]> pere.pagekite.me Git - text-free-culture-lessig.git/blob - freeculture.xml
Make indexes easier to compare with sisu source, correct index locations, wrap lines...
[text-free-culture-lessig.git] / freeculture.xml
1 <?xml version='1.0' encoding='UTF-8' ?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href="docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type="text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012 with input from Martin Borg. -->
5 <!--
6 TODO
7 * indexterm primary
8 -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC "-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
11 [
12 <!ENTITY copy "©">
13 <!ENTITY translationblock "">
14 ]>
15 <book id="index" lang="en">
16 <bookinfo>
17 <title>Free Culture</title>
18
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
20
21 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
22 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY</subtitle>
23
24 <pubdate>2004-03-25</pubdate>
25
26 <releaseinfo>Version 2004-02-10</releaseinfo>
27
28 <authorgroup>
29 <author>
30 <firstname>Lawrence</firstname>
31 <surname>Lessig</surname>
32 </author>
33 </authorgroup>
34
35 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
36 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
37 -->
38 <subjectset scheme="libraryofcongress">
39 <subject>
40 <subjectterm>Intellectual property&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
41 </subject>
42 <subject>
43 <subjectterm>Mass media&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
44 </subject>
45 <subject>
46 <subjectterm>Technological innovations&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
47 </subject>
48 <subject>
49 <subjectterm>Art&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
50 </subject>
51 </subjectset>
52
53
54 <publisher>
55 <publishername>The Penguin Press</publishername>
56 <address><city>New York</city></address>
57 </publisher>
58
59 <copyright>
60 <year>2004</year>
61 <holder>Lawrence Lessig</holder>
62 </copyright>
63 <legalnotice>
64 <para>
65 <inlinemediaobject>
66 <imageobject>
67 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.png" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
68 </imageobject>
69 <imageobject>
70 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.svg" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
71 </imageobject>
72 <textobject>
73 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved</phrase>
74 </textobject>
75 </inlinemediaobject>
76 </para>
77
78 <para>
79 This version of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is licensed under
80 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
81 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
82 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
83 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/</ulink>
84 </para>
85 </legalnotice>
86
87 <abstract>
88 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR</title>
89 <para>
90 LAWRENCE LESSIG
91 (<ulink url="http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org</ulink>),
92 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
93 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
94 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
95 (<ulink url="http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org</ulink>).
96 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) and Code: And
97 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), Lessig is a member of
98 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
99 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
100 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
101 twice listed in BusinessWeek's <quote>e.biz 25,</quote> and named one of Scientific
102 American's <quote>50 visionaries.</quote> A graduate of the University of
103 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
104 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
105 Appeals.
106 </para>
107 </abstract>
108
109 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
110 <mediaobject role="cover">
111 <imageobject remap="lrg" role="front-large">
112 <imagedata fileref="images/cover.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
113 </imageobject>
114 <!--
115 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
116 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
117 </imageobject>
118 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
119 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
120 </imageobject>
121 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
122 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
123 </imageobject>
124 -->
125 </mediaobject>
126
127 <biblioid class="isbn">1-59420-006-8</biblioid>
128
129 <!-- LCCN from
130 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
131 -->
132 <biblioid class="libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
133
134 </bookinfo>
135 <!--PAGE BREAK 1-->
136 <dedication id="salespoints">
137 <title></title>
138 <para>
139 You can buy a copy of this book by clicking on one of the links below:
140 </para>
141 <itemizedlist mark="number" spacing="compact">
142 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.amazon.com/">Amazon</ulink></para></listitem>
143 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.barnesandnoble.com/">B&amp;N</ulink></para></listitem>
144 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.penguin.com/">Penguin</ulink></para></listitem>
145 <!-- <ulink url="">Local Bookstore</ulink> -->
146 </itemizedlist>
147 </dedication>
148 <!-- PAGE BREAK 2 -->
149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
150 <dedication id="alsobylessig">
151 <title></title>
152 <para>
153 ALSO BY LAWRENCE LESSIG
154 </para>
155 <para>
156 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
157 </para>
158 <para>
159 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
160 </para>
161 </dedication>
162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
163 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
164 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
165 <colophon>
166 <para>
167 THE PENGUIN PRESS, a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc. 375 Hudson Street New
168 York, New York
169 </para>
170 <para>
171 Copyright &copy; Lawrence Lessig. All rights reserved.
172 </para>
173 <para>
174 Excerpt from an editorial titled <quote>The Coming of Copyright Perpetuity,</quote>
175 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, January 16, 2003. Copyright
176 &copy; 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted with permission.
177 </para>
178 <para>
179 Cartoon in <xref linkend="fig-1711"/> by Paul Conrad, copyright Tribune
180 Media Services, Inc. All rights reserved. Reprinted with permission.
181 </para>
182 <para>
183 Diagram in <xref linkend="fig-1761"/> courtesy of the office of FCC
184 Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
185 </para>
186 <para>
187 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
188 </para>
189 <para>
190 Lessig, Lawrence.
191 Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law to lock down
192 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
193 </para>
194 <para>
195 p. cm.
196 </para>
197 <para>
198 Includes index.
199 </para>
200 <para>
201 ISBN 1-59420-006-8 (hardcover)
202 </para>
203
204 <para>
205 1. Intellectual property&mdash;United States. 2. Mass media&mdash;United States.
206 </para>
207 <para>
208 3. Technological innovations&mdash;United States. 4. Art&mdash;United States. I. Title.
209 </para>
210 <para>
211 KF2979.L47
212 </para>
213 <para>
214 343.7309'9&mdash;dc22
215 </para>
216 <para>
217 This book is printed on acid-free paper.
218 </para>
219 <para>
220 Printed in the United States of America
221 </para>
222 <para>
223 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4
224 </para>
225 <para>
226 Designed by Marysarah Quinn
227 </para>
228
229 <para>
230 &translationblock;
231 </para>
232
233 <para>
234 Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of
235 this publication may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a
236 retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means
237 (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise),
238 without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and
239 the above publisher of this book.
240 </para>
241 <para>
242 The scanning, uploading, and distribution of this book via the
243 Internet or via any other means without the permission of the
244 publisher is illegal and punishable by law. Please purchase only
245 authorized electronic editions and do not participate in or encourage
246 electronic piracy of copyrighted materials. Your support of the
247 author's rights is appreciated.
248 </para>
249 </colophon>
250
251 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
252 <dedication><title></title>
253 <para>
254 To Eric Eldred&mdash;whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
255 it continues still.
