]> pere.pagekite.me Git - text-free-culture-lessig.git/blob - freeculture.xml
Generated.
[text-free-culture-lessig.git] / freeculture.xml
1 <?xml version='1.0' encoding='UTF-8' ?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href="docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type="text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012 with input from Martin Borg. -->
5 <!--
6 TODO
7 * indexterm primary
8 -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC "-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
11 [
12 <!ENTITY copy "©">
13 <!ENTITY translationblock "">
14 ]>
15 <book id="index" lang="en">
16 <bookinfo>
17 <title>Free Culture</title>
18
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
20
21 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
22 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY</subtitle>
23
24 <pubdate>2004-03-25</pubdate>
25
26 <releaseinfo>Version 2004-02-10</releaseinfo>
27
28 <authorgroup>
29 <author>
30 <firstname>Lawrence</firstname>
31 <surname>Lessig</surname>
32 </author>
33 <!--
34 Keep these out to avoid showing up as author in the PDF.
35
36 <editor>
37 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
38 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
39 </editor>
40
41 <othercredit role='converter'>
42 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
43 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
44 <contrib>Created this Docbook version from an earlier version</contrib>
45 </othercredit>
46 -->
47 </authorgroup>
48
49 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
50 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
51 -->
52 <subjectset scheme="libraryofcongress">
53 <subject>
54 <subjectterm>Intellectual property&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
55 </subject>
56 <subject>
57 <subjectterm>Mass media&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
58 </subject>
59 <subject>
60 <subjectterm>Technological innovations&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
61 </subject>
62 <subject>
63 <subjectterm>Art&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
64 </subject>
65 </subjectset>
66
67
68 <publisher>
69 <publishername>Petter Reinholdtsen</publishername>
70 <address><city>Oslo</city></address>
71 </publisher>
72
73 <copyright>
74 <year>2004</year>
75 <holder>Lawrence Lessig</holder>
76 </copyright>
77 <legalnotice>
78 <para>
79 <inlinemediaobject>
80 <imageobject>
81 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.png" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
82 </imageobject>
83 <imageobject>
84 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.svg" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
85 </imageobject>
86 <textobject>
87 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved</phrase>
88 </textobject>
89 </inlinemediaobject>
90 </para>
91
92 <para>
93 This version of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is licensed under
94 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
95 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
96 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
97 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/</ulink>
98 </para>
99 </legalnotice>
100
101 <abstract>
102 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR</title>
103 <para>
104 LAWRENCE LESSIG
105 (<ulink url="http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org</ulink>),
106 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
107 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
108 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
109 (<ulink url="http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org</ulink>).
110 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) and Code: And
111 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), Lessig is a member of
112 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
113 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
114 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
115 twice listed in BusinessWeek's <quote>e.biz 25,</quote> and named one of Scientific
116 American's <quote>50 visionaries.</quote> A graduate of the University of
117 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
118 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
119 Appeals.
120 </para>
121 </abstract>
122
123 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
124 <mediaobject role="cover">
125 <imageobject remap="lrg" role="front-large">
126 <imagedata fileref="images/cover.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
127 </imageobject>
128 <!--
129 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
130 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
131 </imageobject>
132 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
133 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
134 </imageobject>
135 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
136 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
137 </imageobject>
138 -->
139 </mediaobject>
140
141 <biblioid class="isbn">978-82-92812-XX-Y</biblioid>
142
143 <!-- LCCN from
144 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
145 -->
146 <biblioid class="libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
147
148 </bookinfo>
149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
150 <dedication id="alsobylessig">
151 <title></title>
152 <para>
153 ALSO BY LAWRENCE LESSIG
154 </para>
155 <para>
156 <!-- 2014 -->
157 The USA is lesterland: The nature of congressional corruption
158 </para>
159 <para>
160 <!-- 2011, 2012 -->
161 Republic, lost: How money corrupts Congress - and a plan to stop it
162 </para>
163 <para>
164 <!-- 2008 -->
165 Remix: Making art and commerce thrive in the hybrid economy
166 </para>
167 <para>
168 <!-- 2006 -->
169 Code: Version 2.0
170 </para>
171 <para>
172 <!-- 2001, 2002 -->
173 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
174 </para>
175 <para>
176 <!-- 1999 -->
177 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
178 </para>
179 </dedication>
180 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
182 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
183 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
184 <dedication><title></title>
185 <para>
186 To Eric Eldred &mdash; whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
187 it continues still.
188 </para>
189 </dedication>
190
191 <toc id="toc"></toc>
192
193 <lot>
194 <title>List of figures</title>
195 </lot>
196
197 <!--
198 c PREFACE xiii
199 c INTRODUCTION
200 c "PIRACY"
201 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
202 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
203 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
204 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
205 2 Film
206 2 Recorded Music
207 2 Radio
208 2 Cable TV
209 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
210 2 Piracy I
211 2 Piracy II
212 c "PROPERTY"
213 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
214 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
215 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
216 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
217 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
218 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
219 2 Beginnings
220 2 Law: Duration
221 2 Law: Scope
222 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
223 2 Architecture and Law: Force
224 2 Market: Concentration
225 2 Together
226 c PUZZLES
227 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
228 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
229 2 Constraining Creators
230 2 Constraining Innovators
231 2 Corrupting Citizens
232 c BALANCES
233 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
234 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
235 c CONCLUSION
236 c AFTERWORD
237 1 Us, Now
238 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
239 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
240 1 Them, Soon
241 2 1. More Formalities
242 3 Registration and Renewal
243 3 Marking
244 2 2. Shorter Terms
245 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
246 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
247 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
248 c NOTES
249 c ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
250 c INDEX
251 -->
252
253 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
254
255 <preface id="preface">
256 <title>PREFACE</title>
257 <indexterm id='idxpoguedavid' class='startofrange'><primary>Pogue, David</primary></indexterm>
258 <para>
259 <emphasis role="bold">At the end</emphasis> of his review of my first
260 book, <citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle>, David
261 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
262 computer-related texts, wrote this:
263 </para>
264 <blockquote>
265 <para>
266 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
267 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
268 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
269 system, you can always flip off the modem.<footnote id="preface01"><para>
270 David Pogue, <quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 30 January 2000.
271 </para></footnote>
272 </para>
273 </blockquote>
274 <para>
275 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book&mdash;that
276 software, or <quote>code,</quote> functioned as a kind of law&mdash;and his review
277 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
278 could always <quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome</quote>-like simply flip a
279 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
280 any troubles that exist in <emphasis>that</emphasis> space wouldn't
281 <quote>affect</quote> us anymore.
282 </para>
283 <para>
284 Pogue might have been right in 1999&mdash;I'm skeptical, but maybe.
285 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
286 <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
287 causes even after the modem is turned
288 <!--PAGE BREAK 12-->
289 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
290 on-line have fundamentally affected <quote>people who aren't online.</quote> There
291 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
292 </para>
293 <indexterm startref='idxpoguedavid' class='endofrange'/>
294 <para>
295 But unlike <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
296 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
297 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
298 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
299 important.
300 </para>
301 <para>
302 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
303 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of <quote>free culture</quote>&mdash;not
304 <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free beer</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
305 free software movement<footnote>
306 <para>
307 Richard M. Stallman, <citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed. 2002).
308 </para></footnote>), but <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free speech,</quote> <quote>free markets,</quote>
309 <quote>free trade,</quote> <quote>free enterprise,</quote> <quote>free will,</quote> and <quote>free elections.</quote> A
310 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
311 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
312 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
313 follow-on creators and innovators remain <emphasis>as free as
314 possible</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
315 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
316 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
317 <quote>permission culture</quote>&mdash;a culture in which creators get to create
318 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
319 past.
320 </para>
321 <para>
322 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not <quote>we</quote>
323 on the Left or <quote>you</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
324 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
325 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
326 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
327 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
328 culture deem fundamental.
329 </para>
330 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
331 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
332 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
333 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted</primary></indexterm>
334 <para>
335 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
336 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
337 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
338 generated more than 700,000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
339 As William Safire described marching <quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
340 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
341 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,</quote> he formulated perhaps
342 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
343 he asked,
344 </para>
345 <blockquote>
346 <para>
347 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
348 power&mdash;political, corporate, media, cultural&mdash;should be anathema to
349 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
350 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
351 the greatest expression of democracy.<footnote><para> William Safire,
352 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 May 2003.
353 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
354 </para></footnote>
355 </para>
356 </blockquote>
357 <para>
358 This idea is an element of the argument of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle>, though my
359 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
360 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
361 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
362 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
363 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
364 you&mdash;whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
365 Safire's left or on his right.
366 </para>
367 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'/>
368 <para>
369 <emphasis role="strong">The inspiration</emphasis> for the title and for
370 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
371 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
372 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in <citetitle>Free Software, Free
373 Society</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
374 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
375 that this work is <quote>merely</quote> derivative.
376 </para>
377 <para>
378 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
379 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
380 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
381 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
382 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
383 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
384 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
385 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
386
387 <!--PAGE BREAK 14-->
388 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
389 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
390 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
391 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
392 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
393 what I advance here.
394 </para>
395 <para>
396 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
397 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
398 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
399 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
400 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
401 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
402 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
403 book is written.
404 </para>
405
406 </preface>
407 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
408
409 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
410 <chapter label="0" id="c-introduction">
411 <title>INTRODUCTION</title>
412 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
413 <para>
414 <emphasis role="strong">On December 17</emphasis>, 1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
415 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
416 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
417 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
418 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
419 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
420 </para>
421 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.</primary></indexterm>
422 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
423 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
424 <para>
425 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
426 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
427 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
428 and all the space above, to <quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.</quote><footnote><para>
429 St. George Tucker, <citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
430 Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18.
431 </para></footnote>
432 For many
433 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
434 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
435 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
436 </para>
437 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
438 <para>
439 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
440 law&mdash;deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
441 by the most important legal thinkers of our past&mdash;mattered. If
442 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
443 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
444 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
445 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
446 </para>
447 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
448 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
449 <para>
450 In 1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
451 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
452 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
453 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
454 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
455 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
456 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to <quote>an indefinite
457 extent, upwards,</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
458 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
459 </para>
460 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
461 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
462 <indexterm id='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='startofrange'><primary>Douglas, William O.</primary></indexterm>
463 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on airspace vs. land rights</secondary></indexterm>
464 <para>
465 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
466 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
467 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
468 <quote>taking</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
469 that <quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
470 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.</quote> But Justice Douglas
471 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
472 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
473 </para>
474 <blockquote>
475 <para>
476 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
477 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
478 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
479 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
480 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
481 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
482 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
483 the public has a just claim.<footnote>
484 <para>
485 United States v. Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. The Court did find
486 that there could be a <quote>taking</quote> if the government's use of its land
487 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
488 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, <quote>(Intellectual)
489 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
490 Authorship,</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review</citetitle> 48 (1996): 1293, 1333. See also Paul
491 Goldstein, <citetitle>Real Property</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press, 1984),
492 1112&ndash;13.
493 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
494 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
495 </para></footnote>
496 </para>
497 </blockquote>
498 <para>
499 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.</quote>
500 </para>
501 <indexterm startref='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='endofrange'/>
502 <para>
503 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
504 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
505 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
506 <!--PAGE BREAK 18-->
507 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: <quote>Common sense revolts
508 at the idea.</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
509 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
510 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
511 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
512 </para>
513 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
514 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
515 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
516 <para>
517 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
518 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
519 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
520 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
521 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
522 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
523 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
524 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
525 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by <quote>what
526 seemed reasonable</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
527 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
528 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
529 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
530 end, the force of what seems <quote>obvious</quote> to everyone else&mdash;the power of
531 <quote>common sense</quote>&mdash;would prevail. Their <quote>private interest</quote> would not be
532 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
533 </para>
534 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'/>
535 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'/>
536 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'/>
537 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='endofrange'/>
538 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
539 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham</primary></indexterm>
540 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
541 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael</primary></indexterm>
542 <indexterm id='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
543 <para>
544 <emphasis role='strong'>Edwin Howard Armstrong</emphasis> is one of
545 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
546 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
547 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
548 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
549 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
550 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in 1831. But
551 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
552 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
553 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
554 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
555 </para>
556 <para>
557 On the day after Christmas, 1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
558 for his most significant invention&mdash;FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
559 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
560 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
561 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
562 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
563 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
564 much less transmitter power and static.
565 </para>
566 <para>
567 On November 5, 1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
568 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
569 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
570 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
571 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
572 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
573 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
574 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
575 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.</quote>
576 </para>
577 <para>
578 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
579 </para>
580 <blockquote>
581 <para>
582 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
583 sounded like a glass of water being poured. &hellip; A paper was crumpled
584 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
585 fire. &hellip; Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
586 and guitar number were performed. &hellip; The music was projected with a
587 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio <quote>music
588 box.</quote><footnote><para>
589 Lawrence Lessing, <citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong</citetitle>
590 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209.
591 </para></footnote>
592 </para>
593 </blockquote>
594 <indexterm id='idxrca' class='startofrange'><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
595 <indexterm id='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
596 <para>
597 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
598 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
599 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
600 AM radio market. By 1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
601 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
602 a handful of networks.
603 <!--PAGE BREAK 20-->
604 </para>
605 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
606 <para>
607 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
608 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
609 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
610 that removed static from <quote>radio.</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
611 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
612 </para>
613 <blockquote>
614 <para>
615 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
616 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
617 revolution&mdash; start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
618 RCA.<footnote><para> See <quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
619 Electronic Era,</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
620 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
621
622 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #1</ulink>.
623 </para></footnote>
624 </para>
625 </blockquote>
626 <indexterm id='idxfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
627 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
628 <para>
629 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
630 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
631 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
632 described,
633 </para>
634 <indexterm id='idxlessinglawrence' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessing, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
635 <blockquote>
636 <para>
637 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
638 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
639 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
640 unrestrained, posed &hellip; a complete reordering of radio power
641 &hellip; and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
642 on which RCA had grown to power.<footnote><para>Lessing, 226.
643 </para></footnote>
644 </para>
645 </blockquote>
646 <indexterm id='idxfcconfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FCC</primary><secondary>on FM radio</secondary></indexterm>
647 <para>
648 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
649 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
650 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
651 FM radio's deployment generally. In 1936, RCA hired the former head
652 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
653 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM&mdash;principally by moving FM
654 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
655 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
656 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
657 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
658 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
659 </para>
660 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
661 <blockquote>
662 <para>
663 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
664 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
665 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
666 deviousness.<footnote><para>
667 Lessing, 256.
668 </para></footnote>
669 </para>
670 </blockquote>
671 <indexterm startref='idxlessinglawrence' class='endofrange'/>
672 <indexterm><primary>AT&amp;T</primary></indexterm>
673 <para>
674 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
675 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
676 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
677 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
678 (This change was strongly supported by AT&amp;T, because the loss of
679 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
680 wired links from AT&amp;T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
681 least temporarily.
682 </para>
683 <indexterm startref='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='endofrange'/>
684 <indexterm startref='idxfcconfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
685 <para>
686 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
687 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
688 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
689 invalid&mdash;baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
690 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
691 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
692 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
693 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
694 now broke, in 1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
695 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
696 </para>
697 <indexterm startref='idxfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
698 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'/>
699 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
700 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
701 <para>
702 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
703 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
704 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
705 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
706 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
707 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
708 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
709 course always public spirited; the reality is something
710 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
711 to themselves, would crumble in
712 <!--PAGE BREAK 22-->
713 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
714 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
715 effect of technological change.
716 </para>
717 <indexterm startref='idxrca' class='endofrange'/>
718 <indexterm startref='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='endofrange'/>
719 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
720 <para>
721 <emphasis role="strong">There's no</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
722 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
723 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
724 Internet and American Life Project, 58 percent of Americans had access
725 to the Internet in 2002, up from 49 percent two years
726 before.<footnote><para>
727 Amanda Lenhart, <quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
728 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,</quote> Pew Internet and American
729 Life Project, 15 April 2003: 6, available at
730 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #2</ulink>.
731 </para></footnote>
732 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
733 of 2004.
734 </para>
735 <para>
736 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
737 changed things. Some of these changes are technical&mdash;the Internet has
738 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
739 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
740 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
741 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
742 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
743 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
744 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
745 </para>
746 <para>
747 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
748 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
749 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
750 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
751 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
752 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
753 has introduced.
754 </para>
755 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
756 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel</primary></indexterm>
757 <indexterm id='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='startofrange'><primary>culture</primary><secondary>commercial vs. noncommercial</secondary></indexterm>
758 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah</primary></indexterm>
759 <para>
760 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
761 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
762 regulation of each. By <quote>commercial culture</quote> I mean that part of our
763 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
764 <quote>noncommercial culture</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
765 parks or on
766 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
767 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
768 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his <quote>Reader,</quote> or
769 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
770 </para>
771 <para>
772 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
773 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
774 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
775 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
776 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
777 left this culture <quote>free.</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
778 individuals shared and transformed their culture&mdash;telling
779 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
780 clubs, sharing music, making tapes&mdash;were left alone by the law.
781 </para>
782 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>commercial creativity as primary purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
783 <para>
784 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
785 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
786 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
787 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
788 marketplace.<footnote>
789 <para>
790 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
791 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
792 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
793 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
794 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
795 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
796 D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote> Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193,
797 198&ndash;200.
798 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
799 </para></footnote>
800 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
801 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
802 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
803 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
804 </para>
805 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
806 <indexterm><primary>permission culture</primary><secondary> free culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
807 <para>
808 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
809 been erased.<footnote><para>
810 See Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
811 2001), ch. 13.
812 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
813 </para></footnote>
814 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
815 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
816 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
817 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
818 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
819 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
820 the balance of our history&mdash;between uses of our culture that were
821 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission&mdash;has
822 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
823 culture, more and more a permission culture.
824 </para>
825 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
826 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
827 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
828 <indexterm><primary>protection of artists vs. business interests</primary></indexterm>
829 <para>
830 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
831 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
832 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
833 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
834 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
835 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
836 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
837 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
838 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
839 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
840 Causbys.
841 </para>
842 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='endofrange'/>
843 <para>
844 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
845 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
846 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
847 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
848 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
849 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
850 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
851 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
852 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
853 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
854 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
855 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
856 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
857 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
858 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
859 than creators do today&mdash;all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
860 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
861 </para>
862 <para>
863 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
864 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
865 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
866 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
867 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
868 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
869 remakes them.
870 </para>
871 <indexterm startref='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='endofrange'/>
872 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary> on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
873 <para>
874 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
875 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
876 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
877 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions&mdash;whether <quote>piracy</quote> will
878 be permitted, and whether <quote>property</quote> will be protected. The <quote>war</quote> that
879 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet&mdash;what
880 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
881 calls his <quote>own terrorist war</quote><footnote><para>
882 Amy Harmon, <quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
883 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,</quote> <citetitle>New York
884 Times</citetitle>, 17 January 2002.
885 </para></footnote>&mdash;has been framed as a battle about the
886 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
887 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
888 against it.
889 </para>
890 <para>
891 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
892 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
893 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
894 <quote>creative property.</quote> I believe that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that the
895 law, properly tuned, should punish <quote>piracy,</quote> whether on or off the
896 Internet.
897 </para>
898 <para>
899 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
900 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
901 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet <quote>pirates</quote> will also rid our
902 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
903 </para>
904 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
905 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
906 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
907 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
908 <para>
909 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first 180 years of
910 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
911 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
912 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
913 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,<footnote>
914 <para>
915 Neil W. Netanel, <quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
916 Journal</citetitle> 106 (1996): 283.
917 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
918 </para></footnote>
919 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
920 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
921 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
922 could cultivate and extend our culture.
923 </para>
924 <para>
925 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
926 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
927 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
928 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist&ndash;like,
929 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
930 granted&mdash;but it is not often granted to the critical or the
931 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
932 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
933 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
934 </para>
935 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Ask author if "Is it" should be "It is" ? -->
936 <para>
937 The story that follows is about this war. It is not about the
938 <quote>centrality of technology</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
939 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
940 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
941 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
942 against an industry.
943 </para>
944 <para>
945 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
946 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
947 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
948 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
949 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
950 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
951 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
952 </para>
953 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
954 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
955 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary></indexterm>
956 <para>
957 <emphasis role="strong">Like the Causbys'</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about <quote>property.</quote> The
958 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
959 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
960 this <quote>property</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
961 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
962 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
963 of <quote>intellectual property</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
964 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
965 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
966 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
967 <quote>trespassing</quote> upon legitimate claims of <quote>property.</quote> It is as plain to
968 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
969 trespass.
970 </para>
971 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
972 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
973 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
974 <para>
975 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
976 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
977 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
978 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
979 war. Unlike
980 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
981 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
982 on its side.
983 </para>
984 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
985 <para>
986 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
987 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
988 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
989 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
990 our <quote>culture</quote> was as <quote>owned</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
991 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
992 <emphasis>uses</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
993 accepted as it is now.
994 </para>
995 <para>
996 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
997 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
998 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
999 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1000 </para>
1001 <para>
1002 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1003 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1004 </para>
1005 <para>
1006 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1007 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1008 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1009 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1010 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1011 </para>
1012 <para>
1013 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1014 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1015 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1016 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1017 view?
1018 </para>
1019 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1020 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1021 <para>
1022 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1023 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1024 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1025 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of <quote>intellectual
1026 property.</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1027 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1028 this silliness will be much more profound.
1029 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1030 </para>
1031 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='endofrange'/>
1032 <para>
1033 <emphasis role="strong">The struggle</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas: <quote>piracy</quote> and
1034 <quote>property.</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1035 ideas.
1036 </para>
1037 <para>
1038 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1039 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1040 obscure French theorists&mdash;however natural that is for the weird
1041 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1042 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1043 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1044 </para>
1045 <para>
1046 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1047 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1048 government, pushed by big media to respond to this <quote>something new,</quote> is
1049 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1050 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let <quote>common
1051 sense</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1052 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1053 law&mdash;and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1054 fundamental about who we have always been.
1055 </para>
1056 <para>
1057 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1058 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1059 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1060 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1061 of one more consequence of this form of corruption&mdash;a consequence
1062 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1063 </para>
1064 </chapter>
1065 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1066 <part id="c-piracy">
1067 <title><quote>PIRACY</quote></title>
1068 <partintro>
1069 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1070 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
1071 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
1072 <indexterm><primary>music publishing</primary></indexterm>
1073 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
1074 <para>
1075 <emphasis role="strong">Since the inception</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1076 been a war against <quote>piracy.</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1077 <quote>piracy,</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1078 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1079 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1080 </para>
1081 <blockquote>
1082 <para>
1083 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1084 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1085 of them for his own use.<footnote><para>
1086 <!-- f1 -->
1087 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield).
1088 </para></footnote>
1089 </para>
1090 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='endofrange'/>
1091 </blockquote>
1092 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary> efficient content distribution on</secondary></indexterm>
1093 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='startofrange'><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>efficiency of</secondary></indexterm>
1094 <para>
1095 Today we are in the middle of another <quote>war</quote> against <quote>piracy.</quote> The
1096 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1097 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1098 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1099 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1100 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1101 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1102 </para>
1103 <para>
1104 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1105 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1106 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1107 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1108 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will <quote>rob the author of the
1109 profit.</quote>
1110 </para>
1111 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='endofrange'/>
1112 <para>
1113 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1114 increasingly to technology to defend their <quote>property</quote> against this
1115 <quote>piracy.</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1116 raised to believe that <quote>property</quote> should be <quote>free.</quote> Forget tattoos,
1117 never mind body piercing&mdash;our kids are becoming
1118 <emphasis>thieves</emphasis>!
1119 </para>
1120 <para>
1121 There's no doubt that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1122 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1123 notion of <quote>piracy</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1124 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1125 </para>
1126 <para>
1127 The idea goes something like this:
1128 </para>
1129 <blockquote>
1130 <para>
1131 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1132 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1133 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1134 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1135 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1136 piracy.
1137 </para>
1138 </blockquote>
1139 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP</primary></indexterm>
1140 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle</primary></indexterm>
1141 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts</primary></indexterm>
1142 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory of</secondary></indexterm>
1143 <indexterm id='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
1144 <para>
1145 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1146 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1147 theory of creative property<footnote><para>
1148 <!-- f2 -->
1149 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, <quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1150 in the Pepsi Generation,</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review</citetitle> 65 (1990): 397.
1151 </para></footnote>
1152 &mdash;if there is value, then someone must have a
1153 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1154 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1155 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.<footnote><para>
1156 <!-- f3 -->
1157 Lisa Bannon, <quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1158 Up,</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 21 August 1996, available at
1159 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #3</ulink>; Jonathan
1160 Zittrain, <quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1161 Speech, No One Wins,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 24 November 2002.
1162 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
1163 </para></footnote>
1164 There was <quote>value</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1165 <quote>right</quote>&mdash;even against the Girl Scouts.
1166 </para>
1167 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='endofrange'/>
1168 <para>
1169 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1170 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1171 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1172 of law protecting creative property. But the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1173 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1174 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1175 </para>
1176 <indexterm startref='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='endofrange'/>
1177 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
1178 <indexterm id='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>legal restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
1179 <para>
1180 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1181 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1182 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1183 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1184 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1185 </para>
1186 <para>
1187 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1188 takes care to draw&mdash;the distinction between republishing someone's
1189 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1190 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1191 copyright law today regulates both.
1192 </para>
1193 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='endofrange'/>
1194 <para>
1195 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1196 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1197 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1198 entities could bear the burden of the law&mdash;even the burden of the
1199 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1200 more expense of doing business.
1201 </para>
1202 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>creativity impeded by</secondary></indexterm>
1203 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1204 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1205 <para>
1206 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1207 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1208 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1209 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1210 <quote>copying,</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1211 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1212 outweighs any original benefit&mdash;certainly as it affects
1213 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1214 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1215 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1216 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1217 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1218 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1219 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1220 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1221 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1222 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the <quote>Rise of the Creative
1223 Class.</quote><footnote>
1224 <para>
1225 <!-- f4 -->
1226 In <citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class</citetitle> (New York:
1227 Basic Books, 2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1228 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1229 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1230 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1231 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1232 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1233
1234 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1235 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1236 </para></footnote>
1237 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1238 this creative class.
1239 </para>
1240 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='endofrange'/>
1241 <para>
1242 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1243 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1244 context the current battles about behavior labeled <quote>piracy.</quote>
1245 </para>
1246 </partintro>
1247
1248 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1249 <chapter label="1" id="creators">
1250 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators</title>
1251 <indexterm id='idxanimatedcartoons' class='startofrange'><primary>animated cartoons</primary></indexterm>
1252 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'><primary>cartoon films</primary></indexterm>
1253 <indexterm id='idxfilmsanimated' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>animated</secondary></indexterm>
1254 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatwillie' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Willie</primary></indexterm>
1255 <indexterm id='idxmickeymouse' class='startofrange'><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
1256 <para>
1257 <emphasis role="strong">In 1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1258 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called <citetitle>Plane Crazy</citetitle>.
1259 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1260 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle> brought
1261 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1262 </para>
1263 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1264 <para>
1265 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1266 movie <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1267 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1268 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1269 Disney ran a test in the summer of 1928, the results were unambiguous.
1270 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1271 </para>
1272 <blockquote>
1273 <para>
1274 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1275 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1276 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1277 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1278 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1279 </para>
1280 <para>
1281 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1282 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1283 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1284 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1285 synchronization was pretty close.
1286 </para>
1287 <para>
1288 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1289 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1290 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1291 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1292 it was something new!<footnote><para>
1293 <!-- f1 -->
1294 Leonard Maltin, <citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1295 Cartoons</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34&ndash;35.
1296 </para></footnote>
1297 </para>
1298 </blockquote>
1299 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub</primary></indexterm>
1300 <para>
1301 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1302 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: <quote>I have never been so thrilled
1303 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.</quote>
1304 </para>
1305 <para>
1306 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1307 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1308 rarely&mdash;except in Disney's hands&mdash;been anything more than
1309 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1310 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1311 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1312 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1313 </para>
1314 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt' class='endofrange'/>
1315 <indexterm id='idxkeatonbuster' class='startofrange'><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1316 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1317 <para>
1318 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that 1928 also marks
1319 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1320 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1321 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>.
1322 </para>
1323 <para>
1324 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in 1895. In the era of silent
1325 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1326 uncontrollable laughter from his audience. <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1327 Jr</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1328 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton&mdash;wildly popular
1329 and among the best of its genre.
1330 </para>
1331 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1332 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1333 <para>
1334 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1335 Willie.
1336 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1337 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1338 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,<footnote><para>
1339 <!-- f2 -->
1340 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1341 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #4</ulink>.
1342 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1343 use the music for five songs in <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>: <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote> <quote>The
1344 Simpleton</quote> (Delille), <quote>Mischief Makers</quote> (Carbonara), <quote>Joyful Hurry No. 1</quote>
1345 (Baron), and <quote>Gawky Rube</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song, <quote>The Turkey in the
1346 Straw,</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1347 Harry Surden, 10 July 2003, on file with author.
1348 </para></footnote>
1349 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1350 the invention of synchronized sound in <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle> that we
1351 get <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1352 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote>
1353 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1354 Mouse.
1355 </para>
1356 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatwillie' class='endofrange'/>
1357 <indexterm startref='idxmickeymouse' class='endofrange'/>
1358 <indexterm startref='idxkeatonbuster' class='endofrange'/>
1359 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='endofrange'/>
1360 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1361 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
1362 <para>
1363 This <quote>borrowing</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1364 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1365 films of his day.<footnote><para>
1366 <!-- f3 -->
1367 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, <quote>The Mouse
1368 that Ate the Public Domain,</quote> Findlaw, 5 March 2002, at
1369 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #5</ulink>.
1370 </para></footnote>
1371 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1372 knockoffs&mdash;slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1373 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1374 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1375 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1376 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1377 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1378 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1379 old.
1380 </para>
1381 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1382 <para>
1383 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1384 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1385 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1386 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1387 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1388 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1389 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1390 </para>
1391 <para>
1392 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1393 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1394 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1395 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1396 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1397 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1398 work of others is astonishing when set together: <citetitle>Snow White</citetitle>
1399 (1937), <citetitle>Fantasia</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Pinocchio</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Dumbo</citetitle>
1400 (1941), <citetitle>Bambi</citetitle> (1942), <citetitle>Song of the South</citetitle> (1946),
1401 <citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle> (1950), <citetitle>Alice in Wonderland</citetitle> (1951), <citetitle>Robin
1402 Hood</citetitle> (1952), <citetitle>Peter Pan</citetitle> (1953), <citetitle>Lady and the Tramp</citetitle>
1403 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1404 (1955), <citetitle>Mulan</citetitle> (1998), <citetitle>Sleeping Beauty</citetitle> (1959), <citetitle>101
1405 Dalmatians</citetitle> (1961), <citetitle>The Sword in the Stone</citetitle> (1963), and
1406 <citetitle>The Jungle Book</citetitle> (1967)&mdash;not to mention a recent example
1407 that we should perhaps quickly forget, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>
1408 (2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1409 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1410 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1411 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1412 </para>
1413 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales' class='endofrange'/>
1414 <para>
1415 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1416 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1417 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1418 its importance. We could call this <quote>Disney creativity,</quote> though that
1419 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, <quote>Walt Disney
1420 creativity</quote>&mdash;a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1421 culture around us and makes it something different.
1422 </para>
1423 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='endofrange'/>
1424 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='endofrange'/>
1425 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='endofrange'/>
1426 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
1427 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>defined</secondary></indexterm>
1428 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>traditional term for conversion to</secondary></indexterm>
1429 <para> In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1430 relatively fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was
1431 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1432 thirty years&mdash;for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1433 copyrighted.<footnote><para>
1434 <!-- f4 -->
1435 Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1436 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the <quote>average</quote> term by
1437 determining
1438 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1439 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in year
1440 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the
1441 average
1442 term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1443 Web site associated with this book, available at
1444 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #6</ulink>.
1445 </para></footnote>
1446 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1447 copyright holders of a creative work had an <quote>exclusive right</quote> to control
1448 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1449 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1450 </para>
1451 <para>
1452 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1453 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1454 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a <quote>lawyer-free
1455 zone.</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1456 for Disney to use and build upon in 1928. It was free for
1457 anyone&mdash; whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1458 approved or not&mdash;to use and build upon.
1459 </para>
1460 <indexterm startref='idxanimatedcartoons' class='endofrange'/>
1461 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsanimated' class='endofrange'/>
1462 <para>
1463 This is the ways things always were&mdash;until quite recently. For most
1464 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1465 until 1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1466 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1467
1468 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1469 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1470 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s
1471 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1472 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1473 content from before the Great Depression.
1474 </para>
1475 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'/>
1476 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc' class='endofrange'/>
1477 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='endofrange'/>
1478 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='endofrange'/>
1479 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='endofrange'/>
1480 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1481 <para>
1482 <emphasis role="strong">Of course</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on <quote>Walt Disney creativity.</quote>
1483 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1484 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1485 universal.
1486 </para>
1487 <indexterm id='idxcomicsjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1488 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1489 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1490 <indexterm id='idxmanga' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1491 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1492 <para>
1493 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1494 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: <citetitle>manga</citetitle>, or
1495 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of
1496 publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives
1497 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1498 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1499 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1500 </para>
1501 <para>
1502 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1503 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1504 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1505 the stories that these <quote>graphic novels</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1506 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are <quote>men in tights.</quote>
1507 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1508 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1509 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1510 interestingly different way.
1511 </para>
1512 <para>
1513 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1514 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1515 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1516 </para>
1517 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1518 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1519 <para>
1520 This is the phenomenon of <citetitle>doujinshi</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1521 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1522 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is <emphasis>just</emphasis> a
1523 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1524 transforming it either subtly or
1525 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1526 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1527 develop it differently&mdash;with a different story line. Or the comic can
1528 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1529 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently <quote>different.</quote> But they
1530 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1531 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1532 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1533 </para>
1534 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1535 <para>
1536 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1537 huge. More than 33,000 <quote>circles</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1538 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come
1539 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1540 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1541 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1542 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1543 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1544 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1545 </para>
1546 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1547 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1548 <para>
1549 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1550 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1551 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1552 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1553 one. Doujinshi are plainly <quote>derivative works.</quote> There is no general
1554 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1555 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1556 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1557 Jr</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that <quote>taking</quote> without
1558 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1559 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1560 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1561 </para>
1562 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt2' class='endofrange'/>
1563 <indexterm id='idxwinickjudd' class='startofrange'><primary>Winick, Judd</primary></indexterm>
1564 <para>
1565 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1566 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1567 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, <quote>The
1568 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1569 in Japan now. &hellip; American comics were born out of copying each
1570 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1571 other. &hellip; That's how [the artists] learn to draw &mdash; by going into comic
1572 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them</quote>
1573 and building from them.<footnote><para>
1574 <!-- f5 -->
1575 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, <citetitle>Reinventing Comics</citetitle> (New
1576 York: Perennial, 2000).
1577 </para></footnote>
1578 </para>
1579 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1580 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics</primary></indexterm>
1581 <para>
1582 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1583 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1584 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, <quote>there are these rules
1585 and you have to stick to them.</quote> There are things Superman <quote>cannot</quote>
1586 do. <quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1587 which are fifty years old.</quote>
1588 </para>
1589 <indexterm startref='idxwinickjudd' class='endofrange'/>
1590 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1591 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1592 <indexterm id='idxmehrasalil' class='startofrange'><primary>Mehra, Salil</primary></indexterm>
1593 <para>
1594 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1595 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1596 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1597 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1598 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1599 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1600 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.<footnote><para>
1601 <!-- f6 -->
1602 See Salil K. Mehra, <quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1603 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1604 Review</citetitle> 55 (2002): 155, 182. <quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1605 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1606 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1607 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1608 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1609 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.</quote>
1610 </para></footnote>
1611 </para>
1612 <indexterm startref='idxcomicsjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1613 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics' class='endofrange'/>
1614 <indexterm startref='idxmanga' class='endofrange'/>
1615 <para>
1616 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1617 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1618 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1619 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1620 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1621 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1622 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1623 a more general pattern of blocking this <quote>free taking</quote> by the doujinshi
1624 culture?
1625 </para>
1626 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='endofrange'/>
1627 <indexterm startref='idxmehrasalil' class='endofrange'/>
1628 <para>
1629 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1630 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1631 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. <quote>We don't have enough
1632 lawyers,</quote> he told me one afternoon. There <quote>just aren't enough resources
1633 to prosecute cases like this.</quote>
1634 </para>
1635 <para>
1636 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1637 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1638 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1639 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1640 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1641 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1642 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1643 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1644 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1645 their clients or hurt them?
1646 </para>
1647 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics' class='endofrange'/>
1648 <para>
1649 <emphasis role='strong'>Let's pause</emphasis> for a moment.
1650 </para>
1651 <para>
1652 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1653 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1654 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1655 </para>
1656 <para>
1657 We live in a world that celebrates <quote>property.</quote> I am one of those
1658 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1659 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1660 <quote>intellectual property.</quote><footnote><para>
1661 <!-- f7 -->
1662 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
1663 The term <citetitle>intellectual property</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1664 Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 11 (New York: New York
1665 University Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
1666 (New York: Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately
1667 describes a set of <quote>property</quote> rights &mdash; copyright, patents,
1668 trademark, and trade-secret &mdash; but the nature of those rights is
1669 very different.
1670 </para></footnote>
1671 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1672 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1673 property.
1674 </para>
1675 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt3' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1676 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1677 <indexterm><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1678 <para>
1679 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1680 plenty of value out there that <quote>property</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1681 mean <quote>money can't buy you love,</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1682 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1683 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1684 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1685 condemning that taking as wrong&mdash; even though trivial, even if
1686 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1687 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1688 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1689 Disney's use would have been considered <quote>fair.</quote> There was nothing
1690 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1691 the public domain.
1692 </para>
1693 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>derivative works based on</secondary></indexterm>
1694 <para>
1695 Thus, even though the things that Disney took&mdash;or more generally,
1696 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity&mdash;are
1697 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1698
1699 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1700 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1701 freedom is good.
1702 </para>
1703 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='endofrange'/>
1704 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1705 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1706 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1707 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1708 <indexterm id='idxmanga2' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1709 <para>
1710 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1711 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1712 work&mdash;or even one copy&mdash;without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1713 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1714 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1715 form, whether large or small.
1716 </para>
1717 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='endofrange'/>
1718 <para>
1719 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1720 say that the copycat comic artists are <quote>stealing.</quote> This form of Walt
1721 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1722 particular find it hard to say why.
1723 </para>
1724 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1725 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1726 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='endofrange'/>
1727 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1728 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1729 <indexterm startref='idxmanga2' class='endofrange'/>
1730 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
1731 <para>
1732 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1733 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1734 without asking or paying for the privilege. (<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1735 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1736 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?</quote>) Acting companies
1737 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1738 permission from anyone. (Does <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> believe
1739 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1740 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1741 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1742 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s;
1743 two volcano disaster films in 1997.
1744 </para>
1745 <para>
1746 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1747 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1748 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1749 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1750 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1751 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1752 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking&mdash;free
1753 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1754 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1755 </para>
1756 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt3' class='endofrange'/>
1757 <para>
1758 The hard question is therefore not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> a
1759 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1760 question instead is <quote><emphasis>How</emphasis> free is this culture?</quote>
1761 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1762 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1763 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1764 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1765 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1766 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1767 a studio or not?
1768 </para>
1769 <para>
1770 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1771 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1772 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1773 </para>
1774 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='endofrange'/>
1775
1776 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1777 </chapter>
1778 <chapter label="2" id="mere-copyists">
1779 <title>CHAPTER TWO: <quote>Mere Copyists</quote></title>
1780 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis</primary></indexterm>
1781 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1782 <indexterm id='idxphotography' class='startofrange'><primary>photography</primary></indexterm>
1783 <para>
1784 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1785 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1786 <quote>photographs.</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1787 <quote>daguerreotypes.</quote> The process was complicated and
1788 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1789 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1790 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1791 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1792 </para>
1793 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William</primary></indexterm>
1794 <para>
1795 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1796 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1797 <quote>automatic pictures.</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1798 making <quote>negatives.</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1799 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1800 the 1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1801 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1802 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1803 amateurs.
1804 </para>
1805 <indexterm id='idxeastmangeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Eastman, George</primary></indexterm>
1806 <para>
1807 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1808 didn't happen until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1809 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1810 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1811 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1812 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1813 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1814 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1815 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1816 population of photographers.
1817 </para>
1818 <indexterm id='idxkodakcameras' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1819 <indexterm id='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)</primary></indexterm>
1820 <para>
1821 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1822 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1823 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. <quote>You press the button and we
1824 do the rest.</quote><footnote><para>
1825 <!-- f1 -->
1826 Reese V. Jenkins, <citetitle>Images and Enterprise</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975), 112.
1827 </para></footnote> As he described in <citetitle>The Kodak Primer</citetitle>:
1828 </para>
1829 <blockquote>
1830 <para>
1831 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1832 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1833 that only an expert can do. &hellip; We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1834 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1835 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1836 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1837 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1838 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1839 chemicals.<footnote>
1840 <para>
1841 <!-- f2 -->
1842 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1843 Brian Coe, <citetitle>The Birth of Photography</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1844 1977), 53.
1845 </para></footnote>
1846 </para>
1847 </blockquote>
1848 <indexterm startref='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='endofrange'/>
1849 <para>
1850 For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1851 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1852 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1853 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1854 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1855 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in 1888; one
1856 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1857 From 1888 through 1909, while industrial production was rising by 4.7
1858 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by 11
1859 percent.<footnote><para>
1860 <!-- f3 -->
1861 Jenkins, 177.
1862 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1863 an average annual increase of over 17 percent.<footnote><para>
1864 <!-- f4 -->
1865 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p. 178.
1866 </para></footnote>
1867 </para>
1868 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1869 <para>
1870
1871 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1872 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1873 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1874 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1875 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1876 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, <quote>For the
1877 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1878 permanent record of his family and its activities. &hellip; For the first
1879 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1880 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1881 interpretation or bias.</quote><footnote><para>
1882 <!-- f5 -->
1883 Coe, 58.
1884 </para></footnote>
1885 </para>
1886 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
1887 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
1888 <para>
1889 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1890 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1891 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1892 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1893 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1894 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its <quote>quality</quote>;
1895 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1896 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1897 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1898 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1899 have before.
1900 </para>
1901 <indexterm startref='idxkodakcameras' class='endofrange'/>
1902 <indexterm id='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>permissions</primary><secondary>photography exempted from</secondary></indexterm>
1903 <para>
1904 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1905 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1906 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1907 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1908 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1909 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1910 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1911 he wanted. Their answer was no.<footnote><para>
1912 <!-- f6 -->
1913 For illustrative cases, see, for example, <citetitle>Pavesich</citetitle>
1914 v. <citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co</citetitle>., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905);
1915 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Chinn</citetitle>, 123090 S.W. 364, 366
1916 (Ky. 1909); <citetitle>Corliss</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Walker</citetitle>, 64 F. 280 (Mass.
1917 Dist. Ct. 1894).
1918 </para></footnote>
1919 </para>
1920 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology' class='endofrange'/>
1921 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt4' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1922 <indexterm id='idximagesownershipof' class='startofrange'><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
1923 <para>
1924 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1925 familiar. The photographer was <quote>taking</quote> something from the person or
1926 building whose photograph he shot&mdash;pirating something of
1927 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1928 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1929 draw
1930 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1931 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1932 that they thought valuable.
