370 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville</primary></indexterm>
15371 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of</secondary></indexterm>
15372 <para>
15373 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
15374 <quote>radical</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
15375 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
15376 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
15377 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
15378 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
15379 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
15380 Nimmer, thought it obvious.<footnote><para>
15381 <!-- f10. -->
15382 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Copyright's First Amendment</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
15383 Memorial Lecture), <citetitle>UCLA Law Review</citetitle> 48 (2001): 1057, 1069&ndash;70.
15384 </para></footnote>
15385
15386 </para>
15387 <para>
15388 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
15389 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
15390 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
15391 </para>
15392 <para>
15393 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
15394 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
15395 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
15396 the legal system are slight.<footnote><para>
15397 <!-- f11. -->
15398 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
15399 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
15400 leading him to question his own publicly stated
15401 position&mdash;twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
15402 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
15403 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
15404 J. Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
15405 Drive the Digital Marketplace</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002), (reviewing his
15406 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
15407 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?</quote> working paper, June 2003,
15408 available at
15409 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #86</ulink>.
15410 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
15411 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
15412 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
15413 <citetitle>Rethinking</citetitle>, 174&ndash;76.
15414 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
15415 </para></footnote>
15416 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
15417 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
15418 them it works.
15419 </para>
15420 <para>
15421 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
15422 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
15423 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
15424 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
15425 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
15426 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
15427 practically never be done.
15428 </para>
15429 <para>
15430 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
15431 billed at the largest firms at more than $400 per hour. How much time
15432 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
15433 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
15434 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
15435 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
15436 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
15437 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
15438 </para>
15439 <para>
15440 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
15441 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
15442 their duty to change the way the law works&mdash;or better, to change the
15443 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
15444 top 1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
15445 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
15446 </para>
15447 <para>
15448 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
15449 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
15450 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
15451 its review.
15452 </para>
15453 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
15454 <para>
15455 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
15456 technology&mdash;the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
15457 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
15458 technology&mdash;a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
15459 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
15460 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
15461 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
15462 </para>
15463 <para>
15464 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture&mdash;but it should
15465 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
15466
15467 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311-->
15468 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
15469 simple pragmatic question: <quote>Will it do good?</quote> When challenged about
15470 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, <quote>Why not?</quote>
15471 </para>
15472 <para>
15473 We should ask, <quote>Why?</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
15474 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
15475 keep your lawyers away.
15476 </para>
15477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
15478 </section>
15479 </section>
15480 </chapter>
15481 <chapter label="17" id="c-notes">
15482 <title>NOTES</title>
15483 <para>
15484 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
15485 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
15486 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
15487 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
15488 this book. For each link below, you can go to
15489 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
15490 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
15491 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
15492 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
15493 the material.
15494 </para>
15495
15496 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
15497 <?latex \theendnotes ?>
15498
15499 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
15500
15501 </chapter>
15502 <chapter label="18" id="c-acknowledgments">
15503 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS</title>
15504 <para>
15505 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
15506 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
15507 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
15508 to him that this book is dedicated.
15509 </para>
15510 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
15511 <para>
15512 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
15513 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
15514 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
15515 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
15516 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
15517 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
15518 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
15519 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
15520 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
15521 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
15522 critical eye on much of this.
15523 </para>
15524 <para>
15525 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
15526 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
15527 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
15528 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
15529 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
15530 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
15531 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
15532 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
15533 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
15534 </para>
15535 <para>
15536 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
15537 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
15538 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
15539 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
15540 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
15541 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
15542 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
15543 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
15544 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
15545 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
15546 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
15547 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
15548 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
15549 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
15550 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, <quote>Wink,</quote> Roger Wood, <quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,</quote>
15551 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
15552 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
15553 a bunch of great replies.)
15554 </para>
15555 <para>
15556 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
15557 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
15558 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
15559 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
15560 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
15561 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
15562 throughout this book.
15563 </para>
15564 <para>
15565 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
15566 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
15567 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
15568 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
15569 </para>
15570 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->
15571
15572 </chapter>
15573 <index></index>
15574 <colophon>
15575 <para>
15576 THE PENGUIN PRESS, a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc. 375 Hudson Street New
15577 York, New York
15578 </para>
15579 <para>
15580 Copyright &copy; Lawrence Lessig. All rights reserved.
15581 </para>
15582 <para>
15583 Excerpt from an editorial titled <quote>The Coming of Copyright Perpetuity,</quote>
15584 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, January 16, 2003. Copyright
15585 &copy; 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted with permission.
15586 </para>
15587 <para>
15588 Cartoon in <xref linkend="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/> by Paul Conrad, copyright Tribune
15589 Media Services, Inc. All rights reserved. Reprinted with permission.
15590 </para>
15591 <para>
15592 Diagram in <xref linkend="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership"/> courtesy of the office of FCC
15593 Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
15594 </para>
15595 <para>
15596 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
15597 </para>
15598 <para>
15599 Lessig, Lawrence.
15600 Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law to lock down
15601 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
15602 </para>
15603 <para>
15604 p. cm.
15605 </para>
15606 <para>
15607 Includes index.
15608 </para>
15609 <para>
15610 ISBN 1-59420-006-8 (hardcover)
15611 </para>
15612
15613 <para>
15614 1. Intellectual property&mdash;United States. 2. Mass media&mdash;United States.
15615 </para>
15616 <para>
15617 3. Technological innovations&mdash;United States. 4. Art&mdash;United States. I. Title.
15618 </para>
15619 <para>
15620 KF2979.L47
15621 </para>
15622 <para>
15623 343.7309'9&mdash;dc22
15624 </para>
15625 <para>
15626 This book is printed on acid-free paper.
15627 </para>
15628 <para>
15629 Printed in the United States of America
15630 </para>
15631 <para>
15632 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4
15633 </para>
15634 <para>
15635 Designed by Marysarah Quinn
15636 </para>
15637
15638 <para>
15639 &translationblock;
15640 </para>
15641
15642 <para>
15643 Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of
15644 this publication may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a
15645 retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means
15646 (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise),
15647 without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and
15648 the above publisher of this book.
15649 </para>
15650 <para>
15651 The scanning, uploading, and distribution of this book via the
15652 Internet or via any other means without the permission of the
15653 publisher is illegal and punishable by law. Please purchase only
15654 authorized electronic editions and do not participate in or encourage
15655 electronic piracy of copyrighted materials. Your support of the
15656 author's rights is appreciated.
15657 </para>
15658 </colophon>
15659 </book>