256 </para>
257 </dedication>
258
259 <toc id="toc"></toc>
260
261 <lot>
262 <title>List of figures</title>
263 </lot>
264
265 <!--
266 c PREFACE xiii
267 c INTRODUCTION
268 c "PIRACY"
269 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
270 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
271 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
272 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
273 2 Film
274 2 Recorded Music
275 2 Radio
276 2 Cable TV
277 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
278 2 Piracy I
279 2 Piracy II
280 c "PROPERTY"
281 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
282 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
283 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
284 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
285 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
286 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
287 2 Beginnings
288 2 Law: Duration
289 2 Law: Scope
290 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
291 2 Architecture and Law: Force
292 2 Market: Concentration
293 2 Together
294 c PUZZLES
295 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
296 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
297 2 Constraining Creators
298 2 Constraining Innovators
299 2 Corrupting Citizens
300 c BALANCES
301 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
302 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
303 c CONCLUSION
304 c AFTERWORD
305 1 Us, Now
306 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
307 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
308 1 Them, Soon
309 2 1. More Formalities
310 3 Registration and Renewal
311 3 Marking
312 2 2. Shorter Terms
313 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
314 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
315 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
316 c NOTES
317 c ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
318 c INDEX
319 -->
320
321 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
322
323 <preface id="preface">
324 <title>PREFACE</title>
325 <indexterm id="idxpoguedavid" class='startofrange'><primary>Pogue, David</primary></indexterm>
326 <para>
327 <emphasis role="bold">At the end</emphasis> of his review of my first
328 book, <citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle>, David
329 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
330 computer-related texts, wrote this:
331 </para>
332 <blockquote>
333 <para>
334 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
335 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
336 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
337 system, you can always flip off the modem.<footnote id="preface01"><para>
338 David Pogue, <quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 30 January 2000.
339 </para></footnote>
340 </para>
341 </blockquote>
342 <para>
343 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book&mdash;that
344 software, or <quote>code,</quote> functioned as a kind of law&mdash;and his review
345 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
346 could always <quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome</quote>-like simply flip a
347 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
348 any troubles that exist in <emphasis>that</emphasis> space wouldn't
349 <quote>affect</quote> us anymore.
350 </para>
351 <para>
352 Pogue might have been right in 1999&mdash;I'm skeptical, but maybe.
353 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
354 <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
355 causes even after the modem is turned
356 <!--PAGE BREAK 12-->
357 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
358 on-line have fundamentally affected <quote>people who aren't online.</quote> There
359 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
360 </para>
361 <indexterm startref="idxpoguedavid" class='endofrange'/>
362 <para>
363 But unlike <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
364 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
365 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
366 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
367 important.
368 </para>
369 <para>
370 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
371 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of <quote>free culture</quote>&mdash;not
372 <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free beer</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
373 free software movement<footnote>
374 <para>
375 Richard M. Stallman, <citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed. 2002).
376 </para></footnote>), but <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free speech,</quote> <quote>free markets,</quote>
377 <quote>free trade,</quote> <quote>free enterprise,</quote> <quote>free will,</quote> and <quote>free elections.</quote> A
378 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
379 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
380 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
381 follow-on creators and innovators remain <emphasis>as free as
382 possible</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
383 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
384 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
385 <quote>permission culture</quote>&mdash;a culture in which creators get to create
386 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
387 past.
388 </para>
389 <para>
390 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not <quote>we</quote>
391 on the Left or <quote>you</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
392 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
393 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
394 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
395 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
396 culture deem fundamental.
397 </para>
398 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
399 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
400 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
401 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted</primary></indexterm>
402 <para>
403 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
404 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
405 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
406 generated more than 700,000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
407 As William Safire described marching <quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
408 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
409 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,</quote> he formulated perhaps
410 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
411 he asked,
412 </para>
413 <blockquote>
414 <para>
415 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
416 power&mdash;political, corporate, media, cultural&mdash;should be anathema to
417 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
418 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
419 the greatest expression of democracy.<footnote><para> William Safire,
420 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 May 2003.
421 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
422 </para></footnote>
423 </para>
424 </blockquote>
425 <para>
426 This idea is an element of the argument of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle>, though my
427 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
428 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
429 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
430 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
431 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
432 you&mdash;whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
433 Safire's left or on his right.
434 </para>
435 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'/>
436 <para>
437 <emphasis role="strong">The inspiration</emphasis> for the title and for
438 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
439 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
440 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in <citetitle>Free Software, Free
441 Society</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
442 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
443 that this work is <quote>merely</quote> derivative.
444 </para>
445 <para>
446 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
447 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
448 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
449 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
450 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
451 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
452 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
453 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
454
455 <!--PAGE BREAK 14-->
456 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
457 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
458 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
459 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
460 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
461 what I advance here.
462 </para>
463 <para>
464 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
465 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
466 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
467 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
468 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
469 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
470 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
471 book is written.
472 </para>
473
474 </preface>
475 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
476
477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
478 <chapter label="0" id="c-introduction">
479 <title>INTRODUCTION</title>
480 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
481 <para>
482 <emphasis role="strong">On December 17</emphasis>, 1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
483 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
484 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
485 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
486 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
487 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
488 </para>
489 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.</primary></indexterm>
490 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
491 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
492 <para>
493 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
494 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
495 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
496 and all the space above, to <quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.</quote><footnote><para>
497 St. George Tucker, <citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
498 Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18.
499 </para></footnote>
500 For many
501 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
502 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
503 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
504 </para>
505 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
506 <para>
507 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
508 law&mdash;deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
509 by the most important legal thinkers of our past&mdash;mattered. If
510 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
511 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
512 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
513 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
514 </para>
515 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
516 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
517 <para>
518 In 1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
519 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
520 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
521 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
522 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
523 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
524 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to <quote>an indefinite
525 extent, upwards,</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
526 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
527 </para>
528 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
529 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
530 <para>
531 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
532 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
533 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
534 <quote>taking</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
535 that <quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
536 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.</quote> But Justice Douglas
537 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
538 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
539 </para>
540 <blockquote>
541 <para>
542 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
543 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
544 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
545 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
546 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
547 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
548 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
549 the public has a just claim.<footnote>
550 <para>
551 United States v. Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. The Court did find
552 that there could be a <quote>taking</quote> if the government's use of its land
553 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
554 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, <quote>(Intellectual)
555 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
556 Authorship,</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review</citetitle> 48 (1996): 1293, 1333. See also Paul
557 Goldstein, <citetitle>Real Property</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press, 1984),
558 1112&ndash;13.