1933 </para>
1934 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1935 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1936 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology2' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1937 <para>
1938 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1939 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1940 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1941 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1942 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.<footnote>
1943 <para>
1944 <!-- f7 -->
1945 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote>
1946 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review</citetitle> 4 (1890): 193.
1947 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1948 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.</primary></indexterm>
1949 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1950 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1951 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1952 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1953 </para>
1954 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt4' class='endofrange'/>
1955 <para>
1956 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1957 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1958 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1959 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1960 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1961 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1962 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1963 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1964 clearing the rights to do the capturing.<footnote><para>
1965 <!-- f8 -->
1966 See Melville B. Nimmer, <quote>The Right of Publicity,</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
1967 Problems</citetitle> 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, <quote>Privacy,</quote> <citetitle>California Law
1968 Review</citetitle> 48 (1960) 398&ndash;407; <citetitle>White</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
1969 Inc</citetitle>., 971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951
1970 (1993).
1971 </para></footnote>)
1972 </para>
1973 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1974 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
1975 <para>
1976 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1977 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1978 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1979 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1980 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1981 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1982 Kodak would be benefiting from the <quote>theft</quote> committed by the
1983 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1984 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1985 from the <quote>image-right</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
1986 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1987 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1988 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1989 </para>
1990 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology2' class='endofrange'/>
1991 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology3' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1992 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
1993 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
1994 <para>
1995
1996 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
1997 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
1998 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
1999 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
2000 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
2001 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
2002 technology as they did&mdash;since professionals could have more
2003 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
2004 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
2005 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
2006 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
2007 realized.
2008 </para>
2009 <indexterm startref='idxphotography' class='endofrange'/>
2010 <indexterm startref='idxeastmangeorge' class='endofrange'/>
2011 <indexterm startref='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
2012 <indexterm startref='idximagesownershipof' class='endofrange'/>
2013 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
2014 <indexterm id='idxjustthink' class='startofrange'><primary>Just Think!</primary></indexterm>
2015 <para>
2016 <emphasis role='strong'>If you drive</emphasis> through San
2017 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
2018 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
2019 <quote>Just Think!</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
2020 there's little that's <quote>just</quote> cerebral in the projects
2021 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
2022 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
2023 the film of your VCR. Rather the <quote>film</quote> of digital
2024 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
2025 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
2026 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
2027 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
2028 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
2029 think. By tinkering, they learn.
2030 </para>
2031 <indexterm id='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>education</primary><secondary>in media literacy</secondary></indexterm>
2032 <indexterm id='idxmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>media literacy</primary></indexterm>
2033 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>media literacy and</secondary></indexterm>
2034 <para>
2035 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
2036 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
2037 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, <quote>Five years ago, a good
2038 real-time digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get
2039 professional quality for $595.</quote><footnote><para>
2040 <!-- f9 -->
2041 H. Edward Goldberg, <quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
2042 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,</quote>
2043 cadalyst, February 2002, available at
2044 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #7</ulink>.
2045 </para></footnote>
2046 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
2047 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
2048 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
2049 learning more and more of something teachers call <quote>media literacy.</quote>
2050 </para>
2051 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2052 <para>
2053 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
2054 <quote>Media literacy,</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
2055 Think!, puts it, <quote>is the ability &hellip; to understand, analyze, and
2056 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2057 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2058 the way people access it.</quote>
2059 </para>
2060 <indexterm startref='idxjustthink' class='endofrange'/>
2061 <para>
2062 This may seem like an odd way to think about <quote>literacy.</quote> For most
2063 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2064 and noticing split infinitives are the things that <quote>literate</quote> people know
2065 about.
2066 </para>
2067 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2068 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
2069 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
2070 <para>
2071 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of
2072 television commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000
2073 commercials generally,<footnote><para>
2074 <!-- f10 -->
2075 Judith Van Evra, <citetitle>Television and Child Development</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2076 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990); <quote>Findings on Family and TV
2077 Study,</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post</citetitle>, 25 May 1997, B6.
2078 </para></footnote>
2079 it is increasingly important to understand the <quote>grammar</quote> of media. For
2080 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2081 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2082 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2083 (at least at first) terrible media.
2084 </para>
2085 <para>
2086 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2087 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2088 has written understands how difficult writing is&mdash;how difficult
2089 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2090 language to be understandable&mdash;few of us have any real sense of
2091 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2092 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2093 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2094 </para>
2095 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology3' class='endofrange'/>
2096 <para>
2097 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2098 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2099 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2100 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2101 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2102 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2103 </para>
2104 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2105 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael</primary></indexterm>
2106 <para>
2107 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2108 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2109 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2110
2111 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2112 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2113 about <quote>the placement of objects, color, &hellip; rhythm, pacing, and
2114 texture.</quote><footnote>
2115 <para>
2116 <!-- f11 -->
2117 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish, 13 December
2118 2002.
2119 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2120 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2121 </para></footnote>
2122 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2123 <quote>played</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2124 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2125 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2126 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2127 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2128 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2129 to a wildly successful author.<footnote><para>
2130 <!-- f12 -->
2131 See Scott Steinberg, <quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,</quote> E!online, 4
2132 November 2000, available at
2133 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #8</ulink>; <quote>Timeline,</quote> 22 November 2000,
2134 available at
2135 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #9</ulink>.
2136 </para></footnote>
2137 </para>
2138 <indexterm><primary>computer games</primary></indexterm>
2139 <para>
2140 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2141 describes, <quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2142 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2143 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2144 led.</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2145 </para>
2146 <para>
2147 Yet the push for an expanded literacy&mdash;one that goes beyond text
2148 to include audio and visual elements&mdash;is not about making better
2149 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2150 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2151 </para>
2152 <blockquote>
2153 <para>
2154 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2155 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2156 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2157 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2158 being read-only.
2159 </para>
2160 </blockquote>
2161 <para>
2162 <quote>Read-only.</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2163 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2164 twentieth century.
2165 </para>
2166 <para>
2167 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2168 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2169 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2170 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2171 literacy,
2172 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2173 and this literacy in particular, is to <quote>empower people to choose the
2174 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2175 express.</quote><footnote>
2176 <para>
2177 <!-- f13 -->
2178 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2179 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2180 </para></footnote> It is to enable students <quote>to communicate in the
2181 language of the twenty-first century.</quote><footnote><para>
2182 <!-- f14 -->
2183 Ibid.
2184 </para></footnote>
2185 </para>
2186 <indexterm id='idxbarishstephanie' class='startofrange'><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2187 <para>
2188 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2189 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2190 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2191 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2192 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2193 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2194 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2195 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2196 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2197 students know something about&mdash;gun violence.
2198 </para>
2199 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='endofrange'/>
2200 <para>
2201 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2202 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2203 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2204 away. The <quote>kids were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night,</quote>
2205 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2206 what education should be about&mdash;learning how to express themselves.
2207 </para>
2208 <para>
2209 Using whatever <quote>free web stuff they could find,</quote> and relatively simple
2210 tools to enable the kids to mix <quote>image, sound, and text,</quote> Barish said
2211 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2212 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2213 close to the lives of these students. The project <quote>gave them a tool
2214 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2215 it,</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2216 expression&mdash;far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2217 been created using only text. <quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2218 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2219 gone and done something else,</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2220 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2221 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2222 <emphasis>these</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2223 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2224 </para>
2225 <indexterm startref='idxbarishstephanie' class='endofrange'/>
2226 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2227 <para>
2228
2229 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2230 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?</quote> I asked. In part,
2231 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2232 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of <quote>constructing
2233 meaning.</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2234 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2235 part&mdash;and increasingly, not the most powerful part&mdash;of
2236 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2237 our interview,
2238 </para>
2239 <blockquote>
2240 <para>
2241 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2242 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2243 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2244 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2245 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2246 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2247 you say, <quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.</quote>
2248 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2249 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2250 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, <quote>Well, with all these things that you
2251 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2252 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2253 for me something that reflects that.</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2254 camera and &hellip; saying, <quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2255 make a little movie.</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2256 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2257 about the topic.&hellip;
2258 </para>
2259 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2260 <para>
2261 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2262 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2263 bump up against the fact, <quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2264 to write something.</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2265 they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 times, till they got it right.
2266 </para>
2267 <para>
2268 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2269 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2270 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2271 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2272 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2273 had a lot of power with this language.
2274 </para>
2275 <!-- FIXME removed a " from the end of the previous paragraph that did
2276 not match with any start quote. -->
2277 </blockquote>
2278 <indexterm startref='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2279 <indexterm startref='idxmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2280 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='endofrange'/>
2281 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='endofrange'/>
2282 <indexterm id='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='startofrange'><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2283 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center</primary></indexterm>
2284 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
2285 <para>
2286 <emphasis role='strong'>When two planes</emphasis> crashed into the
2287 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2288 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2289 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2290 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2291 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2292 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2293 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2294 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2295 watching.
2296 </para>
2297 <para>
2298 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2299 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2300 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was <quote>balance,</quote>
2301 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2302 increasingly come to expect it, <quote>news as entertainment,</quote> even if the
2303 entertainment is tragedy.
2304 </para>
2305 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
2306 <indexterm><primary>CBS</primary></indexterm>
2307 <para>
2308 But in addition to this produced news about the <quote>tragedy of September
2309 11,</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2310 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2311 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2312 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2313 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2314 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2315 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2316 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2317 the term in his book <citetitle>Cyber Rights</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2318 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2319 was also the Internet.
2320 </para>
2321 <indexterm startref='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='endofrange'/>
2322 <para>
2323 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet&mdash;though I do think the
2324 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2325 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2326 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2327 movie
2328 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2329 by a student on the <quote>Just Think!</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2330 with sound or text.
2331 </para>
2332 <para>
2333 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2334 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2335 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2336 tradition&mdash;not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2337 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2338 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2339 spread practically instantaneously.
2340 </para>
2341 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2342 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2343 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2344 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2345 <para>
2346 September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2347 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2348 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2349 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2350 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2351 cultures, it records private facts in a public way&mdash;it's a kind
2352 of electronic <citetitle>Jerry Springer</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2353 </para>
2354 <indexterm><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2355 <indexterm id='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>public discourse conducted on</secondary></indexterm>
2356 <para>
2357 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2358 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2359 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2360 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2361 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2362 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2363 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2364 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2365 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2366 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2367 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2368 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2369 </para>
2370 <indexterm id='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
2371 <indexterm id='idxelections' class='startofrange'><primary>elections</primary></indexterm>
2372 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
2373 <para>
2374 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2375 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2376 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2377 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2378 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2379 people vote
2380 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2381 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2382 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2383 </para>
2384 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2385 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson' class='endofrange'/>
2386 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2387 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de</primary></indexterm>
2388 <indexterm id='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>public discourse in</secondary></indexterm>
2389 <indexterm><primary>jury system</primary></indexterm>
2390 <para>
2391 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2392 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2393 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2394 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2395 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2396 most important account of early <quote>Democracy in America.</quote> It wasn't
2397 popular elections that fascinated him&mdash;it was the jury, an
2398 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2399 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2400 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2401 deliberated. Members argued about the <quote>right</quote> result; they tried to
2402 persuade each other of the <quote>right</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2403 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2404 come to an end.<footnote><para>
2405 <!-- f15 -->
2406 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, <citetitle>Democracy in America</citetitle>,
2407 bk. 1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16.
2408 </para></footnote>
2409 </para>
2410 <indexterm startref='idxelections' class='endofrange'/>
2411 <para>
2412 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2413 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2414 are pushing to create just such an institution.<footnote><para>
2415 <!-- f16 -->
2416 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, <quote>Deliberation Day,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2417 Political Philosophy</citetitle> 10 (2) (2002): 129.
2418 </para></footnote>
2419 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2420 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2421 place for <quote>democratic deliberation</quote> to occur.
2422 </para>
2423 <indexterm id='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='startofrange'><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2424 <para>
2425 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2426 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2427 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2428 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2429 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2430 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.<footnote><para>
2431 <!-- f17 -->
2432 Cass Sunstein, <citetitle>Republic.com</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001),
2433 65&ndash;80, 175, 182, 183, 192.
2434 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2435 little beyond what our friends say.
2436 </para>
2437 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2438 <indexterm><primary>e-mail</primary></indexterm>
2439 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2440 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2441 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='endofrange'/>
2442 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='endofrange'/>
2443 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='endofrange'/>
2444 <para>
2445 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2446 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2447 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2448 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2449 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2450
2451 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2452 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2453 place.
2454 </para>
2455 <para>
2456 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2457 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2458 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2459 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2460 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2461 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2462 </para>
2463 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard</primary></indexterm>
2464 <para>
2465 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2466 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race
2467 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2468 is having an effect.
2469 </para>
2470 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent</primary></indexterm>
2471 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom</primary></indexterm>
2472 <indexterm id='idxmediablogpressureon' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>blog pressure on</secondary></indexterm>
2473 <indexterm id='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>news events on</secondary></indexterm>
2474 <para>
2475 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2476 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2477 <quote>misspoke</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2478 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2479 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2480 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2481 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2482 more instances of the same <quote>misspeaking</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2483 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2484 resign as senate majority leader.<footnote><para>
2485 <!-- f18 -->
2486 Noah Shachtman, <quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,</quote> New
2487 York Times, 16 January 2003, G5.
2488 </para></footnote>
2489 </para>
2490 <indexterm id='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2491 <para>
2492 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2493 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2494 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2495 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2496 on.
2497 </para>
2498 <indexterm startref='idxmediablogpressureon' class='endofrange'/>
2499 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>peer-generated rankings on</secondary></indexterm>
2500 <para>
2501 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2502 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2503 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2504 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2505 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2506 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2507 peer-generated rankings.
2508 </para>
2509 <indexterm startref='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='endofrange'/>
2510 <indexterm id='idxjournalism' class='startofrange'><primary>journalism</primary></indexterm>
2511 <indexterm id='idxwinerdave' class='startofrange'><primary>Winer, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2512 <para>
2513 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2514 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2515 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2516 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2517 difference is the absence of a financial <quote>conflict of interest.</quote> <quote>I think you
2518 have to take the conflict of interest</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2519 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2520 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2521 get it out of the way.</quote>
2522 </para>
2523 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2524 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2525 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2526 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
2527 <para>
2528 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2529 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2530 from the public than an unconcentrated media can&mdash;as CNN admitted
2531 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2532 its own employees.<footnote><para>
2533 <!-- f19 -->
2534 Telephone interview with David Winer, 16 April 2003.
2535 </para></footnote>
2536 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2537 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2538 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2539 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2540 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2541 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2542 told her that <emphasis>they</emphasis> were writing <quote>the story.</quote>)
2543 </para>
2544 <indexterm startref='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='endofrange'/>
2545 <para>
2546 Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2547 debate&mdash;<quote>amateur</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced,
2548 but in the sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to
2549 give their reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a
2550 story, as reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds
2551 from across the southwest United States turned to the Internet to
2552 retell what they had seen.<footnote><para>
2553 <!-- f20 -->
2554 John Schwartz, <quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2555 Information Online,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci
2556 D. Kramer, <quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,</quote>
2557 Online Journalism Review, 2 February 2003, available at
2558 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #10</ulink>.
2559 </para></footnote>
2560 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2561 <quote>triangulate,</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2562 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2563 out of it</quote>&mdash;with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2564 </para>
2565 <para>
2566 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2567 with blogs. <quote>It's going to become an essential skill,</quote> Winer predicts,
2568 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2569 not clear that <quote>journalism</quote> is happy about this&mdash;some journalists
2570 have been told to curtail their blogging.<footnote>
2571 <para>
2572 <!-- f21 -->
2573 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2574 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2575 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve</primary></indexterm>
2576 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2577 See Michael Falcone, <quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?</quote> <citetitle>New
2578 York Times</citetitle>, 29 September 2003, C4. (<quote>Not all news organizations have
2579 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2580 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2581 war on March 9, stopped posting 12 days later at his bosses'
2582 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a <citetitle>Houston Chronicle</citetitle> reporter, was
2583 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2584 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.</quote>)
2585 </para></footnote>
2586 But it is clear that we are still in transition. <quote>A
2587
2588 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2589 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,</quote> Winer told me.
2590 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2591 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2592 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, <quote>we will
2593 be the last thing that gets shut down.</quote>
2594 </para>
2595 <indexterm startref='idxjournalism' class='endofrange'/>
2596 <para>
2597 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because <quote>you
2598 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.</quote>
2599 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2600 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2601 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2602 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2603 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2604 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2605 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2606 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2607 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2608 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2609 extraordinary to report.
2610 </para>
2611 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage' class='endofrange'/>
2612 <indexterm startref='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='endofrange'/>
2613 <indexterm startref='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='endofrange'/>
2614 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2615 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson2' class='endofrange'/>
2616 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2617 <indexterm startref='idxwinerdave' class='endofrange'/>
2618 <indexterm id='idxbrownjohnseely' class='startofrange'><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
2619 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2620 <para>
2621 <emphasis role='strong'>John Seely Brown</emphasis> is the chief
2622 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2623 describes it, is <quote>human learning and &hellip; the creation of
2624 knowledge ecologies for creating &hellip; innovation.</quote>
2625 </para>
2626 <para>
2627 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2628 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2629 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2630 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2631 affect learning.
2632 </para>
2633 <para>
2634 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When <quote>a lot of us grew up,</quote>
2635 he explains, that tinkering was done <quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2636 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.</quote> But digital technologies
2637 enable a different kind of tinkering&mdash;with abstract ideas though
2638 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2639 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2640 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2641 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2642 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2643 or <quote>free collage,</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2644 the tinkering of many others.
2645 </para>
2646 <para>
2647 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2648 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2649 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2650 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2651 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2652 </para>
2653 <para>
2654 This opportunity creates a <quote>completely new kind of learning platform,</quote>
2655 as Brown describes. <quote>As soon as you start doing that, you &hellip;
2656 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2657 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2658 if they can improve it.</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2659 apprenticeship. <quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.</quote>
2660 </para>
2661 <para>
2662 In this process, <quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2663 They are code.</quote> Kids are <quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2664 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2665 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2666 platform. &hellip; You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2667 you tinker the more you improve.</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2668 learn.
2669 </para>
2670 <para>
2671 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2672 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2673 it, <quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2674 intelligence.</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2675 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2676 text. <quote>The Web &hellip; says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2677 you are visual, if you are interested in film &hellip; [then] there is a
2678 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2679 these multiple forms of intelligence.</quote>
2680 </para>
2681 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'/>
2682 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2683 <para>
2684 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2685 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2686
2687 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2688 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2689 kind of recognition.
2690 </para>
2691 <para>
2692 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2693 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2694 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2695 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2696 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2697 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2698 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2699 </para>
2700 <para>
2701 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2702 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2703 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>)
2704 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the <quote>right to
2705 tinker</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2706 general.<footnote><para>
2707 <!-- f22 -->
2708 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, <quote>Technological Access
2709 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2710 of the Association for Computer Machinery</citetitle> 43 (2000): 9.
2711 </para></footnote>
2712 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2713 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2714 </para>
2715 <para>
2716 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,</quote> Brown
2717 explains. We need to <quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2718 and want to learn.</quote>
2719 </para>
2720 <para>
2721 <quote>Yet,</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2722 evince, <quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2723 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. &hellip; We're building an
2724 architecture that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2725 system that closes down that part of the brain.</quote>
2726 </para>
2727 <indexterm startref='idxbrownjohnseely' class='endofrange'/>
2728 <para>
2729 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2730 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2731 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2732 the law to close down that technology.
2733 </para>
2734 <para>
2735 <quote>No way to run a culture,</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2736 chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="collectors"/>,
2737 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2738 </para>
2739 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2740 </chapter>
2741 <chapter label="3" id="catalogs">
2742 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs</title>
2743 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2744 <indexterm><primary>RPI</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</see></indexterm>
2745 <indexterm id='idxrensselaer' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary></indexterm>
2746 <indexterm id='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary><secondary>computer network search engine of</secondary></indexterm>
2747 <indexterm id='idxsearchengines' class='startofrange'><primary>search engines</primary></indexterm>
2748 <indexterm id='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='startofrange'><primary>university computer networks, p2p sharing on</primary></indexterm>
2749 <indexterm id='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>search engines used on</secondary></indexterm>
2750 <para>
2751 <emphasis role='strong'>In the fall</emphasis> of 2002, Jesse Jordan
2752 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2753 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2754 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2755 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2756 was available on the RPI network.
2757 </para>
2758 <para>
2759 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2760 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2761 to information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand
2762 undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school
2763 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2764 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2765 </para>
2766 <para>
2767 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2768 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2769 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2770 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2771 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2772 </para>
2773 <indexterm id='idxgoogle' class='startofrange'><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2774 <para>
2775 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2776 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2777 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2778 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2779 engines can do this even better. The idea of <quote>intranet</quote> search
2780 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2781 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2782 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2783 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2784 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2785 </para>
2786 <indexterm id='idxjordanjesse' class='startofrange'><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2787 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>network file system of</secondary></indexterm>
2788 <para>
2789 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2790 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2791 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2792 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2793 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2794 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2795 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2796 </para>
2797 <indexterm startref='idxgoogle' class='endofrange'/>
2798 <para>
2799 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2800 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2801 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2802 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2803 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2804 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2805 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2806 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2807 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2808 on-line.
2809 </para>
2810 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='endofrange'/>
2811 <para>
2812 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2813 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2814 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2815 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2816 be on users' computers.
2817 </para>
2818 <indexterm startref='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='endofrange'/>
2819 <para>
2820 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2821 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2822 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2823 might have created; university brochures&mdash;basically anything that
2824 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2825 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2826 computer.
2827 </para>
2828 <indexterm><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2829 <indexterm><primary>education</primary><secondary>tinkering as means of</secondary></indexterm>
2830 <para>
2831 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2832 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2833 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and&mdash;so that this
2834 point is absolutely clear&mdash;Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2835 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2836 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2837 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2838 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2839 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2840 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2841 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2842 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2843 supposed to do.
2844 </para>
2845 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
2846 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>against student file sharing</secondary></indexterm>
2847 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
2848 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
2849 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='endofrange'/>
2850 <para>
2851 On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2852 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2853 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2854 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2855 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2856 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2857 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2858 </para>
2859 <para>
2860 <quote>It was absurd,</quote> he told me. <quote>I don't think I did anything
2861 wrong. &hellip; I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2862 engine that I ran or &hellip; what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2863 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2864 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2865 easier to use</quote>&mdash;again, a <emphasis>search engine</emphasis>,
2866 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2867 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2868 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2869 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2870 with music.
2871 </para>
2872 <indexterm startref='idxsearchengines' class='endofrange'/>
2873 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
2874 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>statutory damages of</secondary></indexterm>
2875 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>individual defendants intimidated by</secondary></indexterm>
2876 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages</primary></indexterm>
2877 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>intimidation tactics of</secondary></indexterm>
2878 <para>
2879 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2880 network and had therefore <quote>willfully</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2881 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2882 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2883 <quote>willful infringement,</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2884 call <quote>statutory damages.</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2885 claim $150,000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2886 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2887 Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000.
2888 </para>
2889 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University</primary></indexterm>
2890 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University</primary></indexterm>
2891 <para>
2892 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2893 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2894 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2895 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2896 huge demands for <quote>damages</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2897 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2898 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $100
2899 <emphasis>billion</emphasis>&mdash;six times the
2900 <emphasis>total</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2901 2001.<footnote><para>
2902
2903 <!-- f1 -->
2904 Tim Goral, <quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks:
2905 Suit Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages,</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC</citetitle> 6
2906 (2003): 5, available at 2003 WL 55179443.
2907 </para></footnote>
2908 </para>
2909 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaer' class='endofrange'/>
2910 <para>
2911 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2912 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2913 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2914 $12,000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2915 $12,000 to dismiss the case.
2916 </para>
2917 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt</primary></indexterm>
2918 <para>
2919 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2920 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2921 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2922 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2923 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2924 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2925 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, <quote>You don't want to pay another
2926 visit to a dentist like me.</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2927 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2928 </para>
2929 <indexterm><primary>legal system, attorney costs in</primary></indexterm>
2930 <para>
2931 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2932 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2933 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2934 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2935 at least $250,000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2936 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2937 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2938 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2939 </para>
2940 <para>
2941 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $250,000 and a chance at winning,
2942 or $12,000 and a settlement.
2943 </para>
2944 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
2945 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
2946 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
2947 <para>
2948 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2949 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2950 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2951 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2952 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $1 million a year.
2953 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2954 artist makes $45,900.<footnote><para>
2955 <!-- f2 -->
2956 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001)
2957 (27&ndash;2042&mdash;Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2958 the Arts, <citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon</citetitle> (2000).
2959 </para></footnote>
2960 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2961 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2962 student for running a search engine?<footnote><para>
2963 <!-- f3 -->
2964 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in <quote>KaZaA and Punishment,</quote>
2965 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, A24.
2966 </para></footnote>
2967 </para>
2968 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='endofrange'/>
2969 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='endofrange'/>
2970 <para>
2971 On June 23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2972 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2973 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $15 million lawsuit became an
2974 activist:
2975 </para>
2976 <blockquote>
2977 <para>
2978 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2979 an activist. &hellip; [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2980 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2981 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2982 </para>
2983 </blockquote>
2984 <para>
2985 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2986 his father told me, Jesse <quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
2987 I. &hellip; He's not a tree hugger. &hellip; I think it's bizarre that they would
2988 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2989 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.</quote>
2990 </para>
2991 <indexterm startref='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='endofrange'/>
2992 <indexterm startref='idxjordanjesse' class='endofrange'/>
2993 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
2994 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='endofrange'/>
2995 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='endofrange'/>
2996 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='endofrange'/>
2997 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
2998 </chapter>
2999 <chapter label="4" id="pirates">
3000 <title>CHAPTER FOUR: <quote>Pirates</quote></title>
3001 <indexterm id='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in development of content industry</secondary></indexterm>
3002 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
3003 <para>
3004 <emphasis role='strong'>If <quote>piracy</quote> means</emphasis>
3005 using the creative property of others without their
3006 permission&mdash;if <quote>if value, then right</quote> is
3007 true&mdash;then the history of the content industry is a history of
3008 piracy. Every important sector of <quote>big media</quote>
3009 today&mdash;film, records, radio, and cable TV&mdash;was born of a
3010 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
3011 generation's pirates join this generation's country club&mdash;until
3012 now.
3013 </para>
3014 <section id="film">
3015 <title>Film</title>
3016 <para>
3017 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.<footnote><para>
3018 <!-- f1 -->
3019 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
3020 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
3021 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 87&ndash;93,
3022 which details Edison's <quote>adventures</quote> with copyright and patent.
3023 </para></footnote>
3024 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
3025 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
3026 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
3027 exercised through a monopoly <quote>trust,</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
3028 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
3029 property&mdash;patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
3030 this creative property
3031 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
3032 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
3033 </para>
3034 <para>
3035 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
3036 </para>
3037 <blockquote>
3038 <para>
3039 A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
3040 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
3041 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
3042 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
3043 summer of 1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
3044 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
3045 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
3046 </para>
3047 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William</primary></indexterm>
3048 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company</primary></indexterm>
3049 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3050 <para>
3051 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
3052 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
3053 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
3054 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
3055 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
3056 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
3057 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
3058 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
3059 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
3060 license was revoked.<footnote><para>
3061 <!-- f2 -->
3062 J. A. Aberdeen, <citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
3063 Picture Producers</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts
3064 posted at <quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
3065 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,</quote> available at
3066 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #11</ulink>. For a
3067 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
3068 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, <quote>From
3069 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
3070 the Propertization of Copyright</quote> (September 2002), University of
3071 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
3072 Working Paper No. 159.
3073 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
3074 </para></footnote>
3075 </para>
3076 </blockquote>
3077 <para>
3078 The Napsters of those days, the <quote>independents,</quote> were companies like
3079 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
3080 resisted. <quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
3081 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
3082 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.</quote><footnote><para>
3083 <!-- f3 -->
3084 Marc Wanamaker, <quote>The First Studios,</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority</citetitle>, archived at
3085 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #12</ulink>.
3086 </para></footnote>
3087 That led the independents to flee the East
3088 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
3089 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
3090 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
3091 did just that.
3092 </para>
3093 <para>
3094 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
3095 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
3096 patent holder a truly <quote>limited</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
3097
3098 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
3099 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
3100 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
3101 Edison's creative property.
3102 </para>
3103 </section>
3104 <section id="recordedmusic">
3105 <title>Recorded Music</title>
3106 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
3107 <para>
3108 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
3109 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
3110 </para>
3111 <indexterm id='idxfourneauxhenri' class='startofrange'><primary>Fourneaux, Henri</primary></indexterm>
3112 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil</primary></indexterm>
3113 <para>
3114 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
3115 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
3116 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
3117 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
3118 their music. In other words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
3119 1899 hit <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
3120 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
3121 right to perform it publicly.
3122 </para>
3123 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3124 <para>
3125 But what if I wanted to record <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> using Edison's phonograph
3126 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
3127 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
3128 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
3129 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
3130 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
3131 <quote>public performance</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
3132 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
3133 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
3134 brain are not&mdash;yet&mdash; regulated by copyright law). So if I
3135 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
3136 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
3137 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
3138 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
3139 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
3140 its composer anything.
3141 </para>
3142 <indexterm startref='idxfourneauxhenri' class='endofrange'/>
3143 <para>
3144 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
3145 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
3146 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
3147 put it,
3148 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3149 </para>
3150 <blockquote>
3151 <para>
3152 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3153 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3154 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3155 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3156 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3157 rights.<footnote><para>
3158 <!-- f4 -->
3159 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3160 S. 6330 and H.R. 19853 Before the (Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th
3161 Cong. 59, 1st sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3162 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in <citetitle>Legislative History of the
3163 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3164 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3165 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3166 </para></footnote>
3167 </para>
3168 </blockquote>
3169 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip</primary></indexterm>
3170 <para>
3171 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3172 people's works were <quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3173 genius of American composers,</quote><footnote><para>
3174 <!-- f5 -->
3175 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223
3176 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3177 </para></footnote>
3178 and the <quote>music publishing industry</quote>
3179 was thereby <quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.</quote><footnote><para>
3180 <!-- f6 -->
3181 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226
3182 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3183 </para></footnote>
3184 As John Philip
3185 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, <quote>When they make money
3186 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.</quote><footnote><para>
3187 <!-- f7 -->
3188 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23
3189 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3190 </para></footnote>
3191 </para>
3192 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company</primary></indexterm>
3193 <indexterm><primary>player pianos</primary></indexterm>
3194 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
3195 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
3196 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
3197 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
3198 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>statutory license system in</secondary></indexterm>
3199 <para>
3200 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3201 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3202 player piano argued that <quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3203 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3204 of anything he had before their introduction.</quote> Rather, the machines
3205 increased the sales of sheet music.<footnote><para>
3206 <!-- f8 -->
3207
3208 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283&ndash;84
3209 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3210 Perforating Company of New York).
3211 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3212 Congress was <quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3213 they represent, and whose servants they are.</quote> <quote>All talk about
3214 `theft,'</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3215 wrote, <quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3216 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3217 statute.</quote><footnote><para>
3218 <!-- f9 -->
3219 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared
3220 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3221 Graphophone Company Association).
3222 </para></footnote>
3223 </para>
3224 <indexterm><primary>cover songs</primary></indexterm>
3225 <para>
3226 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3227 <emphasis>and</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3228 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the <quote>mechanical
3229 reproductions</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3230 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3231 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3232 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3233 recorded once. This is the part of
3234
3235 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3236 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3237 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3238 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3239 </para>
3240 <indexterm id='idxcompulsorylicense' class='startofrange'><primary>compulsory license</primary></indexterm>
3241 <indexterm id='idxstatutorylicenses' class='startofrange'><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
3242 <para>
3243 American law ordinarily calls this a <quote>compulsory license,</quote> but I will
3244 refer to it as a <quote>statutory license.</quote> A statutory license is a license
3245 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3246 Copyright Act in 1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3247 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3248 the fee set by the statute.
3249 </para>
3250 <indexterm id='idxgrishamjohn' class='startofrange'><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
3251 <para>
3252 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3253 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3254 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3255 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3256 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3257 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3258 Grisham.
3259 </para>
3260 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='endofrange'/>
3261 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3262 <para>
3263 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3264 thus, in effect, the law <emphasis>subsidizes</emphasis> the recording
3265 industry through a kind of piracy&mdash;by giving recording artists a
3266 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3267 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3268 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3269 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3270 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3271 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3272 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3273 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3274 creativity.<footnote><para>
3275
3276 <!-- f10 -->
3277 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and
3278 H.R. 11794 Before the (Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st
3279 sess., 217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3280 in <citetitle>Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3281 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3282 </para></footnote>
3283 </para>
3284 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='endofrange'/>
3285 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3286 <indexterm startref='idxgrishamjohn' class='endofrange'/>
3287 <para>
3288 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3289 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3290 records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3291 relates,
3292 </para>
3293 <blockquote>
3294 <para>
3295 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3296 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3297 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3298 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3299 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3300 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3301 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3302 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3303 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before 1909 and
3304 the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3305 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3306 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3307 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3308 choice.<footnote><para>
3309 <!-- f11 -->
3310 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee
3311 on the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8
3312 March 1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3313 this report.</para></footnote>
3314 </para>
3315 </blockquote>
3316 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='endofrange'/>
3317 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='endofrange'/>
3318 <indexterm startref='idxcompulsorylicense' class='endofrange'/>
3319 <indexterm startref='idxstatutorylicenses' class='endofrange'/>
3320 <para>
3321 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3322 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3323 </para>
3324 </section>
3325 <section id="radio">
3326 <title>Radio</title>
3327 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
3328 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
3329 <para>
3330 Radio was also born of piracy.
3331 </para>
3332 <para>
3333 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3334 <quote>public performance</quote> of the composer's work.<footnote><para>
3335 <!-- f12 -->
3336 See 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning,
3337 record companies printed <quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast</quote> and other
3338 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3339 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3340 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3341 station. See <citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Whiteman</citetitle>, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd
3342 Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3343 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3344 Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 281.
3345 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned</primary></indexterm>
3346 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3347 </para></footnote>
3348 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3349 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3350 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3351 </para>
3352 <para>
3353 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3354 copy of the <emphasis>composer's</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3355 also performing a copy of the <emphasis>recording artist's</emphasis>
3356 work. It's one thing to have <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> sung on the radio by the
3357 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3358 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3359 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3360 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3361 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3362 music for his work.
3363 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
3364
3365 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3366 </para>
3367 <para>
3368 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3369 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3370 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3371 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3372 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3373 of playing the song.
3374 </para>
3375 <indexterm id='idxmadonna' class='startofrange'><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3376 <para>
3377 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3378 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3379 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3380 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3381 </para>
3382 <para>
3383 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3384 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3385 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3386 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3387 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3388 <quote>protected</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3389 <emphasis>pirate</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3390 her anything.
3391 </para>
3392 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='endofrange'/>
3393 <indexterm startref='idxmadonna' class='endofrange'/>
3394 <para>
3395 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3396 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3397 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3398 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3399 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3400 to take something for nothing.
3401 </para>
3402 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='endofrange'/>
3403 </section>
3404 <section id="cabletv">
3405 <title>Cable TV</title>
3406 <indexterm id='idxcabletelevision' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
3407 <para>
3408 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3409 </para>
3410 <para>
3411 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3412 television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3413 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3414 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3415 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3416 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3417 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3418 did&mdash; Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3419 give away.
3420 </para>
3421 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas</primary></indexterm>
3422 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin</primary></indexterm>
3423 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3424 <para>
3425 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3426 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3427 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.</quote><footnote><para>
3428 <!-- f13 -->
3429 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the
3430 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3431 Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966)
3432 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3433 Commission).
3434 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3435 </para></footnote>
3436 There may have been a <quote>public interest</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3437 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3438 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, <quote>Does public
3439 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?</quote><footnote><para>
3440 <!-- f14 -->
3441 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3442 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3443 </para></footnote>
3444 As another broadcaster put it,
3445 </para>
3446 <blockquote>
3447 <para>
3448 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3449 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3450 paid for.<footnote><para>
3451 <!-- f15 -->
3452 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3453 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3454 </para></footnote>
3455 </para>
3456 </blockquote>
3457 <para>
3458 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3459 </para>
3460 <blockquote>
3461 <para>
3462 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3463 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3464 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3465 think there are harsher words which would fit it.<footnote><para>
3466 <!-- f16 -->
3467 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3468 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3469 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3470 </para></footnote>
3471 </para>
3472 </blockquote>
3473 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3474 <para>
3475 These were <quote>free-ride[rs],</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3476 Heston said, who were <quote>depriving actors of
3477 compensation.</quote><footnote><para>
3478 <!-- f17 -->
3479 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3480 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3481 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3482 </para>
3483 </footnote>
3484 </para>
3485 <para>
3486 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3487 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3488 </para>
3489 <blockquote>
3490 <para>
3491 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3492 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3493 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3494 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. &hellip; The
3495
3496 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3497 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3498 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.<footnote><para>
3499 <!-- f18 -->
3500 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M.
3501 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3502 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3503 </para></footnote>
3504 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3505 </para>
3506 </blockquote>
3507 <para>
3508 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3509 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3510 </para>
3511 <para>
3512 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3513 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they <quote>pirated.</quote>
3514 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3515 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3516 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3517 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3518 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3519 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3520 companies thus built their empire in part upon a <quote>piracy</quote> of the value
3521 created by broadcasters' content.
3522 </para>
3523 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3524 <indexterm startref='idxcabletelevision' class='endofrange'/>
3525 <para>
3526 <emphasis role='strong'>These separate stories</emphasis> sing a
3527 common theme. If <quote>piracy</quote> means using value from someone
3528 else's creative property without permission from that creator&mdash;as
3529 it is increasingly described today<footnote><para>
3530 <!-- f19 -->
3531 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, <citetitle>The Engine
3532 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet&mdash;The Myth of Free
3533 Information</citetitle>, available at
3534 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #13</ulink>. <quote>The
3535 threat of piracy&mdash;the use of someone else's creative work without
3536 permission or compensation&mdash;has grown with the Internet.</quote>
3537 </para></footnote>
3538 &mdash; then <emphasis>every</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3539 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3540 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV. &hellip; The list is long and
3541 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3542 last. Every generation&mdash;until now.
3543 </para>
3544 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3545 </section>
3546 </chapter>
3547 <chapter label="5" id="piracy">
3548 <title>CHAPTER FIVE: <quote>Piracy</quote></title>
3549 <para>
3550 <emphasis role='strong'>There is piracy</emphasis> of copyrighted
3551 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3552 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3553 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3554 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3555 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3556 </para>
3557 <para>
3558 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of <quote>taking</quote>
3559 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3560 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3561 taking <quote>piracy,</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3562 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3563 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3564 has so often done in the past.
3565 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3566 </para>
3567 <section id="piracy-i">
3568 <title>Piracy I</title>
3569 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3570 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3571 <para>
3572 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3573 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3574 content, copy it, and sell it&mdash;all without the permission of a copyright
3575 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion
3576 every year to physical piracy<footnote><para>
3577 <!-- f1 -->
3578 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), <citetitle>The
3579 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003</citetitle>, July 2003, available
3580 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #14</ulink>. See
3581 also Ben Hunt, <quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3582 Times</citetitle>, 14 February 2003, 11.
3583 </para></footnote>
3584 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3585 estimates that it loses $3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3586 </para>
3587 <para>
3588 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3589 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3590 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3591 This piracy is wrong.
3592 </para>
3593 <para>
3594 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3595 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3596 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3597 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3598 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3599 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3600 of our existence, treated as right.
3601 </para>
3602 <para>
3603 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3604 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3605 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3606 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3607 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3608 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3609 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3610 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3611 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3612 </para>
3613 <para>
3614 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3615 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3616 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3617 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3618 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3619 similar childhood.
3620 </para>
3621 <para>
3622 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3623 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3624 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3625 of intellectual property law.<footnote><para>
3626 <!-- f2 -->
3627 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3628 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The
3629 New Press, 2003), 10&ndash;13, 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3630 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3631 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3632 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3633 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3634 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3635 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3636 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3637 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3638 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3639 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3640 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3641 TRIPS framework.
3642 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents</primary></indexterm>
3643 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
3644 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3645 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3646 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3647 is wrong.
3648 </para>
3649 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3650 <para>
3651 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3652 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3653 to American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3654 bought those American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any
3655 less money than they otherwise would have had.<footnote><para>
3656 <!-- f3 -->
3657 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3658 Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002),
3659 144&ndash;90. <quote>In some instances &hellip; the impact of piracy on the
3660 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3661 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3662 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3663 pirating were not an option.</quote> Ibid., 149.
3664 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3665 </para></footnote>
3666 </para>
3667 <para>
3668 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3669 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3670 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3671 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3672 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes &amp; Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3673 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?</quote>
3674 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes &amp;
3675 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3676 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3677 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3678 piracy of the tangible.
3679 </para>
3680 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'/>
3681 <para>
3682 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3683 property right of a very special sort, it <emphasis>is</emphasis> a
3684 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3685 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3686 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3687 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3688 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3689 give people the right to <quote>take</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3690 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3691
3692 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3693 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3694 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3695 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3696 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3697 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what <quote>property</quote> means.
3698 </para>
3699 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3700 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
3701 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
3702 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3703 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3704 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of</secondary></indexterm>
3705 <indexterm><primary>Windows</primary></indexterm>
3706 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>international software piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3707 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of</secondary></indexterm>
3708 <para>
3709 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3710 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese <quote>steal</quote>
3711 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3712 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3713 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3714 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3715 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3716 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3717 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3718 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3719 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3720 </para>
3721 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
3722 <para>
3723 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3724 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3725 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3726 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3727 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3728 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3729 </para>
3730 <indexterm><primary>Netscape</primary></indexterm>
3731 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer</primary></indexterm>
3732 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3733 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3734 <para>
3735 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3736 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3737 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3738 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3739 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3740 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3741 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3742 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3743 what&mdash;at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3744 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3745 violating the law is still wrong.
3746 </para>
3747 <para>
3748 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3749 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3750 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3751 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3752 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3753 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3754 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3755 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3756 is flat out wrong.
3757 </para>
3758 <para>
3759 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3760 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is. Or
3761 at least, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3762 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of <quote>piracy</quote> are useful
3763 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3764 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3765 <quote>piracy</quote> in that sense of the term.
3766 </para>
3767 <para>
3768 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3769 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3770 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3771 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3772 </para>
3773 <para>
3774 For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3775 controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it
3776 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable
3777 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3778 </para>
3779 <para>
3780 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3781 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3782 sharing to survive.
3783 </para>
3784 </section>
3785 <section id="piracy-ii">
3786 <title>Piracy II</title>
3787 <para>
3788 The key to the <quote>piracy</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that <quote>rob[s]
3789 the author of [his] profit.</quote><footnote><para>
3790 <!-- f4 -->
3791 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777).
3792 </para></footnote>
3793 This means we must determine whether
3794 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3795 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3796 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3797 author of his profit.
3798 </para>
3799 <para>
3800 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn</primary></indexterm>
3801 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3802 <indexterm id='idxnapster' class='startofrange'><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
3803 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3804 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3805 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3806 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well<footnote><para>
3807 <!-- f5 -->
3808 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3809 See Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3810 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle> (New York:
3811 HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3812 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3813 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3814 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3815 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3816 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 89&ndash;92, 139.