559 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
560 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
561 </para></footnote>
562 </para>
563 </blockquote>
564 <para>
565 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.</quote>
566 </para>
567 <para>
568 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
569 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
570 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
571 <!--PAGE BREAK 18-->
572 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: <quote>Common sense revolts
573 at the idea.</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
574 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
575 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
576 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
577 </para>
578 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
579 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
580 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
581 <para>
582 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
583 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
584 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
585 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
586 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
587 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
588 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
589 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
590 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by <quote>what
591 seemed reasonable</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
592 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
593 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
594 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
595 end, the force of what seems <quote>obvious</quote> to everyone else&mdash;the power of
596 <quote>common sense</quote>&mdash;would prevail. Their <quote>private interest</quote> would not be
597 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
598 </para>
599 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'/>
600 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'/>
601 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'/>
602 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
603 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham</primary></indexterm>
604 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
605 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael</primary></indexterm>
606 <para>
607 <emphasis role='strong'>Edwin Howard Armstrong</emphasis> is one of
608 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
609 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
610 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
611 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
612 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
613 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in 1831. But
614 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
615 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
616 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
617 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
618 </para>
619 <para>
620 On the day after Christmas, 1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
621 for his most significant invention&mdash;FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
622 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
623 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
624 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
625 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
626 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
627 much less transmitter power and static.
628 </para>
629 <para>
630 On November 5, 1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
631 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
632 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
633 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
634 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
635 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
636 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
637 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
638 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.</quote>
639 </para>
640 <para>
641 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
642 </para>
643 <blockquote>
644 <para>
645 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
646 sounded like a glass of water being poured. &hellip; A paper was crumpled
647 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
648 fire. &hellip; Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
649 and guitar number were performed. &hellip; The music was projected with a
650 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio <quote>music
651 box.</quote><footnote><para>
652 Lawrence Lessing, <citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong</citetitle>
653 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209.
654 </para></footnote>
655 </para>
656 </blockquote>
657 <para>
658 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
659 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
660 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
661 AM radio market. By 1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
662 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
663 a handful of networks.
664 <!--PAGE BREAK 20-->
665 </para>
666 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
667 <para>
668 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
669 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
670 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
671 that removed static from <quote>radio.</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
672 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
673 </para>
674 <blockquote>
675 <para>
676 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
677 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
678 revolution&mdash; start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
679 RCA.<footnote><para> See <quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
680 Electronic Era,</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
681 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
682
683 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #1</ulink>.
684 </para></footnote>
685 </para>
686 </blockquote>
687 <indexterm id='idxlessing' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessing, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
688 <para>
689 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
690 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
691 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
692 described,
693 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
694 </para>
695 <blockquote>
696 <para>
697 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
698 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
699 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
700 unrestrained, posed &hellip; a complete reordering of radio power
701 &hellip; and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
702 on which RCA had grown to power.<footnote><para>Lessing, 226.
703 </para></footnote>
704 </para>
705 </blockquote>
706 <para>
707 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
708 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
709 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
710 FM radio's deployment generally. In 1936, RCA hired the former head
711 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
712 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM&mdash;principally by moving FM
713 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
714 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
715 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
716 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
717 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
718 </para>
719 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
720 <blockquote>
721 <para>
722 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
723 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
724 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
725 deviousness.<footnote><para>
726 Lessing, 256.
727 </para></footnote>
728 </para>
729 </blockquote>
730 <indexterm startref='idxlessing' class='endofrange'/>
731 <indexterm><primary>AT&amp;T</primary></indexterm>
732 <para>
733 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
734 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
735 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
736 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
737 (This change was strongly supported by AT&amp;T, because the loss of
738 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
739 wired links from AT&amp;T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
740 least temporarily.
741 </para>
742 <para>
743 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
744 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
745 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
746 invalid&mdash;baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
747 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
748 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
749 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
750 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
751 now broke, in 1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
752 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
753 </para>
754 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'/>
755 <para>
756 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
757 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
758 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
759 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
760 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
761 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
762 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
763 course always public spirited; the reality is something
764 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
765 to themselves, would crumble in
766 <!--PAGE BREAK 22-->
767 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
768 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
769 effect of technological change.
770 </para>
771 <para>
772 <emphasis role="strong">There's no</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
773 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
774 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
775 Internet and American Life Project, 58 percent of Americans had access
776 to the Internet in 2002, up from 49 percent two years
777 before.<footnote><para>
778 Amanda Lenhart, <quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
779 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,</quote> Pew Internet and American
780 Life Project, 15 April 2003: 6, available at
781 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #2</ulink>.
782 </para></footnote>
783 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
784 of 2004.
785 </para>
786 <para>
787 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
788 changed things. Some of these changes are technical&mdash;the Internet has
789 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
790 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
791 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
792 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
793 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
794 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
795 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
796 </para>
797 <para>
798 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
799 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
800 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
801 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
802 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
803 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
804 has introduced.
805 </para>
806 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel</primary></indexterm>
807 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah</primary></indexterm>
808 <para>
809 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
810 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
811 regulation of each. By <quote>commercial culture</quote> I mean that part of our
812 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
813 <quote>noncommercial culture</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
814 parks or on
815 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
816 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
817 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his <quote>Reader,</quote> or
818 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
819 </para>
820 <para>
821 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
822 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
823 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
824 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
825 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
826 left this culture <quote>free.</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
827 individuals shared and transformed their culture&mdash;telling
828 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
829 clubs, sharing music, making tapes&mdash;were left alone by the law.
830 </para>
831 <para>
832 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
833 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
834 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
835 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
836 marketplace.<footnote>
837 <para>
838 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
839 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
840 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
841 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
842 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
843 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
844 D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote> Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193,
845 198&ndash;200.
846 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
847 </para></footnote>
848 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
849 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
850 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
851 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
852 </para>
853 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
854 <indexterm><primary>permission culture</primary><secondary> free culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
855 <para>
856 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
857 been erased.<footnote><para>
858 See Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
859 2001), ch. 13.
860 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
861 </para></footnote>
862 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
863 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
864 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
865 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
866 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
867 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
868 the balance of our history&mdash;between uses of our culture that were
869 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission&mdash;has
870 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
871 culture, more and more a permission culture.
872 </para>
873 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
874 <para>
875 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
876 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
877 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
878 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
879 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
880 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
881 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
882 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
883 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
884 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
885 Causbys.
886 </para>
887 <para>
888 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
889 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
890 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
891 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
892 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
893 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
894 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
895 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
896 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
897 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
898 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
899 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
900 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
901 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
902 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
903 than creators do today&mdash;all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
904 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
905 </para>
906 <para>
907 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
908 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
909 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
910 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
911 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
912 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
913 remakes them.
914 </para>
915 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary> on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
916 <para>
917 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
918 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
919 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
920 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions&mdash;whether <quote>piracy</quote> will
921 be permitted, and whether <quote>property</quote> will be protected. The <quote>war</quote> that
922 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet&mdash;what
923 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
924 calls his <quote>own terrorist war</quote><footnote><para>
925 Amy Harmon, <quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
926 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,</quote> <citetitle>New York
927 Times</citetitle>, 17 January 2002.
928 </para></footnote>&mdash;has been framed as a battle about the
929 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
930 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
931 against it.
932 </para>
933 <para>
934 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
935 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
936 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
937 <quote>creative property.</quote> I believe that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that the
938 law, properly tuned, should punish <quote>piracy,</quote> whether on or off the
939 Internet.
940 </para>
941 <para>
942 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
943 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
944 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet <quote>pirates</quote> will also rid our
945 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
946 </para>
947 <para>
948 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first 180 years of
949 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
950 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
951 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
952 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,<footnote>
953 <para>
954 Neil W. Netanel, <quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
955 Journal</citetitle> 106 (1996): 283.
956 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
957 </para></footnote>
958 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
959 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
960 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
961 could cultivate and extend our culture.
962 </para>
963 <para>
964 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
965 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
966 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
967 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist&ndash;like,
968 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
969 granted&mdash;but it is not often granted to the critical or the
970 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
971 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
972 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
973 </para>
974 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Should "Is it" be "It is" ? -->
975 <para>
976 The story that follows is about this war. Is it not about the
977 <quote>centrality of technology</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
978 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
979 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
980 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
981 against an industry.
982 </para>
983 <para>
984 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
985 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
986 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
987 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
988 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
989 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
990 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
991 </para>
992 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
993 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
994 <para>
995 <emphasis role="strong">Like the Causbys'</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about <quote>property.</quote> The
996 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
997 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
998 this <quote>property</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
999 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
1000 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
1001 of <quote>intellectual property</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
1002 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
1003 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
1004 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
1005 <quote>trespassing</quote> upon legitimate claims of <quote>property.</quote> It is as plain to
1006 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
1007 trespass.
1008 </para>
1009 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1010 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1011 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
1012 <para>
1013 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
1014 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
1015 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
1016 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
1017 war. Unlike
1018 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
1019 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
1020 on its side.
1021 </para>
1022 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
1023 <para>
1024 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
1025 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
1026 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
1027 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
1028 our <quote>culture</quote> was as <quote>owned</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
1029 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
1030 <emphasis>uses</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
1031 accepted as it is now.
1032 </para>
1033 <para>
1034 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
1035 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
1036 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
1037 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1038 </para>
1039 <para>
1040 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1041 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1042 </para>
1043 <para>
1044 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1045 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1046 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1047 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1048 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1049 </para>
1050 <para>
1051 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1052 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1053 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1054 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1055 view?
1056 </para>
1057 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1058 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1059 <para>
1060 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1061 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1062 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1063 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of <quote>intellectual
1064 property.</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1065 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1066 this silliness will be much more profound.
1067 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1068 </para>
1069 <para>
1070 <emphasis role="strong">The struggle</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas: <quote>piracy</quote> and
1071 <quote>property.</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1072 ideas.
1073 </para>
1074 <para>
1075 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1076 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1077 obscure French theorists&mdash;however natural that is for the weird
1078 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1079 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1080 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1081 </para>
1082 <para>
1083 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1084 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1085 government, pushed by big media to respond to this <quote>something new,</quote> is
1086 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1087 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let <quote>common
1088 sense</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1089 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1090 law&mdash;and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1091 fundamental about who we have always been.
1092 </para>
1093 <para>
1094 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1095 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1096 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1097 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1098 of one more consequence of this form of corruption&mdash;a consequence
1099 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1100 </para>
1101 </chapter>
1102 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1103 <part id="c-piracy">
1104 <title><quote>PIRACY</quote></title>
1105 <partintro>
1106 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1107 <indexterm><primary>Copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
1108 <indexterm id="idxmansfield1" class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
1109 <indexterm><primary>music publishing</primary></indexterm>
1110 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
1111 <para>
1112 <emphasis role="strong">Since the inception</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1113 been a war against <quote>piracy.</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1114 <quote>piracy,</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1115 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1116 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1117 </para>
1118 <blockquote>
1119 <para>
1120 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1121 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1122 of them for his own use.<footnote><para>
1123 <!-- f1 -->
1124 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield).
1125 </para></footnote>
1126 </para>
1127 <indexterm startref="idxmansfield1" class='endofrange'/>
1128 </blockquote>
1129 <para>
1130 Today we are in the middle of another <quote>war</quote> against <quote>piracy.</quote> The
1131 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1132 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1133 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1134 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1135 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1136 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1137 </para>
1138 <para>
1139 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1140 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1141 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1142 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1143 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will <quote>rob the author of the
1144 profit.</quote>
1145 </para>
1146 <para>
1147 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1148 increasingly to technology to defend their <quote>property</quote> against this
1149 <quote>piracy.</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1150 raised to believe that <quote>property</quote> should be <quote>free.</quote> Forget tattoos,
1151 never mind body piercing&mdash;our kids are becoming
1152 <emphasis>thieves</emphasis>!
1153 </para>
1154 <para>
1155 There's no doubt that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1156 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1157 notion of <quote>piracy</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1158 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1159 </para>
1160 <para>
1161 The idea goes something like this:
1162 </para>
1163 <blockquote>
1164 <para>
1165 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1166 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1167 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1168 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1169 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1170 piracy.
1171 </para>
1172 </blockquote>
1173 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP</primary></indexterm>
1174 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle</primary></indexterm>
1175 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts</primary></indexterm>
1176 <indexterm id='idxifvalue' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
1177 <para>
1178 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1179 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1180 theory of creative property<footnote><para>
1181 <!-- f2 -->
1182 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, <quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1183 in the Pepsi Generation,</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review</citetitle> 65 (1990): 397.