3817
3818 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
3819 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3820 put together components that had been developed independently.
3821 </para>
3822 <para>
3823 <indexterm><primary>Kazaa</primary></indexterm>
3824 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>number of registrations on</secondary></indexterm>
3825 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>replacement of</secondary></indexterm>
3826 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999,
3827 Napster amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After
3828 eighteen months, there were close to 80 million registered users of the
3829 system.<footnote><para>
3830 <!-- f6 -->
3831 See Carolyn Lochhead, <quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,</quote> <citetitle>San
3832 Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24 September 2002, A1; <quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,</quote>
3833 <citetitle>New Scientist</citetitle>, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Napster Names CEO,
3834 Secures New Financing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 23 May 2003, C1;
3835 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton,
3836 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet</quote> (London) <citetitle>Times</citetitle>, 26 July 2002, 18.
3837 </para></footnote>
3838 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3839 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3840 boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3841 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3842 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3843 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend&mdash;
3844 or your 20,000 best friends.
3845 </para>
3846 <indexterm startref='idxnapster' class='endofrange'/>
3847 <para>
3848 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3849 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3850 September 2002 estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded
3851 music&mdash;28 percent of Americans older than 12.<footnote><para>
3852
3853 <!-- f7 -->
3854 See Ipsos-Insight, <citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution</citetitle>
3855 (September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3856 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have
3857 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3858 </para></footnote>
3859 A survey by the NPD group quoted in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>
3860 estimated that 43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3861 exchange content in May 2003.<footnote><para>
3862 <!-- f8 -->
3863 Amy Harmon, <quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,</quote> <citetitle>New
3864 York Times</citetitle>, 6 June 2003, A1.
3865 </para></footnote>
3866 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3867 massive quantity of content is being <quote>taken</quote> on these networks. The
3868 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3869 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3870 </para>
3871 <para>
3872 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3873 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3874 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3875 complicated than one might think. So consider&mdash;a bit more
3876 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3877 do&mdash;the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3878 of harm it entails.
3879 </para>
3880 <para>
3881 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3882 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3883 different kinds into four types.
3884 </para>
3885 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
3886 <listitem>
3887 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3888 <para>
3889 <!-- A. -->
3890 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3891 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3892 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3893 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3894 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3895 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3896 users who download instead of purchasing.
3897 </para></listitem>
3898 <listitem><para>
3899 <!-- B. -->
3900 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3901 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3902 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3903 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3904 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3905 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3906 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3907 music purchased.
3908 </para></listitem>
3909 <listitem><para>
3910 <!-- C. -->
3911 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3912 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3913 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3914 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3915 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3916 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3917 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend <quote>recalling</quote> old
3918 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3919 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3920 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3921 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero&mdash;the same
3922 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to
3923 a local collector.
3924 </para></listitem>
3925 <listitem><para>
3926 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3927 <!-- D. -->
3928 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3929 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3930 wants to give away.
3931 </para></listitem>
3932 </orderedlist>
3933 <para>
3934 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3935 </para>
3936 <para>
3937 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3938 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3939 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3940 harmful.<footnote><para>
3941 <!-- f9 -->
3942 See Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle>, 148&ndash;49.
3943 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3944 </para></footnote>
3945 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3946 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3947 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3948 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3949 answer&mdash;and certainly much more difficult than the current
3950 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3951 </para>
3952 <para>
3953 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3954 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3955 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3956 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3957 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of <quote>theft</quote> that is
3958 <quote>devastating</quote> the industry.
3959 </para>
3960 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
3961 <para>
3962 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3963 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3964 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3965 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3966 &amp; Young put it, <quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3967 technology, the labels fought it.</quote><footnote><para>
3968 <!-- f10 -->
3969 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary></indexterm>
3970 See Cap Gemini Ernst &amp; Young, <citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
3971 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis</citetitle> (2003), 3. This report
3972 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3973 practice of cassette taping in the 1970s, including an advertising
3974 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption <quote>Home taping
3975 is killing music.</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3976 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3977 behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3978 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3979 Assessment, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law</citetitle>,
3980 OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3981 October 1989), 145&ndash;56. </para></footnote>
3982 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3983 when record sales fell by 11.4 percent in 1981, the industry claimed
3984 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3985 regulating technology was the answer.
3986 </para>
3987 <indexterm><primary>MTV</primary></indexterm>
3988 <para>
3989 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3990 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3991 turnaround. <quote>In the end,</quote> Cap Gemini concludes, <quote>the `crisis' &hellip; was
3992 not the fault of the tapers&mdash;who did not [stop after MTV came into
3993 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
3994 being]&mdash;but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
3995 innovation at the major labels.</quote><footnote><para>
3996 <!-- f11 -->
3997 U.S. Congress, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying</citetitle>, 4.
3998 </para></footnote>
3999 </para>
4000 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'/>
4001 <para>
4002 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
4003 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
4004 the industry in particular, and society in general&mdash;or at least
4005 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
4006 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
4007 VCR&mdash;the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
4008 harmful. The question is also <emphasis>how</emphasis> harmful type A
4009 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
4010 </para>
4011 <para>
4012 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
4013 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
4014 The <quote>net harm</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
4015 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
4016 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
4017 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
4018 therefore have little <emphasis>static</emphasis> reason to resist
4019 them.
4020
4021 </para>
4022 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>sales levels of</secondary></indexterm>
4023 <para>
4024 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
4025 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
4026 actually suggest it might be close.
4027 </para>
4028 <para>
4029 In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9 percent,
4030 from 882 million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7
4031 percent.<footnote><para>
4032 <!-- f12 -->
4033 See Recording Industry Association of America, <citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics</citetitle>,
4034 available at
4035 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #15</ulink>. A later
4036 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
4037 Association of America, <citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy</citetitle>, 25 June 2003,
4038 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
4039 #16</ulink>: <quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
4040 have fallen by 26 percent from 1.16 billion units in to 860 million
4041 units in 2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
4042 of sales, revenues are down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in to $12.6
4043 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
4044 industry worldwide has gone from a $39 billion industry in 2000 down
4045 to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
4046 shipments).</quote>
4047 </para></footnote>
4048 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
4049 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
4050 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
4051 than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That no
4052 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
4053 account for at least some of the loss. <quote>From 1999 to 2001, the average
4054 price of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19.</quote><footnote>
4055 <!-- f13 -->
4056 <para>
4057 Jane Black, <quote>Big Music's Broken Record,</quote> BusinessWeek online, 13
4058 February 2003, available at
4059 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #17</ulink>.
4060 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane</primary></indexterm>
4061 </para>
4062 </footnote>
4063 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
4064 the decline. As Jane Black of <citetitle>BusinessWeek</citetitle> notes, <quote>The
4065 soundtrack to the film <citetitle>High Fidelity</citetitle> has a list price of
4066 $18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
4067 $19.99.</quote><footnote><para>
4068 <!-- f14 -->
4069 Ibid.
4070 </para></footnote>
4071 </para>
4072 <para>
4073
4074 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
4075 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
4076 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
4077 that the RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
4078 estimates that 2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
4079 although 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4080 free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 percent.
4081 </para>
4082 <para>
4083 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
4084 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
4085 The recording industry constantly asks, <quote>What's the difference between
4086 downloading a song and stealing a CD?</quote>&mdash;but their own numbers
4087 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
4088 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
4089 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
4090 downloads. If every download were a lost sale&mdash;if every use of
4091 Kazaa <quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit</quote>&mdash;then the industry
4092 would have suffered a 100 percent drop in sales last year, not a 7
4093 percent drop. If 2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4094 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, then there is
4095 a huge difference between <quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.</quote>
4096 </para>
4097 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'/>
4098 <para>
4099 These are the harms&mdash;alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
4100 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
4101 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
4102 these costs?
4103 </para>
4104 <para>
4105 One benefit is type C sharing&mdash;making available content that
4106 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
4107 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
4108 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
4109 available.<footnote><para>
4110 <!-- f15 -->
4111 By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels
4112 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
4113 Law&mdash;Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
4114 Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April
4115 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
4116 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #18</ulink>.
4117 </para></footnote>
4118 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
4119 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
4120 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
4121 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
4122 sense <emphasis>to the company</emphasis> to make it available.
4123 </para>
4124 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4125 <para>
4126 In real space&mdash;long before the Internet&mdash;the market had a simple
4127 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
4128 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
4129 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
4130 today.<footnote><para>
4131 <!-- f16 -->
4132 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4133 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
4134 in existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the
4135 United States, an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter
4136 Press, <citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
4137 Market</citetitle> (2002), available at
4138 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #19</ulink>. Used
4139 records accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See National
4140 Association of Recording Merchandisers, <quote>2002 Annual Survey
4141 Results,</quote> available at
4142 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #20</ulink>.
4143 </para></footnote>
4144 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
4145 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
4146 content, <emphasis>even if the content is still under
4147 copyright</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
4148 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
4149 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
4150 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
4151 the content they sell.
4152 </para>
4153 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
4154 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard</primary></indexterm>
4155 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
4156 <para>
4157 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
4158 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
4159 the content available isn't making money from making the content
4160 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
4161 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
4162 when someone shares my 1949 recording of Bernstein's <quote>Two Love Songs,</quote>
4163 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
4164 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
4165 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
4166 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
4167 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
4168 </para>
4169 <para>
4170 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
4171 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
4172 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
4173 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
4174 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
4175 shut as well?
4176 </para>
4177 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
4178 <indexterm><primary>Doctorow, Cory</primary></indexterm>
4179 <indexterm><primary>Down and Out in the Magic Kingdom (Doctorow)</primary></indexterm>
4180 <para>
4181 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4182 type D sharing to occur&mdash;the sharing of content that copyright owners
4183 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4184 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4185 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
4186 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4187
4188 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4189 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4190 would be a great advertisement for the <quote>real</quote> book. People would read
4191 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4192 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4193 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4194 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4195 great book!)
4196 </para>
4197 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'/>
4198 <para>
4199 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4200 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4201 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4202 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4203 </para>
4204 <para>
4205 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4206 understandably says, <quote>This is how much we've lost,</quote> we must also ask,
4207 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4208 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4209 unavailable?</quote>
4210 </para>
4211 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson' class='endofrange'/>
4212 <para>
4213 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4214 chapter, much of the <quote>piracy</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4215 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4216 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="pirates"/>, much of
4217 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4218 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4219 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4220 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4221 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4222 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4223 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4224 found only with time.
4225 </para>
4226 <para>
4227 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4228 just what you call type A sharing?</quote>
4229 </para>
4230 <para>
4231 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The effect
4232 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4233 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4234 Napster case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4235 developed a technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of
4236 identified
4237
4238 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4239 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4
4240 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4241 <quote>down to zero.</quote><footnote><para>
4242 <!-- f17 -->
4243 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34-
4244 35 (N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183
4245 MHP, available at
4246
4247 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #21</ulink>. For an
4248 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4249 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster</citetitle> (New
4250 York: Crown Business, 2003), 269&ndash;82.
4251 </para></footnote>
4252 </para>
4253 <para>
4254 If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4255 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4256 assure that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance
4257 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of
4258 VCRs or 100 percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns
4259 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4260 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4261 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4262 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4263 </para>
4264 <para>
4265 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4266 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4267 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4268 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4269 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4270 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4271 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4272 </para>
4273 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
4274 <indexterm><primary>composers, copyright protections of</primary></indexterm>
4275 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4276 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
4277 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
4278 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
4279 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>music recordings played on</secondary></indexterm>
4280 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
4281 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright protections in</secondary></indexterm>
4282 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
4283 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
4284 <indexterm><primary>composer's rights vs. producers' rights in</primary></indexterm>
4285 <para>
4286 So, as we've seen, when <quote>mechanical reproduction</quote> threatened the
4287 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4288 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4289 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4290 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4291 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4292 complained to Congress that their <quote>creative property</quote> was not being
4293 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4294 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4295 benefit was enough.
4296 </para>
4297 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
4298 <para>
4299 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4300 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4301 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4302 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4303 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4304 price.
4305 </para>
4306 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='endofrange'/>
4307 <para>
4308
4309 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4310 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4311 pianos, served two important goals&mdash;indeed, the two central goals
4312 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4313 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4314 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4315 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4316 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4317 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4318 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4319 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4320 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4321 Congress chose a path that would assure
4322 <emphasis>compensation</emphasis> without giving the past
4323 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4324 </para>
4325 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='endofrange'/>
4326 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='endofrange'/>
4327 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'/>
4328 <indexterm id='idxbetamax' class='startofrange'><primary>Betamax</primary></indexterm>
4329 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
4330 <para>
4331 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4332 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4333 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4334 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4335 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4336 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4337 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4338 <quote>record</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4339 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4340 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4341 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4342 </para>
4343 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='endofrange'/>
4344 <para>
4345 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4346 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4347 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4348 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4349 machine to copy only if there were a special <quote>copy me</quote> signal on the
4350 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4351 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4352 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4353 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4354 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4355 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4356 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4357 for the architecture it chose.
4358 </para>
4359 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4360 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on VCR technology</secondary></indexterm>
4361 <para>
4362 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4363 champion. Valenti called VCRs <quote>tapeworms.</quote> He warned, <quote>When there are
4364 20, 30, 40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4365 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4366 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4367 copyright.</quote><footnote><para>
4368 <!-- f18 -->
4369 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4370 S. 1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st
4371 and 2nd sess., 459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4372 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4373 </para></footnote>
4374 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4375 creative judgment,</quote> he told Congress, <quote>to understand the devastation
4376 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4377 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4378 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4379 and plain common sense.</quote><footnote><para>
4380 <!-- f19 -->
4381 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475.
4382 </para></footnote>
4383 Indeed, as surveys would later show, 45
4384 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more<footnote><para>
4385 <!-- f20 -->
4386 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 480 F. Supp. 429,
4387 (C.D. Cal., 1979).
4388 </para></footnote>
4389 &mdash; a use the Court would later hold was not <quote>fair.</quote> By
4390 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4391 copyright infringement without creating a mechanism to compensate
4392 copyright owners,</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would <quote>take from the
4393 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4394 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4395 profit from its reproduction.</quote><footnote><para>
4396 <!-- f21 -->
4397 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony
4398 of Jack Valenti).
4399 </para></footnote>
4400 </para>
4401 <indexterm startref='idxbetamax' class='endofrange'/>
4402 <para>
4403 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4404 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4405 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction&mdash;leading Judge Alex
4406 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the <quote>Hollywood
4407 Circuit</quote>&mdash;held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4408 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4409 rule, this totally familiar technology&mdash;which Jack Valenti had
4410 called <quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry</quote> (worse
4411 yet, it was a <emphasis>Japanese</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4412 American film industry)&mdash;was an illegal
4413 technology.<footnote><para>
4414 <!-- f22 -->
4415 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th Cir.
4416 1981).
4417 </para></footnote>
4418 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex</primary></indexterm>
4419 </para>
4420 <para>
4421 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4422
4423 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4424 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4425 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4426 Court wrote,
4427 </para>
4428 <blockquote>
4429 <para>
4430 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4431 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4432 market
4433 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4434 authority
4435 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4436 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4437 implicated
4438 by such new technology.<footnote><para>
4439 <!-- f23 -->
4440 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417, 431 (1984).
4441 </para></footnote>
4442 </para>
4443 </blockquote>
4444 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='endofrange'/>
4445 <para>
4446 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4447 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4448 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4449 enough, this <quote>taking</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4450 together, a pattern is clear:
4451 </para>
4452
4453 <informaltable id="t1">
4454 <tgroup cols="4" align="left">
4455 <thead>
4456 <row>
4457 <entry>CASE</entry>
4458 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS <quote>PIRATED</quote></entry>
4459 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS</entry>
4460 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS</entry>
4461 </row>
4462 </thead>
4463 <tbody>
4464 <row>
4465 <entry>Recordings</entry>
4466 <entry>Composers</entry>
4467 <entry>No protection</entry>
4468 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4469 </row>
4470 <row>
4471 <entry>Radio</entry>
4472 <entry>Recording artists</entry>
4473 <entry>N/A</entry>
4474 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4475 </row>
4476 <row>
4477 <entry>Cable TV</entry>
4478 <entry>Broadcasters</entry>
4479 <entry>No protection</entry>
4480 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4481 </row>
4482 <row>
4483 <entry>VCR</entry>
4484 <entry>Film creators</entry>
4485 <entry>No protection</entry>
4486 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4487 </row>
4488 </tbody>
4489 </tgroup>
4490 </informaltable>
4491 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'/>
4492 <para>
4493 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4494 way content was distributed.<footnote><para>
4495 <!-- f24 -->
4496 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4497 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4498 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4499 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4500 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4501 1992 (Title 17 of the <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat.
4502 4237, codified at 17 U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4503 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4504 Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 71. See also Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,</quote>
4505 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 293&ndash;96.
4506 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
4507 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
4508 </para></footnote>
4509 In each case, throughout our history,
4510 that change meant that someone got a <quote>free ride</quote> on someone else's
4511 work.
4512 </para>
4513 <para>
4514 In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4515 Congress eliminate all free riding. In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of
4516 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4517 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4518 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of <quote>piracy.</quote>
4519 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4520 the behavior of the <quote>pirates.</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4521 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4522 interests at stake.
4523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4524 </para>
4525 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
4526 <para>
4527 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4528 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4529 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4530 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4531 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4532 regulated?
4533 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4534 to $15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4535 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4536 permission to record a song?
4537 </para>
4538 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on balance of interests in copyright law</secondary></indexterm>
4539 <para>
4540 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4541 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4542 copyright <quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4543 over all possible uses of his work.</quote><footnote><para>
4544 <!-- f25 -->
4545 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
4546 (1984).
4547 </para></footnote>
4548 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4549 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4550 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4551 balancing has historically been done <emphasis>after</emphasis> a
4552 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4553 facilitate the distribution of content.
4554 </para>
4555 <para>
4556 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4557 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4558 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4559 should not become a tool for <quote>stealing</quote> from artists. But neither
4560 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4561 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4562 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4563 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4564 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4565 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4566 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4567 public interest that innovation continue.
4568 </para>
4569 <para>
4570
4571 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4572 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4573 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4574 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4575 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4576 efficient. Yet these <quote>potential public benefits,</quote> as John Schwartz
4577 writes in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, <quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4578 fight.</quote><footnote><para>
4579 <!-- f26 -->
4580 John Schwartz, <quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4581 Echoes Past Efforts,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 September 2003, C3.
4582 </para></footnote>
4583 </para>
4584 <para>
4585 <emphasis role='strong'>Yet when anyone</emphasis> begins to talk
4586 about <quote>balance,</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4587 argument. <quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4588 incentives,</quote> they say, <quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4589 content,</quote> the warriors insist, <quote>is our
4590 <emphasis>property</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4591 `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4592 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4593 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether
4594 the car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?</quote>
4595 </para>
4596 <para>
4597 <quote>It is <emphasis>our property</emphasis>,</quote> the warriors
4598 insist. <quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4599 is protected.</quote>
4600 </para>
4601 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4602 </section>
4603 </chapter>
4604 </part>
4605 <part id="c-property">
4606 <title><quote>PROPERTY</quote></title>
4607 <partintro>
4608 <para>
4609
4610 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4611 <emphasis role='strong'>The copyright warriors</emphasis> are right: A
4612 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4613 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4614 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4615 that partially determine the price she can get.
4616 </para>
4617 <para>
4618 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a <quote>property</quote> right is a
4619 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4620 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4621 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4622 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4623 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4624 when I take the good <emphasis>idea</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4625 table in the backyard&mdash;by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4626 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4627 then?
4628 </para>
4629 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
4630 <para>
4631 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4632 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4633 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4634 in the ordinary case&mdash;indeed, in practically every case except for a
4635 narrow
4636 range of exceptions&mdash;ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4637 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress&mdash;though I
4638 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4639 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4640 when I copy the way someone else dresses), <quote>He who receives an idea
4641 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4642 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.</quote><footnote><para>
4643 <!-- f1 -->
4644 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in
4645 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson</citetitle>, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4646 Ellery Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333&ndash;34.
4647 </para></footnote>
4648 </para>
4649 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>intangibility of</secondary></indexterm>
4650 <para>
4651 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4652 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4653 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4654 expression
4655 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4656 property.
4657 </para>
4658 <para>
4659 But how, and to what extent, and in what form&mdash;the details,
4660 in other words&mdash;matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4661 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4662 <quote>property</quote> in its proper context.<footnote><para>
4663 <!-- f2 -->
4664 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4665 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4666 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4667 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4668 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4669 Adam Mossoff, <quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,</quote>
4670 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review</citetitle> 45 (2003): 373, 429 n. 241.
4671 </para></footnote>
4672 </para>
4673 <para>
4674 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4675 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4676 <quote>copyright material is property</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4677 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4678 these stories, the significance of this true
4679 statement&mdash;<quote>copyright material is property</quote>&mdash; will be a bit
4680 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4681 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4682 </para>
4683 </partintro>
4684
4685 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4686 <chapter label="6" id="founders">
4687 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders</title>
4688 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for</secondary></indexterm>
4689 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
4690 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
4691 <indexterm id='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='startofrange'><primary>England, copyright laws developed in</primary></indexterm>
4692 <indexterm id='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='startofrange'><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>history of copyright law in</secondary></indexterm>
4693 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4694 <indexterm><primary>Henry V</primary></indexterm>
4695 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4696 <indexterm id='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='startofrange'><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4697 <para>
4698 <emphasis role='strong'>William Shakespeare</emphasis> wrote
4699 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> in 1595. The play was first
4700 published in 1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4701 written. He would continue to write plays through 1613, and the plays
4702 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4703 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4704 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4705 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4706 Henry V: <quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4707 clichés.</quote>
4708 </para>
4709 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4710 <indexterm id='idxtonsonjacob' class='startofrange'><primary>Tonson, Jacob</primary></indexterm>
4711 <para>
4712 In 1774, almost 180 years after <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> was written, the
4713 <quote>copy-right</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4714 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.<footnote><para>
4715 <!-- f1 -->
4716 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben</primary></indexterm>
4717 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John</primary></indexterm>
4718 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4719 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4720 handsome <quote>definitive editions</quote> of classic works. In addition to <citetitle>Romeo and
4721 Juliet</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4722 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4723 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, <quote>Jacob Tonson,
4724 Bookseller,</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar</citetitle> 61:3 (1992): 424&ndash;31.
4725 </para></footnote>
4726 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4727 the Conger<footnote><para>
4728 <!-- f2 -->
4729 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle> (Nashville:
4730 Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 151&ndash;52.
4731 </para></footnote>
4732 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4733 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the <quote>copy</quote> of
4734 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4735 that no
4736 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4737 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4738 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4739 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4740 </para>
4741 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4742 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4743 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
4744 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4745 <para>
4746 Now, there's something puzzling about the year 1774 to anyone who
4747 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4748 history of copyright is 1710, the year that the British Parliament
4749 adopted the first <quote>copyright</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4750 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4751 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4752 works already published by 1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4753 additional years.<footnote><para>
4754 <!-- f3 -->
4755 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4756 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4757 <quote>copyright law.</quote> See Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 40.
4758 </para></footnote> Under this law, <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> should have been
4759 free in 1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4760 Tonson's control in 1774?
4761 </para>
4762 <indexterm startref='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='endofrange'/>
4763 <indexterm startref='idxtonsonjacob' class='endofrange'/>
4764 <indexterm id='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
4765 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
4766 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (1662)</primary></indexterm>
4767 <para>
4768 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a <quote>copyright</quote>
4769 was&mdash;indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4770 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4771 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of 1662, had
4772 expired in 1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4773 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4774 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4775 that the publishers, or <quote>Stationers,</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4776 books.
4777 </para>
4778 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='endofrange'/>
4779 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
4780 <para>
4781 There was no <emphasis>positive</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4782 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4783 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4784 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4785 from legislatures <quote>positive law.</quote> We call the words from judges
4786 <quote>common law.</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4787 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4788 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4789 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4790 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4791 </para>
4792 <indexterm startref='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='endofrange'/>
4793 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4794 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4795 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
4796 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4797 <para>
4798 This question was important to the publishers, or <quote>booksellers,</quote> as
4799 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4800 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4801 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4802
4803 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4804 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4805 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4806 ultimately
4807 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4808 </para>
4809 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>as narrow monopoly right</secondary></indexterm>
4810 <para>
4811 The Statute of Anne granted the author or <quote>proprietor</quote> of a book an
4812 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4813 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4814 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4815 copyright <quote>expired,</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4816 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4817 believed.
4818 </para>
4819 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne' class='endofrange'/>
4820 <para>
4821 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4822 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4823 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4824 <emphasis>at all?</emphasis>
4825 </para>
4826 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'/>
4827 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4828 <indexterm><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4829 <para>
4830 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4831 strong claim. Take <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> as an example: That play
4832 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4833 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4834 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4835 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4836 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4837 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4838 reason is there to allow someone else to <quote>steal</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4839 </para>
4840 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4841 <para>
4842 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4843 about the notion of <quote>copyright</quote> that existed at the time of the
4844 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4845 <quote>booksellers.</quote>
4846 </para>
4847 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
4848 <para>
4849 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4850 to apply the concept of <quote>copyright</quote> ever more broadly. But in 1710, it
4851 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4852 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4853 others from reprinting a book. In 1710, the <quote>copy-right</quote> was a right
4854 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4855 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4856 generally how
4857 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4858 a work could be <emphasis>used</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4859 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4860 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4861 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4862 </para>
4863 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4864 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4865 <para>
4866 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4867 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4868 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4869 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4870 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4871 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4872 allowed to make his films. The <quote>copy-right</quote> was only an exclusive
4873 right to print&mdash;no less, of course, but also no more.
4874 </para>
4875 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England</primary></indexterm>
4876 <indexterm id='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='startofrange'><primary>monopoly, copyright as</primary></indexterm>
4877 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (1656)</primary></indexterm>
4878 <para>
4879 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4880 They had had a long and ugly experience with <quote>exclusive rights,</quote>
4881 especially <quote>exclusive rights</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4882 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4883 monopolies&mdash;especially monopolies for works that already
4884 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4885 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4886 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In 1656, it passed the
4887 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4888 inventions. And by 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4889 monopoly in publishing.
4890 </para>
4891 <para>
4892 Thus the <quote>copy-right,</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4893 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4894 claim that <quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,</quote> try
4895 sounding convincing when uttering, <quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4896 have it forever.</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4897 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4898 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4899 </para>
4900 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
4901 <indexterm id='idxbooksellersenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>booksellers, English</primary></indexterm>
4902 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4903 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4904 <para>
4905 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4906 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4907 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4908 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4909 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4910
4911 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4912 kind&mdash;tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4913 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4914 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as <quote>old patentees
4915 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling</quote>; they were <quote>men who do
4916 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4917 indetted.</quote><footnote><para>
4918
4919 <!-- f4 -->
4920 Philip Wittenberg, <citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4921 Property</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31.
4922 </para></footnote>
4923 </para>
4924 <indexterm><primary>Enlightenment</primary></indexterm>
4925 <indexterm><primary>knowledge, freedom of</primary></indexterm>
4926 <para>
4927 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4928 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4929 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4930 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4931 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4932 with that idea.
4933 </para>
4934 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament2' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4935 <para>
4936 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4937 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4938 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4939 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4940 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4941 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4942 compromise
4943 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4944 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4945 construction and spread of culture.
4946 </para>
4947 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne2' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)
4948 </primary></indexterm>
4949 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
4950 <para>
4951 When 1731 (1710 + 21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4952 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4953 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4954 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4955 to control publication. But in 1735 and 1737, they tried to persuade
4956 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4957 they said; they needed more time.
4958 </para>
4959 <para>
4960 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4961 words that echo today,
4962 </para>
4963 <blockquote>
4964 <para>
4965 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4966 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4967 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4968 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4969 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4970 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4971 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4972 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4973 Booksellers.<footnote><para>
4974 <!-- f5 -->
4975 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4976 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4977 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4978 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4979 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4980 mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4981 al., 8, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618).
4982 </para></footnote>
4983 </para>
4984 </blockquote>
4985 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne2' class='endofrange'/>
4986 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='endofrange'/>
4987 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
4988 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
4989 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
4990 <para>
4991 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4992 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4993 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
4994 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
4995 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
4996 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
4997 creative <quote>property</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
4998 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
4999 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
5000 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
5001 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
5002 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
5003 way to protect authors.
5004 </para>
5005 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament2' class='endofrange'/>
5006 <para>
5007 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
5008 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
5009 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
5010 <quote>The publishers &hellip; had as much concern for authors as a cattle
5011 rancher has for cattle.</quote><footnote><para>
5012 <!-- f6 -->
5013 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5014 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
5015 Lyman Ray Patterson, <quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
5016 Law Review</citetitle> 40 (1987): 28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
5017 Vaidhyanathan, 37&ndash;48.
5018 </para></footnote>
5019 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
5020 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
5021 </para>
5022 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5023 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5024 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5025 <para>
5026 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
5027 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
5028 Donaldson.<footnote><para>
5029 <!-- f7 -->
5030 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, <citetitle>Authorship and Copyright</citetitle>
5031 (London: Routledge, 1992), 62&ndash;69.
5032 </para></footnote>
5033 </para>
5034 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne3' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
5035 <indexterm id='idxconger' class='startofrange'><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
5036 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James</primary></indexterm>
5037 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew</primary></indexterm>
5038 <para>
5039 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
5040 career in Edinburgh in 1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
5041 reprints <quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,</quote> at least
5042 under the Statute of Anne.<footnote><para>
5043 <!-- f8 -->
5044 Mark Rose, <citetitle>Authors and Owners</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
5045 1993), 92.
5046 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
5047 </para></footnote>
5048 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
5049 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
5050 and became <quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.</quote> <quote>[A]mong
5051 them,</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was <quote>the young James Boswell
5052 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
5053 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.</quote><footnote><para>
5054 <!-- f9 -->
5055 Ibid., 93.
5056 </para></footnote>
5057 </para>
5058 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5059 <para>
5060 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
5061 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
5062 inexpensive editions <quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
5063 of the supposed common law right of Literary
5064 Property.</quote><footnote><para>
5065 <!-- f10 -->
5066 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5067 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle>, 167 (quoting
5068 Borwell).
5069 </para></footnote>
5070 His books undercut the Conger prices by 30 to 50 percent, and he
5071 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
5072 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
5073 </para>
5074 <indexterm startref='idxconger' class='endofrange'/>
5075 <indexterm id='idxmillarvtaylor' class='startofrange'><primary>Millar v. Taylor</primary></indexterm>
5076 <para>
5077 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block <quote>piracy</quote> like
5078 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the <quote>pirates,</quote>
5079 the most important early victory being <citetitle>Millar</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Taylor</citetitle>.
5080 </para>
5081 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='endofrange'/>
5082 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers' class='endofrange'/>
5083 <indexterm id='idxthomsonjames' class='startofrange'><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5084 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5085 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)</primary></indexterm>
5086 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert</primary></indexterm>
5087 <para>
5088 Millar was a bookseller who in 1729 had purchased the rights to James
5089 Thomson's poem <quote>The Seasons.</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
5090 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
5091 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
5092 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
5093 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.<footnote><para>
5094 <!-- f11 -->
5095 Howard B. Abrams, <quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
5096 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review</citetitle> 29
5097 (1983): 1152.
5098 </para></footnote>
5099 </para>
5100 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
5101 <para>
5102 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
5103 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
5104 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
5105 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
5106 law would protect the author against subsequent <quote>pirates.</quote>
5107 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
5108 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
5109 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
5110 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
5111 </para>
5112 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw' class='endofrange'/>
5113 <indexterm startref='idxthomsonjames' class='endofrange'/>
5114 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='endofrange'/>
5115 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament3' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5116 <para>
5117 Considered as a matter of abstract justice&mdash;reasoning as if
5118 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
5119 principles&mdash;Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
5120 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
5121 with in 1710: How best to limit
5122 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
5123 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
5124 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in 1710, but
5125 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
5126 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
5127 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
5128 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
5129 </para>
5130 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='endofrange'/>
5131 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5132 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers2' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5133 <para>
5134 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
5135 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
5136 </para>
5137 <indexterm><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5138 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
5139 <indexterm id='idxhouseoflords' class='startofrange'><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5140 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>House of Lords vs.</secondary></indexterm>
5141 <para>
5142 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
5143 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
5144 Thomas Beckett.<footnote><para>
5145 <!-- f12 -->
5146 Ibid., 1156.
5147 </para></footnote>
5148 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
5149 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in <citetitle>Millar</citetitle>,
5150 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
5151 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
5152 Court. In February of 1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
5153 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
5154 </para>
5155 <indexterm startref='idxmillarvtaylor' class='endofrange'/>
5156 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament3' class='endofrange'/>
5157 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson v. Beckett</primary></indexterm>
5158 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5159 <para>
5160 As few legal cases ever do, <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle> drew an
5161 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
5162 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
5163 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
5164 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
5165 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
5166 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
5167 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
5168 </para>
5169 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne3' class='endofrange'/>
5170 <para>
5171 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
5172 presented to the House and voted upon first by the <quote>law lords,</quote>
5173 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
5174 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
5175 House of Lords generally voted.
5176 </para>
5177 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='endofrange'/>
5178 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5179 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5180 <para>
5181 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
5182 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
5183 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
5184 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
5185 (22 to 11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
5186 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
5187 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
5188 passed into the public domain.
5189 </para>
5190 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis</primary></indexterm>
5191 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John</primary></indexterm>
5192 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel</primary></indexterm>
5193 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
5194 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
5195 <para>
5196 <quote>The public domain.</quote> Before the case of <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle>
5197 v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
5198 England. Before 1774, there was a strong argument that common law
5199 copyrights were perpetual. After 1774, the public domain was
5200 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
5201 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
5202 history&mdash;including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
5203 and Bunyan&mdash;were free of legal restraint.
5204 </para>
5205 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='endofrange'/>
5206 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers2' class='endofrange'/>
5207 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw2' class='endofrange'/>
5208 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='endofrange'/>
5209 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5210 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5211 <para>
5212 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
5213 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
5214 where most of the <quote>pirate publishers</quote> did their work, people
5215 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the <citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser</citetitle>
5216 reported, <quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
5217 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
5218 decision of which so many individuals were interested.</quote> <quote>Great
5219 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
5220 and illuminations.</quote><footnote><para>
5221 <!-- f13 -->
5222 Rose, 97.
5223 </para></footnote>
5224 </para>
5225 <indexterm startref='idxhouseoflords' class='endofrange'/>
5226 <para>
5227 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
5228 equally strong in the opposite direction. The <citetitle>Morning Chronicle</citetitle>
5229 reported:
5230 </para>
5231 <blockquote>
5232 <para>
5233 By the above decision &hellip; near 200,000 pounds worth of what was
5234 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
5235 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
5236 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
5237 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
5238 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
5239 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
5240 successors.<footnote><para>
5241 <!-- f14 -->
5242 Ibid.
5243 </para></footnote>
5244 </para>
5245 </blockquote>
5246 <indexterm><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5247 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5248 <para>
5249 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
5250 <quote>Ruined</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
5251 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
5252 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
5253 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
5254 <emphasis>free</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
5255 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
5256 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
5257 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
5258 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
5259 book from someone. But <emphasis>free</emphasis> in the sense that the
5260 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
5261 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
5262 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
5263 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
5264 develop&mdash; chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
5265 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a <emphasis>competitive
5266 context</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
5267 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
5268 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
5269 </para>
5270 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellersenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5271 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5272 <para>
5273 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
5274 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
5275 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
5276 protected.
5277 </para>
5278 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='endofrange'/>
5279 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5280 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5281 <indexterm startref='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='endofrange'/>
5282 <indexterm startref='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='endofrange'/>
5283 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='endofrange'/>
5284 <indexterm startref='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='endofrange'/>
5285 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='endofrange'/>
5286 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='endofrange'/>
5287 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
5288 </chapter>
5289 <chapter label="7" id="recorders">
5290 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders</title>
5291 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
5292 <indexterm id='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>documentary film</primary></indexterm>
5293 <indexterm id='idxelsejon' class='startofrange'><primary>Else, Jon</primary></indexterm>
5294 <indexterm id='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>in documentary film</secondary></indexterm>
5295 <indexterm id='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>fair use of copyrighted material in</secondary></indexterm>
5296 <para>
5297 <emphasis role='strong'>Jon Else</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5298 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5299 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5300 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5301 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5302 </para>
5303 <para>
5304 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5305 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5306 today.
5307 </para>
5308 <indexterm id='idxwagnerrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5309 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5310 <para>
5311 In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5312 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5313 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5314 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5315 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5316 stage.
5317 </para>
5318 <indexterm id='idxsimpsonsthe' class='startofrange'><primary>Simpsons, The</primary></indexterm>
5319 <para>
5320 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5321 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5322 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5323 and the opera company played Wagner, was <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. As Else judged
5324 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5325 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5326 about the scene.
5327 </para>
5328 <indexterm startref='idxwagnerrichard' class='endofrange'/>
5329 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>multiple copyrights associated with</secondary></indexterm>
5330 <para>
5331 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5332 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>.
5333 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5334 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5335 unless <quote>fair use</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5336 </para>
5337 <indexterm id='idxgraciefilms' class='startofrange'><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5338 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt' class='startofrange'><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5339 <para>
5340 Else called <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5341 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5342 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5343 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5344 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5345 </para>
5346 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5347 <para>
5348 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5349 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5350 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5351 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5352 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5353 </para>
5354 <indexterm startref='idxgraciefilms' class='endofrange'/>
5355 <para>
5356 Then, as Else told me, <quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5357 &hellip; that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation&mdash;or at
5358 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.</quote>
5359 And second, Fox <quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5360 to use this four-point-five seconds of &hellip; entirely unsolicited
5361 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.</quote>
5362 </para>
5363 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt' class='endofrange'/>
5364 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='endofrange'/>
5365 <indexterm id='idxherrerarebecca' class='startofrange'><primary>Herrera, Rebecca</primary></indexterm>
5366 <para>
5367 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5368 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5369 explained to her, <quote>There must be some mistake here. &hellip; We're
5370 asking for your educational rate on this.</quote> That was the educational
5371 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5372 confirm what he had been told.
5373 </para>
5374 <indexterm><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5375 <para>
5376 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,</quote> he told me. <quote>Yes, you
5377 have your facts straight,</quote> she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the
5378 clip of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5379 about
5380
5381 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5382 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, <quote>And
5383 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.</quote> As an assistant
5384 to Herrera told Else later on, <quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5385 the money.</quote>
5386 </para>
5387 <indexterm startref='idxherrerarebecca' class='endofrange'/>
5388 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5389 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The</primary></indexterm>
5390 <para>
5391 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5392 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5393 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5394 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5395 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5396 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5397 </para>
5398 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5399 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt2' class='startofrange'><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5400 <para>
5401 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5402 copyright to <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5403 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5404 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5405 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5406 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5407 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5408 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5409 says the owner gets to control.
5410 </para>
5411 <para>
5412 For example, <quote>public performance</quote> is a use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> that the
5413 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5414 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see <quote>My
5415 Favorite <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>,</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5416 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5417 whatever she wants&mdash;$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set
5418 by the law.
5419 </para>
5420 <para>
5421 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5422 thought is <quote>fair use.</quote><footnote><para>
5423 <!-- f1 -->
5424 For an excellent argument that such use is <quote>fair use,</quote> but that
5425 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is <quote>fair use,</quote> see Richard
5426 A. Posner with William F. Patry, <quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5427 Wake of <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5428 Law School, 5 August 2003.
5429 </para></footnote>
5430 Else's use of just 4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>
5431 episode is clearly a fair use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>&mdash;and fair use does
5432 not require the permission of anyone.
5433 </para>
5434 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='endofrange'/>
5435 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt2' class='endofrange'/>
5436 <para>
5437 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5438 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon <quote>fair use.</quote> Here's his reply:
5439 </para>
5440 <blockquote>
5441 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
5442 <para>
5443 The <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5444 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5445 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5446 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was <quote>clearly
5447 fair use</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5448 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5449 </para>
5450 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
5451 <listitem>
5452 <indexterm><primary>Errors and Omissions insurance</primary></indexterm>
5453 <para>
5454 <!-- 1. -->
5455 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5456 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5457 <quote>visual cue sheet</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5458 shot in the film. They take a dim view of <quote>fair use,</quote> and a claim of
5459 <quote>fair use</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5460 </para></listitem>
5461 <listitem>
5462 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5463 <indexterm><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5464 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George</primary></indexterm>
5465 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5466 <para>
5467 <!-- 2. -->
5468 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5469 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5470 tracking down and stopping unlicensed <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> usage, just as George
5471 Lucas had a very high profile litigating <citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5472 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5473 license to four seconds of <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5474 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5475 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5476 principle.
5477 </para></listitem>
5478 <listitem><para>
5479 <!-- 3. -->
5480 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5481 School &hellip; who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5482 that Fox would <quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5483 life,</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5484 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5485 pockets, me or them.
5486 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5487 </para>
5488 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='endofrange'/>
5489 </listitem>
5490 <listitem><para>
5491 <!-- 4. -->
5492 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5493 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5494 money.
5495 </para></listitem>
5496 </orderedlist>
5497 </blockquote>
5498 <indexterm startref='idxsimpsonsthe' class='endofrange'/>
5499 <para>
5500 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5501 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5502 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5503 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5504 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5505 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5506 </para>
5507 <para>
5508 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5509 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5510 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5511 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5512 not.
5513 </para>
5514 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='endofrange'/>
5515 <indexterm startref='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5516 <indexterm startref='idxelsejon' class='endofrange'/>
5517 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5518 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='endofrange'/>
5519 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='endofrange'/>
5520 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5521 </chapter>
5522 <chapter label="8" id="transformers">
5523 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers</title>
5524 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul</primary></indexterm>
5525 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5526 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary></indexterm>
5527 <para>
5528 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5529 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5530 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5531 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5532 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5533 anticipation of the power of networks.
5534 </para>
5535 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on</secondary></indexterm>
5536 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in</primary></indexterm>
5537 <para>
5538 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5539 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology&mdash;not to distribute
5540 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5541 difficult. In 1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5542 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5543 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5544 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5545 important to his career.
5546 </para>
5547 <para>
5548 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5549 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5550 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5551 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5552 </para>
5553 <para>
5554 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5555 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5556 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5557 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5558 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5559 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5560 </para>
5561 <para>
5562 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. <quote>Our
5563 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5564 Eastwood's films,</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5565 arose. <quote>No one had ever really done this before,</quote> Alben explained. <quote>No
5566 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5567 actor's career.</quote>
5568 </para>
5569 <para>
5570 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5571 Slade asked, <quote>Well, what will it take?</quote>
5572 </para>
5573 <para>
5574 Alben replied, <quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5575 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5576 else that we want to use in these film clips.</quote> Slade said, <quote>Great! Go
5577 for it.</quote><footnote>
5578 <para>
5579 <!-- f1 -->
5580 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5581 publicity&mdash;rights an artist has to control the commercial
5582 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden <quote>Rip, Mix,
5583 Burn</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5584 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of</secondary></indexterm>
5585 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5586 </para></footnote>
5587 </para>
5588 <para>
5589 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5590 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5591 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5592 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5593 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5594 </para>
5595 <para>
5596 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5597 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5598 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5599 </para>
5600 <blockquote>
5601 <para>
5602 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5603 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include&mdash;of
5604 course we were going to use the <quote>Make my day</quote> clip from <citetitle>Dirty
5605 Harry</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5606 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5607 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5608 </para>
5609 <para>
5610 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5611 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5612 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5613 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5614 rate at the time was about $600. So we had to identify the
5615 people&mdash;some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5616 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5617 glass&mdash;is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5618 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5619 started calling people.