1184 </para></footnote>
1185 &mdash;if there is value, then someone must have a
1186 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1187 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1188 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.<footnote><para>
1189 <!-- f3 -->
1190 Lisa Bannon, <quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1191 Up,</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 21 August 1996, available at
1192 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #3</ulink>; Jonathan
1193 Zittrain, <quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1194 Speech, No One Wins,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 24 November 2002.
1195 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
1196 </para></footnote>
1197 There was <quote>value</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1198 <quote>right</quote>&mdash;even against the Girl Scouts.
1199 </para>
1200 <para>
1201 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1202 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1203 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1204 of law protecting creative property. But the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1205 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1206 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1207 </para>
1208 <indexterm startref='idxifvalue' class='endofrange'/>
1209 <para>
1210 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1211 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1212 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1213 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1214 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1215 </para>
1216 <para>
1217 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1218 takes care to draw&mdash;the distinction between republishing someone's
1219 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1220 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1221 copyright law today regulates both.
1222 </para>
1223 <para>
1224 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1225 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1226 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1227 entities could bear the burden of the law&mdash;even the burden of the
1228 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1229 more expense of doing business.
1230 </para>
1231 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1232 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1233 <para>
1234 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1235 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1236 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1237 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1238 <quote>copying,</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1239 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1240 outweighs any original benefit&mdash;certainly as it affects
1241 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1242 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1243 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1244 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1245 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1246 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1247 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1248 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1249 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1250 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the <quote>Rise of the Creative
1251 Class.</quote><footnote>
1252 <para>
1253 <!-- f4 -->
1254 In <citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class</citetitle> (New York:
1255 Basic Books, 2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1256 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1257 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1258 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1259 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1260 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1261
1262 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1263 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1264 </para></footnote>
1265 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1266 this creative class.
1267 </para>
1268 <para>
1269 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1270 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1271 context the current battles about behavior labeled <quote>piracy.</quote>
1272 </para>
1273 </partintro>
1274
1275 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1276 <chapter label="1" id="creators">
1277 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators</title>
1278 <indexterm id="idxanimadedcartoons" class='startofrange'><primary>animated cartoons</primary></indexterm>
1279 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'><primary>cartoon films</primary></indexterm>
1280 <para>
1281 <emphasis role="strong">In 1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1282 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called <citetitle>Plane Crazy</citetitle>.
1283 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1284 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle> brought
1285 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1286 </para>
1287 <para>
1288 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1289 movie <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1290 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1291 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1292 Disney ran a test in the summer of 1928, the results were unambiguous.
1293 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1294 </para>
1295 <blockquote>
1296 <para>
1297 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1298 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1299 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1300 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1301 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1302 </para>
1303 <para>
1304 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1305 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1306 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1307 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1308 synchronization was pretty close.
1309 </para>
1310 <para>
1311 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1312 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1313 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1314 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1315 it was something new!<footnote><para>
1316 <!-- f1 -->
1317 Leonard Maltin, <citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1318 Cartoons</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34&ndash;35.
1319 </para></footnote>
1320 </para>
1321 </blockquote>
1322 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub</primary></indexterm>
1323 <para>
1324 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1325 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: <quote>I have never been so thrilled
1326 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.</quote>
1327 </para>
1328 <para>
1329 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1330 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1331 rarely&mdash;except in Disney's hands&mdash;been anything more than
1332 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1333 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1334 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1335 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1336 </para>
1337 <para>
1338 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that 1928 also marks
1339 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1340 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1341 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>.
1342 </para>
1343 <para>
1344 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in 1895. In the era of silent
1345 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1346 uncontrollable laughter from his audience. <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1347 Jr</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1348 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton&mdash;wildly popular
1349 and among the best of its genre.
1350 </para>
1351 <para>
1352 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1353 Willie.
1354 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1355 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1356 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,<footnote><para>
1357 <!-- f2 -->
1358 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1359 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #4</ulink>.
1360 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1361 use the music for five songs in <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>: <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote> <quote>The
1362 Simpleton</quote> (Delille), <quote>Mischief Makers</quote> (Carbonara), <quote>Joyful Hurry No. 1</quote>
1363 (Baron), and <quote>Gawky Rube</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song, <quote>The Turkey in the
1364 Straw,</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1365 Harry Surden, 10 July 2003, on file with author.
1366 </para></footnote>
1367 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1368 the invention of synchronized sound in <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle> that we
1369 get <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1370 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote>
1371 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1372 Mouse.
1373 </para>
1374 <para>
1375 This <quote>borrowing</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1376 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1377 films of his day.<footnote><para>
1378 <!-- f3 -->
1379 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, <quote>The Mouse
1380 that Ate the Public Domain,</quote> Findlaw, 5 March 2002, at
1381 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #5</ulink>.
1382 </para></footnote>
1383 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1384 knockoffs&mdash;slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1385 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1386 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1387 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1388 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1389 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1390 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1391 old.
1392 </para>
1393 <para>
1394 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1395 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1396 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1397 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1398 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1399 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1400 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1401 </para>
1402 <para>
1403 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1404 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1405 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1406 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1407 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1408 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1409 work of others is astonishing when set together: <citetitle>Snow White</citetitle>
1410 (1937), <citetitle>Fantasia</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Pinocchio</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Dumbo</citetitle>
1411 (1941), <citetitle>Bambi</citetitle> (1942), <citetitle>Song of the South</citetitle> (1946),
1412 <citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle> (1950), <citetitle>Alice in Wonderland</citetitle> (1951), <citetitle>Robin
1413 Hood</citetitle> (1952), <citetitle>Peter Pan</citetitle> (1953), <citetitle>Lady and the Tramp</citetitle>
1414 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1415 (1955), <citetitle>Mulan</citetitle> (1998), <citetitle>Sleeping Beauty</citetitle> (1959), <citetitle>101
1416 Dalmatians</citetitle> (1961), <citetitle>The Sword in the Stone</citetitle> (1963), and
1417 <citetitle>The Jungle Book</citetitle> (1967)&mdash;not to mention a recent example
1418 that we should perhaps quickly forget, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>
1419 (2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1420 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1421 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1422 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1423 </para>
1424 <indexterm startref="idxanimadedcartoons" class='endofrange'/>
1425 <para>
1426 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1427 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1428 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1429 its importance. We could call this <quote>Disney creativity,</quote> though that
1430 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, <quote>Walt Disney
1431 creativity</quote>&mdash;a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1432 culture around us and makes it something different.
1433 </para>
1434 <para> In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1435 relatively fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was
1436 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1437 thirty years&mdash;for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1438 copyrighted.<footnote><para>
1439 <!-- f4 -->
1440 Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1441 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the <quote>average</quote> term by
1442 determining
1443 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1444 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in year
1445 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the
1446 average
1447 term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1448 Web site associated with this book, available at
1449 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #6</ulink>.
1450 </para></footnote>
1451 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1452 copyright holders of a creative work had an <quote>exclusive right</quote> to control
1453 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1454 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1455 </para>
1456 <para>
1457 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1458 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1459 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a <quote>lawyer-free
1460 zone.</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1461 for Disney to use and build upon in 1928. It was free for
1462 anyone&mdash; whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1463 approved or not&mdash;to use and build upon.
1464 </para>
1465 <para>
1466 This is the ways things always were&mdash;until quite recently. For most
1467 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1468 until 1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1469 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1470
1471 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1472 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1473 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s
1474 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1475 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1476 content from before the Great Depression.
1477 </para>
1478 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'/>
1479 <para>
1480 <emphasis role="strong">Of course</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on <quote>Walt Disney creativity.</quote>
1481 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1482 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1483 universal.
1484 </para>
1485 <para>
1486 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1487 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: <citetitle>manga</citetitle>, or
1488 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of
1489 publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives
1490 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1491 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1492 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1493 </para>
1494 <para>
1495 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1496 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1497 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1498 the stories that these <quote>graphic novels</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1499 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are <quote>men in tights.</quote>
1500 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1501 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1502 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1503 interestingly different way.
1504 </para>
1505 <para>
1506 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1507 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1508 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1509 </para>
1510 <para>
1511 This is the phenomenon of <citetitle>doujinshi</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1512 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1513 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is <emphasis>just</emphasis> a
1514 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1515 transforming it either subtly or
1516 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1517 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1518 develop it differently&mdash;with a different story line. Or the comic can
1519 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1520 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently <quote>different.</quote> But they
1521 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1522 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1523 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1524 </para>
1525 <para>
1526 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1527 huge. More than 33,000 <quote>circles</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1528 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come
1529 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1530 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1531 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1532 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1533 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1534 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1535 </para>
1536 <para>
1537 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1538 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1539 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1540 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1541 one. Doujinshi are plainly <quote>derivative works.</quote> There is no general
1542 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1543 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1544 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1545 Jr</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that <quote>taking</quote> without
1546 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1547 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1548 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1549 </para>
1550 <indexterm id="idxwinickjudd" class='startofrange'><primary>Winick, Judd</primary></indexterm>
1551 <para>
1552 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1553 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1554 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, <quote>The
1555 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1556 in Japan now. &hellip; American comics were born out of copying each
1557 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1558 other. &hellip; That's how [the artists] learn to draw&mdash;by going into comic
1559 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them</quote>
1560 and building from them.<footnote><para>
1561 <!-- f5 -->
1562 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, <citetitle>Reinventing Comics</citetitle> (New
1563 York: Perennial, 2000).
1564 </para></footnote>
1565 </para>
1566 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics</primary></indexterm>
1567 <para>
1568 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1569 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1570 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, <quote>there are these rules
1571 and you have to stick to them.</quote> There are things Superman <quote>cannot</quote>
1572 do. <quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1573 which are fifty years old.</quote>
1574 </para>
1575 <indexterm startref="idxwinickjudd" class='endofrange'/>
1576 <para>
1577 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1578 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1579 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1580 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1581 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1582 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1583 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.<footnote><para>
1584 <!-- f6 -->
1585 See Salil K. Mehra, <quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1586 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1587 Review</citetitle> 55 (2002): 155, 182. <quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1588 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1589 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1590 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1591 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1592 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.</quote>
1593 </para></footnote>
1594 </para>
1595 <para>
1596 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1597 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1598 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1599 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1600 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1601 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1602 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1603 a more general pattern of blocking this <quote>free taking</quote> by the doujinshi
1604 culture?
1605 </para>
1606 <para>
1607 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1608 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1609 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. <quote>We don't have enough
1610 lawyers,</quote> he told me one afternoon. There <quote>just aren't enough resources
1611 to prosecute cases like this.</quote>
1612 </para>
1613 <para>
1614 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1615 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1616 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1617 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1618 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1619 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1620 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1621 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1622 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1623 their clients or hurt them?
1624 </para>
1625 <para>
1626 <emphasis role='strong'>Let's pause</emphasis> for a moment.
1627 </para>
1628 <para>
1629 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1630 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1631 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1632 </para>
1633 <para>
1634 We live in a world that celebrates <quote>property.</quote> I am one of those
1635 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1636 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1637 <quote>intellectual property.</quote><footnote><para>
1638 <!-- f7 -->
1639 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
1640 The term <citetitle>intellectual property</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1641 Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 11 (New York: New York
1642 University Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
1643 (New York: Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately
1644 describes a set of <quote>property</quote> rights&mdash;copyright, patents,
1645 trademark, and trade-secret&mdash;but the nature of those rights is
1646 very different.
1647 </para></footnote>
1648 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1649 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1650 property.
1651 </para>
1652 <para>
1653 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1654 plenty of value out there that <quote>property</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1655 mean <quote>money can't buy you love,</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1656 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1657 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1658 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1659 condemning that taking as wrong&mdash; even though trivial, even if
1660 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1661 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1662 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1663 Disney's use would have been considered <quote>fair.</quote> There was nothing
1664 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1665 the public domain.
1666 </para>
1667 <para>
1668 Thus, even though the things that Disney took&mdash;or more generally,
1669 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity&mdash;are
1670 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1671
1672 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1673 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1674 freedom is good.
1675 </para>
1676 <para>
1677 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1678 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1679 work&mdash;or even one copy&mdash;without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1680 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1681 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1682 form, whether large or small.
1683 </para>
1684 <para>
1685 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1686 say that the copycat comic artists are <quote>stealing.</quote> This form of Walt
1687 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1688 particular find it hard to say why.
1689 </para>
1690 <para>
1691 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1692 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1693 without asking or paying for the privilege. (<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1694 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1695 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?</quote>) Acting companies
1696 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1697 permission from anyone. (Does <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> believe
1698 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1699 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1700 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1701 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s;
1702 two volcano disaster films in 1997.
1703 </para>
1704 <para>
1705 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1706 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1707 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1708 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1709 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1710 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1711 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking&mdash;free
1712 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1713 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1714 </para>
1715 <para>
1716 The hard question is therefore not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> a
1717 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1718 question instead is <quote><emphasis>How</emphasis> free is this culture?</quote>
1719 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1720 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1721 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1722 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1723 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1724 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1725 a studio or not?