5620 </para>
5621 </blockquote>
5622 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald</primary></indexterm>
5623 <para>
5624 Some actors were glad to help&mdash;Donald Sutherland, for example,
5625 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5626 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5627 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5628 know, $1,200?</quote> And they would say, <quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5629 to get $1,200.</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5630 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5631 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5632 career.
5633 </para>
5634 <para>
5635 It was one <emphasis>year</emphasis> later&mdash;<quote>and even then we
5636 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.</quote>
5637 </para>
5638 <para>
5639 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5640 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5641 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5642 </para>
5643 <blockquote>
5644 <para>
5645 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5646 hands and said, <quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5647 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5648 actors.</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5649 constituent parts and said, <quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5650 directors, &hellip; this many musicians,</quote> and we just went at it very
5651 systematically and cleared the rights.
5652 </para>
5653 </blockquote>
5654 <para>
5655
5656 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5657 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5658 loved it, and it sold very well.
5659 </para>
5660 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter</primary></indexterm>
5661 <para>
5662 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5663 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5664 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, <quote>There is
5665 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5666 at all.</quote><footnote><para>
5667 <!-- f2 -->
5668 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, <citetitle>Seven
5669 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition</citetitle>, available at
5670 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #22</ulink>.
5671 </para></footnote>
5672 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5673 has to be made?
5674 </para>
5675 <para>
5676 For, as he acknowledged, <quote>very few &hellip; have the time and resources,
5677 and the will to do this,</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5678 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5679 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5680 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5681 </para>
5682 <blockquote>
5683 <para>
5684 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5685 he or she gets paid very well. &hellip; And then when 30 seconds of
5686 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5687 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person &hellip; should be
5688 compensated for that.
5689 </para>
5690 </blockquote>
5691 <para>
5692 Or at least, is this <emphasis>how</emphasis> the artist should be
5693 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5694 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5695 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5696 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5697 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5698 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5699 made to be more clean?
5700 </para>
5701 <blockquote>
5702 <para>
5703 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5704 mechanism&mdash;where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5705 subject to estranged former spouses&mdash;you'd see a lot more of this
5706 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5707 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5708 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5709 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5710 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5711 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5712 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5713 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5714 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5715 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5716 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, <quote>Oh, I
5717 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5718 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5719 money,</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5720 </para>
5721 </blockquote>
5722 <para>
5723 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5724 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5725 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5726 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5727 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5728 </para>
5729 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'/>
5730 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'/>
5731 <para>
5732 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5733 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5734 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5735 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5736 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5737 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5738 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5739 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5740 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5741 <quote>Does this still make sense?</quote>
5742 </para>
5743 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'/>
5744 <para>
5745 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5746 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5747 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5748 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5749
5750 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5751 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5752 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5753 </para>
5754 <para>
5755 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5756 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode.
5757 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5758 judges loved every minute of it.
5759 </para>
5760 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David</primary></indexterm>
5761 <para>
5762 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5763 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5764 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5765 room of over 250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5766 began his talk with a question: <quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5767 were just violated in this room?</quote>
5768 </para>
5769 <para>
5770 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5771 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David</primary></indexterm>
5772 <indexterm><primary>Court of Appeals</primary><secondary>Ninth Circuit</secondary></indexterm>
5773 <indexterm><primary>Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals</primary></indexterm>
5774 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
5775 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5776 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5777 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5778 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5779 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle
5780 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5781 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5782 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5783 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5784 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5785 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5786 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5787 couldn't easily do them legally.
5788 </para>
5789 <para>
5790 We live in a <quote>cut and paste</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5791 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5792 and paste architecture of the Internet created&mdash;in a second you can
5793 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5794 planted in your presentation.
5795 </para>
5796 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos</primary></indexterm>
5797 <para>
5798 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5799 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5800 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5801 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5802 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5803 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5804 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5805 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5806 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5807 </para>
5808 <para>
5809 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5810 wanted to be <quote>legal,</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5811 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5812 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5813 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5814 </para>
5815 <para>
5816 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5817 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5818 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5819 necessarily requiring that the <quote>free</quote> use be free as in <quote>free beer.</quote>
5820 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5821 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5822 along: a rule, for example, that says <quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5823 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5824 will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5825 copyright owner.</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5826 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5827 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5828 registers the work.
5829 </para>
5830 <para>
5831 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5832 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5833 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5834 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5835 </para>
5836 <para>
5837 <emphasis role='strong'>In February 2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5838 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5839 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live</citetitle> and
5840 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5841 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5842 would work together to form a <quote>unique filmmaking pact.</quote> Under the
5843 agreement, DreamWorks <quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5844 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and&mdash;with the use
5845 of stateof-the-art digital technology&mdash;insert Myers and other
5846 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5847 entertainment.</quote>
5848 </para>
5849 <para>
5850 The announcement called this <quote>film sampling.</quote> As Myers explained,
5851 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5852 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5853 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5854 to take that same concept and apply it to film.</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5855 quoted as saying, <quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5856 new audiences, it is Mike.</quote>
5857 </para>
5858 <para>
5859 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5860 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5861 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5862 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5863 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5864 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5865 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5866 privilege reserved for the funny and famous&mdash;and presumably rich.
5867 </para>
5868 <para>
5869 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5870 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of <quote>fair use.</quote>
5871 Much of <quote>sampling</quote> should be considered <quote>fair use.</quote> But few would
5872 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5873 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5874 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5875 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5876 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5877 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5878 process is a process of paying lawyers&mdash;again a privilege, or perhaps a
5879 curse, reserved for the few.
5880 </para>
5881 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5882 </chapter>
5883 <chapter label="9" id="collectors">
5884 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors</title>
5885 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
5886 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
5887 <para>
5888 <emphasis role='strong'>In April 1996</emphasis>, millions of
5889 <quote>bots</quote>&mdash;computer codes designed to
5890 <quote>spider,</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5891 content&mdash;began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5892 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5893 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5894 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5895 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5896 Internet and stored them.
5897 </para>
5898 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5899 <para>
5900 By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5901 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5902 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5903 the world. Using a technology called <quote>the Way Back Machine,</quote> you could
5904 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to 1996, as
5905 well as when those pages changed.
5906 </para>
5907 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Orwell, George</primary></indexterm>
5908 <para>
5909 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5910 appreciated. In the dystopia described in <citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5911 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5912 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5913 reports.
5914 </para>
5915 <para>
5916 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5917 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5918 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5919 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5920 </para>
5921 <para>
5922 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5923 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5924 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5925 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5926 library&mdash;constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5927 </para>
5928 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'/>
5929 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5930 <para>
5931 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5932 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5933 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5934 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5935 what others might prefer you forget.<footnote><para>
5936 <!-- f1 -->
5937 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
5938 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases</primary></indexterm>
5939 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5940 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003,
5941 press release stated, <quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.</quote> That was
5942 later changed, without notice, to <quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5943 Have Ended.</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003.
5944 </para></footnote>
5945 </para>
5946 <indexterm><primary>history, records of</primary></indexterm>
5947 <para>
5948 <emphasis role='strong'>We take it</emphasis> for granted that we can
5949 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5950 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5951 race riots in Watts in 1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in 1963,
5952 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5953 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5954 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
5955 remember&mdash;not just what it is convenient to remember, but
5956 remember something close to the truth.
5957 </para>
5958 <para>
5959 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5960 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We <emphasis>all</emphasis>
5961 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
5962 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
5963 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
5964 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
5965 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
5966 </para>
5967 <para>
5968 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5969 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5970 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5971 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5972 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5973 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5974 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5975 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet&mdash;the
5976 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5977 </para>
5978 <para>
5979 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5980 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5981 researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5982 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5983 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5984 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5985 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10
5986 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5987 </para>
5988 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
5989 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive</primary></indexterm>
5990 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University</primary></indexterm>
5991 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5992 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>archival function of</secondary></indexterm>
5993 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage2' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
5994 <para>
5995 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
5996 human history. At the end of 2002, it held <quote>two hundred and thirty
5997 terabytes of material</quote>&mdash;and was <quote>ten times larger than the
5998 Library of Congress.</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
5999 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
6000 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
6001 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
6002 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
6003 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
6004 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University&mdash;thanks to a
6005 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
6006 is available to scholars for a very low fee. <quote>But other than that,
6007 [television] is almost unavailable,</quote> Kahle told me. <quote>If you were
6008 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
6009 just a graduate student?</quote> As Kahle put it,
6010 </para>
6011 <blockquote>
6012 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan</primary></indexterm>
6013 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes</primary></indexterm>
6014 <para>
6015 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
6016 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
6017 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
6018 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
6019 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
6020
6021 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
6022 <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode that came out after it &hellip; it would be almost
6023 impossible. &hellip; Those materials are almost unfindable. &hellip;
6024 </para>
6025 </blockquote>
6026 <indexterm><primary>newspapers</primary><secondary>archives of</secondary></indexterm>
6027 <para>
6028 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
6029 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
6030 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
6031 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
6032 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
6033 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
6034 </para>
6035 <para>
6036 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
6037 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
6038 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
6039 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
6040 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
6041 work.
6042 </para>
6043 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
6044 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6045 <para>
6046 These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library
6047 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
6048 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
6049 borrow back the deposits&mdash;for an unlimited time at no cost. In
6050 1915 alone, there were more than 5,475 films deposited and <quote>borrowed
6051 back.</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
6052 held by any library. The copy exists&mdash;if it exists at
6053 all&mdash;in the library archive of the film company.<footnote><para>
6054 <!-- f2 -->
6055 Doug Herrick, <quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
6056 the Library of Congress,</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly</citetitle> 13 nos. 2&ndash;3
6057 (1980): 5; Anthony Slide, <citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
6058 Preservation in the United States</citetitle> (Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland &amp;
6059 Co., 1992), 36.
6060 </para></footnote>
6061 </para>
6062 <para>
6063 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
6064 were originally not copyrighted&mdash;there was no way to capture the
6065 broadcasts, so there was no fear of <quote>theft.</quote> But as technology enabled
6066 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
6067 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
6068 <quote>copyrighted.</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
6069 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
6070 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
6071 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
6072 </para>
6073 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
6074 <para>
6075 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and
6076 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
6077 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
6078 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
6079 September 11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
6080 stations from around the world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made
6081 their coverage during the week of September 11 available free on-line.
6082 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
6083 events of that day.
6084 </para>
6085 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive</primary></indexterm>
6086 <indexterm><primary>archive.org</primary><seealso>Internet Archive</seealso></indexterm>
6087 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage2' class='endofrange'/>
6088 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6089 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive</primary></indexterm>
6090 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film</primary></indexterm>
6091 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films</primary></indexterm>
6092 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick</primary></indexterm>
6093 <para>
6094 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
6095 archive of film includes close to 45,000 <quote>ephemeral films</quote> (meaning
6096 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
6097 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
6098 1,300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
6099 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
6100 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
6101 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
6102 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
6103 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
6104 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
6105 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
6106 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the <quote>Duck and Cover</quote> film
6107 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
6108 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
6109 few minutes&mdash;for free.
6110 </para>
6111 <para>
6112 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
6113 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
6114 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
6115 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
6116 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
6117 to find them.
6118 </para>
6119 <para>
6120 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
6121 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
6122 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
6123 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
6124 property, but during a second life that all creative property
6125 has&mdash;a noncommercial life.
6126 </para>
6127 <para>
6128 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
6129 of creative property goes through different <quote>lives.</quote> In its first
6130 life, if the
6131
6132 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
6133 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
6134 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
6135 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
6136 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
6137 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
6138 </para>
6139 <para>
6140 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
6141 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
6142 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
6143 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
6144 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
6145 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
6146 longer sold.
6147 </para>
6148 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6149 <para>
6150 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
6151 very quickly (the average today is after about a year<footnote><para>
6152 <!-- f3 -->
6153 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6154 Dave Barns, <quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
6155 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>,
6156 5 September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927
6157 and 1946, only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese,
6158 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,</quote> <citetitle>Boston
6159 College Law Review</citetitle> 44 (2003): 593 n. 51.
6160 </para></footnote>). After
6161 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
6162 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
6163 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
6164 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
6165 important to the spread and stability of culture.
6166 </para>
6167 <para>
6168 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
6169 creative property does not hold true with the most important
6170 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
6171 centuries. For these&mdash;television, movies, music, radio, the
6172 Internet&mdash;there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
6173 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes &amp;
6174 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
6175 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
6176 disappears.
6177 </para>
6178 <para>
6179 <emphasis role='strong'>For most of</emphasis> the twentieth century,
6180 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
6181 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
6182 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
6183 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
6184 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
6185 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
6186 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
6187 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
6188 little practical effect.
6189 </para>
6190 <para>
6191 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
6192 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
6193 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
6194 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
6195 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
6196 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
6197 </para>
6198 <para>
6199 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
6200 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
6201 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
6202 Kahle describes,
6203 </para>
6204 <blockquote>
6205 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>total number of</secondary></indexterm>
6206 <para>
6207 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
6208 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
6209 movies, &hellip; and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
6210 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
6211 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
6212 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
6213 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
6214 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
6215 &hellip; thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
6216 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
6217 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
6218 </para>
6219 </blockquote>
6220 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
6221 <para>
6222 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
6223 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
6224 libraries or archives could be. <emphasis>When</emphasis> the
6225 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
6226 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
6227 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
6228 will draw upon it to understand it;
6229 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
6230 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
6231 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
6232 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past&mdash;a
6233 future <emphasis>for</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
6234 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
6235 </para>
6236 <para>
6237 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
6238 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
6239 call these <quote>archives,</quote> as warm as the idea of a <quote>library</quote> might seem,
6240 the <quote>content</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
6241 someone's <quote>property.</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
6242 that Kahle and others would exercise.
6243 </para>
6244 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'/>
6245 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
6246 </chapter>
6247 <chapter label="10" id="property-i">
6248 <title>CHAPTER TEN: <quote>Property</quote></title>
6249 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon</primary></indexterm>
6250 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
6251 <para>
6252 <emphasis role='strong'>Jack Valenti</emphasis> has been the president
6253 of the Motion Picture Association of America since 1966. He first came
6254 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
6255 administration&mdash;literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
6256 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
6257 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
6258 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
6259 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
6260 </para>
6261 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
6262 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment</primary></indexterm>
6263 <indexterm><primary>MGM</primary></indexterm>
6264 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6265 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox</primary></indexterm>
6266 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6267 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
6268 <para>
6269 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
6270 Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal
6271 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
6272 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
6273 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
6274 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
6275 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
6276 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
6277 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
6278 Warner Brothers.
6279 </para>
6280 <para>
6281 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
6282 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
6283 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
6284 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
6285 political skill of a Southerner&mdash;the ability to appear simple and
6286 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
6287 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
6288 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
6289 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
6290 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
6291 Washingtonian way.
6292 </para>
6293 <para>
6294 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
6295 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
6296 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
6297 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
6298 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
6299 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
6300 redefine the meaning of <quote>creative property.</quote>
6301 </para>
6302 <para>
6303 In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
6304 perfectly:
6305 </para>
6306 <blockquote>
6307 <para>
6308 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
6309 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
6310 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
6311 theme which animates this entire debate: <emphasis>Creative property
6312 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
6313 other property owners in the nation</emphasis>. That is the issue.
6314 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
6315 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.<footnote><para>
6316 <!-- f1 -->
6317 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R.
6318 4794, H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the
6319 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
6320 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
6321 Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack
6322 Valenti).
6323 </para></footnote>
6324 </para>
6325 </blockquote>
6326 <para>
6327 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
6328 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
6329 <quote>central theme</quote> to which <quote>reasonable men and women</quote> will return is
6330 this:
6331 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6332 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6333 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.</quote>
6334 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6335 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6336 </para>
6337 <para>
6338 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6339 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6340 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6341 extreme a claim made by <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> who is serious in
6342 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6343 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6344 it comes to the nature and scope of <quote>creative property.</quote> His views
6345 have <emphasis>no</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6346 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6347 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6348 </para>
6349 <para>
6350 While <quote>creative property</quote> is certainly <quote>property</quote> in a nerdy and
6351 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,<footnote><para>
6352 <!-- f2 -->
6353 Lawyers speak of <quote>property</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6354 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6355 object. Thus, my <quote>property right</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6356 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For
6357 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of <quote>property</quote> to
6358 <quote>lawyer talk,</quote> see Bruce Ackerman, <citetitle>Private Property and the
6359 Constitution</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 26&ndash;27.
6360 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6361 <quote>creative property owners</quote> have been <quote>accorded the same rights and
6362 protection resident in all other property owners.</quote> Indeed, if creative
6363 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6364 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6365 in our tradition.
6366 </para>
6367 <para>
6368 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6369 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6370 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6371 overturned in 1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6372 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6373 culture would develop.
6374 </para>
6375 <para>
6376 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6377 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6378 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6379 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6380 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6381 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6382 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6383 the same would be to
6384
6385 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6386 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6387 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6388 perfect control.
6389 </para>
6390 <para>
6391 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6392 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6393 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6394 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6395 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6396 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6397 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6398 </para>
6399 <para>
6400 <emphasis role='strong'>To get</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6401 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6402 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6403 </para>
6404 <para>
6405 The framers of our Constitution loved <quote>property.</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6406 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6407 important requirement. If the government takes your property&mdash;if
6408 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6409 farm&mdash;it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's <quote>Takings
6410 Clause,</quote> to pay you <quote>just compensation</quote> for that taking. The
6411 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6412 sacred. It cannot <emphasis>ever</emphasis> be taken from the property
6413 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6414 </para>
6415 <para>
6416 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6417 Valenti calls <quote>creative property.</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6418 power to create <quote>creative property,</quote> the Constitution
6419 <emphasis>requires</emphasis> that after a <quote>limited time,</quote> Congress
6420 take back the rights that it has granted and set the <quote>creative
6421 property</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6422 the expiration of a copyright term <quote>takes</quote> your copyright and turns it
6423 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6424 pay <quote>just compensation</quote> for this <quote>taking.</quote> Instead, the same
6425 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6426 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6427 requires that you lose your <quote>creative property</quote> right without any
6428 compensation at all.
6429 </para>
6430 <para>
6431 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6432 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6433 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6434 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6435 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6436 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6437 itself.
6438 </para>
6439 <indexterm id='idxjeffersonthomas' class='startofrange'><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
6440 <para>
6441 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6442 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6443 The Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6444 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6445 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6446 president (as it did in 1800). The framers were no doubt
6447 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6448 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6449 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6450 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6451 </para>
6452 <para>
6453 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6454 least try to understand <emphasis>why</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6455 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6456 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6457 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6458 domain?
6459 </para>
6460 <indexterm startref='idxjeffersonthomas' class='endofrange'/>
6461
6462 <para>
6463 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6464 history of these <quote>creative property</quote> rights, and the control that they
6465 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6466 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6467 should be at the core of this war: Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis>
6468 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6469 <emphasis>whether</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6470 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6471 ought to be. Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6472 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6473 also control how culture develops.
6474 </para>
6475 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>four modalities of constraint on</secondary></indexterm>
6476 <indexterm id='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>four modalities of</secondary></indexterm>
6477 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as ex post regulation modality</secondary></indexterm>
6478 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6479 <para>
6480
6481 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6482 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6483 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6484 than the narrow language of the law allows. In <citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6485 Cyberspace</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6486 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6487 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6488 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6489 </para>
6490 <figure id="fig-1331">
6491 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.</title>
6492 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6493 </figure>
6494 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6495 <para>
6496 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6497 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6498 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6499 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6500 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6501 be regulated&mdash; either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6502 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6503 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6504 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6505 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6506 Web, you can be punished
6507 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6508 with a $150,000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6509 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6510 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6511 </para>
6512 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6513 <para>
6514 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6515 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6516 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6517 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6518 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6519 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6520 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6521 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6522 the source of the enforcement.
6523 </para>
6524 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6525 <para>
6526 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6527 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6528 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6529 norms&mdash;it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6530 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6531 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6532 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6533 individual or group might behave.
6534 </para>
6535 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6536 <para>
6537 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6538 <quote>architecture</quote>&mdash;the physical world as one finds it&mdash;is a
6539 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6540 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6541 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6542 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6543 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6544 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6545 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6546 theft, but by nature, by <quote>architecture.</quote> If a 500-pound boulder
6547 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6548 constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6549 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6550 </para>
6551 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6552 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6553 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints' class='endofrange'/>
6554 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6555 <para>
6556
6557 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6558 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6559 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6560 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6561 undermined by another.
6562 </para>
6563 <para>
6564 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6565 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6566 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6567 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6568 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6569 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6570 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6571 </para>
6572 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6573 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6574 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6575 <indexterm id='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>driving speed, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6576 <indexterm id='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>speeding, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6577 <para>
6578 So, for example, consider the <quote>freedom</quote> to drive a car at a high
6579 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6580 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6581 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6582 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6583 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6584 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6585 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6586 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6587 the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own
6588 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6589 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6590 </para>
6591 <para>
6592 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6593 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6594 special role in affecting the three.<footnote><para>
6595 <!-- f3 -->
6596 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6597 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6598 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6599 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6600 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Code: And
6601 Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90&ndash;95;
6602 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>The New Chicago School,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies</citetitle>,
6603 June 1998.
6604 </para></footnote>
6605 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6606 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6607 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6608 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6609 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6610 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6611 used to require that other laws be more
6612 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6613 strict&mdash;a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6614 limit, for example&mdash;so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6615 driving.
6616 </para>
6617 <indexterm startref='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6618 <indexterm startref='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6619 <figure id="fig-1361">
6620 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.</title>
6621 <graphic fileref="images/1361.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6622
6623 </figure>
6624 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6625 <para>
6626 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6627 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6628 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6629 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6630 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6631 another.<footnote>
6632 <para>
6633 <!-- f4 -->
6634 Some people object to this way of talking about <quote>liberty.</quote> They object
6635 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6636 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6637 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6638 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6639 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6640 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6641 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6642 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6643 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6644 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6645 of liberty. As I argued in <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, we come from a
6646 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6647 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6648 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6649 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6650 <citetitle>On Liberty</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6651 1978), 19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6652 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons, <quote>The
6653 Right to Work,</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6654 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays</citetitle> (London:
6655 Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6656 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6657 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6658 places easier; 42 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
6659 12101 (2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6660 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6661 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6662 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6663 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (1990)</primary></indexterm>
6664 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.</primary></indexterm>
6665 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6666 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6667 </para></footnote>
6668 </para>
6669 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='endofrange'/>
6670 <section id="hollywood">
6671 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right</title>
6672 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
6673 <para>
6674 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6675 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6676 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6677 rallying makes sense.
6678 </para>
6679 <para>
6680 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6681 Internet:
6682 </para>
6683 <figure id="fig-1371">
6684 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6685 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6686
6687 </figure>
6688 <indexterm id='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='startofrange'><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6689 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6690 <indexterm id='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='startofrange'><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6691 <para>
6692 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6693 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6694 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6695 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6696 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6697 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6698 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6699 recognize&mdash;kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6700 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6701 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6702 this form of infringement.
6703 </para>
6704 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright regulatory balance lost with</secondary></indexterm>
6705 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>regulatory balance lost in</secondary></indexterm>
6706 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6707 <indexterm><primary>MP3s</primary></indexterm>
6708 <para>
6709 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6710 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6711 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6712 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6713 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6714 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6715 </para>
6716 <indexterm startref='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='endofrange'/>
6717 <indexterm startref='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='endofrange'/>
6718 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>established industries threatened by changes in</secondary></indexterm>
6719 <para>
6720 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6721 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6722 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6723 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6724 Iraq
6725 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6726 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6727 looting that results.
6728 </para>
6729 <figure id="fig-1381">
6730 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.</title>
6731 <graphic fileref="images/1381.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6732
6733 </figure>
6734 <indexterm><primary>Commerce, U.S. Department of</primary></indexterm>
6735 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
6736 <para>
6737 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6738 warriors. Indeed, in a <quote>White Paper</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6739 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995,
6740 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6741 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6742 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should
6743 strengthen intellectual property law, (2) businesses should adopt
6744 innovative marketing techniques, (3) technologists should push to
6745 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (4) educators should
6746 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6747 </para>
6748 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='endofrange'/>
6749 <indexterm startref='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='endofrange'/>
6750 <indexterm><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6751 <indexterm><primary>steel industry</primary></indexterm>
6752 <para>
6753 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed&mdash;if it was to
6754 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6755 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6756 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6757 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6758 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6759 life. Homeowners living in a
6760
6761 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6762 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6763 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6764 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6765 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6766 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6767 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6768 </para>
6769 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='endofrange'/>
6770 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='endofrange'/>
6771 <indexterm><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
6772 <para>
6773 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6774 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6775 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6776 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6777 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6778 Brown describes it, its <quote>architecture of revenue.</quote>
6779 </para>
6780 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
6781 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
6782 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
6783 <indexterm><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
6784 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
6785 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
6786 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry</primary></indexterm>
6787 <indexterm><primary>remote channel changers</primary></indexterm>
6788 <para>
6789 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6790 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6791 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6792 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6793 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20
6794 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6795 of digital cameras.<footnote><para>
6796 <!-- f5 -->
6797 See Geoffrey Smith, <quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?</quote>
6798 BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at
6799 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #23</ulink>. For a more
6800 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6801 R. Schoenberger, <quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?</quote> Forbes.com, 6
6802 October 2003, available at
6803 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #24</ulink>.
6804 </para></footnote>
6805
6806 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6807 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6808 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6809 <emphasis>for the purpose of</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6810 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6811 weakened the <quote>stickiness</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6812 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf), and it
6813 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6814 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6815 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6816 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6817 </para>
6818 <indexterm id='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='startofrange'><primary>free market, technological changes in</primary></indexterm>
6819 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
6820 <indexterm><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
6821 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
6822 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
6823 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
6824 <indexterm><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
6825 <para>
6826 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6827 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6828 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6829 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6830 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6831 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6832 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6833 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, <quote>established companies
6834 have an interest in excluding future competitors.</quote><footnote><para>
6835 <!-- f6 -->
6836 Fred Warshofsky, <citetitle>The Patent Wars</citetitle> (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170&ndash;71.
6837 </para></footnote>
6838 And relative to a
6839 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6840 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6841 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6842 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6843 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6844 Brezhnev.
6845 </para>
6846 <para>
6847 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6848 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6849 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6850 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6851 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6852 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6853 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6854 opportunities for innovation and change.
6855 </para>
6856 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
6857 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
6858 <indexterm><primary>speech, freedom of</primary><secondary>constitutional guarantee of</secondary></indexterm>
6859 <para>
6860 In the context of laws regulating speech&mdash;which include,
6861 obviously, copyright law&mdash;that duty is even stronger. When the
6862 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6863 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6864 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6865 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6866 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6867 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: <quote>Congress
6868 shall make no law &hellip; abridging the freedom of speech.</quote> So when
6869 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would <quote>abridge</quote> the freedom
6870 of speech, it should ask&mdash; carefully&mdash;whether such
6871 regulation is justified.
6872 </para>
6873 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='endofrange'/>
6874 <indexterm startref='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='endofrange'/>
6875 <para>
6876 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6877 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6878 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6879 <quote>justified.</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6880 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6881 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6882 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6883 </para>
6884 <para>
6885 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6886 </para>
6887 <indexterm id='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='startofrange'><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann</primary></indexterm>
6888 <indexterm id='idxddt' class='startofrange'><primary>DDT</primary></indexterm>
6889 <indexterm id='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='startofrange'><primary>insecticide, environmental consequences of</primary></indexterm>
6890 <indexterm id='idxfarming' class='startofrange'><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6891 <para>
6892 In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss
6893 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6894 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the
6895 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6896 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6897 </para>
6898 <para>
6899 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6900 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6901 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6902 </para>
6903 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6904 <indexterm><primary>Silent Spring (Carson)</primary></indexterm>
6905 <indexterm id='idxenvironmentalism' class='startofrange'><primary>environmentalism</primary></indexterm>
6906 <para>
6907 But in 1962, Rachel Carson published <citetitle>Silent Spring</citetitle>, which argued that
6908 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6909 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6910 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6911 </para>
6912 <para>
6913 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6914 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6915 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6916 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6917 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6918 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6919 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6920 </para>
6921 <indexterm startref='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='endofrange'/>
6922 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James</primary></indexterm>
6923 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovative freedom balanced with fair compensation in</secondary></indexterm>
6924 <para>
6925 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6926 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an <quote>environmentalism</quote> for
6927 culture.<footnote><para>
6928 <!-- f7 -->
6929 See, for example, James Boyle, <quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6930 Environmentalism for the Net?</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal</citetitle> 47 (1997): 87.
6931 </para></footnote>
6932 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6933 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6934 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6935 <quote>for free.</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6936 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6937 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6938 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6939 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6940 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6941 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6942 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6943 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6944 </para>
6945 <indexterm startref='idxfarming' class='endofrange'/>
6946 <para>
6947 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6948 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6949 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6950 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6951 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6952 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6953 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6954 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6955 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6956 </para>
6957 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='endofrange'/>
6958 <para>
6959 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6960 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6961 be lost.
6962 </para>
6963 <indexterm startref='idxddt' class='endofrange'/>
6964 <indexterm startref='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='endofrange'/>
6965 <indexterm startref='idxenvironmentalism' class='endofrange'/>
6966 </section>
6967 <section id="beginnings">
6968 <title>Beginnings</title>
6969 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>on creative property</secondary></indexterm>
6970 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
6971 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
6972 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
6973 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
6974 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>constitutional tradition on</secondary></indexterm>
6975 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
6976 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
6977 <para>
6978 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6979 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of <quote>creative
6980 property</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6981 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6982 </para>
6983 <indexterm id='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>in constitutional Progress Clause</secondary></indexterm>
6984 <para>
6985 The power to establish <quote>creative property</quote> rights is granted to
6986 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6987 odd. Article I, section 8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that:
6988 </para>
6989 <para>
6990 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6991 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6992 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
6993
6994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
6995 We can call this the <quote>Progress Clause,</quote> for notice what this clause
6996 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
6997 <quote>creative property rights.</quote> It says that Congress has the power
6998 <emphasis>to promote progress</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
6999 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
7000 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
7001 </para>
7002 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
7003 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
7004 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>history of American</secondary></indexterm>
7005 <para>
7006 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
7007 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="founders"/>,
7008 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
7009 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
7010 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
7011 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
7012 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
7013 copyrights extend <quote>to Authors</quote> only.
7014 </para>
7015 <indexterm><primary>Senate, U.S.</primary></indexterm>
7016 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>structural checks and balances of</secondary></indexterm>
7017 <indexterm><primary>electoral college</primary></indexterm>
7018 <para>
7019 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
7020 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
7021 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
7022 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
7023 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
7024 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
7025 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
7026 to reinforce the power of the states&mdash;including the Senate, whose
7027 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
7028 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
7029 case, a <emphasis>structure</emphasis> built checks and balances into
7030 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
7031 concentrations of power.
7032 </para>
7033 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='endofrange'/>
7034 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
7035 <para>
7036 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call <quote>copyright</quote>
7037 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
7038 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
7039 <quote>copyright</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210
7040 years since they first struck its design.
7041 </para>
7042 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='endofrange'/>
7043 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='endofrange'/>
7044 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='endofrange'/>
7045 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
7046 <para>
7047 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
7048 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
7049 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
7050 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
7051 started here:
7052 </para>
7053 <figure id="fig-1441">
7054 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
7055 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7056 </figure>
7057 <para>
7058 We will end here:
7059 </para>
7060 <figure id="fig-1442">
7061 <title><quote>Copyright</quote> today.</title>
7062 <graphic fileref="images/1442.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7063 </figure>
7064 <para>
7065 Let me explain how.
7066 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
7067 </para>
7068 </section>
7069 <section id="lawduration">
7070 <title>Law: Duration</title>
7071 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
7072 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7073 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7074 <indexterm><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>common law protections of</secondary></indexterm>
7075 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>balance of U.S. content in</secondary></indexterm>
7076 <para>
7077 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
7078 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
7079 the English had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws
7080 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
7081 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
7082 authorship.<footnote>
7083 <para>
7084 <!-- f8 -->
7085 William W. Crosskey, <citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
7086 the United States</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press, 1953), vol. 1,
7087 485&ndash;86: <quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
7088 Law of the Land,' <emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
7089 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law</emphasis></quote>
7090 (emphasis added).
7091 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.</primary></indexterm>
7092 </para></footnote>
7093 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
7094 States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
7095 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
7096 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
7097 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
7098 domain to reprint and distribute works.
7099 </para>
7100 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
7101 <indexterm id='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>federal vs. state</secondary></indexterm>
7102 <para>
7103 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
7104 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
7105 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
7106 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
7107 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
7108 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
7109 </para>
7110 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
7111 <para>
7112 In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
7113 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
7114 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
7115 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
7116 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
7117 </para>
7118 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='endofrange'/>
7119 <para>
7120 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
7121 ten years of the Republic, only 5 percent of the works were actually
7122 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
7123 in the United States both before 1790 and from 1790 through 1800, 95
7124 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
7125 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
7126 likely within fourteen years.<footnote><para>
7127 <!-- f9 -->
7128 Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790
7129 to 1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, <citetitle>A
7130 History of Book Publishing in the United States</citetitle>, vol. 1, <citetitle>The Creation
7131 of an Industry, 1630&ndash;1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000
7132 imprints recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
7133 1790 act; William J. Maher, <citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
7134 and the Copyright Law of 1790 in Historical Context</citetitle>, 7&ndash;10 (2002),
7135 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
7136 #25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
7137 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
7138 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
7139 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
7140 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
7141 Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124. </para></footnote>
7142 </para>
7143 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact' class='endofrange'/>
7144 <indexterm startref='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='endofrange'/>
7145 <para>
7146 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
7147 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
7148 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
7149 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
7150 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
7151 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
7152 copyright, either.
7153 </para>
7154 <para>
7155 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
7156 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
7157 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
7158 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
7159 domain.<footnote><para>
7160 <!-- f10 -->
7161 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
7162 instance, of the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were
7163 renewed in 1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
7164 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, <quote>Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright,</quote>
7165 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright</citetitle>, vol. 1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
7166 1963), 618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
7167 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote>
7168 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 471, 498&ndash;501, and
7169 accompanying figures. </para></footnote>
7170 </para>
7171 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='endofrange'/>
7172 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
7173 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
7174 <para>
7175 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
7176 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
7177 out of print after one year.<footnote><para>
7178 <!-- f11 -->
7179 See Ringer, ch. 9, n. 2. </para></footnote> When that happens, the
7180 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
7181 no longer <emphasis>effectively</emphasis> controlled by
7182 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
7183 is to sell the books as used books; that use&mdash;because it does not
7184 involve publication&mdash;is effectively free.
7185 </para>
7186 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7187 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
7188 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
7189 <para>
7190 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
7191 changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28
7192 years to a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
7193 from 14 years to 28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
7194 the term increased once again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal
7195 term of 14 years to 28 years, setting a maximum term of 56 years.
7196 </para>
7197 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7198 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
7199 <para>
7200 Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
7201 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
7202 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
7203 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
7204 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
7205 In 1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
7206 And in 1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
7207 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
7208 </para>
7209 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
7210 <para>
7211 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
7212 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
7213 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
7214 years, or 70 percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years
7215
7216 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
7217 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
7218 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
7219 of the expiration of a copyright term.
7220 </para>
7221 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='endofrange'/>
7222 <para>
7223 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
7224 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
7225 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
7226 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
7227 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
7228 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
7229 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
7230 value.
7231 </para>
7232 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7233 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>of natural authors vs. corporations</secondary></indexterm>
7234 <indexterm><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>copyright terms for</secondary></indexterm>
7235 <para>
7236 The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For
7237 all works created after 1978, there was only one copyright term&mdash;the
7238 maximum term. For <quote>natural</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
7239 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992,
7240 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
7241 before 1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
7242 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
7243 was ninety-five years.
7244 </para>
7245 <para>
7246 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
7247 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
7248 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
7249 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
7250 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
7251 that terms be <quote>limited,</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
7252 them.
7253 </para>
7254 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='endofrange'/>
7255 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
7256 <para>
7257 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
7258 dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to
7259 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
7260 in 1973 was just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
7261 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
7262 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95
7263 years.<footnote><para>
7264 <!-- f12 -->
7265 These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the
7266 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
7267 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
7268 Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote> loc. cit.
7269 </para></footnote>
7270 </para>
7271 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='endofrange'/>
7272 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='endofrange'/>
7273 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='endofrange'/>
7274 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='endofrange'/>
7275 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='endofrange'/>
7276 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
7277 </section>
7278 <section id="lawscope">
7279 <title>Law: Scope</title>
7280 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7281 <para>
7282 The <quote>scope</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
7283 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
7284 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
7285 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
7286 </para>
7287 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7288 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>historical shift in copyright coverage of</secondary></indexterm>
7289 <para>
7290 In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only <quote>maps,
7291 charts, and books.</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
7292 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
7293 the author the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> copyrighted works. That
7294 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
7295 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
7296 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
7297 did not extend to what lawyers call <quote>derivative works.</quote> It would not,
7298 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
7299 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
7300 (such as a drama based on a published book).
7301 </para>
7302 <para>
7303 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
7304 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
7305 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
7306 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
7307 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
7308 work not only the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> the work, but also the
7309 exclusive right of control over any <quote>copies</quote> of that work. And most
7310 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
7311 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
7312 <quote>derivative work</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
7313 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
7314 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
7315 on the initial creative work.
7316 </para>
7317 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>marking of</secondary></indexterm>
7318 <indexterm id='idxformalities' class='startofrange'><primary>formalities</primary></indexterm>
7319 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>registration requirement of</secondary></indexterm>
7320 <para>
7321 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
7322 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
7323 complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition
7324 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
7325 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
7326 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
7327 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
7328 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
7329 famous &copy; or the word <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>. And for most
7330 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
7331 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
7332 secured.
7333 </para>
7334 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='endofrange'/>
7335 <para>
7336 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
7337 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
7338 in the first ten years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible
7339 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
7340 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
7341 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
7342 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
7343 copyrighted&mdash;that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
7344 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
7345 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
7346 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
7347 original author.
7348 </para>
7349 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>European</secondary></indexterm>
7350 <para>
7351 All of these <quote>formalities</quote> were abolished in the American system when
7352 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
7353 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
7354 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
7355 a &copy;; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
7356 copy available for others to copy.
7357 </para>
7358 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='endofrange'/>
7359 <indexterm startref='idxformalities' class='endofrange'/>
7360 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='endofrange'/>
7361 <para>
7362 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
7363 differences.
7364 </para>
7365 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact2' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7366 <para>
7367 If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who
7368 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
7369 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
7370 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
7371 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were
7372 174 publishers in the United States.<footnote><para>
7373 <!-- f13 -->
7374 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, <quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
7375 Creation of American Literature,</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
7376 International Law and Politics</citetitle> 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
7377 Federal Copyright Records, 1790&ndash;1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987).
7378
7379 </para></footnote>
7380 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
7381 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
7382 the United States&mdash;publishers.
7383 </para>
7384 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7385 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7386 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7387 <para>
7388 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
7389 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
7390 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
7391 was totally unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and made
7392 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
7393 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
7394 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
7395 were restrained.
7396 </para>
7397 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact2' class='endofrange'/>
7398 <para>
7399 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
7400 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
7401 every note to your spouse, every doodle, <emphasis>every</emphasis>
7402 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form&mdash;all of this is
7403 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
7404 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
7405 protect it.
7406 </para>
7407 <para>
7408 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
7409 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
7410 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
7411 </para>
7412 <para>
7413 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
7414 control
7415 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
7416 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of <quote>derivative
7417 rights.</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
7418 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
7419 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
7420 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
7421 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
7422 exclusive
7423 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
7424 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
7425 </para>
7426 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7427 <para>
7428 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
7429 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
7430 expansion
7431 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
7432 copyright.
7433 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
7434 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
7435 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
7436 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
7437 </para>
7438 <para>
7439 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
7440 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
7441 within a free culture&mdash;at least, it's astonishing when you
7442 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
7443 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
7444 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
7445 <emphasis>that</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
7446 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
7447 all&mdash;they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
7448 not protect derivative rights at all.<footnote><para>
7449 <!-- f14 -->
7450 Jonathan Zittrain, <quote>The Copyright Cage,</quote> <citetitle>Legal
7451 Affairs</citetitle>, July/August 2003, available at
7452 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #26</ulink>.
7453 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
7454 </para></footnote>
7455 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
7456 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7457 the wrong of direct piracy.
7458 </para>
7459 <para>
7460 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7461 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7462 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7463 of my book.<footnote><para>
7464 <!-- f15 -->
7465 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7466 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7467 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere <quote>copies</quote> and
7468 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld, <quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7469 Copyright's Constitutionality,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7470 Journal</citetitle> 112 (2002): 1&ndash;60 (see especially
7471 pp. 53&ndash;59).
7472 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb</primary></indexterm>
7473 </para></footnote>
7474 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7475 </para>
7476 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7477 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
7478 <indexterm><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
7479 <para>
7480 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7481 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7482 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7483 called <quote>Mickey Mouse,</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7484 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7485 created?
7486 </para>
7487 <para>
7488 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7489 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7490 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7491 the rights originally granted.
7492 </para>
7493 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7494 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='endofrange'/>
7495 </section>
7496 <section id="lawreach">
7497 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach</title>
7498 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7499 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7500 <para>
7501 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7502 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7503 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7504 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.<footnote><para>
7505 <!-- f16 -->
7506 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7507 certainly regulates more than <quote>copies</quote>&mdash;a public performance of a
7508 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7509 per se doesn't make a copy; 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7510 106(4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a <quote>copy</quote>; 17
7511 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section 112(a). But the presumption under the
7512 existing law (which regulates <quote>copies;</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7513 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7514 </para></footnote>
7515 </para>
7516 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
7517 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>other property rights vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7518 <para>
7519 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7520 <quote>Copies.</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7521 <emphasis>copy</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7522 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that <quote>creative
7523 property</quote> deserves the <quote>same rights</quote> as all other property, it is the
7524 <emphasis>obvious</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7525 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7526 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7527 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7528 copies should <emphasis>not</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7529 law. More precisely, they should not <emphasis>always</emphasis> be
7530 the trigger for copyright law.
7531 </para>
7532 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='endofrange'/>
7533 <para>
7534 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7535 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7536 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7537 the law of copyright automatically applies,<footnote><para>
7538 <!-- f17 -->
7539 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7540 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7541 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7542 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7543 technology.
7544 </para></footnote>
7545 because it is clear that the
7546 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7547 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7548 </para>
7549 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7550 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='endofrange'/>
7551 <para>
7552 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7553 empty circle.
7554 </para>
7555 <figure id="fig-1521">
7556 <title>All potential uses of a book.</title>
7557 <graphic fileref="images/1521.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7558 </figure>
7559 <indexterm id='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>three types of uses of</secondary></indexterm>
7560 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7561 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright applicability altered by technology of</secondary></indexterm>
7562 <indexterm id='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='startofrange'><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright intent altered by</secondary></indexterm>
7563 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7564 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7565 <para>
7566 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7567 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7568 all its potential <emphasis>uses</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7569 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7570 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7571 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7572 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7573 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7574 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7575 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7576 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7577 acts do not make a copy.
7578 </para>
7579 <figure id="fig-1531">
7580 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.</title>
7581 <graphic fileref="images/1531.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7582 </figure>
7583 <para>
7584 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7585 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7586 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7587 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7588 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see
7589 diagram in <xref linkend="fig-1541"/>).
7590 </para>
7591 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7592 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7593 <indexterm id='idxfairuse' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary></indexterm>
7594 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7595 <para>
7596 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7597 that remain unregulated because the law considers these <quote>fair uses.</quote>
7598 </para>
7599 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7600 <figure id="fig-1541">
7601 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.</title>
7602 <graphic fileref="images/1541.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7603 </figure>
7604 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
7605 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
7606 <para>
7607 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7608 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7609 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7610 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7611 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7612 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7613 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such <quote>fair uses</quote>
7614 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7615 </para>
7616 <figure id="fig-1542">
7617 <title>Unregulated copying considered <quote>fair uses.</quote></title>
7618 <graphic fileref="images/1542.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7619 </figure>
7620 <para> </para>
7621 <figure id="fig-1551">
7622 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.</title>
7623 <graphic fileref="images/1551.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7624 </figure>
7625 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7626 <para>
7627 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7628 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7629 sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that
7630 are nonetheless deemed <quote>fair</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7631 </para>
7632 <indexterm startref='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='endofrange'/>
7633 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7634 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
7635 <indexterm><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7636 <para>
7637 Enter the Internet&mdash;a distributed, digital network where every use
7638 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.<footnote><para>
7639 <!-- f18 -->
7640 I don't mean <quote>nature</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7641 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7642 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7643 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7644 of copies remain.
7645 </para></footnote>
7646 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7647 digital network, the scope of category 1 changes dramatically. Uses
7648 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7649 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7650 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7651 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7652 a copy&mdash;category 1 gets sucked into category 2. And those who
7653 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7654 exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7655 shift.
7656 </para>
7657 <indexterm startref='idxfairuse' class='endofrange'/>
7658 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='endofrange'/>
7659 <para>
7660 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7661 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7662 be no plausible <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>-related argument that
7663 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7664 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7665 the book once, ten times, or every
7666 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7667 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7668 use&mdash;reading&mdash; could be regulated by copyright law because
7669 none of those uses produced a copy.
7670 </para>
7671 <indexterm id='idxebooks' class='startofrange'><primary>e-books</primary></indexterm>
7672 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>technological developments and</secondary></indexterm>
7673 <para>
7674 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7675 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7676 only once or only once a month, then <emphasis>copyright
7677 law</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7678 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7679 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7680 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7681 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7682 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7683 copyright owner's wish.
7684 </para>
7685 <para>
7686 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7687 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7688 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7689 points also become clear:
7690 </para>
7691 <para>
7692 First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7693 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7694 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7695 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7696 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7697 part of free culture before the Internet.
7698 </para>
7699 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7700 <para>
7701 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7702 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7703 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7704 <emphasis>any</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7705 using a machine. <quote>Copy and paste</quote> and <quote>cut and paste</quote> become
7706 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7707 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7708 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7709 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7710 creative work.
7711 </para>
7712 <indexterm id='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7713 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7714 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>fair use vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7715 <para>
7716 Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary
7717
7718 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7719 burden on category 3 (<quote>fair use</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7720 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7721 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7722 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7723 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7724 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7725 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7726 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7727 regulated.
7728 </para>
7729 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='endofrange'/>
7730 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='endofrange'/>
7731 <indexterm startref='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='endofrange'/>
7732 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='endofrange'/>
7733 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='endofrange'/>
7734 <para>
7735 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7736 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7737 depend upon fair use&mdash;never even addressing the earlier question
7738 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7739 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7740 <emphasis>unregulated</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7741 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7742 enough.
7743 </para>
7744 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='endofrange'/>
7745 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'/>
7746 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson2' class='endofrange'/>
7747 <indexterm startref='idxebooks' class='endofrange'/>
7748 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='endofrange'/>
7749 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='endofrange'/>
7750 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='endofrange'/>
7751 <indexterm id='idxvideopipeline' class='startofrange'><primary>Video Pipeline</primary></indexterm>
7752 <indexterm id='idxadvertising' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
7753 <indexterm id='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='startofrange'><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>trailer advertisements of</secondary></indexterm>
7754 <para>
7755 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7756 in the business of making <quote>trailer</quote> advertisements for movies available
7757 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7758 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7759 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7760 </para>
7761 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7762 <para>
7763 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it began
7764 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7765 previews. The idea was to expand their <quote>selling by sampling</quote>
7766 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7767 <quote>browsing.</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7768 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7769 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7770 </para>
7771 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
7772 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7773 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7774 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
7775 <para>
7776 In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7777 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7778 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7779 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7780 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7781 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter&mdash;he had built a
7782 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7783 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7784 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7785 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7786 <quote>fair use</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7787 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7788 their rights.
7789 </para>
7790 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising' class='endofrange'/>
7791 <indexterm startref='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='endofrange'/>
7792 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7793 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>willful infringement findings in</secondary></indexterm>
7794 <indexterm><primary>willful infringement</primary></indexterm>
7795 <para>
7796 Disney countersued&mdash;for $100 million in damages. Those damages
7797 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had <quote>willfully
7798 infringed</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7799 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7800 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7801 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7802 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7803 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $100 million.
7804 </para>
7805 <para>
7806 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7807 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7808 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7809 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7810 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7811 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7812 Disney's permission.
7813 </para>
7814 <indexterm><primary>first-sale doctrine</primary></indexterm>
7815 <para>
7816 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7817 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7818 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7819 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7820 was in the marketplace, the <quote>first-sale doctrine</quote> would free the
7821 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7822 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7823 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7824 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7825 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7826 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7827 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7828 </para>
7829 <indexterm startref='idxvideopipeline' class='endofrange'/>
7830 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc2' class='endofrange'/>
7831 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='endofrange'/>
7832 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='endofrange'/>
7833 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='endofrange'/>
7834 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='endofrange'/>
7835 <indexterm><primary>Barnes &amp; Noble</primary></indexterm>
7836 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7837 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
7838 <para>
7839 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7840 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7841 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes &amp; Noble has the
7842 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7843 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7844 abuse. If Barnes &amp; Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7845 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7846 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7847 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7848 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7849 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7850 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7851 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7852 happening are quite slight.
7853 </para>
7854 <para>
7855 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7856 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7857 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7858 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7859 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7860 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7861 </para>
7862 </section>
7863 <section id="lawforce">
7864 <title>Architecture and Law: Force</title>
7865 <para>
7866 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7867 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7868 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7869 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7870 </para>
7871 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>technology as automatic enforcer of</secondary></indexterm>
7872 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright enforcement controlled by</secondary></indexterm>
7873 <para>
7874 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7875 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7876 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7877 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7878 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7879 your freedom.
7880 </para>
7881 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca</primary></indexterm>
7882 <indexterm id='idxmarxbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7883 <indexterm id='idxwarnerbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7884 <para>
7885 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7886 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7887 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7888 <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7889 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7890 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7891 plan.<footnote><para>
7892 <!-- f19 -->
7893 See David Lange, <quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7894 Contemporary Problems</citetitle> 44 (1981): 172&ndash;73.
7895 </para></footnote>
7896 </para>
7897 <para>
7898 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7899 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers <quote>were brothers long before
7900 you were.</quote><footnote><para>
7901 <!-- f20 -->
7902 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
7903 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and
7904 Copywrongs</citetitle>, 1&ndash;3.
7905 </para></footnote>
7906 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7907 <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7908 trying to control <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>, then the Marx
7909 Brothers would insist on control over <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>.
7910 </para>
7911 <para>
7912 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7913 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7914 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7915 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7916 </para>
7917 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7918 <para>
7919 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7920 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7921 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7922 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7923 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7924 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7925 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7926 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7927 </para>
7928 <indexterm startref='idxwarnerbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7929 <indexterm startref='idxmarxbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7930
7931 <indexterm id='idxadobeebookreader' class='startofrange'><primary>Adobe eBook Reader</primary></indexterm>
7932 <para>
7933 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7934 </para>
7935 <para>
7936 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7937 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7938 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7939 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7940 technology.
7941 </para>
7942 <para>
7943 In <xref linkend="fig-1611"/> is a picture of an old version of my
7944 Adobe eBook Reader.
7945 </para>
7946 <para>
7947 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7948 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7949 public domain: <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, for example, is in
7950 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7951 public domain: My own book <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
7952 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7953 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7954 copy of
7955 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7956 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7957 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
7958 </para>
7959 <figure id="fig-1611">
7960 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader</title>
7961 <graphic fileref="images/1611.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7962 </figure>
7963 <para>
7964 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7965 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7966 </para>
7967 <figure id="fig-1612">
7968 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.</title>
7969 <graphic fileref="images/1612.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7970 </figure>
7971 <para>
7972 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7973 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
7974 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
7975 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
7976 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
7977 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>
7978 read aloud through the computer.
7979 </para>
7980 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle</primary></indexterm>
7981 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics</citetitle>, (Aristotle)</primary></indexterm>
7982 <para>
7983 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7984 translation): Aristotle's <citetitle>Politics</citetitle>.
7985 </para>
7986 <figure id="fig-1621">
7987 <title>E-book of Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote></title>
7988 <graphic fileref="images/1621.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7989 </figure>
7990 <para>
7991 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7992 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
7993 the book.
7994 </para>
7995 <figure id="fig-1622">
7996 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote>.</title>
7997 <graphic fileref="images/1622.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7998 </figure>
7999 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
8000 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
8001 <para>
8002 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
8003 original e-book version of my last book, <citetitle>The Future of
8004 Ideas</citetitle>:
8005 </para>
8006 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
8007 <figure id="fig-1631">
8008 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>The Future of Ideas</quote>.</title>
8009 <graphic fileref="images/1631.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8010 </figure>
8011 <para>
8012 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
8013 </para>
8014 <para>
8015 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
8016 <quote>permissions</quote>&mdash; as if the publisher has the power to control how
8017 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
8018 certainly does have the power&mdash;up to the limits of the copyright
8019 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
8020 power.<footnote><para>
8021 <!-- f21 -->
8022 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
8023 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
8024 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
8025 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
8026 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
8027 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
8028 subsequently acquired the book.
8029 </para></footnote>
8030 When my e-book of <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> says I have the
8031 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
8032 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
8033 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
8034 control that the law would enable.
8035 </para>
8036 <para>
8037 The control comes instead from the code&mdash;from the technology
8038 within which the e-book <quote>lives.</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
8039 permissions, they are not the sort of <quote>permissions</quote> that most of us
8040 deal with. When a teenager gets <quote>permission</quote> to stay out till
8041 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
8042 till 2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
8043 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
8044 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
8045 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
8046 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
8047 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
8048 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
8049 aloud&mdash;it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
8050 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
8051 won't read aloud.
8052 </para>
8053 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8054 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8055 <para>
8056 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
8057 These are <emphasis>controls</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
8058 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
8059 you tried to type <quote>Warner Brothers,</quote> erased <quote>Brothers</quote> from the
8060 sentence.
8061 </para>
8062 <para>
8063 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
8064 <emphasis>law</emphasis> as copyright <emphasis>code</emphasis>. The
8065 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
8066 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
8067 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
8068 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
8069 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
8070 </para>
8071 <para>
8072 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
8073 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
8074 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
8075 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
8076 to defeat these protections as well?
8077 </para>
8078 <para>
8079 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
8080 eBook Reader.
8081 </para>
8082 <indexterm id='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='startofrange'><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)</primary></indexterm>
8083 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>e-book restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
8084 <para>
8085 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
8086 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
8087 on the Adobe site was a copy of <citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
8088 Wonderland</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
8089 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
8090 following report:
8091 </para>
8092 <figure id="fig-1641">
8093 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>Alice's Adventures in
8094 Wonderland</quote>.</title>
8095 <graphic fileref="images/1641.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8096 </figure>
8097 <!-- PAGE BREAK 164-->
8098 <para>
8099 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
8100 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
8101 <quote>permissions</quote> indicated, not allowed to <quote>read aloud</quote>!
8102 </para>
8103 <para>
8104 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
8105 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
8106 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
8107 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
8108 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
8109 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
8110 </para>
8111 <para>
8112 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
8113 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
8114 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
8115 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
8116 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
8117 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
8118 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
8119 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
8120 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
8121 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
8122 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
8123 </para>
8124 <indexterm startref='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='endofrange'/>
8125 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='endofrange'/>
8126 <para>
8127 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
8128 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
8129 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
8130 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
8131 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
8132 often crazy.
8133 </para>
8134 <indexterm startref='idxadobeebookreader' class='endofrange'/>
8135 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet2' class='endofrange'/>
8136 <para>
8137 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
8138 story of mine that makes the same point.
8139 </para>
8140 <indexterm id='idxaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8141 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog1' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8142 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8143 <para>
8144 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named <quote>Aibo.</quote> The Aibo
8145 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
8146 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
8147 </para>
8148 <para>
8149 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
8150 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
8151 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
8152 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
8153 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
8154 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
8155 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
8156 </para>
8157 <para>
8158 <quote>Teach</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
8159 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
8160 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
8161 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
8162 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
8163 their computer <quote>dog</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
8164 </para>
8165 <indexterm><primary>hacks</primary></indexterm>
8166 <para>
8167 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
8168 <citetitle>hack</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
8169 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
8170 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
8171 them, <citetitle>hack</citetitle> is a much more positive
8172 term. <citetitle>Hack</citetitle> just means code that enables the
8173 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
8174 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
8175 old computer doesn't run, or <quote>drive,</quote> the printer. If you discovered
8176 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
8177 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
8178 you just bought.
8179 </para>
8180 <para>
8181 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
8182 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
8183 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
8184 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
8185 ethically.
8186 </para>
8187 <para>
8188 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
8189 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
8190 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
8191 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
8192 than Sony had built.
8193 </para>
8194 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8195 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog1' class='endofrange'/>
8196 <indexterm startref='idxaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8197 <para>
8198 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
8199 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
8200 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
8201 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
8202 the
8203
8204 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
8205 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
8206 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
8207 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
8208 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
8209 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
8210 thought, <emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
8211 a robot dog to dance?</emphasis>
8212 </para>
8213 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>government case against</secondary></indexterm>
8214 <para>
8215 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show&mdash;
8216 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
8217 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
8218 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
8219 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
8220 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
8221 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
8222 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
8223 into being silent about something he knew very well.
8224 </para>
8225 <para>
8226 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.<footnote><para>
8227 <!-- f22 -->
8228 See Pamela Samuelson, <quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,</quote>
8229 <citetitle>Science</citetitle> 293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, <quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
8230 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect</citetitle>,
8231 January 2002; <quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
8232 DMCA,</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter</citetitle>, 11 December 2001; Bill
8233 Holland, <quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,</quote> <citetitle>Billboard</citetitle>,
8234 May 2001; Janelle Brown, <quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?</quote> Salon.com,
8235 April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, <quote>Frequently Asked
8236 Questions about <citetitle>Felten and USENIX</citetitle> v. <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> Legal Case,</quote> available at
8237 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #27</ulink>.
8238 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
8239 </para></footnote>
8240 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
8241 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
8242 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
8243 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
8244 </para>
8245 <para>
8246 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
8247 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
8248 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
8249 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
8250 <quote>this music cannot be copied,</quote> and have a computer respect that
8251 command. The technology was to be part of a <quote>trusted system</quote> of
8252 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
8253 Internet much more.
8254 </para>
8255 <para>
8256 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
8257 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
8258 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
8259 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
8260 </para>
8261 <para>
8262 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
8263 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
8264 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
8265 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
8266 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
8267 </para>
8268 <para>
8269 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
8270 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
8271 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
8272 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
8273 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
8274 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
8275 </para>
8276 <para>
8277 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
8278 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
8279 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
8280 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
8281 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
8282 constituted, succeed.
8283 </para>
8284 <indexterm id='idxaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8285 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog2' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8286 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8287 <para>
8288 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
8289 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
8290 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
8291 wrote:
8292 </para>
8293 <blockquote>
8294 <para>
8295 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
8296 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
8297 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
8298 </para>
8299 </blockquote>
8300 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8301 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog2' class='endofrange'/>
8302 <indexterm startref='idxaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8303 <para>
8304 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
8305 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
8306 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
8307 </para>
8308 <blockquote>
8309 <para>
8310 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
8311 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
8312 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
8313 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
8314 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (<quote>DMCA</quote>).
8315 </para>
8316 </blockquote>
8317 <para>
8318 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
8319 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
8320 spreading such information an offense.
8321 </para>
8322 <para>
8323 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
8324 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
8325 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
8326 These new technologies would be copyright protection
8327 technologies&mdash; technologies to control the replication and
8328 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
8329 <emphasis>code</emphasis> to modify the original
8330 <emphasis>code</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
8331 protection for copyright owners.
8332 </para>
8333 <para>
8334 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
8335 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
8336 <emphasis>legal code</emphasis> intended to buttress
8337 <emphasis>software code</emphasis> which itself was intended to
8338 support the <emphasis>legal code of copyright</emphasis>.
8339 </para>
8340 <para>
8341 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
8342 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
8343 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
8344 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
8345 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
8346 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
8347 have been a copyright violation.
8348 </para>
8349 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8350 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8351 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8352 <para>
8353 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
8354 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
8355 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
8356 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
8357 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
8358 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
8359 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
8360 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
8361 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
8362 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
8363 </para>
8364 <para>
8365 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
8366 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
8367 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
8368 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
8369 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
8370 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
8371 </para>
8372 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8373 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8374 <para>
8375 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
8376 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
8377 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
8378 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
8379 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
8380 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka <quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers</citetitle>,</quote>
8381 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
8382 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
8383 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8384 </para>
8385 <blockquote>
8386 <para>
8387 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
8388 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
8389 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
8390 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
8391 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
8392 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the <quote>Neighborhood</quote>
8393 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
8394 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
8395 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
8396 broadcasting has always been <quote>You are an important person just the way
8397 you are. You can make healthy decisions.</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
8398 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
8399 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
8400 important.<footnote><para>
8401 <!-- f23 -->
8402 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8403 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
8404 455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
8405 James Lardner, <citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
8406 the VCR</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270&ndash;71.
8407 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8408 </para></footnote>
8409 </para>
8410 </blockquote>
8411 <para>
8412 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
8413 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
8414 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
8415 the VCR responsible.
8416 </para>
8417 <para>
8418 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
8419 the DMCA.
8420 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8421 </para>
8422 <para>
8423 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
8424 </para>
8425 <para>
8426 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
8427 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
8428 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
8429 pirating of copyrighted material&mdash;a bad end. Or they can be used
8430 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
8431 would be considered fair use&mdash;a good end.
8432 </para>
8433 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'><primary>handguns</primary></indexterm>
8434 <para>
8435 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
8436 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
8437 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
8438 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
8439 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
8440 and bad uses.
8441 </para>
8442 <figure id="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig">
8443 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.</title>
8444 <graphic fileref="images/1711.png" align="center" width="70%"></graphic>
8445 </figure>
8446 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8447 <para>
8448 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
8449 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
8450 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: <emphasis>No one ever
8451 died from copyright circumvention</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
8452 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
8453 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
8454 </para>
8455 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'/>
8456 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'/>
8457 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8458 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8459 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8460 <para>
8461 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
8462 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
8463 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
8464 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
8465 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
8466 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
8467 </para>
8468 <para>
8469 This is how <emphasis>code</emphasis> becomes
8470 <emphasis>law</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
8471 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
8472 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
8473 law&mdash;increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
8474 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
8475 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
8476 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect&mdash;at
8477 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
8478 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
8479 </para>
8480 <para>
8481 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
8482 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
8483 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
8484 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
8485 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
8486 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
8487 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
8488 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
8489 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
8490 </para>
8491 <para>
8492
8493 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
8494 For example, imagine you were part of a <citetitle>Star Trek</citetitle> fan club. You
8495 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
8496 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
8497 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
8498 simply continue it.<footnote><para>
8499 <!-- f24 -->
8500 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, <quote>Legal Fictions,
8501 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
8502 Entertainment Law Journal</citetitle> 17 (1997): 651.
8503 </para></footnote>
8504 </para>
8505 <para>
8506 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
8507 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
8508 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
8509 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
8510 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
8511 </para>
8512 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
8513 <para>
8514 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
8515 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
8516 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
8517 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
8518 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
8519 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
8520 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
8521 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
8522 </para>
8523 <para>
8524 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
8525 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
8526 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
8527 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8528 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8529 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8530 </para>
8531 </section>
8532 <section id="marketconcentration">
8533 <title>Market: Concentration</title>
8534 <para>
8535 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically&mdash;tripled in
8536 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8537 well&mdash;from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8538 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8539 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8540 find better ways
8541 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8542 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8543 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8544 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8545 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8546 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8547 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8548 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8549 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8550 control.
8551 </para>
8552 <para>
8553 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8554 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8555 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8556 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8557 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8558 </para>
8559 <para>
8560 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8561 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8562 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8563 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8564 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8565 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8566 announced in June 2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8567 live in a world where just three companies control more than 85 percent
8568 of the media.
8569 </para>
8570 <para>
8571 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8572 nature.
8573 </para>
8574 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8575 <indexterm><primary>BMG</primary></indexterm>
8576 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
8577 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John</primary></indexterm>
8578 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8579 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8580 <para>
8581 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8582 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8583 ownership, <quote>five companies control 85 percent of our media sources.</quote><footnote><para>
8584 <!-- f25 -->
8585 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8586 Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003)
8587 (statement of Senator John McCain). </para></footnote>
8588 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8589 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 percent of the
8590 U.S. music market.<footnote><para>
8591 <!-- f26 -->
8592 Lynette Holloway, <quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8593 Slide,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 23 December 2002.
8594 </para></footnote>
8595 The <quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8596 programming to 74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.</quote><footnote><para>
8597 <!-- f27 -->
8598 Molly Ivins, <quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette</citetitle>,
8599 31 May 2003.
8600 </para></footnote>
8601 </para>
8602 <para>
8603 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8604 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8605 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8606 seventy-five stations. Today <emphasis>one</emphasis> company owns
8607 more than 1,200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8608 total number of radio owners dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most
8609 markets, the two largest broadcasters control 74 percent of that
8610 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control 90 percent of
8611 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8612 </para>
8613 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8614 <para>
8615 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8616 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8617 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8618 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8619 the United States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all
8620 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent
8621 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8622 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8623 protected&mdash; by the market.
8624 </para>
8625 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8626 <para>
8627 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8628 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8629 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8630 </para>
8631 <blockquote>
8632 <para>
8633 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8634 unmatched in its integration. They supply content&mdash;Fox movies
8635 &hellip; Fox TV shows &hellip; Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8636 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8637 advertisers&mdash;in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8638 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8639 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8640 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8641 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8642 the same function in the United States.<footnote><para>
8643 <!-- f28 -->
8644 James Fallows, <quote>The Age of Murdoch,</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly</citetitle> (September
8645 2003): 89.
8646 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8647 </para></footnote>
8648 </para>
8649 </blockquote>
8650 <para>
8651 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8652 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8653 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8654 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8655 </para>
8656 <figure id="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership">
8657 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.</title>
8658 <graphic fileref="images/1761.png" align="center" width="90%"></graphic>
8659 </figure>
8660 <para>
8661 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8662 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8663 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8664 distribute content?
8665 </para>
8666 <para>
8667 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8668 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8669 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8670 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8671 </para>
8672 <para>
8673 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8674 integration may matter.
8675 </para>
8676 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman</primary></indexterm>
8677 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8678 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8679 <para>
8680 In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle>. He took
8681 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8682 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8683 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8684 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8685 </para>
8686 <para>
8687 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8688 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8689 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8690 control.<footnote><para>
8691 <!-- f29 -->
8692 Leonard Hill, <quote>The Axis of Access,</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8693 Forum, <quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,</quote> St. Louis,
8694 Missouri, 3 April 2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8695 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #28</ulink>;
8696 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8697 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #29</ulink>).
8698 </para></footnote>
8699 </para>
8700 <para>
8701
8702 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8703 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8704 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8705 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8706 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992,
8707 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8708 television&mdash;75 percent of it&mdash;was <quote>independent</quote> of the
8709 networks.
8710 </para>
8711 <para>
8712 In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8713 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985,
8714 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8715 2002, only five independent television studios remained. <quote>In 1992,
8716 only 15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8717 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8718 controlled companies more than quintupled to 77 percent.</quote> <quote>In 1992, 16
8719 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8720 year there was one.</quote><footnote><para>
8721 <!-- f30 -->
8722 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8723 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st
8724 sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8725 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8726 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8727 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8728 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February
8729 2003.
8730 </para></footnote>
8731 In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8732 that ran it. <quote>In the ten-year period between 1992 and 2002, the number
8733 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8734 increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8735 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8736 63%.</quote><footnote><para>
8737 <!-- f31 -->
8738 Ibid.
8739 </para></footnote>
8740 </para>
8741 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8742 <para>
8743 Today, another Norman Lear with another <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle> would
8744 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8745 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8746 owned by the network.
8747 </para>
8748 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry</primary></indexterm>
8749 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill</primary></indexterm>
8750 <para>
8751 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8752 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8753 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8754 </para>
8755 <blockquote>
8756 <para>
8757 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8758 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8759 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8760 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8761 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8762 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8763 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8764 handful.<footnote><para>
8765 <!-- f32 -->
8766 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers</citetitle>, Bill
8767 Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at
8768 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #31</ulink>.
8769 </para></footnote>
8770 </para>
8771 </blockquote>
8772 <para>
8773 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8774 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8775 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8776 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8777 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8778 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8779 question without risk of consequence&mdash;not necessarily banishment
8780 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8781 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8782 democracy.
8783 </para>
8784 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.</primary></indexterm>
8785 <para>
8786 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8787 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the <quote>Innovator's
8788 Dilemma</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8789 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8790 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8791 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.<footnote><para>
8792 <!-- f33 -->
8793 Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8794 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle>
8795 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press, 1997). Christensen
8796 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8797 Kim B. Clark, <quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8798 Concepts in Technological Evolution,</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy</citetitle> 14 (1985):
8799 235&ndash;51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8800 Kaplan, <citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8801 Underperform the Market&mdash;and How to Successfully Transform Them</citetitle>
8802 (New York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001). </para></footnote>
8803
8804 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8805 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8806 sprinting.
8807 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
8808 </para>
8809 <para>
8810 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8811 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8812 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8813 measure.
8814 </para>
8815 <para>
8816 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8817 suggest the concern.
8818 </para>
8819 <para>
8820 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8821 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8822 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8823 </para>
8824 <para>
8825 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8826 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8827 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8828
8829 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8830 wrecked by drugs&mdash;though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8831 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8832 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8833 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8834 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8835 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8836 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8837 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8838 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8839 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8840 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8841 outweigh these costs.
8842 </para>
8843 <para>
8844 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8845 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8846 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8847 these issues.
8848 </para>
8849 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8850 <indexterm id='idxcommercials' class='startofrange'><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
8851 <indexterm id='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='startofrange'><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
8852 <indexterm><primary>Nick and Norm anti-drug campaign</primary></indexterm>
8853 <para>
8854 Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8855 a media campaign as part of the <quote>war on drugs.</quote> The campaign produced
8856 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8857 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8858 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8859 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8860 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8861 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8862 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8863 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8864 </para>
8865 <para>
8866 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8867 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8868 </para>
8869 <para>
8870 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8871 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8872 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8873 war. Can you do it?
8874 </para>
8875 <para>
8876 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8877 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8878 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8879 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8880 message will be heard then?
8881 </para>
8882 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
8883 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
8884 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on television advertising bans</secondary></indexterm>
8885 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>controversy avoided by</secondary></indexterm>
8886 <para>
8887 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8888 <quote>controversial</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8889 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8890 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8891 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8892 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8893 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8894 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8895 rights of the stations to be this biased.<footnote><para>
8896 <!-- f34 -->
8897 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8898 <indexterm><primary>Comcast</primary></indexterm>
8899 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project</primary></indexterm>
8900 <indexterm><primary>NBC</primary></indexterm>
8901 <indexterm><primary>WJOA</primary></indexterm>
8902 <indexterm><primary>WRC</primary></indexterm>
8903 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8904 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads
8905 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8906 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as <quote>against
8907 [their] policy.</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8908 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8909 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8910 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8911 Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8912 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, <quote>On the
8913 Issue of an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV
8914 Networks,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 13 March
8915 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time there is very little
8916 that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to even the playing
8917 field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, <quote>Ad Hoc Access:
8918 The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8919 Radio,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review</citetitle> 6
8920 (1988): 449&ndash;79, and for a more recent summary of the stance of
8921 the FCC and the courts, see <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors
8922 Association</citetitle> v. <citetitle>FCC</citetitle>, 184 F. 3d 872
8923 (D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8924 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8925 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8926 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, <quote>Antidiesel Group
8927 Fuming After Muni Rejects Ad,</quote> SFGate.com, 16 June 2003,
8928 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
8929 #32</ulink>. The ground was that the criticism was <quote>too
8930 controversial.</quote>
8931 </para></footnote>
8932 </para>
8933 <indexterm startref='idxcommercials' class='endofrange'/>
8934 <indexterm startref='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='endofrange'/>
8935 <para>
8936 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well&mdash;if we lived
8937 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8938 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8939 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8940 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8941 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8942 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8943 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8944 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8945 </para>
8946 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'/>
8947 </section>
8948 <section id="together">
8949 <title>Together</title>
8950 <para>
8951 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8952 copyright warriors that the government should <quote>protect my property.</quote>
8953 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8954 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8955 </para>
8956 <para>
8957 But when we see how dramatically this <quote>property</quote> has changed&mdash;
8958 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8959 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8960 cultivate our culture is dramatically different&mdash;the claim begins
8961 to seem
8962
8963 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8964 less innocent and obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to
8965 supplement the law's control, and (2) the power of concentrated
8966 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8967 the massively expanded <quote>property</quote> rights granted by copyright
8968 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8969 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8970 be redefined.
8971 </para>
8972 <para>
8973 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8974 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8975 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8976 our culture today.
8977 </para>
8978 <para>
8979 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8980 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8981 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8982 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8983 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8984 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8985 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8986 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8987 traditionally defined copyright's regulation&mdash;a weakening of that
8988 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
8989 </para>
8990 <para>
8991 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
8992 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
8993 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
8994 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
8995 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
8996 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
8997 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
8998 future. And these changes have to be <emphasis>reductions</emphasis>
8999 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
9000 in control that technology and the market enable.
9001 </para>
9002 <para>
9003 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
9004 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
9005 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
9006 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
9007 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
9008 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
9009 more of the development of our culture than now</emphasis>.
9010 </para>
9011 <para>
9012 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
9013 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
9014 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
9015 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
9016 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
9017 were independent of the networks. <emphasis>Never</emphasis> has
9018 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
9019 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
9020 regulation&mdash;a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
9021 energy of a nation at the founding&mdash;is now a massive regulation
9022 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
9023 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
9024 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
9025 known.<footnote><para>
9026 <!-- f35 -->
9027 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
9028 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his <quote>four surrenders</quote> of
9029 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan, 159&ndash;60.
9030 </para></footnote>
9031 </para>
9032 <para>
9033 <emphasis role='strong'>This has been</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
9034 point can now be briefly stated.
9035 </para>
9036 <para>
9037 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
9038 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
9039 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
9040 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
9041 that copyright law has undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this:
9042 </para>
9043
9044 <informaltable id="t2">
9045 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9046 <thead>
9047 <row>
9048 <entry></entry>
9049 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9050 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9051 </row>
9052 </thead>
9053 <tbody>
9054 <row>
9055 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9056 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9057 <entry>Free</entry>
9058 </row>
9059 <row>
9060 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9061 <entry>Free</entry>
9062 <entry>Free</entry>
9063 </row>
9064 </tbody>
9065 </tgroup>
9066 </informaltable>
9067
9068 <para>
9069 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
9070 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
9071 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
9072
9073 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
9074 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
9075 noncommercial work was also free.
9076 </para>
9077 <para>
9078 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
9079 </para>
9080
9081 <informaltable id="t3">
9082 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9083 <thead>
9084 <row>
9085 <entry></entry>
9086 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9087 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9088 </row>
9089 </thead>
9090 <tbody>
9091 <row>
9092 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9093 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9094 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9095 </row>
9096 <row>
9097 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9098 <entry>Free</entry>
9099 <entry>Free</entry>
9100 </row>
9101 </tbody>
9102 </tgroup>
9103 </informaltable>
9104
9105 <para>
9106 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law&mdash;if
9107 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
9108 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
9109 transformation were still essentially free.
9110 </para>
9111 <para>
9112 In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
9113 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
9114 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
9115 expanded. Thus by 1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
9116 we could say the law began to look like this:
9117 </para>
9118
9119 <informaltable id="t4">
9120 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9121 <thead>
9122 <row>
9123 <entry></entry>
9124 <entry>COPY</entry>
9125 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9126 </row>
9127 </thead>
9128 <tbody>
9129 <row>
9130 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9131 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9132 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9133 </row>
9134 <row>
9135 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9136 <entry>&copy; / Free</entry>
9137 <entry>Free</entry>
9138 </row>
9139 </tbody>
9140 </tgroup>
9141 </informaltable>
9142
9143 <para>
9144 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
9145 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
9146 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
9147 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
9148 that the law now looks like this:
9149 </para>
9150
9151 <informaltable id="t5">
9152 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9153 <thead>
9154 <row>
9155 <entry></entry>
9156 <entry>COPY</entry>
9157 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9158 </row>
9159 </thead>
9160 <tbody>
9161 <row>
9162 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9163 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9164 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9165 </row>
9166 <row>
9167 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9168 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9169 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9170 </row>
9171 </tbody>
9172 </tgroup>
9173 </informaltable>
9174
9175 <para>
9176 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
9177 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
9178 creativity&mdash;
9179 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
9180 commercial or not, transformative or not&mdash;with the same rules
9181 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
9182 </para>
9183 <para>
9184 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
9185 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
9186 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
9187 these domains actually does any good.
9188 </para>
9189 <para>
9190 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
9191 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
9192 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
9193 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
9194 reasons sketched especially in chapters
9195 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/> and
9196 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>, one
9197 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
9198 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
9199 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
9200 </para>
9201 <para>
9202 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
9203 course copyright is a kind of <quote>property,</quote> and of course, as with any
9204 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
9205 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
9206 property rights<footnote><para>
9207 <!-- f36 -->
9208 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement</primary></indexterm>
9209 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
9210 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
9211 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, <quote>The
9212 Disintegration of Property,</quote> in <citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property</citetitle>, J. Roland
9213 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
9214 Press, 1980).
9215 </para></footnote>)
9216 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
9217 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
9218 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
9219 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the <quote>copyright</quote>
9220 did not control <emphasis>at all</emphasis> the freedom of others to
9221 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
9222 free, and for almost 180 years our country consistently protected a
9223 vibrant and rich free culture.
9224 </para>
9225 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
9226 <para>
9227 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
9228 limits on the scope of the interests protected by <quote>property.</quote> The very
9229 birth of <quote>copyright</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
9230 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
9231 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9232 linkend="founders"/>). The tradition of <quote>fair use</quote> is
9233 animated by a similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the
9234 costs of exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the
9235 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9236 linkend="recorders"/>). Adding
9237 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
9238 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
9239 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter <xref
9240 xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>). And
9241 granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect, claims of
9242 property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing the soul
9243 of a culture (chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9244 linkend="collectors"/>). Free cultures, like free markets, are built
9245 with property. But the nature of the property that builds a free
9246 culture is very different from the extremist vision that dominates the
9247 debate today.
9248 </para>
9249 <para>
9250 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
9251 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
9252 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
9253 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
9254 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
9255 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
9256 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
9257 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
9258 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
9259 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
9260 lawyer.
9261 </para>
9262 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
9263 </section>
9264 </chapter>
9265 </part>
9266 <part id="c-puzzles">
9267 <title>PUZZLES</title>
9268
9269 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
9270 <chapter label="11" id="chimera">
9271 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera</title>
9272 <indexterm id='idxchimera' class='startofrange'><primary>chimeras</primary></indexterm>
9273 <indexterm id='idxwells' class='startofrange'><primary>Wells, H. G.</primary></indexterm>
9274 <indexterm id='idxtcotb' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The</quote> (Wells)</primary></indexterm>
9275
9276 <para>
9277 <emphasis role='strong'>In a well-known</emphasis> short story by
9278 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
9279 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
9280 Andes.<footnote><para>
9281 <!-- f1. -->
9282 H. G. Wells, <quote>The Country of the Blind</quote> (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells,
9283 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
9284 York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
9285 </para></footnote>
9286 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with <quote>sweet water, pasture,
9287 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
9288 that bore an excellent fruit.</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
9289 takes this as an opportunity. <quote>In the Country of the Blind,</quote> he tells
9290 himself, <quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.</quote> So he resolves to live with the
9291 villagers to explore life as a king.
9292 </para>
9293 <para>
9294 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
9295 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
9296 <quote>blind.</quote> They don't have the word <citetitle>blind</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
9297 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
9298 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
9299 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. <quote>`You
9300 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
9301 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
9302 alone!'</quote>
9303 </para>
9304 <para>
9305 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
9306 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
9307 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
9308 affection, a young woman who to him seems <quote>the most beautiful thing in
9309 the whole of creation,</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
9310 description of what he sees <quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
9311 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
9312 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
9313 indulgence.</quote> <quote>She did not believe,</quote> Wells tells us, and <quote>she could
9314 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.</quote>
9315 </para>
9316 <para>
9317 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his <quote>mysteriously delighted</quote>
9318 love, the father and the village object. <quote>You see, my dear,</quote> her
9319 father instructs, <quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
9320 anything right.</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
9321 </para>
9322 <para>
9323 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. <quote>His brain
9324 is affected,</quote> he reports.
9325 </para>
9326 <para>
9327 <quote>What affects it?</quote> the father asks. <quote>Those queer things that are
9328 called the eyes &hellip; are diseased &hellip; in such a way as to affect
9329 his brain.</quote>
9330 </para>
9331 <para>
9332 The doctor continues: <quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
9333 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
9334 simple and easy surgical operation&mdash;namely, to remove these
9335 irritant bodies [the eyes].</quote>
9336 </para>
9337 <para>
9338 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
9339 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
9340 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
9341 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
9342 </para>
9343 <para>
9344 <emphasis role='strong'>It sometimes</emphasis> happens that the eggs
9345 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
9346 <quote>chimera.</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
9347 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
9348 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
9349
9350 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
9351 plot for murder mysteries. <quote>But the DNA shows with 100 percent
9352 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
9353 scene. &hellip;</quote>
9354 </para>
9355 <indexterm startref='idxtcotb' class='endofrange'/>
9356 <indexterm startref='idxwells' class="endofrange"/>
9357 <para>
9358 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
9359 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
9360 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
9361 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
9362 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
9363 understanding of a <quote>person</quote> should reflect this reality.
9364 </para>
9365 <para>
9366 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
9367 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
9368 unfairly enough, <quote>the copyright wars,</quote> the more I think we're dealing
9369 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question <quote>What is
9370 p2p file sharing?</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
9371 wrong. One side says, <quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
9372 others' records&mdash;the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
9373 thirty years without any question at all.</quote> That's true, at least in
9374 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
9375 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
9376 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
9377 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
9378 </para>
9379 <para>
9380 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
9381 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
9382 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
9383 <quote>friends</quote> beyond recognition to say <quote>my ten thousand best friends</quote> can
9384 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
9385 what <quote>we have always been allowed to do,</quote> we have not always been
9386 allowed to share music with <quote>our ten thousand best friends.</quote>
9387 </para>
9388 <para>
9389 Likewise, when the other side says, <quote>File sharing is just like walking
9390 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
9391 with it,</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
9392 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
9393 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
9394 from Tower.
9395 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9396 </para>
9397 <para>
9398
9399 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
9400 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
9401 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
9402 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
9403 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
9404 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
9405 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
9406 $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
9407 CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.)
9408 </para>
9409 <para>
9410 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
9411 that it is both&mdash;both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
9412 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
9413 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
9414 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
9415 </para>
9416 <para>
9417 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
9418 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
9419 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
9420 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
9421 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
9422 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
9423 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
9424 implemented.<footnote><para>
9425 <!-- f2. -->
9426 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9427 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
9428 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
9429 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003,
9430 available at
9431 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9432 #33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
9433 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
9434 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
9435 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, <quote>House Bill Aims to Up
9436 Stakes on Piracy,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 17 July 2003, available at
9437 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #34</ulink>. Civil
9438 penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied song. For a recent
9439 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
9440 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 songs
9441 through a family computer, see <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
9442 re. Verizon Internet Services)</citetitle>, 240 F. Supp. 2d 24
9443 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $90
9444 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
9445 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
9446 $12,000 to $17,500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
9447 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $98
9448 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
9449 Elizabeth Young, <quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,</quote> redandblack.com,
9450 August 2003, available at
9451 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #35</ulink>. For an
9452 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
9453 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
9454 identities, see James Collins, <quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
9455 Name Students,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 8 August 2003, D3, available at
9456 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #36</ulink>.
9457 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
9458 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
9459 </para></footnote>
9460
9461 </para>
9462 <indexterm startref='idxchimera' class='endofrange'/>
9463 <para>
9464 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
9465 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
9466 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
9467 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
9468 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
9469 </para>
9470 <para>
9471 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
9472 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
9473 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
9474 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
9475 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
9476 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe <emphasis>either</emphasis> extreme
9477 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
9478 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
9479 </para>
9480 <para>
9481
9482 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
9483 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
9484 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
9485 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
9486 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
9487 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
9488 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
9489 </para>
9490 <para>
9491 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to <quote>steal</quote> music. My
9492 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
9493 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
9494 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
9495 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
9496 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
9497 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
9498 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
9499 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
9500 protection for copyrighted material,
9501 </para>
9502 <blockquote>
9503 <para>
9504 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
9505 material, and we want to protect those rights.
9506 </para>
9507 <para>
9508 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
9509 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
9510 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
9511 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
9512 produce a totally different industry model.
9513 </para>
9514 <para>
9515 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
9516 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
9517 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
9518 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
9519 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
9520 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
9521 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
9522 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
9523 interests.<footnote><para>
9524 <!-- f3. -->
9525 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
9526 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
9527 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
9528 House Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement of Peter
9529 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
9530 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
9531 Congressional Testimony File. </para></footnote>
9532 </para>
9533 </blockquote>
9534 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
9535 <para>
9536 In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
9537 one of <quote>the major labels.</quote> Its position on these matters has now
9538 changed.
9539 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9540 </para>
9541 <para>
9542 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
9543 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9544 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9545 </para>
9546
9547 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9548 </chapter>
9549 <chapter label="12" id="harms">
9550 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms</title>
9551 <para>
9552 <emphasis role='strong'>To fight</emphasis> <quote>piracy,</quote> to
9553 protect <quote>property,</quote> the content industry has launched a
9554 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9555 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9556 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9557 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9558 </para>
9559 <para>
9560 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9561 particular, the consequences for <quote>free culture.</quote> But my aim now is to
9562 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9563 justified?