1726 </para>
1727 <para>
1728 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1729 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1730 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1731 </para>
1732
1733 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1734 </chapter>
1735 <chapter label="2" id="mere-copyists">
1736 <title>CHAPTER TWO: <quote>Mere Copyists</quote></title>
1737 <indexterm id='idxcameratech' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1738 <indexterm id="idxphotography" class='startofrange'><primary>photography</primary></indexterm>
1739 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis</primary></indexterm>
1740 <para>
1741 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1742 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1743 <quote>photographs.</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1744 <quote>daguerreotypes.</quote> The process was complicated and
1745 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1746 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1747 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1748 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1749 </para>
1750 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William</primary></indexterm>
1751 <para>
1752 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1753 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1754 <quote>automatic pictures.</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1755 making <quote>negatives.</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1756 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1757 the 1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1758 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1759 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1760 amateurs.
1761 </para>
1762 <indexterm id="idxeastmangeorge" class='startofrange'><primary>Eastman, George</primary></indexterm>
1763 <para>
1764 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1765 didn't happen until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1766 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1767 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1768 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1769 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1770 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1771 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1772 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1773 population of photographers.
1774 </para>
1775 <indexterm><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)</primary></indexterm>
1776 <para>
1777 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1778 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1779 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. <quote>You press the button and we
1780 do the rest.</quote><footnote><para>
1781 <!-- f1 -->
1782 Reese V. Jenkins, <citetitle>Images and Enterprise</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975), 112.
1783 </para></footnote> As he described in <citetitle>The Kodak Primer</citetitle>:
1784 </para>
1785 <blockquote>
1786 <para>
1787 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1788 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1789 that only an expert can do. &hellip; We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1790 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1791 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1792 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1793 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1794 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1795 chemicals.<footnote>
1796 <para>
1797 <!-- f2 -->
1798 Brian Coe, <citetitle>The Birth of Photography</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1799 1977), 53.
1800 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1801 </para></footnote>
1802 </para>
1803 </blockquote>
1804 <para>
1805 For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1806 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1807 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1808 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1809 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1810 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in 1888; one
1811 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1812 From 1888 through 1909, while industrial production was rising by 4.7
1813 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by 11
1814 percent.<footnote><para>
1815 <!-- f3 -->
1816 Jenkins, 177.
1817 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1818 an average annual increase of over 17 percent.<footnote><para>
1819 <!-- f4 -->
1820 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p. 178.
1821 </para></footnote>
1822 </para>
1823 <indexterm startref='idxcameratech' class='endofrange'/>
1824 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1825 <para>
1826
1827 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1828 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1829 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1830 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1831 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1832 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, <quote>For the
1833 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1834 permanent record of his family and its activities. &hellip; For the first
1835 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1836 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1837 interpretation or bias.</quote><footnote><para>
1838 <!-- f5 -->
1839 Coe, 58.
1840 </para></footnote>
1841 </para>
1842 <para>
1843 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1844 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1845 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1846 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1847 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1848 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its <quote>quality</quote>;
1849 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1850 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1851 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1852 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1853 have before.
1854 </para>
1855 <para>
1856 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1857 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1858 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1859 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1860 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1861 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1862 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1863 he wanted. Their answer was no.<footnote><para>
1864 <!-- f6 -->
1865 For illustrative cases, see, for example, <citetitle>Pavesich</citetitle>
1866 v. <citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co</citetitle>., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905);
1867 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Chinn</citetitle>, 123090 S.W. 364, 366
1868 (Ky. 1909); <citetitle>Corliss</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Walker</citetitle>, 64 F. 280 (Mass.
1869 Dist. Ct. 1894).
1870 </para></footnote>
1871 </para>
1872 <para>
1873 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1874 familiar. The photographer was <quote>taking</quote> something from the person or
1875 building whose photograph he shot&mdash;pirating something of
1876 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1877 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1878 draw
1879 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1880 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1881 that they thought valuable.
1882 </para>
1883 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1884 <para>
1885 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1886 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1887 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1888 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1889 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.<footnote>
1890 <para>
1891 <!-- f7 -->
1892 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote>
1893 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review</citetitle> 4 (1890): 193.
1894 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1895 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.</primary></indexterm>
1896 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1897 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1898 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1899 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1900 </para>
1901 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
1902 <para>
1903 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1904 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1905 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1906 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1907 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1908 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1909 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1910 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1911 clearing the rights to do the capturing.<footnote><para>
1912 <!-- f8 -->
1913 See Melville B. Nimmer, <quote>The Right of Publicity,</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
1914 Problems</citetitle> 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, <quote>Privacy,</quote> <citetitle>California Law
1915 Review</citetitle> 48 (1960) 398&ndash;407; <citetitle>White</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
1916 Inc</citetitle>., 971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951
1917 (1993).
1918 </para></footnote>)
1919 </para>
1920 <para>
1921 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1922 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1923 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1924 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1925 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1926 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1927 Kodak would be benefiting from the <quote>theft</quote> committed by the
1928 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1929 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1930 from the <quote>image-right</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
1931 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1932 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1933 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1934 </para>
1935 <para>
1936
1937 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
1938 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
1939 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
1940 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
1941 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
1942 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
1943 technology as they did&mdash;since professionals could have more
1944 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
1945 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
1946 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
1947 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
1948 realized.
1949 </para>
1950 <indexterm><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1951 <para>
1952 <emphasis role='strong'>If you drive</emphasis> through San
1953 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
1954 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
1955 <quote>Just Think!</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
1956 there's little that's <quote>just</quote> cerebral in the projects
1957 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
1958 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
1959 the film of your VCR. Rather the <quote>film</quote> of digital
1960 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
1961 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
1962 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
1963 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
1964 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
1965 think. By tinkering, they learn.
1966 </para>
1967 <indexterm startref="idxeastmangeorge" class='endofrange'/>
1968 <indexterm startref="idxphotography" class='endofrange'/>
1969 <para>
1970 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
1971 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
1972 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, <quote>Five years ago, a good
1973 real-time digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get
1974 professional quality for $595.</quote><footnote><para>
1975 <!-- f9 -->
1976 H. Edward Goldberg, <quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
1977 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,</quote>
1978 cadalyst, February 2002, available at
1979 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #7</ulink>.