9564 </para>
9565 <para>
9566 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9567 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9568 power of the property called <quote>intellectual property</quote> is at its greatest in
9569 our history.
9570 </para>
9571 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
9572 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
9573 <para>
9574 Yet <quote>common sense</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9575 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9576 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9577 rejection of <quote>piracy</quote> still has play.
9578 </para>
9579 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9580 <para>
9581 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9582 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9583 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9584 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9585 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9586 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9587 </para>
9588 <section id="constrain">
9589 <title>Constraining Creators</title>
9590 <para>
9591 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9592 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9593 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9594 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9595 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9596 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9597 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9598 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9599 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9600 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9601 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9602 weave together a string&mdash;a mash-up&mdash; of songs from your
9603 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9604 </para>
9605 <para>
9606 This digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> is in part an extension of the
9607 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9608 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9609 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9610 of digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9611 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9612 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9613 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9614 the culture all around.
9615 </para>
9616 <para>
9617 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9618 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9619
9620 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9621
9622 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9623 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9624 storytelling extended across the globe.
9625 </para>
9626 <para>
9627 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9628 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9629 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9630 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9631 that catalog cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9632 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9633 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9634 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9635 work is presumptively illegal.
9636 </para>
9637 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom</primary></indexterm>
9638 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9639 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9640 <indexterm><primary>doctors malpractice claims against</primary></indexterm>
9641 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
9642 <para>
9643 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9644 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9645 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9646 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9647 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9648 by the RIAA (Jesse Jordan of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9649 labelnumber" linkend="catalogs"/> was just one) were threatened with a
9650 $98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted songs
9651 to be copied. Yet World-Com&mdash;which defrauded investors of $11
9652 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization of
9653 over $200 billion&mdash;received a fine of a mere $750
9654 million.<footnote><para>
9655 <!-- f1. -->
9656 See Lynne W. Jeter, <citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom</citetitle>
9657 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley &amp; Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of
9658 the settlement, see MCI press release, <quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9659 Approval for SEC Settlement</quote> (7 July 2003), available at
9660 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #37</ulink>.
9661 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom</primary></indexterm>
9662 </para></footnote>
9663 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9664 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9665 no more than $250,000 in damages for pain and
9666 suffering.<footnote>
9667 <para>
9668 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9669 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For
9670 an overview, see Tanya Albert, <quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9671 Say Tort Reformers,</quote> amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at
9672 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #38</ulink>,
9673 and <quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,</quote> CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003,
9674 available at
9675 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9676 recent months.
9677 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.</primary></indexterm>
9678 </para></footnote>
9679 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9680 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9681 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9682 </para>
9683 <indexterm><primary>art, underground</primary></indexterm>
9684 <para>
9685 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9686 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9687 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9688 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9689 Disneys <quote>pirates.</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9690 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9691 designed to
9692
9693 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9694 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9695 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9696 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9697 we will begin to see a world of underground art&mdash;not because the
9698 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9699 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9700 fraught. Already, exhibits of <quote>illegal art</quote> tour the United
9701 States.<footnote><para>
9702 <!-- f3. -->
9703
9704 See Danit Lidor, <quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,</quote> <citetitle>Wired</citetitle>, 7 July
9705 2003, available at
9706 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9707 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #41</ulink>.
9708 </para></footnote>
9709 In what does their <quote>illegality</quote> consist?
9710 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9711 critical or reflective.
9712 </para>
9713 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9714 <para>
9715 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9716 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9717 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. But an
9718 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9719 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9720 discovered in 2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9721 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9722 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9723 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9724 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9725 </para>
9726 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
9727 <para>
9728 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9729 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9730 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9731 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9732 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9733 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9734 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9735 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9736 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9737 </para>
9738 <para>
9739 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9740 described in chapter
9741 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/>, in
9742 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9743 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9744 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9745 use.
9746 </para>
9747 <para>
9748
9749 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9750 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9751 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9752 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad&mdash;in
9753 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9754 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9755 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9756 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9757 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9758 </para>
9759 <para>
9760 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9761 <quote>breathing room</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9762 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9763 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9764 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9765 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9766 journalists&mdash; these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9767 these rules have little relationship to the <quote>law</quote> with which judges
9768 comfort themselves.
9769 </para>
9770 <para>
9771 For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful
9772 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9773 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9774 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9775 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak&mdash;in that
9776 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9777 <quote>copyright</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9778 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9779 culture that is free.
9780 </para>
9781 <para>
9782 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9783 </para>
9784 <blockquote>
9785 <para>
9786 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9787 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9788 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9789 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made &hellip; you're not
9790 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9791 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9792 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, <quote>This has been
9793 cleared.</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9794 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9795 </para>
9796 </blockquote>
9797 </section>
9798 <section id="innovators">
9799 <title>Constraining Innovators</title>
9800 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovation hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
9801 <indexterm id='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>innovation</primary><secondary>industry establishment opposed to</secondary></indexterm>
9802 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
9803 <para>
9804 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9805 story&mdash;creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9806 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9807 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9808 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9809 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9810 </para>
9811 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints2' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9812 <para>
9813 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9814 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9815 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9816 one at that, <xref xrefstyle="select: pagenumber"
9817 linkend="innovators"/> pages into a book like this), then you
9818 can see this other aspect by substituting <quote>free market</quote>
9819 every place I've spoken of <quote>free culture.</quote> The point is
9820 the same, even if the interests affecting culture are more
9821 fundamental.
9822 </para>
9823 <para>
9824 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9825 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9826 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary&mdash;at
9827 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9828 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9829 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9830 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9831 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9832 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9833 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9834 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9835 </para>
9836 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints2' class='endofrange'/>
9837 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9838 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
9839 <para>
9840 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9841 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9842 strategy that I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9843 labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9844 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9845 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9846 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9847 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9848 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9849 lesson. That lesson&mdash;what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9850 <quote>nuclear pall</quote> that has fallen over the Valley&mdash;has been learned.
9851 </para>
9852 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
9853 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
9854 <para>
9855 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9856 I told in <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9857 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9858 </para>
9859 <indexterm id='idxmpcom' class='startofrange'><primary>MP3.com</primary></indexterm>
9860 <indexterm id='idxmympcom' class='startofrange'><primary>my.mp3.com</primary></indexterm>
9861 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael</primary></indexterm>
9862 <para>
9863 In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9864 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9865 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9866 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9867 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9868 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9869 </para>
9870 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9871 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>preference data on</secondary></indexterm>
9872 <para>
9873 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9874 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9875 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9876 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9877 Raitt. And so on.
9878 </para>
9879 <para>
9880 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9881 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9882 preference data. In January 2000, the company launched a service
9883 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9884 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9885 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9886 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9887 wherever you were&mdash;at work or at home&mdash;you could get access
9888 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9889 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9890 </para>
9891 <para>
9892 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9893 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9894
9895 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9896 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9897 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9898 the kind of content the users liked.
9899 </para>
9900 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'/>
9901 <para>
9902 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000
9903 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9904 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9905 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9906 therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9907 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9908 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9909 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was 50,000
9910 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers something
9911 they had already bought.
9912 </para>
9913 <indexterm id='idxvivendiuniversal' class='startofrange'><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9914 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
9915 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9916 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9917 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
9918 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
9919 <indexterm><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>outsize penalties of</secondary></indexterm>
9920 <para>
9921 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9922 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9923 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9924 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9925 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9926 MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9927 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $54 million. Vivendi
9928 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9929 </para>
9930 <para>
9931 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9932 </para>
9933 <para>
9934 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9935 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9936 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9937 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9938 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9939 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9940 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9941 demanded.
9942 </para>
9943 <indexterm startref='idxvivendiuniversal' class='endofrange'/>
9944 <para>
9945 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9946 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9947 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9948 clients in this
9949 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9950 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9951 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9952 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9953 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9954 </para>
9955 <indexterm startref='idxmpcom' class='endofrange'/>
9956 <indexterm startref='idxmympcom' class='endofrange'/>
9957 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='endofrange'/>
9958 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9959 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
9960 <indexterm id='idxbmw' class='startofrange'><primary>BMW</primary></indexterm>
9961 <indexterm id='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='startofrange'><primary>cars, MP3 sound systems in</primary></indexterm>
9962 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
9963 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John</primary></indexterm>
9964 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9965 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad</primary></indexterm>
9966 <indexterm><primary>MP3 players</primary></indexterm>
9967 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>venture capital for</secondary></indexterm>
9968 <indexterm id='idxneedlemanrafe' class='startofrange'><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
9969 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
9970 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
9971 <para>
9972 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003,
9973 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9974 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9975 its development, its cofounder (John Hummer), and general partner
9976 (Hank Barry).<footnote><para>
9977 <!-- f4. -->
9978 See Joseph Menn, <quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9979 Times</citetitle>, 23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9980 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, <quote>The Music
9981 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,</quote> Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available
9982 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #42</ulink>.
9983 See also Jon Healey, <quote>Online Music Services Besieged,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9984 Times</citetitle>, 28 May 2001.
9985 </para></footnote>
9986 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
9987 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
9988 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
9989 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
9990 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
9991 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
9992 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
9993 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
9994 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
9995 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
9996 <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
9997 discussion with BMW:
9998 </para>
9999 <blockquote>
10000 <para>
10001 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
10002 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
10003 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
10004 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
10005 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
10006 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
10007 United States with bona fide MP3 players. &hellip; <footnote>
10008 <para>
10009 <!-- f5. -->
10010 Rafe Needleman, <quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,</quote> <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, 16 June
10011 2003, available at
10012 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #43</ulink>. I am grateful
10013 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
10014 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
10015 </para></footnote>
10016 </para>
10017 </blockquote>
10018 <indexterm startref='idxbmw' class='endofrange'/>
10019 <indexterm startref='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='endofrange'/>
10020 <indexterm startref='idxneedlemanrafe' class='endofrange'/>
10021 <para>
10022 This is the world of the mafia&mdash;filled with <quote>your money or your
10023 life</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
10024 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
10025 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
10026 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
10027 constantly threatened by litigation.
10028 </para>
10029 <para>
10030
10031 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
10032 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
10033 enterprises. The point is the definition of <quote>illegal.</quote> The law is a
10034 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
10035 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
10036 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
10037 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
10038 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
10039 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
10040 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
10041 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
10042 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
10043 much less creativity.
10044 </para>
10045 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
10046 <para>
10047 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
10048 use. Whatever the <quote>real</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
10049 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
10050 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
10051 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
10052 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
10053 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
10054 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
10055 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
10056 produce an overregulated-regulated market.
10057 </para>
10058 <para>
10059 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
10060 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
10061 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
10062 culture&mdash;a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
10063 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
10064 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
10065 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
10066 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
10067 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
10068 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
10069 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
10070 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
10071 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
10072 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
10073 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
10074 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
10075 result.
10076 </para>
10077 <para>
10078 <emphasis role='strong'>The uncertainty</emphasis> of the law is one
10079 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
10080 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
10081 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
10082 better protects their content.
10083 </para>
10084 <para>
10085 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
10086 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
10087 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
10088 this feature is a <quote>bug.</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
10089 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
10090 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
10091 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables <quote>piracy,</quote> then,
10092 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
10093 </para>
10094 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10095 <para>
10096 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
10097 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
10098 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
10099 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.<footnote><para>
10100 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> GartnerG2 and
10101 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
10102 (2003), 33&ndash;35, available at
10103 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10104 </para></footnote>
10105 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
10106 <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
10107 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
10108 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
10109 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
10110 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
10111 copyright violators and disable their machines.<footnote><para>
10112 <!-- f7. -->
10113 GartnerG2, 26&ndash;27.
10114 </para></footnote>
10115 </para>
10116 <para>
10117 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
10118 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
10119 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
10120 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
10121 and costs on
10122 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
10123 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
10124 those requirements.
10125 </para>
10126 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
10127 <para>
10128 In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
10129 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
10130 would impose.<footnote><para>
10131 <!-- f8. -->
10132 See David McGuire, <quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,</quote> Newsbytes,
10133 February 2002 (Entertainment).
10134 </para></footnote>
10135 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
10136 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
10137 harm than good.
10138 </para>
10139 <para>
10140 <emphasis role='strong'>There is one</emphasis> more obvious way in
10141 which this war has harmed innovation&mdash;again, a story that will be
10142 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
10143 </para>
10144 <para>
10145 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
10146 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
10147 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
10148 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
10149 </para>
10150 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
10151 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
10152 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
10153 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
10154 <para>
10155 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10156 linkend="property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
10157 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
10158 Jessica Litman in her book <citetitle>Digital
10159 Copyright</citetitle>,<footnote><para>
10160 <!-- f9. -->
10161 Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (Amherst,
10162 N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 2001).
10163 <indexterm><primary>Digital Copyright (Litman)</primary></indexterm>
10164 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
10165 </para></footnote>
10166 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter
10167 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/> details,
10168 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
10169 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
10170 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
10171 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
10172 </para>
10173 <para>
10174 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
10175 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
10176 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
10177 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
10178 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
10179 </para>
10180 <indexterm id='idxinternetradioon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>radio on</secondary></indexterm>
10181 <indexterm id='idxradiooninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
10182 <para>
10183 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.<footnote><para>
10184 <!-- f10. -->
10185 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.</primary></indexterm>
10186 The only circuit court exception is found in <citetitle>Recording Industry
10187 Association of America (RIAA)</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems</citetitle>, 180 F. 3d
10188 1072 (9th Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
10189 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
10190 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
10191 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
10192 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
10193 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
10194 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Grokster, Ltd</citetitle>., 259 F. Supp. 2d
10195 1029 (C.D. Cal., 2003), where the court found the link between the
10196 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
10197 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
10198 liability.
10199 </para></footnote>
10200 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
10201 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
10202 here.<footnote><para>
10203 <!-- f11. -->
10204 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy</primary></indexterm>
10205 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
10206 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz</primary></indexterm>
10207 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10208 For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
10209 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize
10210 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
10211 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
10212 August 2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
10213 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
10214 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that
10215 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
10216 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
10217 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
10218 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, <quote>Copyright and
10219 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003, 33&ndash;34,
10220 available at
10221 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10222 </para></footnote>
10223 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
10224 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
10225 </para>
10226 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10227 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
10228 <para>
10229
10230 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
10231 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10232 linkend="pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
10233 artist doesn't get paid for that <quote>radio performance</quote> unless he or she
10234 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
10235 version of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote>&mdash;to memorialize her famous
10236 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden&mdash;
10237 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
10238 copyright owners of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> would get some money, whereas
10239 Marilyn Monroe would not.
10240 </para>
10241 <para>
10242 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
10243 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
10244 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
10245 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
10246 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
10247 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
10248 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
10249 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
10250 recording artists.
10251 </para>
10252 <para>
10253 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
10254 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
10255 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
10256 spectrum. Thus, I can <quote>tune in</quote> to an Internet radio station in
10257 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
10258 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
10259 metropolitan area.
10260 </para>
10261 <para>
10262 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
10263 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
10264 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
10265 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
10266 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
10267 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
10268 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
10269 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
10270 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
10271 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
10272 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
10273 </para>
10274 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
10275 <para>
10276
10277 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
10278 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
10279 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
10280 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
10281 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
10282 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
10283 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
10284 FM radio,
10285 </para>
10286 <blockquote>
10287 <para>
10288 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
10289 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
10290 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
10291 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
10292 than by technical restrictions. &hellip; Armstrong likened the situation
10293 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
10294 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
10295 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
10296 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
10297 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
10298 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
10299 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
10300 shackles.<footnote><para>
10301 <!-- f12. -->
10302 Lessing, 239.
10303 </para></footnote>
10304 </para>
10305 </blockquote>
10306 <para>
10307 This potential for FM radio was never realized&mdash;not
10308 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
10309 underestimated the power of <quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
10310 legislation</quote><footnote><para>
10311 <!-- f13. -->
10312 Ibid., 229.
10313 </para></footnote>
10314 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
10315 </para>
10316 <para>
10317 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
10318 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
10319 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
10320 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
10321 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
10322 radio?
10323 </para>
10324 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10325 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
10326 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on radio</secondary></indexterm>
10327 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
10328 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10329 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
10330 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>Internet radio hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
10331 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10332 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
10333 <para>
10334 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
10335 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
10336
10337 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
10338 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
10339 of Internet radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
10340 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
10341 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
10342 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
10343 of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> on the air, <emphasis>Internet radio
10344 does</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
10345 radio&mdash;the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
10346 burdens terrestrial radio.
10347 </para>
10348 <para>
10349 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
10350 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
10351 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
10352 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
10353 over $1 million a year.<footnote>
10354 <para>
10355 <!-- f14. -->
10356 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
10357 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
10358 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
10359 iLaw (Stanford), 3 July 2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
10360 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
10361 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
10362 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP
10363 DTRA 1 and 2, available at
10364 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #45</ulink>.
10365 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
10366 C. Picker, <quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
10367 Distribution,</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin</citetitle> (Summer/Fall 2002): 461: <quote>This was
10368 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
10369 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
10370 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
10371 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
10372 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.</quote>
10373 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)</primary></indexterm>
10374 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
10375 </para></footnote>
10376 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
10377 equivalent fee.
10378 </para>
10379 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='endofrange'/>
10380 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='endofrange'/>
10381 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='endofrange'/>
10382 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='endofrange'/>
10383 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='endofrange'/>
10384 <para>
10385 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
10386 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
10387 station) would have to collect the following data from <emphasis>every
10388 listening transaction</emphasis>:
10389 </para>
10390 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
10391 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
10392 <listitem><para>
10393 name of the service;
10394 </para></listitem>
10395 <listitem><para>
10396 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
10397 </para></listitem>
10398 <listitem><para>
10399 type of program (archived/looped/live);
10400 </para></listitem>
10401 <listitem><para>
10402 date of transmission;
10403 </para></listitem>
10404 <listitem><para>
10405 time of transmission;
10406 </para></listitem>
10407 <listitem><para>
10408 time zone of origination of transmission;
10409 </para></listitem>
10410 <listitem><para>
10411 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
10412 </para></listitem>
10413 <listitem><para>
10414 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
10415 </para></listitem>
10416 <listitem><para>
10417 sound recording title;
10418 </para></listitem>
10419 <listitem><para>
10420 ISRC code of the recording;
10421 </para></listitem>
10422 <listitem><para>
10423 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
10424 </para></listitem>
10425 <listitem><para>
10426 featured recording artist;
10427 </para></listitem>
10428 <listitem><para>
10429 retail album title;
10430 </para></listitem>
10431 <listitem><para>
10432 recording label;
10433 </para></listitem>
10434 <listitem><para>
10435 UPC code of the retail album;
10436 </para></listitem>
10437 <listitem><para>
10438 catalog number;
10439 </para></listitem>
10440 <listitem><para>
10441 copyright owner information;
10442 </para></listitem>
10443 <listitem><para>
10444 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
10445 </para></listitem>
10446 <listitem><para>
10447 name of the service or entity;
10448 </para></listitem>
10449 <listitem><para>
10450 channel or program;
10451 </para></listitem>
10452 <listitem><para>
10453 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
10454 </para></listitem>
10455 <listitem><para>
10456 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
10457 </para></listitem>
10458 <listitem><para>
10459 time zone where the signal was received (user);
10460 </para></listitem>
10461 <listitem><para>
10462 unique user identifier;
10463 </para></listitem>
10464 <listitem><para>
10465 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
10466 </para></listitem>
10467 </orderedlist>
10468 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
10469 <para>
10470 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
10471 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
10472 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
10473 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
10474 Internet radio has to pay a <emphasis>type of copyright fee</emphasis>
10475 that terrestrial radio does not.
10476 </para>
10477 <para>
10478 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
10479 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
10480 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
10481 </para>
10482 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
10483 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
10484 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10485 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10486 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10487 <para>
10488 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
10489 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
10490 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
10491 </para>
10492 <blockquote>
10493 <para>
10494 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
10495 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
10496 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
10497 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
10498 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
10499 webcasters asked the RIAA, &hellip; <quote>How do you come up with a
10500
10501 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
10502 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
10503 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
10504 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
10505 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
10506 business. &hellip;</quote>
10507 </para>
10508 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10509 <para>
10510 And the RIAA experts said, <quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
10511 industry with thousands of webcasters, <emphasis>we think it should be
10512 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
10513 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market</emphasis>.</quote> (Emphasis
10514 added.)
10515 </para>
10516 </blockquote>
10517 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'/>
10518 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='endofrange'/>
10519 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='endofrange'/>
10520 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='endofrange'/>
10521 <para>
10522 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
10523 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
10524 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
10525 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
10526 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
10527 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
10528 effective to prevent it.
10529 </para>
10530 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10531 <indexterm startref='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='endofrange'/>
10532 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='endofrange'/>
10533 <indexterm startref='idxinternetradioon' class='endofrange'/>
10534 <indexterm startref='idxradiooninternet' class='endofrange'/>
10535 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10536 </section>
10537 <section id="corruptingcitizens">
10538 <title>Corrupting Citizens</title>
10539 <para>
10540 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
10541 dinosaurs
10542 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
10543 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
10544 </para>
10545 <para>
10546 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
10547 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
10548 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
10549 </para>
10550 <para>
10551 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
10552 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
10553 large number of citizens. According to <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, 43 million
10554 Americans downloaded music in May 2002.<footnote><para>
10555 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, <quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,</quote> Pew
10556 Internet and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at
10557 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #46</ulink>.
10558 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that 37 million
10559 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early 2001.
10560 </para></footnote>
10561 According to the RIAA,
10562 the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
10563 set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As the
10564
10565 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
10566 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
10567 the world, but against students building search engines, and
10568 increasingly
10569 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
10570 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
10571 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
10572 extreme
10573 response by the other.
10574 </para>
10575 <para>
10576 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
10577 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
10578 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
10579 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
10580 ($15,000,000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
10581 paying all the money in the world in damages ($250,000 in legal fees)
10582 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
10583 ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
10584 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September 2003, the RIAA
10585 sued 261 individuals&mdash;including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
10586 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
10587 was.<footnote><para>
10588 <!-- f16. -->
10589 Alex Pham, <quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,</quote> <citetitle>Los
10590 Angeles Times</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, Business.
10591 </para></footnote>
10592 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
10593 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
10594 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000
10595 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
10596 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
10597 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
10598 they oppose.
10599 </para>
10600 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition</primary></indexterm>
10601 <para>
10602 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
10603 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
10604 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
10605 consumption of alcohol was 1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
10606 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just 30 percent
10607 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10608 consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition
10609 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10610 number were criminals.<footnote><para>
10611 <!-- f17. -->
10612 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, <quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10613 Prohibition,</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review</citetitle> 81, no. 2 (1991): 242.
10614 </para></footnote>
10615 We have
10616 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10617 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10618 narcotics that 7 percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.<footnote><para>
10619 <!-- f18. -->
10620 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10621 Reform Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of
10622 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10623 </para></footnote>
10624 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of
10625 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10626 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10627 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10628 cheat.<footnote><para>
10629 <!-- f19. -->
10630 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, <quote>Tax
10631 Compliance,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature</citetitle> 36 (1998): 818 (survey of
10632 compliance literature).
10633 </para></footnote>
10634 We pride ourselves on our <quote>free society,</quote> but an endless array of
10635 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10636 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10637 </para>
10638 <indexterm><primary>law schools</primary></indexterm>
10639 <para>
10640 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10641 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10642 students about the importance of <quote>ethics.</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10643 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10644 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10645 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10646 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10647 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10648 teach them how to behave ethically&mdash;how to say no to bribes, or
10649 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10650 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10651 Americans&mdash;more significantly in some parts of America than in
10652 others, but still, everywhere in America today&mdash;can't live their
10653 lives both normally and legally, since <quote>normally</quote> entails a certain
10654 degree of illegality.
10655 </para>
10656 <para>
10657 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10658 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10659 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10660 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10661 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10662 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10663 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10664 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10665 to consider the alternative.
10666 </para>
10667 <para>
10668
10669 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10670 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10671 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10672 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10673 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10674 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10675 </para>
10676 <para>
10677 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10678 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10679 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10680 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10681 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10682 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10683 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10684 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10685 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10686 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10687 introduced this different idea of <quote>sharing.</quote> We need to be able to
10688 call these twenty million Americans <quote>citizens,</quote> not <quote>felons.</quote>
10689 </para>
10690 <para>
10691 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10692 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10693 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10694 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10695 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10696 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10697 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10698 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10699 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10700 a nation of felons?
10701 </para>
10702 <para>
10703 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10704 </para>
10705 <para>
10706 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10707 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10708 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10709 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10710 used
10711
10712 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10713 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That <quote>use</quote> of the
10714 recordings is free.
10715 </para>
10716 <para>
10717 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10718 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10719 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am <quote>free</quote> to copy,
10720 or <quote>rip,</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10721 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that <quote>freedom</quote> was a
10722 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the <quote>Rip, Mix, Burn</quote>
10723 capacities of digital technologies.
10724 </para>
10725 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda</primary></indexterm>
10726 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>mix technology and</secondary></indexterm>
10727 <para>
10728 This <quote>use</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10729 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10730 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10731 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10732 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10733 Others&mdash;the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10734 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10735 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10736 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10737 </para>
10738 <para>
10739 This use is enabled by unprotected media&mdash;either CDs or records.
10740 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10741 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10742 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10743 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10744 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10745 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10746 on people's machines.
10747 </para>
10748 <para>
10749 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10750 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10751 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10752 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10753 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10754 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10755
10756 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10757 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10758 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10759 plastic or were part of a massively complex <quote>digital rights
10760 management</quote> system.
10761 </para>
10762 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'/>
10763 <para>
10764 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10765 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10766 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10767 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10768 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10769 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10770 freedom to move content easily?
10771 </para>
10772 <para>
10773 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10774 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10775 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10776 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10777 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10778 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10779 alternative&mdash;namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10780 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10781 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10782 </para>
10783 <para>
10784 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10785 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10786 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10787 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10788 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10789 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10790 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10791 </para>
10792 <para>
10793 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10794 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10795 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10796 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10797 </para>
10798 <para>
10799 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10800 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10801
10802 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10803
10804 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10805 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10806 </para>
10807 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
10808 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
10809 <para>
10810 <emphasis role='strong'>There's one more</emphasis> aspect to this
10811 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10812 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10813 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10814 <quote>collateral damage</quote> that <quote>arises whenever you turn
10815 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.</quote> This
10816 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10817 </para>
10818 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10819 <para>
10820 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,</quote> von Lohmann
10821 explains,
10822 </para>
10823 <blockquote>
10824 <para>
10825 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10826 evaporate to one degree or another. &hellip; If you're a copyright
10827 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10828 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10829 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10830 access? &hellip; Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, <quote>Oh, well,
10831 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.</quote> Well, what this campaign
10832 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10833 American Internet-using population into <quote>lawbreakers.</quote>
10834 </para>
10835 </blockquote>
10836 <para>
10837 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10838 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10839 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10840 </para>
10841 <para>
10842 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA
10843 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10844 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10845 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10846 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10847 an Internet user is revealed.
10848 </para>
10849 <para>
10850 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10851 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10852 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10853 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10854 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10855 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10856 the family could be liable for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10857 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10858 Jesse Jordan.<footnote><para>
10859 <!-- f20. -->
10860 See Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10861 Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,</quote>
10862 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, <quote>Worried Parents
10863 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10864 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10865 Being Sued,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson
10866 Graham, <quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 15 September
10867 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, <quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10868 Fan, Either,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 25 September 2003, C1; Margo Varadi, <quote>Is
10869 Brianna a Criminal?</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star</citetitle>, 18 September 2003, P7.
10870 </para></footnote>
10871
10872 </para>
10873 <para>
10874 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10875 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10876 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.<footnote><para>
10877 <!-- f21. -->
10878 See <quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10879 Some Methods Used,</quote> CNN.com, available at
10880 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #47</ulink>.
10881 </para></footnote>
10882 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10883 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10884 one of those MP3s will have the same <quote>fingerprint.</quote>
10885 </para>
10886 <para>
10887 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10888 friend gives a CD to your daughter&mdash;a collection of songs just
10889 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10890 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10891 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10892 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10893 network is <quote>cooperating</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10894 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10895 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10896 as a <quote>criminal.</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10897 to deploy,<footnote><para>
10898 <!-- f22. -->
10899 See Jeff Adler, <quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,</quote>
10900 <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, <quote>Four
10901 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10902 Colleges,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10903 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10904 Monitor</citetitle>, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, <quote>Music
10905 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10906 Lawsuit Possible,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 16 July 2003, 1C; Beth Cox, <quote>RIAA
10907 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,</quote> <citetitle>Internet News</citetitle>, 30 January
10908 2003, available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10909 #48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Download Warning 101: Freshman
10910 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10911 Sharing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 11 August 2003, E11; <quote>Raid, Letters
10912 Are Weapons at Universities,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 26 September 2000, 3D.
10913 </para></footnote>
10914 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10915 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10916 </para>
10917 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'/>
10918 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10919 <para>
10920 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10921 a lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10922 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10923 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10924 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10925 this <quote>contraband</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10926 college students
10927
10928 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10929 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10930 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10931 Says von Lohmann,
10932 </para>
10933 <blockquote>
10934 <para>
10935 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10936 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10937 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10938 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10939 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10940 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10941 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10942 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10943 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10944 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10945 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10946 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10947 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10948 larger number of Americans than drug use. &hellip; If forty to sixty
10949 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10950 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10951 million of them.
10952 </para>
10953 </blockquote>
10954 <para>
10955 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered <quote>criminals</quote> under
10956 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective&mdash;
10957 securing rights to authors&mdash;without these millions being
10958 considered <quote>criminals,</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10959 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10960 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10961 </para>
10962
10963 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10964 </section>
10965 </chapter>
10966 </part>
10967 <part id="c-balances">
10968 <title>BALANCES</title>
10969 <partintro>
10970
10971 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10972 <para>
10973 <emphasis role='strong'>So here's</emphasis> the picture: You're
10974 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
10975 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
10976 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
10977 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10978 </para>
10979 <para>
10980 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10981 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10982 stop&mdash;or before she understands just why she should
10983 stop&mdash;the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10984 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10985 everything around.
10986 </para>
10987 <para>
10988 <emphasis role='strong'>A war</emphasis> about copyright rages all
10989 around&mdash;and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
10990 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
10991 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
10992 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
10993 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
10994 that if let alone would burn itself out.
10995 </para>
10996 <para>
10997 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
10998 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
10999 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
11000 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
11001 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
11002 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
11003 made that is happening all around.
11004 </para>
11005 <para>
11006 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
11007 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
11008 gasoline onto this fire.
11009 </para>
11010 <para>
11011 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
11012 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
11013 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
11014 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
11015 </para>
11016 <para>
11017 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
11018 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
11019 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
11020 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
11021 success will require.
11022 </para>
11023 </partintro>
11024
11025 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
11026 <chapter label="13" id="eldred">
11027 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred</title>
11028 <indexterm id='idxeldrederic' class='startofrange'><primary>Eldred, Eric</primary></indexterm>
11029 <indexterm id='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='startofrange'><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel</primary></indexterm>
11030 <para>
11031 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
11032 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
11033 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
11034 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
11035 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
11036 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
11037 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
11038 </para>
11039 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>of public-domain literature</secondary></indexterm>
11040 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>library of works derived from</secondary></indexterm>
11041 <para>
11042 It didn't work&mdash;at least for his daughters. They didn't find
11043 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
11044 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
11045 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
11046 them available for free.
11047 </para>
11048 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt5' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11049 <indexterm><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
11050 <para>
11051 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
11052 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
11053 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
11054 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
11055 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
11056 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
11057 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
11058 many others, into a form more accessible&mdash;technically
11059 accessible&mdash;today.
11060 </para>
11061 <indexterm><primary>Scarlet Letter, The (Hawthorne)</primary></indexterm>
11062 <para>
11063 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
11064 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's <citetitle>Scarlet Letter</citetitle> had passed into the
11065 public domain in 1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
11066 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
11067 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
11068 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
11069 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
11070 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (<citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle>), sometimes not
11071 (<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame</citetitle>, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>). These are all
11072 commercial publications of public domain works.
11073 </para>
11074 <indexterm startref='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='endofrange'/>
11075 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt5' class='endofrange'/>
11076 <para>
11077 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
11078 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
11079 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
11080 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
11081 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
11082 call the <quote>noncommercial publishing industry,</quote> which before the
11083 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
11084 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
11085 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
11086 generally.<footnote><para>
11087 <!-- f1. -->
11088 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
11089 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
11090 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
11091 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers&mdash;people who
11092 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
11093 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
11094 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
11095 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
11096 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
11097 Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on
11098 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
11099 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
11100 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
11101 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
11102 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
11103 protect noncommercial pornographers.</para></footnote>
11104 </para>
11105 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
11106 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11107 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
11108 <indexterm><primary>Frost, Robert</primary></indexterm>
11109 <indexterm><primary>New Hampshire (Frost)</primary></indexterm>
11110 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
11111 <indexterm id='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
11112 <para>
11113 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's
11114 collection of poems <citetitle>New Hampshire</citetitle> was slated to
11115 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
11116 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
11117 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
11118 linkend="property-i"/>, in 1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
11119 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights&mdash;this time by
11120 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
11121 than 1923 to his collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
11122 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
11123 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
11124 more than 1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
11125 </para>
11126 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='endofrange'/>
11127 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
11128 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11129 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11130 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
11131 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11132 <para>
11133
11134 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
11135 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
11136 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
11137 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
11138 <quote>copyrights should be forever.</quote><footnote><para>
11139 <!-- f2. -->
11140 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11141 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11142 The full text is: <quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
11143 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
11144 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
11145 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
11146 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
11147 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
11148 Congress,</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998).
11149 </para></footnote>
11150 </para>
11151 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
11152 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>felony punishment for infringement of</secondary></indexterm>
11153 <indexterm><primary>NET (No Electronic Theft) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11154 <indexterm><primary>No Electronic Theft (NET) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11155 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>felony punishments for</secondary></indexterm>
11156 <para>
11157 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
11158 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
11159 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
11160 second law passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
11161 of publishing would make Eldred a felon&mdash;whether or not anyone
11162 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
11163 to undertake.
11164 </para>
11165 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='endofrange'/>
11166 <indexterm id='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
11167 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
11168 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause2' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
11169 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11170 <para>
11171 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
11172 constitutional
11173 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
11174 interpretation.
11175 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
11176 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
11177 importantly
11178 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
11179 </para>
11180 <blockquote>
11181 <para>
11182 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science &hellip;
11183 by securing for limited Times to Authors &hellip; exclusive Right to
11184 their &hellip; Writings. &hellip;
11185 </para>
11186 </blockquote>
11187 <indexterm startref='idxeldrederic' class='endofrange'/>
11188 <para>
11189 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
11190 clause of Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
11191 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
11192 something&mdash;for example, to regulate <quote>commerce among the several
11193 states</quote> or <quote>declare War.</quote> But here, the <quote>something</quote> is something quite
11194 specific&mdash;to <quote>promote &hellip; Progress</quote>&mdash;through means that
11195 are also specific&mdash; by <quote>securing</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights</quote> (i.e.,
11196 copyrights) <quote>for limited Times.</quote>
11197 </para>
11198 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='endofrange'/>
11199 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause2' class='endofrange'/>
11200 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='endofrange'/>
11201 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
11202 <para>
11203 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
11204 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
11205 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
11206 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be <quote>limited</quote> will have
11207 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
11208 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
11209 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
11210 what the Constitution plainly forbids&mdash;perpetual terms <quote>on the
11211 installment plan,</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
11212 </para>
11213 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='endofrange'/>
11214 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='endofrange'/>
11215 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11216 <para>
11217 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
11218 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
11219 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
11220 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
11221 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
11222 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
11223 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
11224 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
11225 this gravy train going.
11226 </para>
11227 <para>
11228 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
11229 government. <quote>Corruption</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
11230 bribed. Rather, <quote>corruption</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
11231 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
11232 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
11233 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
11234 do&mdash;and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
11235 </para>
11236 <para>
11237 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
11238 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
11239 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
11240 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry
11241 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
11242 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
11243 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
11244 published by anyone for free.
11245 </para>
11246 <para>
11247 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from
11248 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
11249 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
11250 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
11251 report:
11252 </para>
11253 <para>
11254 <quote>Next year,</quote> the adviser announces, <quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
11255
11256 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
11257 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
11258 receiving the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of
11259 those works.</quote>
11260 </para>
11261 <para>
11262 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,</quote> she continues, <quote>that
11263 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
11264 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
11265 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.</quote>
11266 </para>
11267 <para>
11268 <quote>Hope?</quote> a fellow board member says. <quote>Can't we be doing something
11269 about it?</quote>
11270 </para>
11271 <para>
11272 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>We could contribute
11273 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
11274 they support the bill.</quote>
11275 </para>
11276 <para>
11277 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
11278 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. <quote>How much
11279 would we get if this extension were passed?</quote> you ask the adviser. <quote>How
11280 much is it worth?</quote>
11281 </para>
11282 <para>
11283 <quote>Well,</quote> the adviser says, <quote>if you're confident that you will continue
11284 to get at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
11285 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent),
11286 then this law would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate.</quote>
11287 </para>
11288 <para>
11289 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
11290 correct conclusion:
11291 </para>
11292 <para>
11293 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
11294 $1,000,000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
11295 contributions
11296 would assure that the bill was passed?</quote>
11297 </para>
11298 <para>
11299 <quote>Absolutely,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>It is worth it to you to
11300 contribute
11301 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
11302 copyrights. Which for us means over $1,000,000.</quote>
11303 </para>
11304 <para>
11305 You quickly get the point&mdash;you as the member of the board and, I
11306 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
11307 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
11308 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
11309 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
11310 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
11311 copyrights
11312 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
11313 the copyright term extended.
11314 </para>
11315 <para>
11316 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
11317 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
11318 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
11319 </para>
11320 <para>
11321 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
11322 Copyright
11323 Term Extension Act, this <quote>theory</quote> about incentives was proved
11324 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
11325 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
11326 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
11327 contributions.<footnote><para>
11328 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, <quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
11329 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years,</quote>
11330 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 17 October 1998, 22.
11331 </para></footnote>
11332 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
11333 $1.5 million lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more
11334 than $200,000 in campaign contributions.<footnote><para>
11335 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, <quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
11336 Age,</quote> available at
11337 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #49</ulink>.
11338 </para></footnote>
11339 Disney is estimated to have
11340 contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in the
11341 cycle.<footnote><para>
11342 <!-- f5. -->
11343 Alan K. Ota, <quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,</quote>
11344 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week</citetitle>, 8 August 1990, available at
11345 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #50</ulink>.
11346 </para></footnote>
11347
11348 </para>
11349 <para>
11350 <emphasis role='strong'>Constitutional law</emphasis> is not oblivious
11351 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
11352 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
11353 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
11354 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
11355 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
11356 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
11357 constitutional requirement that terms be <quote>limited.</quote> If
11358 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
11359 again.
11360 </para>
11361 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='endofrange'/>
11362 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='endofrange'/>
11363 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='endofrange'/>
11364 <para>
11365 It was also my judgment that <emphasis>this</emphasis> Supreme Court
11366 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
11367 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
11368 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
11369 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
11370 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
11371 Supreme Court's
11372
11373 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
11374 decision in 1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
11375 guns near schools.
11376 </para>
11377 <para>
11378 Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
11379 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
11380 power to regulate only <quote>commerce among the several states</quote> (aka
11381 <quote>interstate
11382 commerce</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
11383 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
11384 interstate
11385 commerce.
11386 </para>
11387 <para>
11388 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
11389 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
11390 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
11391 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
11392 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
11393 </para>
11394 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
11395 <para>
11396 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
11397 that in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The government had
11398 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
11399 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
11400 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
11401 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
11402 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
11403 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
11404 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
11405 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
11406 position to second-guess Congress.
11407 </para>
11408 <para>
11409 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,</quote>
11410 the Chief Justice wrote.<footnote><para>
11411 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995).
11412 </para></footnote>
11413 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
11414 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
11415 Congress's power. The decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
11416 later in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>.<footnote><para>
11417 <!-- f7. -->
11418 <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>, 529 U.S. 598 (2000).
11419 </para></footnote>
11420 </para>
11421 <para>
11422 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
11423 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.<footnote><para>
11424 <!-- f8. -->
11425 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
11426 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
11427 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
11428 by the government would allow the government unending power to
11429 regulate commerce&mdash;the limitation to interstate commerce
11430 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
11431 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
11432 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights&mdash;the
11433 limitation to <quote>limited times</quote> notwithstanding.
11434 </para></footnote>
11435 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
11436 yield the conclusion that Congress
11437 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
11438 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
11439 term, then there would be no <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power over
11440 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
11441 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
11442 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
11443 term of existing copyrights.
11444 </para>
11445 <para>
11446 <emphasis>If</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
11447 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> stood for
11448 politics&mdash;a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
11449 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
11450 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
11451 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
11452 demonstrating the <quote>fidelity</quote> in such an interpretation of the
11453 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
11454 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
11455 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
11456 were going to be petty politicians.
11457 </para>
11458 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
11459 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
11460 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11461 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11462 <para>
11463 <emphasis role='strong'>Now let's pause</emphasis> for a moment to
11464 make sure we understand what the argument in
11465 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
11466 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
11467 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
11468 piracy&mdash;piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
11469 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
11470 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
11471 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
11472 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
11473 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
11474 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
11475 power&mdash;expressed through the power of lobbyists' money&mdash;to
11476 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
11477 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
11478 piracy that affects us all.
11479 </para>
11480 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association</primary></indexterm>
11481 <para>
11482 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
11483
11484 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
11485 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
11486 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than <quote>legal piracy.</quote><footnote><para>
11487 <!-- f9. -->
11488 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11489 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available
11490 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #51</ulink>.
11491 </para></footnote>
11492 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
11493 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
11494 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
11495 charter.
11496 </para>
11497 <para>
11498 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
11499 copyright
11500 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
11501 influence
11502 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
11503 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
11504 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
11505 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
11506 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
11507 bought to extend them again.
11508 </para>
11509 <para>
11510 <emphasis role='strong'>It is valuable</emphasis> copyrights that are
11511 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
11512 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.</quote> These works are too valuable for
11513 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
11514 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
11515 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
11516 the 1920s and 1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
11517 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
11518 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
11519 and no longer available as a result.
11520 </para>
11521 <para>
11522 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to
11523 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
11524 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
11525 copyright holders for that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
11526 But the law and its effect were not limited to that 2 percent. The law
11527 extended the terms of copyright generally.<footnote><para>
11528 <!-- f10. --> The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
11529 Congressional
11530 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
11531 of Petitioners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 7, available at
11532 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #52</ulink>.
11533 </para></footnote>
11534
11535 </para>
11536 <para>
11537 Think practically about the consequence of this
11538 extension&mdash;practically,
11539 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
11540
11541 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
11542 work. In 1930, 10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those
11543 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
11544 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
11545 remaining
11546 9,873. What would you have to do?
11547 </para>
11548 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11549 <para>
11550 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were
11551 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
11552 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
11553 titles and authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration
11554 and renewal records for works published in 1930. That will produce a
11555 list of books still under copyright.
11556 </para>
11557 <para>
11558 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
11559 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
11560 </para>
11561 <para>
11562 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
11563 owners
11564 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
11565 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
11566 being at least a list?
11567 </para>
11568 <para>
11569 But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in
11570 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
11571 practically
11572 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
11573 thousands
11574 of such records&mdash;especially since the person who registered is
11575 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930!
11576 </para>
11577 <para>
11578 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,</quote> the
11579 apologists for the system respond. <quote>Why should there be a list of
11580 copyright owners?</quote>
11581 </para>
11582 <para>
11583 Well, actually, if you think about it, there <emphasis>are</emphasis>
11584 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
11585 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
11586 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
11587 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
11588 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
11589 what tangible property.
11590 </para>
11591 <para>
11592 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
11593 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
11594 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
11595
11596 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
11597 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
11598 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
11599 happen
11600 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
11601 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
11602 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
11603 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
11604 know quite well who owns what property.
11605 </para>
11606 <para>
11607 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
11608 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
11609 already
11610 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
11611 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
11612 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
11613 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
11614 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
11615 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
11616 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
11617 </para>
11618 <para>
11619 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
11620 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
11621 consequence
11622 for other creative works is much more dire.
11623 </para>
11624 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'><primary>Agee, Michael</primary></indexterm>
11625 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
11626 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films</primary></indexterm>
11627 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The</primary></indexterm>
11628 <para>
11629 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
11630 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
11631 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
11632 made between 1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, <citetitle>The Lucky Dog</citetitle>, is
11633 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923
11634 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
11635 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
11636 money. According to one estimate, <quote>Roach has sold about 60,000
11637 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's silent
11638 films.</quote><footnote><para>
11639 <!-- f11. -->
11640 See David G. Savage, <quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,</quote>
11641 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, <quote>Classic Movies,
11642 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
11643 Down Copyright Extension,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 9 October 2002.
11644 </para></footnote>
11645 </para>
11646 <para>
11647 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
11648 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
11649 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11650 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11651 </para>
11652 <para>
11653 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11654
11655 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11656 any continuing commercial value. The rest&mdash;to the extent it
11657 survives at all&mdash;sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11658 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11659 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11660 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11661 work available for distribution.
11662 </para>
11663 <para>
11664 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11665 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11666 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11667 it cost more than $10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11668 film in 1993, it can now cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of
11669 8 mm film.<footnote><para>
11670 <!-- f12. -->
11671 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11672 Supporting the Petitoners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11673 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01- 618), 12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11674 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11675 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, available at
11676 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #53</ulink>.
11677 </para></footnote>
11678
11679 </para>
11680 <para>
11681 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11682 important.
11683 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11684 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11685 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11686 locate the copyright owner.
11687 </para>
11688 <para>
11689 Or more accurately, <emphasis>owners</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11690 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11691 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11692 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11693 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11694 to these films is exceptionally high.
11695 </para>
11696 <para>
11697 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11698 copyright owner when she shows up?</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11699 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11700 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11701 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11702 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11703 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11704 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11705 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11706 </para>
11707 <para>
11708 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11709
11710 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11711 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11712 benefit
11713 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11714 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11715 the copyright expires.
11716 </para>
11717 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'/>
11718 <para>
11719 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11720 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11721 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11722 canisters
11723 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11724 than dust.
11725 </para>
11726 <para>
11727 <emphasis role='strong'>Of all the</emphasis> creative work produced
11728 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11729 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11730 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11731 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11732 the copyright acts as an <quote>engine of free expression.</quote>
11733 </para>
11734 <para>
11735 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11736 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11737 indicated,
11738 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11739 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11740 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11741 distributors,
11742 the commercial life ends.
11743 </para>
11744 <para>
11745 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11746 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes &amp; Noble, and
11747 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11748 between
11749 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11750 Friday
11751 night watching a 1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11752 of culture is important and valuable&mdash;for entertainment but also, and
11753 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11754 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11755 have, we need to have access to this history.
11756 </para>
11757 <para>
11758 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11759
11760 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11761 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11762 this context do no good.
11763 </para>
11764 <para>
11765 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11766 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11767 <emphasis>copyright-related use</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11768 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11769 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11770 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11771 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11772 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11773 was independent of copyright law.
11774 </para>
11775 <para>
11776 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11777 a film&mdash;the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs&mdash;were
11778 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11779 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11780 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11781 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11782 market didn't have more to offer.
11783 </para>
11784 <para>
11785 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11786 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11787 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11788 would not have interfered with anything.
11789 </para>
11790 <para>
11791 But this situation has now changed.
11792 </para>
11793 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11794 <para>
11795 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11796 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11797 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11798 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11799 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11800 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11801 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11802 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11803 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11804 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11805 </para>
11806 <para>
11807 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11808 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11809 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11810 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11811 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11812 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11813 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11814 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11815 written for a radically different context.
11816 </para>
11817 <para>
11818 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11819 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11820 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11821 <emphasis>copyright</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11822 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11823 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11824 context, copyright is serving no purpose <emphasis>at all</emphasis>
11825 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11826 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11827 </para>
11828 <para>
11829 You may well ask, <quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11830 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11831 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11832 culture widely?</quote>
11833 </para>
11834 <para>
11835 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11836 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes &amp; Noble
11837 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11838 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11839 of a library is to serve what <quote>the market</quote> would demand. But if you
11840 think the role of a library is bigger than this&mdash;if you think its
11841 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11842 particular bit of that culture or not&mdash;then we can't count on the
11843 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11844 </para>
11845 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'/>
11846 <para>
11847 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11848 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11849 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11850 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11851
11852 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11853 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11854 culture, 94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11855 1923 and 1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11856 commercial market, if access is a value, then 6 percent is a failure
11857 to provide that value.<footnote><para>
11858 <!-- f13. -->
11859 Jason Schultz, <quote>The Myth of the 1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,</quote> 20
11860 December 2002, available at
11861 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #54</ulink>.
11862 </para></footnote>
11863
11864 </para>
11865 <para>
11866 <emphasis role='strong'>In January 1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11867 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11868 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11869 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (1)
11870 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11871 <quote>limited Times</quote> requirement, and (2) that extending terms
11872 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11873 </para>
11874 <para>
11875 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11876 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11877 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11878 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11879 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11880 </para>
11881 <para>
11882 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11883 copyrights be for <quote>limited Times</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11884 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11885 <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11886 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11887 terms that are <quote>limited.</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11888 to interpret the term <quote>limited Times</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11889 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11890 power to extend existing terms.
11891 </para>
11892 <para>
11893 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11894 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11895 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11896 whole, where the court will sit <quote>en banc</quote> to hear the case.
11897 </para>
11898 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David</primary></indexterm>
11899 <para>
11900 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11901 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11902
11903 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11904 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11905 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11906 overstepped its bounds.
11907 </para>
11908 <para>
11909 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11910 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11911 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11912 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11913 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11914 </para>
11915 <para>
11916 But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11917 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11918 was set for October of 2002. The summer would be spent writing
11919 briefs and preparing for argument.
11920 </para>
11921 <para>
11922 <emphasis role='strong'>It is over</emphasis> a year later as I write
11923 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
11924 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
11925 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
11926 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
11927 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
11928 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
11929 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
11930 client, Eric Eldred.
11931 </para>
11932 <para>
11933 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11934 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11935 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11936 mistake lost it.
11937 </para>
11938 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11939 <para>
11940 <emphasis role='strong'>The mistake</emphasis> was made early, though
11941 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
11942 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
11943 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
11944 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
11945 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11946 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11947 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11948 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11949 </para>
11950 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11951 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan</primary></indexterm>
11952 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11953 <para>
11954 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11955 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11956 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11957 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11958 told me, if we could make the issue seem <quote>important</quote> to the Supreme
11959 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11960 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against <quote>the
11961 most powerful media companies in the world.</quote>
11962 </para>
11963 <para>
11964 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
11965 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
11966 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
11967 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
11968 <quote>right</quote> as in <quote>true,</quote> I thought, but it is <quote>wrong</quote> as in <quote>it just shouldn't be
11969 that way.</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
11970 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
11971 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
11972 interpretation
11973 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
11974 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
11975 unconstitutional,
11976 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
11977 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
11978 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
11979 Constitution,
11980 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
11981 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
11982 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
11983 </para>
11984 <para>
11985 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
11986 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
11987 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
11988 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
11989 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
11990 why it was unconstitutional.
11991 </para>
11992 <para>
11993 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
11994
11995 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
11996 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
11997 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
11998 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
11999 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
12000 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
12001 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
12002 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
12003 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
12004 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
12005 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
12006 <emphasis>law</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
12007 the widest range of credible critics&mdash;credible not because they
12008 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
12009 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
12010 </para>
12011 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
12012 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis</primary></indexterm>
12013 <para>
12014 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
12015 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
12016 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
12017 Congress. In November 1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
12018 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
12019 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
12020 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
12021 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
12022 to get bogged down?</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
12023 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
12024 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
12025 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
12026 </para>
12027 <para>
12028 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
12029 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
12030 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
12031 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
12032 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
12033 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
12034 </para>
12035 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12036 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
12037 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12038 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
12039 <para>
12040 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
12041 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
12042
12043 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
12044 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/Linux
12045 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
12046 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
12047 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
12048 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
12049 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
12050 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
12051 </para>
12052 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries</primary></indexterm>
12053 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union</primary></indexterm>
12054 <para>
12055 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
12056 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
12057 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
12058 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
12059 </para>
12060 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
12061 <para>
12062 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
12063 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
12064 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
12065 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
12066 clear.
12067 </para>
12068 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George</primary></indexterm>
12069 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
12070 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James</primary></indexterm>
12071 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12072 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton</primary></indexterm>
12073 <para>
12074 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
12075 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
12076 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
12077 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
12078 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
12079 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
12080 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
12081 nothing more than <quote>rent-seeking</quote>&mdash;the fancy term economists use
12082 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
12083 </para>
12084 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12085 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan</primary></indexterm>
12086 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen</primary></indexterm>
12087 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12088 <para>
12089 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
12090 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
12091 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
12092 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
12093 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
12094 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
12095 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
12096 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
12097
12098 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
12099 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
12100 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
12101 </para>
12102 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12103 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
12104 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Commerce Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
12105 <para>
12106 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
12107 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
12108 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
12109 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
12110 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
12111 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
12112 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
12113 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
12114 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
12115 confidence in our argument.
12116 </para>
12117 <para>
12118 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
12119 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these <quote>friends</quote> included
12120 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
12121 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
12122 copyright holders.
12123 </para>
12124 <para>
12125 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
12126 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either&mdash;they
12127 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
12128 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
12129 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
12130 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
12131 wanted to control.
12132 </para>
12133 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George</primary></indexterm>
12134 <indexterm><primary>Porgy and Bess</primary></indexterm>
12135 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
12136 <para>
12137 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
12138 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
12139 Dr. Seuss's work&mdash; better than allowing it to fall into the
12140 public domain&mdash;because if this creativity were in the public
12141 domain, then people could use it to <quote>glorify drugs or to create
12142 pornography.</quote><footnote><para>
12143 <!-- f14. -->
12144 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
12145 U.S. (2003) (No. 01-618), 19.
12146 </para></footnote>
12147 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
12148 <quote>protection</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
12149 to license <citetitle>Porgy and Bess</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
12150 Americans in the cast.<footnote><para>
12151 <!-- f15. -->
12152 Dinitia Smith, <quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
12153 Mouse Joins the Fray,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 28 March 1998, B7.
12154 </para></footnote>
12155 That's
12156 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
12157 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
12158 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
12159 </para>
12160 <para>
12161 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
12162 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
12163 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
12164 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
12165 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, <quote>Give us twenty years
12166 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
12167 better with them than anyone else.</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
12168 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
12169 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
12170 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
12171 </para>
12172 <para>
12173 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
12174 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
12175 copyrights&mdash;extensions that would further concentrate the market;
12176 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
12177 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
12178 </para>
12179 <para>
12180 <emphasis role='strong'>Between February</emphasis> and October, there
12181 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
12182 I set the strategy.
12183 </para>
12184 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
12185 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12186 <para>
12187 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
12188 called <quote>the Conservatives.</quote> The other we called <quote>the Rest.</quote> The
12189 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
12190 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
12191 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
12192 five who had supported the <citetitle>Lopez/Morrison</citetitle> line
12193 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
12194 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
12195 </para>
12196 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12197 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12198 <para>
12199 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
12200 Congress's power. These four&mdash;Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
12201 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer&mdash;had repeatedly argued that
12202 the Constitution
12203 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
12204 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
12205 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
12206 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
12207 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
12208 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
12209 </para>
12210 <para>
12211 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
12212 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
12213 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
12214 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
12215 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
12216 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
12217 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
12218 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
12219 sense.
12220 </para>
12221 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12222 <para>
12223 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
12224 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
12225 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
12226 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
12227 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
12228 these retrospective extensions.
12229 </para>
12230 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'/>
12231 <para>
12232 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
12233 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
12234 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
12235 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
12236 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
12237 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
12238 </para>
12239 <para>
12240 This analysis of <quote>the Rest</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
12241 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
12242 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
12243 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
12244 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation&mdash;the
12245 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
12246 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
12247 powers have limits.
12248 </para>
12249 <para>
12250 This then was the core of our strategy&mdash;a strategy for which I am
12251 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
12252 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
12253 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
12254 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
12255 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
12256 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
12257 supposed to be <quote>limited.</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
12258 reconcile <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> with
12259 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
12260 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
12261 be limited.
12262 </para>
12263 <para>
12264 <emphasis role='strong'>The argument</emphasis> on the government's
12265 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
12266 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
12267 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
12268 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
12269 that practice is unconstitutional.
12270 </para>
12271 <para>
12272 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
12273 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in 1831
12274 and in 1909. And of course, in 1962, Congress began extending
12275 existing
12276 terms regularly&mdash;eleven times in forty years.
12277 </para>
12278 <para>
12279 But this <quote>consistency</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
12280 extended
12281 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
12282 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
12283 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
12284 existing
12285 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
12286 restraint
12287 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
12288 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
12289 hesitated
12290 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
12291 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
12292 </para>
12293 <para>
12294 <emphasis role='strong'>Oral argument</emphasis> was scheduled for the
12295 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
12296 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
12297 <quote>mooted</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
12298
12299 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
12300 help in the case. Such <quote>moots</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
12301 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
12302 </para>
12303 <para>
12304 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
12305 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
12306 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
12307 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
12308 Congress
12309 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
12310 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
12311 this central idea.
12312 </para>
12313 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12314 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12315 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12316 <para>
12317 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
12318 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
12319 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
12320 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
12321 </para>
12322 <para>
12323 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
12324 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
12325 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
12326 the harm&mdash;passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
12327 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.</quote>
12328 </para>
12329 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12330 <para>
12331 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
12332 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
12333 right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
12334 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
12335 does the right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it is right. As
12336 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
12337 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
12338 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
12339 </para>
12340 <para>
12341 <emphasis role='strong'>The night before</emphasis> the argument, a
12342 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
12343 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
12344 culture. Hundreds stood in line
12345
12346 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
12347 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
12348 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
12349 </para>
12350 <para>
12351 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
12352 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
12353 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
12354 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
12355 congressmen
12356 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
12357 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
12358 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
12359 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
12360 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
12361 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
12362 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
12363 family of the Justices.
12364 </para>
12365 <para>
12366 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
12367 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
12368 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
12369 those enumerated powers had any limit.
12370 </para>
12371 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12372 <para>
12373 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
12374 The history was bothering her.
12375 </para>
12376 <blockquote>
12377 <para>
12378 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
12379 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
12380 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
12381 practice that began with the very first act.
12382 </para>
12383 </blockquote>
12384 <para>
12385 She was quite willing to concede <quote>that this flies directly in the face
12386 of what the framers had in mind.</quote> But my response again and again
12387 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
12388 </para>
12389 <blockquote>
12390 <para>
12391 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
12392 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
12393 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
12394 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
12395 is yes.
12396 </para>
12397 </blockquote>
12398 <para>
12399 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
12400 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
12401 Kennedy, who observed,
12402 </para>
12403 <blockquote>
12404 <para>
12405 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
12406 the '76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
12407 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
12408 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
12409 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
12410 </para>
12411 </blockquote>
12412 <para>
12413 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
12414 student,
12415 I answered,
12416 </para>
12417 <blockquote>
12418 <para>
12419 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
12420 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
12421 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
12422 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
12423 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
12424 </para>
12425 </blockquote>
12426 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12427 <para>
12428 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
12429 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
12430 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
12431 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
12432 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
12433 </para>
12434 <para>
12435 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
12436 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> ruling,
12437 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
12438 </para>
12439 <para>
12440 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
12441 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
12442
12443 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
12444 </para>
12445 <blockquote>
12446 <para>
12447 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
12448 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
12449 </para>
12450 <para>
12451 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
12452 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
12453 domain
12454 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
12455 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
12456 into the Copyright Clause.
12457 </para>
12458 </blockquote>
12459 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.</primary></indexterm>
12460 <para>
12461 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
12462 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
12463 asked Solicitor General Olson,
12464 </para>
12465 <blockquote>
12466 <para>
12467 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12468 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
12469 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
12470 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12471 time.
12472 </para>
12473 </blockquote>
12474 <para>
12475 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
12476 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
12477 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
12478 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
12479 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
12480 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
12481 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
12482 Patent Clause&mdash; indeed, the very first case striking a law of
12483 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
12484 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
12485 Court to my side.
12486 </para>
12487 <para>
12488 <emphasis role='strong'>As I left</emphasis> the court that day, I
12489 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
12490 hundred questions I wished I had
12491
12492 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
12493 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
12494 optimistic.
12495 </para>
12496 <para>
12497 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
12498 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
12499 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
12500 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
12501 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
12502 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
12503 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
12504 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
12505 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
12506 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
12507 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court&mdash;in particular,
12508 the Conservatives&mdash;would feel itself constrained by the rule of
12509 law that it had established elsewhere.
12510 </para>
12511 <para>
12512 <emphasis role='strong'>The morning</emphasis> of January 15, 2003, I
12513 was five minutes late to the office and missed the 7:00 A.M. call from
12514 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
12515 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
12516 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
12517 majority. There were two dissents.
12518 </para>
12519 <para>
12520 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
12521 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
12522 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
12523 </para>
12524 <para>
12525 My <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
12526 money in the world against <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. And here
12527 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
12528 reasoning.
12529 </para>
12530 <para>
12531 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
12532 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
12533 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
12534 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
12535 even appear in the Court's opinion.
12536 </para>
12537 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12538 <para>
12539
12540 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
12541 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
12542 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
12543 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
12544 </para>
12545 <para>
12546 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable&mdash;for her, and for Justice
12547 Souter. Neither believes in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
12548 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
12549 they had worked so hard to defeat.
12550 </para>
12551 <para>
12552 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
12553 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
12554 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
12555 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
12556 reconcile the two simply <emphasis>by not addressing the
12557 argument</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
12558 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
12559 followed from the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
12560 be limited, but in this context it would not.
12561 </para>
12562 <para>
12563 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
12564 they would respect? By what right did they&mdash;the silent
12565 five&mdash;get to select the part of the Constitution they would
12566 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
12567 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
12568 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
12569 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
12570 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
12571 the system we have.
12572 </para>
12573 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12574 <para>
12575 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
12576 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
12577 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
12578 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
12579 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
12580 the Court discounted the parallel&mdash;without explaining how the
12581 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
12582 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
12583 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
12584 </para>
12585 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12586 <para>
12587 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
12588 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
12589 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
12590 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
12591 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8
12592 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
12593 that the actual number was 99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
12594 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
12595 <quote>limited,</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
12596 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
12597 </para>
12598 <para>
12599 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
12600 because neither believed in the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
12601 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
12602 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
12603 Sentelle. It was <citetitle>Hamlet</citetitle> without the Prince.
12604 </para>
12605 <para>
12606 <emphasis role='strong'>Defeat brings depression</emphasis>. They say
12607 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
12608 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
12609 sorts.
12610 </para>
12611 <indexterm><primary>originalism</primary></indexterm>
12612 <para>
12613 It was first anger with the five <quote>Conservatives.</quote> It would have been
12614 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> didn't
12615 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
12616 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
12617 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
12618 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
12619 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is <quote>originalism</quote>&mdash;to
12620 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
12621 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
12622 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> and many other <quote>originalist</quote> rulings. Where was their
12623 <quote>originalism</quote> now?
12624 </para>
12625 <para>
12626 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
12627 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
12628 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
12629 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
12630
12631 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
12632 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
12633 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
12634 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
12635 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
12636 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
12637 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
12638 own principles.
12639 </para>
12640 <para>
12641 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
12642 myself.
12643 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
12644 the law as it is.
12645 </para>
12646 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12647 <para>
12648 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
12649 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
12650 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
12651 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
12652 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
12653 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12654 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12655 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12656 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12657 </para>
12658 <para>
12659 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12660 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12661 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12662 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12663 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12664 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12665 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12666 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12667 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12668 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12669 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12670 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12671 effort to persuade; but I
12672 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12673 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12674 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12675 should decide the issue.
12676 </para>
12677 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12678 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12679 <para>
12680 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12681 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12682 Kathleen Sullivan?
12683 </para>
12684 <para>
12685 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12686 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12687 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12688 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12689 </para>
12690 <para>
12691 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12692 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12693 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12694 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12695 have persuaded.
12696 </para>
12697 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12698 <para>
12699 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12700 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12701 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12702 case was a mistake. <quote>The Court is not ready,</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12703 issue should not be raised until it is.
12704 </para>
12705 <para>
12706 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12707 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12708 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12709 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12710 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12711 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12712 this case&mdash;a decision I had made four years before&mdash;was wrong.
12713 </para>
12714 <para>
12715 <emphasis role='strong'>While the reaction</emphasis> to the Sonny
12716 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12717 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12718 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12719 that battle over ideas. Where
12720
12721 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12722 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12723 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12724 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12725 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12726 harmful law. <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12727 </para>
12728 <blockquote>
12729 <para>
12730 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12731 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12732 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12733 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12734 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12735 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12736 </para>
12737 </blockquote>
12738 <para>
12739 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12740 hilarious images&mdash;of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12741 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced in
12742 <xref linkend="fig-18"/>. The <quote>powerful and wealthy</quote> line is a bit
12743 unfair. But the punch in the face felt exactly like that.
12744 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12745 </para>
12746 <figure id="fig-18">
12747 <title>Tom the Dancing Bug cartoon</title>
12748 <graphic fileref="images/18.png" align="center" width="95%"></graphic>
12749 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12750 </figure>
12751 <para>
12752 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12753 quote from <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>. That <quote>grand experiment</quote> we call the
12754 <quote>public domain</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think, <quote>Honey,
12755 I shrunk the Constitution.</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12756 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12757 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12758 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12759 </para>
12760 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12761 </chapter>
12762 <chapter label="14" id="eldred-ii">
12763 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II</title>
12764 <para>
12765 <emphasis role='strong'>The day</emphasis>
12766 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12767 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12768 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was denied&mdash;meaning the case was
12769 really finally over&mdash;fate would have it that I was giving a
12770 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12771 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12772 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12773 wrote an op-ed piece.
12774 </para>
12775 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12776 <para>
12777 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12778 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12779 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12780 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12781 Justice Kennedy: <quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12782 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12783 that.</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12784 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12785 </para>
12786 <para>
12787 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12788 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12789 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12790 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12791 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12792 the work passed into the public domain.
12793 </para>
12794 <para>
12795 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12796 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12797 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12798 </para>
12799 <para>
12800 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12801 is either the <quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act</quote> or the <quote>Copyright
12802 Term Deregulation Act.</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12803 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12804 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12805 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $1. But for
12806 everything else, let the content go.
12807 </para>
12808 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12809 <para>
12810 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12811 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12812 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12813 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12814 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12815 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12816 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12817 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12818 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12819 the stupid harm of the present system.
12820 </para>
12821 <para>
12822 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12823 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12824 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12825 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12826 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12827 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12828 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12829 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12830 where copyright owners could be identified.
12831 </para>
12832 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12833 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12834 <para>
12835 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12836 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
12837 linkend="property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12838 removed in 1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12839 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.<footnote><para>
12840 <!-- f1. -->
12841 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law</primary></indexterm>
12842 Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12843 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12844 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12845 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act,
12846 every text of the Convention has provided that <quote>the enjoyment and the
12847 exercise</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention <quote>shall not be subject
12848 to any formality.</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12849 embodied in Article 5(2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12850 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12851 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12852 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12853 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12854 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12855 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12856 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12857 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>International
12858 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12859 Press, 2001), 153&ndash;54. </para></footnote>
12860 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a <quote>natural right.</quote> Natural
12861 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12862 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12863 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12864 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12865 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12866 </para>
12867 <para>
12868 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12869 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12870 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12871 <quote>Walt Disney creativity</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12872 know what's protected and what's not.
12873 </para>
12874 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12875 <para>
12876 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12877 Berlin in 1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12878 Convention in 1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12879 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12880 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12881 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12882 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an <citetitle>i</citetitle> or cross a
12883 <citetitle>t</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12884 </para>
12885 <para>
12886 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12887 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12888 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12889 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12890 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12891 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12892 </para>
12893 <para>
12894 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12895 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12896 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12897 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12898 burden
12899 imposed upon creators.
12900 </para>
12901 <para>
12902 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was
12903 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12904
12905 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12906 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12907 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12908 the government. He has a property right over the table <quote>naturally,</quote>
12909 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12910 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12911 table.
12912 </para>
12913 <para>
12914 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12915 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12916 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12917 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12918 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12919 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12920 spread.
12921 </para>
12922 <para>
12923 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12924 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12925 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12926 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12927 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12928 important reason to secure registration&mdash;both because it makes
12929 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12930 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12931 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12932 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12933 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12934 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12935 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12936 system of protection for property generally.
12937 </para>
12938 <para>
12939 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12940 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12941 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12942 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12943 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12944 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12945 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12946 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12947
12948 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12949 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12950 <emphasis>lawyer</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12951 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
12952 </para>
12953 <para>
12954 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12955 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12956 didn't <quote>get.</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
12957 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
12958 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, <quote>short,</quote> then this
12959 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
12960 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
12961 be presumptively uncontrolled.
12962 </para>
12963 <para>
12964 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
12965 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
12966 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
12967 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
12968 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
12969 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
12970 seen before <emphasis>because there are no formalities</emphasis>.
12971 </para>
12972 <para>
12973 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
12974 it is worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
12975 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
12976 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
12977 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
12978 </para>
12979 <para>
12980 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
12981 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
12982 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
12983 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
12984 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you.
12985 </para>
12986 <para>
12987 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
12988 registering the work mean that the $1 is really misleading? Isn't the
12989 hassle worth more than $1? Isn't that the real problem with
12990 registration?
12991 </para>
12992 <para>
12993 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
12994 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
12995 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
12996
12997 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
12998 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
12999 address the real problem of <emphasis>governments</emphasis> standing
13000 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
13001 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
13002 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
13003 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
13004 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
13005 upon historical data, that system would move up to 98 percent of
13006 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
13007 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
13008 </para>
13009 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
13010 <para>
13011 <emphasis role='strong'>When Steve Forbes</emphasis> endorsed the
13012 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
13013 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
13014 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
13015 willing to take the first step.
13016 </para>
13017 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe</primary></indexterm>
13018 <para>
13019 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
13020 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
13021 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
13022 possible. In May 2003, it looked as if the bill would be
13023 introduced. On May 16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, <quote>we are
13024 close.</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
13025 something good might happen here.
13026 </para>
13027 <para>
13028 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
13029 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
13030 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
13031 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
13032 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
13033 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
13034 </para>
13035 <para>
13036 The MPAA argued first that Congress had <quote>firmly rejected the central
13037 concept in the proposed bill</quote>&mdash;that copyrights be renewed. That
13038 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's <quote>firm rejection</quote> had occurred
13039 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
13040 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
13041 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
13042 owners&mdash;apparently those who could not afford the $1 fee. Third,
13043 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
13044 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
13045 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
13046 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
13047 off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
13048 argued that the bill would impose <quote>enormous</quote> costs, since a
13049 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
13050 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
13051 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
13052 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
13053 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
13054 film is a valid derivative use.
13055 </para>
13056 <para>
13057 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
13058 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
13059 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
13060 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
13061 or not&mdash;a controversial claim in any case&mdash;unless they know
13062 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
13063 </para>
13064 <para>
13065 <emphasis role='strong'>At the beginning</emphasis> of this book, I
13066 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
13067 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
13068 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
13069 opposition&mdash;the power of the side that fought to defend the
13070 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
13071 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
13072 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
13073 </para>
13074 <para>
13075 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
13076 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
13077 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
13078 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
13079 sense?
13080 </para>
13081 <para>
13082
13083 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
13084 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
13085 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
13086 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
13087 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
13088 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
13089 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
13090 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
13091 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
13092 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
13093 </para>
13094 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin</primary></indexterm>
13095 <para>
13096 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
13097 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
13098 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
13099 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
13100 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
13101 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the <quote>Dark
13102 Content</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
13103 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
13104 </para>
13105 <para>
13106 What does this industry really want?
13107 </para>
13108 <para>
13109 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
13110 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
13111 protecting <emphasis>their</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
13112 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
13113 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
13114 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
13115 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
13116 content that doesn't require <emphasis>their</emphasis> permission
13117 first.
13118 </para>
13119 <para>
13120 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
13121 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
13122 its aim not the protection of <quote>property</quote> but the rejection of a
13123 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
13124 theirs. <emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
13125 theirs</emphasis>.
13126 </para>
13127 <para>
13128 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
13129 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
13130
13131 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
13132 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
13133 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
13134 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
13135 and to share its own creation.
13136 </para>
13137 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13138 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13139 <para>
13140 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
13141 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
13142 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
13143 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
13144 block the progress of others.
13145 </para>
13146 <para>
13147 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
13148 <quote>property</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
13149 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
13150 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing <quote>permission
13151 society.</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
13152 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
13153 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
13154 </para>
13155 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
13156 </chapter>
13157 </part>
13158 <chapter label="15" id="c-conclusion">
13159 <title>CONCLUSION</title>
13160 <indexterm id='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='startofrange'><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in</primary></indexterm>
13161 <indexterm id='idxaidsmedications' class='startofrange'><primary>AIDS medications</primary></indexterm>
13162 <indexterm id='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='startofrange'><primary>antiretroviral drugs</primary></indexterm>
13163 <indexterm id='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>developing countries, foreign patent costs in</primary></indexterm>
13164 <indexterm id='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='startofrange'><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13165 <indexterm id='idxhivaidstherapies' class='startofrange'><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies</primary></indexterm>
13166 <para>
13167 <emphasis role='strong'>There are more</emphasis> than 35 million
13168 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
13169 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
13170 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
13171 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
13172 </para>
13173 <para>
13174 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
13175 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
13176 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
13177 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
13178 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
13179 the disease almost invisible.
13180 </para>
13181 <para>
13182 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
13183 United States, they cost between $10,000 and $15,000 per person per
13184 year. Today, some cost $25,000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
13185 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
13186 population:
13187 $15,000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
13188 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.<footnote><para>
13189 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, <quote>Final Report: Integrating
13190 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy</quote> (London, 2002),
13191 available at
13192 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
13193 release
13194 issued 9 July 2002, only 230,000 of the 6 million who need drugs in
13195 the developing world receive them&mdash;and half of them are in Brazil.
13196 </para></footnote>
13197 </para>
13198 <indexterm id='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13199 <indexterm id='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>pharmaceutical patents</primary></indexterm>
13200 <para>
13201 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
13202 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
13203 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
13204 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
13205 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
13206 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
13207 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
13208 </para>
13209 <para>
13210 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
13211 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
13212 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
13213 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
13214 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
13215 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
13216 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
13217 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
13218 changes.
13219 </para>
13220 <para>
13221 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
13222 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
13223 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
13224 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
13225 costs significantly below the market price.
13226 </para>
13227 <indexterm id='idxinternationallaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>international law</primary></indexterm>
13228 <indexterm id='idxparallelimportation' class='startofrange'><primary>parallel importation</primary></indexterm>
13229 <indexterm id='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='startofrange'><primary>South Africa, Republic of, pharmaceutical imports by</primary></indexterm>
13230 <para>
13231 In 1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
13232 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
13233 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
13234 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
13235 Africa from India. This is called <quote>parallel importation,</quote> and it is
13236 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
13237 permitted within the European Union.<footnote>
13238 <para>
13239 <!-- f2. -->
13240 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
13241 Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37.
13242 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13243 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13244 </para></footnote>
13245 </para>
13246 <indexterm><primary>United States Trade Representative (USTR)</primary></indexterm>
13247 <para>
13248 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
13249 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
13250 characterized it, <quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa &hellip;
13251 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
13252 imports.</quote><footnote><para>
13253 <!-- f3. -->
13254 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13255 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13256 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13257 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 14, available at
13258 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #56</ulink>. For a
13259 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
13260 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
13261 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess.,
13262 Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150&ndash;57 (statement of James
13263 Love).
13264 </para></footnote>
13265 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
13266 government asked South Africa to change the law&mdash;and to add
13267 pressure to that request, in 1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
13268 possible trade sanctions.
13269 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
13270 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
13271 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
13272 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
13273 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
13274 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
13275 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
13276 patent&mdash; pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
13277 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
13278 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
13279 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.<footnote><para>
13280 <!-- f4. -->
13281 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13282 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13283 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13284 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 15. </para></footnote>
13285 </para>
13286 <indexterm startref='idxparallelimportation' class='endofrange'/>
13287 <para>
13288 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
13289 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
13290 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
13291 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
13292 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
13293 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
13294 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
13295 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
13296 </para>
13297 <para>
13298 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
13299 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
13300 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
13301 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
13302 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
13303 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save 15 to 30 million lives.
13304 </para>
13305 <para>
13306 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
13307 profits of United States drug companies&mdash;at least, not substantially. It
13308 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
13309 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
13310 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
13311 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
13312 by U.S. companies.
13313 </para>
13314 <para>
13315 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
13316 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
13317 argument
13318 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
13319 about the sanctity of property.<footnote><para>
13320 <!-- f5. -->
13321 See Sabin Russell, <quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
13322 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24
13323 May 1999, A1, available at
13324 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #57</ulink>
13325 (<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
13326 system of intellectual property protection</quote>); Robert Weissman, <quote>AIDS
13327 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
13328 Medicines,</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus</citetitle> 4:23 (August 1999), available at
13329 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #58</ulink>
13330 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, <quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
13331 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
13332 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
13333 Symposium Journal</citetitle> (Spring 2001): 175.
13334 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
13335 </para></footnote>
13336 It was because <quote>intellectual property</quote> would be violated that these
13337 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
13338 importance of <quote>intellectual property</quote> that led these government actors
13339 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
13340 </para>
13341 <indexterm startref='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='endofrange'/>
13342 <para>
13343 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
13344 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
13345 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
13346 direct cost would be to speed the death of 15 to 30 million Africans,
13347 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the <quote>sanctity</quote> of an
13348 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
13349 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
13350 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
13351 </para>
13352 <indexterm id='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>in pharmaceutical industry</secondary></indexterm>
13353 <para>
13354 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
13355 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
13356 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
13357 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
13358 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system&mdash;
13359 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
13360 </para>
13361 <para>
13362 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
13363 drug companies would love&mdash;they say, and I believe them&mdash;to
13364 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
13365 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
13366 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
13367 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
13368 </para>
13369 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>of drug patents</secondary></indexterm>
13370 <para>
13371 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
13372 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
13373 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, <quote>How
13374 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $1 a pill, but the same
13375 drug would cost an American $1,500?</quote> Because there is no <quote>sound
13376 bite</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
13377 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
13378 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
13379 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
13380 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
13381 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
13382 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal&mdash;the sanctity of an
13383 idea called <quote>intellectual property.</quote>
13384 </para>
13385 <indexterm startref='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='endofrange'/>
13386 <indexterm startref='idxaidsmedications' class='endofrange'/>
13387 <indexterm startref='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='endofrange'/>
13388 <indexterm startref='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='endofrange'/>
13389 <indexterm startref='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='endofrange'/>
13390 <indexterm startref='idxhivaidstherapies' class='endofrange'/>
13391 <indexterm startref='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='endofrange'/>
13392 <para>
13393 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
13394 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
13395 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
13396 What is the argument?
13397 </para>
13398 <para>
13399 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
13400 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
13401 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
13402 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
13403 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
13404 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
13405 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
13406 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
13407 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
13408 were balanced in just this sense.
13409 </para>
13410 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='endofrange'/>
13411 <indexterm startref='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13412 <indexterm startref='idxinternationallaw2' class='endofrange'/>
13413 <para>
13414 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
13415 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
13416 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
13417 our tradition, now reigns in this culture&mdash;bizarrely, and with
13418 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
13419 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
13420 </para>
13421 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13422 <para>
13423 <emphasis role='strong'>A simple idea</emphasis> blinds us, and under
13424 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
13425 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
13426 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
13427 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
13428 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
13429 control of that property removes our
13430 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
13431 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
13432 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
13433 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
13434 this common sense open its eyes.
13435 </para>
13436 <para>
13437 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
13438 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
13439 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
13440 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
13441 to fight <quote>piracy,</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
13442 the idea of <quote>creative property,</quote> while transforming real creators into
13443 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
13444 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
13445 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
13446 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
13447 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
13448 produce the <quote>perfect storm</quote> for free culture.
13449 </para>
13450 <indexterm><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
13451 <indexterm><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13452 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13453 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
13454 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13455 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
13456 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
13457 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>public projects in</secondary></indexterm>
13458 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)</primary></indexterm>
13459 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust</primary></indexterm>
13460 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13461 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web</primary></indexterm>
13462 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System</primary></indexterm>
13463 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
13464 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13465 <para>
13466 <emphasis role='strong'>In August 2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
13467 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
13468 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.<footnote><para>
13469 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>,
13470 August 2003, E1, available at
13471 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #59</ulink>; William New, <quote>Global Group's
13472 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13473 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13474 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #60</ulink>; William New, <quote>U.S. Official
13475 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13476 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13477 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #61</ulink>.
13478 </para></footnote>
13479 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
13480 a meeting to discuss <quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
13481 goods.</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
13482 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
13483 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
13484 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
13485 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
13486 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
13487 that I describe in chapter
13488 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="c-afterword"/>. It
13489 included a project to develop single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs),
13490 which are thought to have great significance in biomedical
13491 research. (That nonprofit project comprised a consortium of the
13492 Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and technological companies,
13493 including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
13494 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
13495 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
13496 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
13497 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
13498 in the early 1980s. And it included <quote>open source and free software.</quote>
13499 </para>
13500 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'/>
13501 <para>
13502 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
13503 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
13504 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
13505 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
13506 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
13507 </para>
13508 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>in international debate on intellectual property</secondary></indexterm>
13509 <para>
13510 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.<footnote><para>
13511 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
13512 meeting.
13513 </para></footnote>
13514 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
13515 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
13516 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
13517 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
13518 property issues.
13519 </para>
13520 <indexterm id='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='startofrange'><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13521 <para>
13522 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
13523 about WIPO. In February 2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
13524 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
13525 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
13526 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
13527 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
13528 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
13529 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
13530 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
13531 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
13532 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
13533 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
13534 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
13535 talk about an <quote>Information Society</quote> unless one also talked about the
13536 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
13537 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
13538 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
13539 stuff of
13540 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
13541 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
13542 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
13543 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
13544 </para>
13545 <para>
13546 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
13547 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
13548 thus the meeting about <quote>open and collaborative projects to create
13549 public goods</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
13550 </para>
13551 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='endofrange'/>
13552 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='endofrange'/>
13553 <indexterm startref='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='endofrange'/>
13554 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
13555 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
13556 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>on free software</secondary></indexterm>
13557 <para>
13558 But there is one project within that list that is highly
13559 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is <quote>open source
13560 and free software.</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
13561 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
13562 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
13563 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
13564 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
13565 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
13566 rather than <quote>proprietary software,</quote> for their own internal uses.
13567 </para>
13568 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft</quote> licenses</primary></indexterm>
13569 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13570 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13571 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13572 <para>
13573 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
13574 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
13575 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
13576 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
13577 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
13578 operating system, the most famous bit of <quote>free software</quote>&mdash;and IBM
13579 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support <quote>open source and
13580 free software</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
13581 to support a mode of software development that is different from
13582 Microsoft's.<footnote><para>
13583 <!-- f8. -->
13584 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
13585 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
13586 <quote>open source</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
13587 principal opposition is to <quote>free software</quote> licensed under a <quote>copyleft</quote>
13588 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
13589 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, <quote>The Future
13590 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
13591 Toward Open Source Software</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
13592 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
13593 Public Policy Research, 2002), 69, available at
13594 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #62</ulink>. See also
13595 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, <citetitle>The Commercial Software
13596 Model</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (3
13597 May 2001), available at
13598 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #63</ulink>.
13599 </para></footnote>
13600 </para>
13601 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='endofrange'/>
13602 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)</primary></indexterm>
13603 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)</primary></indexterm>
13604 <para>
13605 More important for our purposes, to support <quote>open source and free
13606 software</quote> is not to oppose copyright. <quote>Open source and free software</quote>
13607 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
13608 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
13609 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
13610 by
13611 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
13612 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
13613 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
13614 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
13615 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
13616 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
13617 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
13618 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
13619 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
13620 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
13621 </para>
13622 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13623 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13624 <indexterm id='idxkrimjonathan' class='startofrange'><primary>Krim, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
13625 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by</secondary></indexterm>
13626 <para>
13627 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
13628 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
13629 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
13630 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
13631 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
13632 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
13633 States government to veto the meeting.<footnote><para>
13634 <!-- f9. -->
13635 Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> available at <ulink
13636 url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #64</ulink>.
13637 </para></footnote>
13638 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
13639 </para>
13640 <para>
13641 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
13642 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
13643 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
13644 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
13645 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
13646 its lobbying efforts.
13647 </para>
13648 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='endofrange'/>
13649 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13650 <para>
13651 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
13652 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
13653 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
13654 Office, explained that <quote>open-source software runs counter to the
13655 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.</quote>
13656 She is quoted as saying, <quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
13657 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
13658 goals of WIPO.</quote>
13659 </para>
13660 <indexterm startref='idxkrimjonathan' class='endofrange'/>
13661 <para>
13662 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
13663 </para>
13664 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='endofrange'/>
13665 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
13666 <para>
13667 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
13668 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
13669 right called <quote>copyright</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
13670 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it <quote>runs counter</quote> to the mission
13671 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
13672 in understanding&mdash;the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
13673 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
13674 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
13675 </para>
13676 <indexterm><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13677 <indexterm><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13678 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs</primary></indexterm>
13679 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13680 <para>
13681 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to <quote>promote</quote>
13682 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
13683 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
13684 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
13685 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
13686 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
13687 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
13688 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
13689 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
13690 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
13691 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
13692 </para>
13693 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
13694 <para>
13695 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
13696 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
13697 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13698 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13699 <emphasis>their</emphasis> rights. If they want to <quote>waive</quote> or
13700 <quote>disclaim</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13701 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $20 billion to do
13702 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13703 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13704 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13705 to do with <emphasis>their</emphasis> property.
13706 </para>
13707 <indexterm id='idxboland' class='startofrange'><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13708 <para>
13709 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13710 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,</quote> she's
13711 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13712 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13713 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13714 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from <quote>waiving</quote> or
13715 <quote>disclaiming</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13716 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13717 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13718 way possible.
13719 </para>
13720 <indexterm id='idxfeudalsystem' class='startofrange'><primary>feudal system</primary></indexterm>
13721 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>feudal system of</secondary></indexterm>
13722 <para>
13723 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13724 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called <quote>feudalism.</quote> Under
13725 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13726 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13727 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13728 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13729 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13730 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13731 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13732 that control.
13733 </para>
13734 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13735 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13736 <para>
13737 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13738 choice we are now making about intellectual property.<footnote><para>
13739 <!-- f10. -->
13740 See Drahos with Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism</citetitle>, 210&ndash;20.
13741 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13742 </para></footnote>
13743 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13744 choice now is whether that information society will be
13745 <emphasis>free</emphasis> or <emphasis>feudal</emphasis>. The trend is
13746 toward the feudal.
13747 </para>
13748 <indexterm startref='idxfeudalsystem' class='endofrange'/>
13749 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='endofrange'/>
13750 <para>
13751 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13752 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13753 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13754 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13755 </para>
13756 <blockquote>
13757 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='endofrange'/>
13758 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='endofrange'/>
13759 <para>
13760 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13761 it should be (<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13762 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13763 not simply to promote intellectual property rights</quote>), not as it is. If
13764 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13765 say anything wrong. But in the world
13766 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13767 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13768 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13769 </para>
13770 </blockquote>
13771 <para>
13772 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13773 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13774 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13775 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13776 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13777 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13778 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13779 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13780 </para>
13781 <indexterm startref='idxboland' class='endofrange'/>
13782 <para>
13783 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13784 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13785 <quote>goal</quote> of a government should be <quote>to promote the right balance</quote> of
13786 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13787 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. <quote>Typical for
13788 an academic,</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13789 </para>
13790 <para>
13791 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13792 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13793 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13794 our own country's history).
13795 </para>
13796 <para>
13797 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13798 government should be to <quote>seek balance,</quote> then count me with the silly,
13799 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13800 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13801 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13802 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13803 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13804 not lies is just na&iuml;ve, then who have we, the most powerful
13805 democracy in the world, become?
13806 </para>
13807 <para>
13808 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13809 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13810 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13811 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13812 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13813 been part of our tradition for most of our history&mdash;free culture.
13814 </para>
13815 <para>
13816 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13817 </para>
13818 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
13819 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
13820 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted</primary></indexterm>
13821 <para>
13822 <emphasis role='strong'>There are moments</emphasis> of hope in this
13823 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13824 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13825 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13826 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13827 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13828 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13829 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing 700,000 letters were
13830 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13831 </para>
13832 <para>
13833 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13834 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13835 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13836 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13837 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13838 concentration in the media.
13839 </para>
13840 <para>
13841 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13842 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13843 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13844 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13845 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13846 </para>
13847 <para>
13848 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13849 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13850 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13851 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13852 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13853 range of rights&mdash;property rights of a historically extreme
13854 form&mdash;that makes their bigness bad.
13855 </para>
13856 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13857 <para>
13858 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13859 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13860 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13861 Americans have a long history of fighting <quote>big,</quote> wisely or not. That
13862 we could be motivated to fight <quote>big</quote> again is not something new.
13863 </para>
13864 <para>
13865 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13866 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13867 the idea of <quote>intellectual property.</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13868 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13869 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13870 called <quote>property</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13871 </para>
13872 <para>
13873 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13874 of our tragedy.
13875 </para>
13876 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob</primary></indexterm>
13877 <para>
13878 <emphasis role='strong'>As I write</emphasis> these final words, the
13879 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
13880 three hundred individuals.<footnote><para>
13881 <!-- f11. -->
13882 John Borland, <quote>RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers,</quote> CNET News.com, September
13883 2003, available at
13884 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #65</ulink>; Paul
13885 R. La Monica, <quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,</quote> CNN/Money, 8 September
13886 2003, available at
13887 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #66</ulink>; Soni
13888 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, <quote>Sued for a Song,
13889 N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among 261 Cited as Sharers,</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News</citetitle>, 9
13890 September 2003, 3; Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13891 Targets; Single Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13892 Defendants,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13893 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,</quote> <citetitle>Wired News</citetitle>, 10 September 2003,
13894 available at
13895 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #67</ulink>.
13896 </para></footnote>
13897 Eminem has just been sued for <quote>sampling</quote> someone else's
13898 music.<footnote><para>
13899 <!-- f12. -->
13900 Jon Wiederhorn, <quote>Eminem Gets Sued &hellip; by a Little Old Lady,</quote>
13901 mtv.com, 17 September 2003, available at
13902 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #68</ulink>.
13903 </para></footnote>
13904 The story about Bob Dylan <quote>stealing</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13905 finished making the rounds.<footnote><para>
13906 <!-- f13. -->
13907 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, <quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13908 Dylan Songs,</quote> Kansascity.com, 9 July 2003, available at
13909 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #69</ulink>.
13910 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13911 </para></footnote>
13912 An insider from Hollywood&mdash;who insists he must remain
13913 anonymous&mdash;reports <quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13914 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13915 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13916 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13917 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.</quote> Congressmen are
13918 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13919 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13920 kids who use a computer to share content.
13921 </para>
13922 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13923 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13924 <indexterm><primary>BBC</primary></indexterm>
13925 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in</primary></indexterm>
13926 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
13927 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto</primary></indexterm>
13928 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>public creative archive in</secondary></indexterm>
13929 <para>
13930 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13931 that it will build a <quote>Creative Archive,</quote> from which British citizens can
13932 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.<footnote><para>
13933 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,</quote> BBC press release,
13934 24 August 2003, available at
13935 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #70</ulink>.
13936 </para></footnote>
13937 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13938 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13939 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13940 country.<footnote><para>
13941 <!-- f15. -->
13942 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,</quote> Creative Commons Weblog, 6 August 2003,
13943 available at
13944 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #71</ulink>.
13945 </para></footnote>
13946 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13947 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13948 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13949 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13950 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13951 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13952 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13953 day into the Causbys.
13954 </para>
13955 <para>
13956 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
13957 potential is ever to be realized.
13958
13959 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
13960
13961 </para>
13962 </chapter>
13963 <chapter label="16" id="c-afterword">
13964 <title>AFTERWORD</title>
13965 <para>
13966
13967 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
13968 <emphasis role='strong'>At least some</emphasis> who have read this
13969 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
13970 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
13971 </para>
13972 <para>
13973 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
13974 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
13975 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
13976 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
13977 </para>
13978 <para>
13979 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
13980 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
13981 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists&mdash;all to tell this
13982 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
13983 is so important.
13984 </para>
13985 <para>
13986 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
13987 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
13988 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
13989 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
13990 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
13991 </para>
13992 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
13993
13994 <section id="usnow">
13995 <title>US, NOW</title>
13996 <para>
13997 <emphasis role='strong'>Common sense</emphasis> is with the copyright
13998 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
13999 extremes&mdash;as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
14000 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
14001 choice, then the warriors should win.
14002 </para>
14003 <para>
14004 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
14005 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
14006 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright&mdash;<quote>All Rights
14007 Reserved</quote>&mdash; and those who reject copyright&mdash;<quote>No Rights
14008 Reserved.</quote> The <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
14009 permission before you <quote>use</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The <quote>No
14010 Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
14011 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
14012 </para>
14013 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
14014 <indexterm id='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>initial free character of</secondary></indexterm>
14015 <para>
14016 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
14017 tilted in the <quote>no rights reserved</quote> direction. Content could be copied
14018 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
14019 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
14020 the
14021
14022 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
14023 original design of the Internet was <quote>no rights reserved.</quote> Content was
14024 <quote>taken</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
14025 unprotected.
14026 </para>
14027 <para>
14028 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
14029 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
14030 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
14031 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
14032 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
14033 architecture made the effective default <quote>no rights reserved,</quote> the
14034 future architecture will make the effective default <quote>all rights
14035 reserved.</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
14036 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
14037 content requires permission. The <quote>cut and paste</quote> world that defines
14038 the Internet today will become a <quote>get permission to cut and paste</quote>
14039 world that is a creator's nightmare.
14040 </para>
14041 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='endofrange'/>
14042 <indexterm startref='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='endofrange'/>
14043 <para>
14044 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle&mdash;neither
14045 <quote>all rights reserved</quote> nor <quote>no rights reserved</quote> but <quote>some rights
14046 reserved</quote>&mdash; and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
14047 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
14048 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
14049 before.
14050 </para>
14051 <section id="examples">
14052 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples</title>
14053 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>restoration efforts on previous aspects of</secondary></indexterm>
14054 <indexterm id='idxbrowsing' class='startofrange'><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
14055 <indexterm id='idxprivacyrights2' class='startofrange'><primary>privacy rights</primary></indexterm>
14056 <para>
14057 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
14058 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
14059 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
14060 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
14061 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
14062 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
14063 to your neighbors or boss. The <quote>privacy</quote> of your browsing habits was
14064 assured.
14065 </para>
14066 <para>
14067 What made it assured?
14068 </para>
14069 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
14070 <para>
14071 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
14072 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>, your
14073 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
14074 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
14075 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
14076 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
14077 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
14078 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
14079 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
14080 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
14081 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
14082 (there is no law protecting <quote>privacy</quote> in public places), and in many
14083 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
14084 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
14085 </para>
14086 <indexterm id='idxamazon' class='startofrange'><primary>Amazon</primary></indexterm>
14087 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet</primary></indexterm>
14088 <indexterm id='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>privacy protection on</secondary></indexterm>
14089 <para>
14090 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
14091 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
14092 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
14093 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
14094 <quote>recently viewed</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
14095 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
14096 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any <quote>privacy</quote>
14097 protected by the friction disappears, too.
14098 </para>
14099 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>privacy rights in use of</secondary></indexterm>
14100 <para>
14101 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
14102 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
14103 people should have the <quote>right</quote> to browse in a library without the
14104 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
14105 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
14106 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
14107 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
14108 disappears.
14109 </para>
14110 <indexterm startref='idxbrowsing' class='endofrange'/>
14111 <indexterm startref='idxamazon' class='endofrange'/>
14112 <para>
14113 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define <quote>privacy</quote>
14114 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
14115 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
14116 friction did.<footnote><para>
14117 <!-- f1. -->
14118
14119 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, <quote>Fair Information Practices and the
14120 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
14121 Law Review</citetitle> 1 (2001): par. 6&ndash;18, available at
14122
14123 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>
14124 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
14125 also Jeffrey Rosen, <citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
14126 in an Anxious Age</citetitle> (New York: Random House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs
14127 between technology and privacy).</para></footnote>
14128 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
14129 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
14130
14131 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
14132 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
14133 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
14134 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
14135 </para>
14136 <indexterm startref='idxprivacyrights2' class='endofrange'/>
14137 <indexterm startref='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='endofrange'/>
14138 <indexterm><primary>Data General</primary></indexterm>
14139 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
14140 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
14141 <para>
14142 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
14143 movement. When computers with software were first made available
14144 commercially, the software&mdash;both the source code and the
14145 binaries&mdash; was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
14146 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
14147 care much about controlling their software.
14148 </para>
14149 <indexterm id='idxstallmanrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Stallman, Richard</primary></indexterm>
14150 <para>
14151 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
14152 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
14153 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
14154 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
14155 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
14156 people's work.
14157 </para>
14158 <para>
14159 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
14160 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
14161 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
14162 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
14163 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
14164 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
14165 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
14166 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
14167 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
14168 anything else?
14169 </para>
14170 <indexterm id='idxproprietarycode' class='startofrange'><primary>proprietary code</primary></indexterm>
14171 <para>
14172 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
14173 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
14174 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
14175 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
14176 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
14177 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
14178 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
14179 </para>
14180 <para>
14181 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
14182 early 1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
14183 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
14184 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
14185 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
14186 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
14187 fundamentally weakened.
14188 </para>
14189 <indexterm startref='idxproprietarycode' class='endofrange'/>
14190 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus</primary></indexterm>
14191 <para>
14192 Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
14193 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
14194 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's <quote>Linux</quote>
14195 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
14196 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14197 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14198 </para>
14199 <para>
14200 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
14201 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
14202 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
14203 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
14204 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
14205 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
14206 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
14207 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
14208 byproduct.
14209 </para>
14210 <para>
14211 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
14212 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
14213 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
14214 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
14215 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
14216 what before had been passively guaranteed.
14217 </para>
14218 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='endofrange'/>
14219 <indexterm startref='idxstallmanrichard' class='endofrange'/>
14220 <indexterm id='idxacademicjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
14221 <indexterm id='idxscientificjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>scientific journals</primary></indexterm>
14222 <para>
14223 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
14224 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
14225 scientific journals are produced.
14226 </para>
14227 <indexterm id='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>Lexis and Westlaw</primary></indexterm>
14228 <indexterm id='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
14229 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14230 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>access to opinions of</secondary></indexterm>
14231 <para>
14232 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
14233 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
14234 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
14235 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
14236 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
14237 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
14238 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
14239 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
14240 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
14241 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
14242 and Westlaw are also free
14243 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
14244 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
14245 Court opinion through their respective services.
14246 </para>
14247 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>access fees for material in</secondary></indexterm>
14248 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>license system for rebuilding of</secondary></indexterm>
14249 <para>
14250 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
14251 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
14252 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
14253 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
14254 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
14255 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
14256 access to material that is not in the public domain.
14257 </para>
14258 <indexterm startref='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='endofrange'/>
14259 <indexterm startref='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='endofrange'/>
14260 <para>
14261 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
14262 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
14263 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
14264 </para>
14265 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14266 <para>
14267 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
14268 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
14269 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
14270 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
14271 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
14272 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
14273 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
14274 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
14275 the technology of paper journals (architecture)&mdash;namely, that it
14276 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
14277 </para>
14278 <para>
14279 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
14280 that libraries not give the general public access to the
14281 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
14282 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
14283 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
14284 granted before.
14285 </para>
14286 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
14287 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
14288 <para>
14289 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
14290 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
14291 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
14292 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
14293 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
14294 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
14295 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
14296 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
14297 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
14298 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
14299 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
14300 </para>
14301 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='endofrange'/>
14302 <para>
14303 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
14304 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
14305 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
14306 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
14307 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
14308 presumptively a good&mdash;especially when it helps spread knowledge
14309 and science.
14310 </para>
14311 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='endofrange'/>
14312 <indexterm startref='idxacademicjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14313 <indexterm startref='idxscientificjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14314 </section>
14315 <section id="oneidea">
14316 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea</title>
14317 <indexterm id='idxcreativecommons' class='startofrange'><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
14318 <para>
14319 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
14320 increasing control effected through law and technology.
14321 </para>
14322 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University</primary></indexterm>
14323 <para>
14324 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
14325 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
14326 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
14327 <emphasis>reasonable</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
14328 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
14329 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
14330 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
14331 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
14332 make this possible.
14333 </para>
14334 <para>
14335 <emphasis>Simple</emphasis>&mdash;which means without a middleman, or
14336 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
14337 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
14338 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
14339 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
14340 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
14341 shared. These three expressions together&mdash;a legal license, a
14342 human-readable description, and
14343 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
14344 machine-readable tags&mdash;constitute a Creative Commons license. A
14345 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
14346 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
14347 that the person associated with the license believes in something
14348 different than the <quote>All</quote> or <quote>No</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
14349 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
14350 certain freedoms are given.
14351 </para>
14352 <para>
14353 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
14354 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
14355 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
14356 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
14357 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
14358 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (<quote>share and share
14359 alike</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
14360 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
14361 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
14362 </para>
14363 <para>
14364 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
14365 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
14366 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
14367 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
14368 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
14369 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
14370 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
14371 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
14372 a public domain.
14373 </para>
14374 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia</primary></indexterm>
14375 <para>
14376 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
14377 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
14378 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
14379 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
14380 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
14381 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
14382 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
14383 of content (<quote>content conducers,</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
14384 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
14385 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
14386 </para>
14387 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
14388 <para>
14389 The aim is not to fight the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts. The aim is to
14390 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
14391 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
14392 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
14393 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
14394 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
14395 the background of digital technologies. New rules&mdash;with different
14396 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
14397 them&mdash;are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
14398 to begin to build those rules.
14399 </para>
14400 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
14401 <para>
14402 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
14403 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
14404 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
14405 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
14406 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
14407 </para>
14408 <para>
14409 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
14410 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1)
14411 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
14412 and (2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
14413 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (1) will download
14414 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2)
14415 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
14416 them (2)-goods. If there are more (2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the
14417 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
14418 <emphasis>increase</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
14419 </para>
14420 <para>
14421 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
14422 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
14423 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
14424 was a total success.
14425 </para>
14426 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)</primary></indexterm>
14427 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter</primary></indexterm>
14428 <para>
14429 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
14430 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
14431 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
14432 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled <citetitle>Free for All</citetitle>,
14433 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
14434 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
14435 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
14436 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
14437 well.
14438 </para>
14439 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'/>
14440 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy</primary></indexterm>
14441 <indexterm><primary>rap music</primary></indexterm>
14442 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter</primary></indexterm>
14443 <para>
14444 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
14445 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
14446 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
14447 reasons. Many who use the <quote>sampling license</quote> do so because anything
14448 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
14449 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
14450 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
14451 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
14452 art&mdash;they, too, sample from others. Because the
14453 <emphasis>legal</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
14454 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
14455 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not <quote>allow</quote>
14456 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
14457 high<footnote><para>
14458 <!-- f2. -->
14459 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
14460 Culture Wars</citetitle> (2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
14461 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
14462 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>.
14463 </para></footnote>),
14464 these artists release into the creative environment content
14465 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
14466 </para>
14467 <para>
14468 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
14469 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
14470 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
14471 you are effectively saying you believe in the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote>
14472 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
14473 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
14474 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
14475 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
14476 this notion of <quote>Some Rights Reserved,</quote> and gives many the chance to
14477 say it to others.
14478 </para>
14479 <para>
14480 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
14481 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
14482 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
14483 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
14484
14485 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
14486 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
14487 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
14488 </para>
14489 <para>
14490 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
14491 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
14492 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
14493 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
14494 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
14495 steps are possible.
14496 </para>
14497 <para>
14498 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
14499 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
14500 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
14501 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
14502 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
14503 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
14504 creativity to spread more easily.
14505 </para>
14506 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='endofrange'/>
14507 <indexterm startref='idxcreativecommons' class='endofrange'/>
14508 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
14509 </section>
14510 </section>
14511 <section id="themsoon">
14512 <title>THEM, SOON</title>
14513 <para>
14514 <emphasis role='strong'>We will</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
14515 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
14516 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
14517 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
14518 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
14519 </para>
14520 <para>
14521 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
14522 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
14523 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
14524 to our end.
14525 </para>
14526
14527 <section id="formalities">
14528 <title>1. More Formalities</title>
14529 <para>
14530 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
14531 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
14532 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
14533 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
14534 </para>
14535 <para>
14536 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
14537 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
14538 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
14539 protected.
14540 </para>
14541 <para>
14542 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
14543 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
14544 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
14545 default is control, and <quote>formalities</quote> are banished.
14546 </para>
14547 <para>
14548 Why?
14549 </para>
14550 <para>
14551 As I suggested in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
14552 linkend="property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
14553 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
14554 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
14555 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
14556 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
14557 formalities were getting in the way.
14558 </para>
14559 <para>
14560 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
14561 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
14562 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
14563 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
14564 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
14565 trace&mdash; there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
14566 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
14567 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
14568 past. And thus, the <emphasis>lack</emphasis> of formalities forces
14569 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
14570 </para>
14571 <para>
14572 The law should therefore change this requirement<footnote><para>
14573 <!-- f1. -->
14574 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
14575 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
14576 adopted by other countries as well.</para></footnote>&mdash;but it
14577 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
14578 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
14579 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
14580 </para>
14581 <para>
14582 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
14583 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
14584 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
14585 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
14586 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
14587 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
14588 developed by others.
14589 </para>
14590
14591 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
14592
14593 <section id="registration">
14594 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL</title>
14595 <para>
14596 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
14597 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
14598 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
14599 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
14600 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
14601 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
14602 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
14603 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
14604 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
14605 panic&mdash;nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
14606 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
14607 </para>
14608 <para>
14609 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
14610 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
14611 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
14612 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
14613 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
14614 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
14615 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
14616 </para>
14617 <para>
14618 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
14619 There are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world.
14620 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
14621 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
14622 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
14623 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
14624 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
14625 with which registration occurs up.
14626 </para>
14627 <para>
14628 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
14629 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
14630 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
14631 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
14632 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
14633 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
14634 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
14635 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
14636 formality&mdash;while producing a database
14637 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
14638 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
14639 </para>
14640
14641 </section>
14642 <section id="marking">
14643 <title>MARKING</title>
14644 <para>
14645 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
14646 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
14647 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule&mdash;akin to
14648 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
14649 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
14650 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
14651 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
14652 uniformly across all media.
14653 </para>
14654 <para>
14655 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
14656 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
14657 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
14658 use the work.
14659 </para>
14660 <para>
14661 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
14662 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
14663 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
14664 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
14665 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
14666 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
14667 signal from the failure to mark&mdash;not the loss of the copyright, but the
14668 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
14669 </para>
14670 <para>
14671 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
14672 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
14673 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
14674 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
14675 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
14676 doesn't give permission.<footnote><para>
14677 <!-- f2. -->
14678 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
14679 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
14680 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
14681 </para></footnote>
14682 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be <quote>use unless someone
14683 complains.</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
14684 stop using the work in any new
14685 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
14686 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
14687 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
14688 their work.
14689 </para>
14690 <para>
14691 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
14692 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
14693 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
14694 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
14695 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
14696 </para>
14697 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>copyright marking of</secondary></indexterm>
14698 <para>
14699 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
14700 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
14701 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
14702 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
14703 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
14704 <emphasis>solely</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
14705 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
14706 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
14707 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
14708 other important functions.
14709 </para>
14710 <para>
14711 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
14712 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
14713 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
14714 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
14715 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
14716 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
14717 </para>
14718 <para>
14719 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
14720 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
14721 make things unclear.
14722 </para>
14723 <para>
14724 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
14725 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
14726 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
14727 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
14728 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
14729 that assertion at the appropriate time.
14730 </para>
14731
14732 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
14733 </section>
14734 </section>
14735 <section id="shortterms">
14736 <title>2. Shorter Terms</title>
14737 <para>
14738 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14739 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14740 natural authors.
14741 </para>
14742 <para>
14743 In <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14744 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14745 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14746 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14747 radical. <citetitle>The Economist</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14748 copyright term.<footnote><para>
14749
14750 <!-- f3. -->
14751 <quote>A Radical Rethink,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 366:8308 (25 January 2003): 15,
14752 available at
14753 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #74</ulink>.
14754 </para></footnote>
14755 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14756 </para>
14757 <para>
14758 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14759 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14760 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14761 terms.
14762 </para>
14763 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14764 <listitem><para>
14765 <!-- (1) -->
14766 <emphasis>Keep it short:</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14767 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14768 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14769 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14770 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14771 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14772 </para></listitem>
14773 <listitem><para>
14774 <!-- (2) -->
14775 <emphasis>Keep it simple:</emphasis> The line between the public
14776 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14777 fuzziness of <quote>fair use,</quote> and the distinction between <quote>ideas</quote> and
14778 <quote>expression.</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14779 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14780 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14781 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14782 <quote>lawyer-free zone</quote> makes the complexities of <quote>fair use</quote> and
14783 <quote>idea/expression</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14784 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14785 </para></listitem>
14786 <listitem>
14787 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions</primary></indexterm>
14788 <para>
14789 <!-- (3) -->
14790 <emphasis>Keep it alive:</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14791 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14792 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14793 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14794 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14795 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14796 pension.<footnote><para>
14797 <!-- f4. -->
14798 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14799 and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001),
14800 available at
14801 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #75</ulink>.
14802 </para></footnote>
14803 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14804 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14805 single form.
14806 </para></listitem>
14807 <listitem><para>
14808 <!-- (4) -->
14809 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14810 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14811 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14812 in 1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14813 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14814 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in 1923 than we
14815 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14816 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14817 the number of authors who wrote in 1923. Of course, we can increase
14818 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14819 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14820 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14821 creativity in 1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14822 we can do about that now. </para></listitem>
14823 </orderedlist>
14824 <para>
14825 These changes together should produce an <emphasis>average</emphasis>
14826 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until 1976,
14827 the average term was just 32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14828 same.
14829 </para>
14830 <para>
14831 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas <quote>radical.</quote> (After all, I
14832 call them <quote>extremists.</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14833 than the term under Richard Nixon. How <quote>radical</quote> can it be to ask for
14834 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14835 </para>
14836
14837 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14838
14839 </section>
14840 <section id="freefairuse">
14841 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use</title>
14842 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
14843 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
14844 <para>
14845 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14846 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14847 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14848 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14849 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14850 the emergence of that new technology.
14851 </para>
14852 <para>
14853 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors <quote>exclusive
14854 right</quote> to <quote>their writings.</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14855 right to <quote>their writings</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14856 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14857 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14858 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14859 though that movie is not <quote>my writing.</quote>
14860 </para>
14861 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin</primary></indexterm>
14862 <para>
14863 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it
14864 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14865 control translations and dramatizations of a work.<footnote><para>
14866 <!-- f5. -->
14867 Benjamin Kaplan, <citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14868 University Press, 1967), 32.
14869 </para></footnote>
14870 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14871 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14872 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14873 </para>
14874 <blockquote>
14875 <para>
14876 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14877 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14878 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14879 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.<footnote><para>
14880 <!-- f6. --> Ibid., 56.
14881 </para></footnote>
14882 </para>
14883 </blockquote>
14884 <para>
14885 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14886 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14887 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14888 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14889 Consider each limitation in turn.
14890 </para>
14891 <para>
14892 <emphasis>Term:</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14893 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14894 sense to protect John
14895
14896 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14897 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14898 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14899 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14900 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14901 after the creative work is done.
14902 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
14903 </para>
14904 <para>
14905 <emphasis>Scope:</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14906 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14907 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14908 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14909 material. When all <quote>reuse</quote> of creative material was within the control
14910 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14911 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14912 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14913 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14914 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14915 the creative process. Smothers it.
14916 </para>
14917 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
14918 <para>
14919 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14920 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14921 foreseeable derivative rights&mdash;turning a book into a movie, or a
14922 poem into a musical score&mdash;it doesn't make sense to require
14923 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14924 much more sense.
14925 </para>
14926 <para>
14927 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14928 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14929 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14930 Paul Goldstein.<footnote>
14931 <para>
14932 <!-- f7. -->
14933 Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14934 Jukebox</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187&ndash;216.
14935 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul</primary></indexterm>
14936 </para></footnote>
14937 His view is that the law should be written so that
14938 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14939 </para>
14940 <para>
14941 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14942 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14943 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14944 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14945 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14946 </para>
14947 <para>
14948 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14949 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
14950 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
14951 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
14952 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
14953 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
14954 </para>
14955 </section>
14956
14957 <section id="liberatemusic">
14958 <title>4. Liberate the Music&mdash;Again</title>
14959 <para>
14960 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
14961 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
14962 is, to most people, most pressing&mdash;music. There is no other
14963 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
14964 battles around the sharing of music.
14965 </para>
14966 <para>
14967 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
14968 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
14969 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
14970 killer app&mdash;possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
14971 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
14972 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
14973 innovation on the network.
14974 </para>
14975 <para>
14976 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
14977 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
14978 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
14979 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
14980 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
14981 </para>
14982 <para>
14983 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
14984 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
14985 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
14986 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="piracy"/>, they enable
14987 four different kinds of sharing:
14988 </para>
14989 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
14990 <listitem><para>
14991 <!-- A. -->
14992 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
14993 for purchasing CDs.
14994 </para></listitem>
14995 <listitem><para>
14996 <!-- B. -->
14997 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
14998 on the way to purchasing CDs.
14999 </para></listitem>
15000 <listitem><para>
15001 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
15002 <!-- C. -->
15003 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15004 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
15005 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
15006 </para></listitem>
15007 <listitem><para>
15008 <!-- D. -->
15009 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15010 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
15011 owner plainly endorses.
15012 </para></listitem>
15013 </orderedlist>
15014 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
15015 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
15016 <para>
15017 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
15018 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
15019 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
15020 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
15021 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
15022 significantly weakened.
15023 </para>
15024 <para>
15025 As I said in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
15026 linkend="piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
15027 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
15028 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
15029 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
15030 networks.
15031 </para>
15032 <para>
15033 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
15034 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
15035 should respond.
15036 </para>
15037 <para>
15038 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
15039 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
15040 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
15041 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
15042 is cumbersome and slow&mdash;we in the United States are lucky to have
15043 broadband service at 1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
15044 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
15045 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
15046 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
15047 Internet is mainly just an idea.
15048 </para>
15049 <para>
15050 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
15051 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
15052 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
15053 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
15054 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
15055 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
15056 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
15057 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
15058 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
15059 where everywhere you are&mdash;except maybe the desert or the
15060 Rockies&mdash;you can instantaneously be connected to the
15061 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
15062 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
15063 </para>
15064 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over</primary></indexterm>
15065 <para>
15066 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
15067 give you access to content on the fly&mdash;such as Internet radio,
15068 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
15069 then, is the critical point: When it is <emphasis>extremely</emphasis>
15070 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
15071 <emphasis>easier</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
15072 access to content than it will be to download and store content
15073 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
15074 content</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
15075 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
15076 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
15077 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
15078 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
15079 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
15080 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
15081 paying for this content even though <quote>free</quote> content is available in the
15082 form of MP3s across the Web.<footnote><para>
15083 <!-- f8. -->
15084 See, for example, <quote>Music Media Watch,</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3
15085 April 2002, available at
15086 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #76</ulink>.
15087 </para></footnote>
15088
15089 </para>
15090 <para>
15091 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
15092 present: It is emphatically temporary. The <quote>problem</quote> with file
15093 sharing&mdash;to the extent there is a real problem&mdash;is a problem
15094 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
15095 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
15096 makers today to be <quote>solving</quote> this problem in light of a technology
15097 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
15098 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
15099 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
15100 artists get paid, during
15101
15102 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
15103 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
15104 and twenty-first-century technologies.
15105 </para>
15106 <para>
15107 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different <quote>problems</quote>
15108 here to solve. Let's start with type D content&mdash;uncopyrighted
15109 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
15110 <quote>problem</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
15111 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
15112 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
15113 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
15114 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
15115 order to eliminate kidnapping.
15116 </para>
15117 <para>
15118 Type C content raises a different <quote>problem.</quote> This is content that was,
15119 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
15120 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
15121 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
15122 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
15123 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
15124 way that returns something to the artist.
15125 </para>
15126 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
15127 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
15128 <para>
15129 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
15130 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
15131 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
15132 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
15133 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
15134 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
15135 from the author's perspective, this <quote>sharing</quote> of his content without
15136 his being compensated is less than ideal.
15137 </para>
15138 <para>
15139 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
15140 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
15141 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
15142 providers would be free, under this rule, to <quote>share</quote> that content,
15143 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
15144 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
15145 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
15146 </para>
15147 <para>
15148
15149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
15150 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
15151 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
15152 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
15153 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
15154 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
15155 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
15156 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
15157 trade.
15158 </para>
15159 <para>
15160 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
15161 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
15162 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
15163 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
15164 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
15165 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
15166 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
15167 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
15168 </para>
15169 <para>
15170 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
15171 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
15172 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
15173 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
15174 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
15175 delivering and accessing content.
15176 </para>
15177 <para>
15178 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
15179 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
15180 </para>
15181 <para>
15182 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
15183 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
15184 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
15185 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
15186 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
15187 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
15188 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
15189 harmed the interests of the content industry.
15190 </para>
15191 <para>
15192 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
15193 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
15194 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
15195 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
15196 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
15197 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
15198 way to compensate those who are harmed.
15199 </para>
15200 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15201 <para>
15202 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
15203 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.<footnote>
15204 <para>
15205 <!-- f9. -->
15206 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15207 William Fisher, <citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities</citetitle> (last
15208 revised: 10 October 2000), available at
15209 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #77</ulink>; William
15210 Fisher, <citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
15211 Entertainment</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
15212 2004), ch. 6, available at
15213 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #78</ulink>. Professor
15214 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
15215 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
15216 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, <quote>Impose a
15217 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,</quote> available at
15218 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Who's Holding Back
15219 Broadband?</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
15220 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
15221 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, 26 February 2002,
15222 available at
15223 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, <citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
15224 Use Fee (IPUF)</citetitle>, 3 March 2002, available at
15225 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
15226 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 13 May
15227 2002, available at
15228 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, <quote>Getting Copyright Right,</quote>
15229 IEEE Spectrum Online, 1 July 2002, available at
15230 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #83</ulink>; Declan
15231 McCullagh, <quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,</quote> CNET News.com, 27 August
15232 2002, available at
15233 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #84</ulink>.
15234 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
15235 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
15236 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
15237 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
15238 debate by about a decade. See
15239 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #85</ulink>.
15240 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William</primary></indexterm>
15241 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
15242 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15243 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'/>
15244 </para></footnote>
15245 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
15246 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
15247 would (1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
15248 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
15249 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
15250 develop (2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
15251 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (3) artists would be
15252 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (4) an appropriate
15253 tax.
15254 </para>
15255 <para>
15256 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
15257 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
15258 <citetitle>Promises to Keep</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
15259 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
15260 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
15261 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
15262 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
15263 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
15264 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
15265 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
15266 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
15267 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
15268 controlling access.
15269 </para>
15270 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'/>
15271 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15272 <para>
15273 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
15274 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
15275 the system supports the widest range of <quote>semiotic democracy</quote>
15276 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
15277 other changes I described were accomplished&mdash;in particular, the
15278 limits on derivative
15279
15280 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
15281 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
15282 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
15283 allowed to do with the content itself.
15284 </para>
15285 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
15286 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore</primary></indexterm>
15287 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
15288 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>prices of</secondary></indexterm>
15289 <para>
15290 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
15291 <quote>harm</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
15292 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
15293 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
15294 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
15295 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat <quote>free</quote> by being
15296 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
15297 of songs at even the very high price of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents,
15298 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
15299 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
15300 Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a song. And no doubt
15301 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
15302 on-line.
15303 </para>
15304 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
15305 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast</secondary></indexterm>
15306 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
15307 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
15308 <indexterm><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in</secondary></indexterm>
15309 <para>
15310 This competition has already occurred against the background of <quote>free</quote>
15311 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
15312 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
15313 that, there is nothing impossible at all about <quote>competing with free.</quote>
15314 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
15315 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
15316 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
15317 theaters are often luxurious&mdash;with <quote>first class</quote> seats, and meals
15318 served while you watch a movie&mdash;as they struggle and succeed in
15319 finding ways to compete with <quote>free.</quote>
15320 </para>
15321 <para>
15322 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
15323 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
15324 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
15325 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
15326 innovators&mdash;ones who would have a right to the content, and would
15327 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
15328 the law.
15329 </para>
15330 <para>
15331 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
15332 </para>
15333 <para>
15334
15335 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
15336 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
15337 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
15338 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
15339 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
15340 create.
15341 </para>
15342 <para>
15343 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
15344 by
15345 </para>
15346 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
15347 <listitem><para>
15348 <!-- 1. -->
15349 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
15350 </para></listitem>
15351 <listitem><para>
15352 <!-- 2. -->
15353 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
15354 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
15355 statute;
15356 </para></listitem>
15357 <listitem><para>
15358 <!-- 3. -->
15359 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
15360 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
15361 </para></listitem>
15362 </orderedlist>
15363 <para>
15364 But what if <quote>piracy</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
15365 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
15366 consumers continue to <quote>take</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
15367 something then?
15368 </para>
15369 <para>
15370 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
15371 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
15372 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
15373 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
15374 technology that is 95 percent secure and produces a market of size <citetitle>x</citetitle>,
15375 or (b) to have a technology that is 50 percent secure but produces a
15376 market of five times <citetitle>x</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
15377 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
15378 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
15379 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
15380 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
15381 pirates.
15382 </para>
15383 <para>
15384 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
15385 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
15386 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
15387
15388 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
15389 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
15390 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
15391 </para>
15392 </section>
15393
15394 <section id="firelawyers">
15395 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers</title>
15396 <para>
15397 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
15398 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
15399 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
15400 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
15401 </para>
15402 <para>
15403 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
15404 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
15405 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
15406 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
15407 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
15408 strong view queers the law.
15409 </para>
15410 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville</primary></indexterm>
15411 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of</secondary></indexterm>
15412 <para>
15413 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
15414 <quote>radical</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
15415 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
15416 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
15417 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
15418 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
15419 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
15420 Nimmer, thought it obvious.<footnote><para>
15421 <!-- f10. -->
15422 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Copyright's First Amendment</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
15423 Memorial Lecture), <citetitle>UCLA Law Review</citetitle> 48 (2001): 1057, 1069&ndash;70.
15424 </para></footnote>
15425
15426 </para>
15427 <para>
15428 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
15429 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
15430 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
15431 </para>
15432 <para>
15433 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
15434 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
15435 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
15436 the legal system are slight.<footnote><para>
15437 <!-- f11. -->
15438 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
15439 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
15440 leading him to question his own publicly stated
15441 position&mdash;twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
15442 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
15443 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
15444 J. Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
15445 Drive the Digital Marketplace</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002), (reviewing his
15446 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
15447 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?</quote> working paper, June 2003,
15448 available at
15449 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #86</ulink>.
15450 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
15451 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
15452 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
15453 <citetitle>Rethinking</citetitle>, 174&ndash;76.
15454 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
15455 </para></footnote>
15456 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
15457 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
15458 them it works.
15459 </para>
15460 <para>
15461 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
15462 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
15463 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
15464 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
15465 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
15466 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
15467 practically never be done.
15468 </para>
15469 <para>
15470 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
15471 billed at the largest firms at more than $400 per hour. How much time
15472 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
15473 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
15474 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
15475 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
15476 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
15477 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
15478 </para>
15479 <para>
15480 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
15481 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
15482 their duty to change the way the law works&mdash;or better, to change the
15483 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
15484 top 1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
15485 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
15486 </para>
15487 <para>
15488 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
15489 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
15490 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
15491 its review.
15492 </para>
15493 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
15494 <para>
15495 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
15496 technology&mdash;the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
15497 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
15498 technology&mdash;a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
15499 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
15500 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
15501 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
15502 </para>
15503 <para>
15504 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture&mdash;but it should
15505 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
15506
15507 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311-->
15508 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
15509 simple pragmatic question: <quote>Will it do good?</quote> When challenged about
15510 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, <quote>Why not?</quote>
15511 </para>
15512 <para>
15513 We should ask, <quote>Why?</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
15514 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
15515 keep your lawyers away.
15516 </para>
15517 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
15518 </section>
15519 </section>
15520 </chapter>
15521 <chapter label="17" id="c-notes">
15522 <title>NOTES</title>
15523 <para>
15524 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
15525 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
15526 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
15527 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
15528 this book. For each link below, you can go to
15529 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
15530 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
15531 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
15532 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
15533 the material.
15534 </para>
15535
15536 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
15537 <?latex \theendnotes ?>
15538
15539 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
15540
15541 </chapter>
15542 <chapter label="18" id="c-acknowledgments">
15543 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS</title>
15544 <para>
15545 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
15546 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
15547 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
15548 to him that this book is dedicated.
15549 </para>
15550 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
15551 <para>
15552 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
15553 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
15554 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
15555 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
15556 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
15557 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
15558 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
15559 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
15560 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
15561 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
15562 critical eye on much of this.
15563 </para>
15564 <para>
15565 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
15566 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
15567 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
15568 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
15569 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
15570 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
15571 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
15572 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
15573 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
15574 </para>
15575 <para>
15576 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
15577 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
15578 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
15579 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
15580 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
15581 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
15582 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
15583 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
15584 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
15585 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
15586 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
15587 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
15588 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
15589 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
15590 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, <quote>Wink,</quote> Roger Wood, <quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,</quote>
15591 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
15592 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
15593 a bunch of great replies.)
15594 </para>
15595 <para>
15596 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
15597 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
15598 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
15599 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
15600 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
15601 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
15602 throughout this book.
15603 </para>
15604 <para>
15605 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
15606 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
15607 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
15608 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
15609 </para>
15610 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->
15611
15612 </chapter>
15613 <index></index>
15614 <colophon>
15615 <para>
15616 This digital book was published by Petter Reinholdtsen in 2014.
15617 </para>
15618 <para>
15619 The original hardcover paper book was published in 2004 by The Penguin
15620 Press, a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc. 375 Hudson Street New
15621 York, New York.
15622 </para>
15623 <para>
15624 Copyright &copy; Lawrence Lessig. Some rights reserved.
15625 </para>
15626 <para>
15627 This version of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is licensed under
15628 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
15629 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
15630 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
15631 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/</ulink>
15632 </para>
15633 <para>
15634 Excerpt from an editorial titled <quote>The Coming of Copyright
15635 Perpetuity,</quote> <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, January
15636 16, 2003. Copyright &copy; 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted
15637 with permission.
15638 </para>
15639 <para>
15640 Cartoon in <xref linkend="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/> by Paul
15641 Conrad, copyright Tribune Media Services, Inc. All rights
15642 reserved. Reprinted with permission.
15643 </para>
15644 <para>
15645 Diagram in <xref linkend="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership"/>
15646 courtesy of the office of FCC Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
15647 </para>
15648 <para>
15649 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
15650 </para>
15651 <para>
15652 Lessig, Lawrence.
15653 Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law to lock down
15654 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
15655 </para>
15656 <para>
15657 p. cm.
15658 </para>
15659 <para>
15660 Includes index.
15661 </para>
15662
15663 <para>
15664 <informaltable id="isbn">
15665 <tgroup cols="2" align="left">
15666 <thead>
15667 <row>
15668 <entry>ISBN</entry>
15669 <entry>Format / MIME-type</entry>
15670 </row>
15671 </thead>
15672 <tbody>
15673 <row>
15674 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15675 <entry>text/plain</entry>
15676 </row>
15677
15678 <row>
15679 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15680 <entry>application/pdf</entry>
15681 </row>
15682 <row>
15683 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15684 <entry>text/html</entry>
15685 </row>
15686 <row>
15687 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15688 <entry>application/epub+zip</entry>
15689 </row>
15690 <row>
15691 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15692 <entry>application/docbook+xml</entry>
15693 </row>
15694 <row>
15695 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15696 <entry>application/x-mobipocket-ebook</entry>
15697 </row>
15698 </tbody>
15699 </tgroup>
15700 </informaltable>
15701 </para>
15702
15703 <para>
15704 1. Intellectual property&mdash;United States.
15705 </para>
15706 <para>
15707 2. Mass media&mdash;United States.
15708 </para>
15709 <para>
15710 3. Technological innovations&mdash;United States.
15711 </para>
15712 <para>
15713 4. Art&mdash;United States. I. Title.
15714 </para>
15715 <para>
15716 KF2979.L47 2004
15717 </para>
15718 <para>
15719 343.7309'9&mdash;dc22 2003063276
15720 </para>
15721
15722 <para>
15723 The source of this version of the text is written using DocBook
15724 notation and the other formats are derived from the DocBook source.
15725 The DocBook source is based on a DocBook XML version created by Hans
15726 Schou, and extended with formatting and index references by Petter
15727 Reinholdtsen. The source files of this book is available as
15728 <ulink url="https://github.com/petterreinholdtsen/free-culture-lessig">a
15729 github project</ulink>.
15730 </para>
15731
15732 <para>
15733 &translationblock;
15734 </para>
15735
15736 </colophon>
15737 </book>