1980 </para></footnote>
1981 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
1982 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
1983 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
1984 learning more and more of something teachers call <quote>media literacy.</quote>
1985 </para>
1986 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave</primary></indexterm>
1987 <para>
1988 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
1989 <quote>Media literacy,</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
1990 Think!, puts it, <quote>is the ability &hellip; to understand, analyze, and
1991 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
1992 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
1993 the way people access it.</quote>
1994 </para>
1995 <para>
1996 This may seem like an odd way to think about <quote>literacy.</quote> For most
1997 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
1998 and noticing split infinitives are the things that <quote>literate</quote> people know
1999 about.
2000 </para>
2001 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2002 <para>
2003 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of
2004 television commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000
2005 commercials generally,<footnote><para>
2006 <!-- f10 -->
2007 Judith Van Evra, <citetitle>Television and Child Development</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2008 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990); <quote>Findings on Family and TV
2009 Study,</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post</citetitle>, 25 May 1997, B6.
2010 </para></footnote>
2011 it is increasingly important to understand the <quote>grammar</quote> of media. For
2012 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2013 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2014 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2015 (at least at first) terrible media.
2016 </para>
2017 <para>
2018 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2019 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2020 has written understands how difficult writing is&mdash;how difficult
2021 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2022 language to be understandable&mdash;few of us have any real sense of
2023 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2024 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2025 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2026 </para>
2027 <para>
2028 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2029 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2030 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2031 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2032 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2033 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2034 </para>
2035 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael</primary></indexterm>
2036 <para>
2037 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2038 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2039 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2040
2041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2042 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2043 about <quote>the placement of objects, color, &hellip; rhythm, pacing, and
2044 texture.</quote><footnote>
2045 <para>
2046 <!-- f11 -->
2047 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish, 13 December
2048 2002.
2049 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2050 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2051 </para></footnote>
2052 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2053 <quote>played</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2054 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2055 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2056 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2057 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2058 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2059 to a wildly successful author.<footnote><para>
2060 <!-- f12 -->
2061 See Scott Steinberg, <quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,</quote> E!online, 4
2062 November 2000, available at
2063 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #8</ulink>; <quote>Timeline,</quote> 22 November 2000,
2064 available at
2065 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #9</ulink>.
2066 </para></footnote>
2067 </para>
2068 <indexterm><primary>computer games</primary></indexterm>
2069 <para>
2070 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2071 describes, <quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2072 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2073 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2074 led.</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2075 </para>
2076 <para>
2077 Yet the push for an expanded literacy&mdash;one that goes beyond text
2078 to include audio and visual elements&mdash;is not about making better
2079 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2080 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2081 </para>
2082 <blockquote>
2083 <para>
2084 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2085 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2086 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2087 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2088 being read-only.
2089 </para>
2090 </blockquote>
2091 <para>
2092 <quote>Read-only.</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2093 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2094 twentieth century.
2095 </para>
2096 <para>
2097 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2098 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2099 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2100 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2101 literacy,
2102 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2103 and this literacy in particular, is to <quote>empower people to choose the
2104 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2105 express.</quote><footnote>
2106 <para>
2107 <!-- f13 -->
2108 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2109 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2110 </para></footnote> It is to enable students <quote>to communicate in the
2111 language of the twenty-first century.</quote><footnote><para>
2112 <!-- f14 -->
2113 Ibid.
2114 </para></footnote>
2115 </para>
2116 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2117 <para>
2118 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2119 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2120 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2121 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2122 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2123 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2124 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2125 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2126 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2127 students know something about&mdash;gun violence.
2128 </para>
2129 <para>
2130 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2131 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2132 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2133 away. The <quote>kids were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night,</quote>
2134 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2135 what education should be about&mdash;learning how to express themselves.
2136 </para>
2137 <para>
2138 Using whatever <quote>free web stuff they could find,</quote> and relatively simple
2139 tools to enable the kids to mix <quote>image, sound, and text,</quote> Barish said
2140 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2141 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2142 close to the lives of these students. The project <quote>gave them a tool
2143 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2144 it,</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2145 expression&mdash;far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2146 been created using only text. <quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2147 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2148 gone and done something else,</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2149 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2150 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2151 <emphasis>these</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2152 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2153 </para>
2154 <para>
2155
2156 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2157 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?</quote> I asked. In part,
2158 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2159 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of <quote>constructing
2160 meaning.</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2161 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2162 part&mdash;and increasingly, not the most powerful part&mdash;of
2163 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2164 our interview,
2165 </para>
2166 <blockquote>
2167 <para>
2168 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2169 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2170 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2171 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2172 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2173 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2174 you say, <quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.</quote>
2175 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2176 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2177 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, <quote>Well, with all these things that you
2178 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2179 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2180 for me something that reflects that.</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2181 camera and &hellip; saying, <quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2182 make a little movie.</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2183 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2184 about the topic.&hellip;
2185 </para>
2186 <para>
2187 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2188 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2189 bump up against the fact, <quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2190 to write something.</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2191 they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 times, till they got it right.
2192 </para>
2193 <para>
2194 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2195 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2196 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2197 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2198 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2199 had a lot of power with this language.
2200 </para>
2201 <!-- FIXME removed a " from the end of the previous paragraph that did
2202 not match with any start quote. -->
2203 </blockquote>
2204 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center</primary></indexterm>
2205 <para>
2206 <emphasis role='strong'>When two planes</emphasis> crashed into the
2207 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2208 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2209 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2210 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2211 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2212 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2213 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2214 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2215 watching.
2216 </para>
2217 <para>
2218 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2219 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2220 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was <quote>balance,</quote>
2221 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2222 increasingly come to expect it, <quote>news as entertainment,</quote> even if the
2223 entertainment is tragedy.
2224 </para>
2225 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
2226 <indexterm><primary>CBS</primary></indexterm>
2227 <para>
2228 But in addition to this produced news about the <quote>tragedy of September
2229 11,</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2230 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2231 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2232 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2233 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2234 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2235 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2236 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2237 the term in his book <citetitle>Cyber Rights</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2238 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2239 was also the Internet.
2240 </para>
2241 <para>
2242 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet&mdash;though I do think the
2243 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2244 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2245 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2246 movie
2247 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2248 by a student on the <quote>Just Think!</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2249 with sound or text.
2250 </para>
2251 <para>
2252 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2253 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2254 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2255 tradition&mdash;not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2256 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2257 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2258 spread practically instantaneously.
2259 </para>
2260 <para>
2261 September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2262 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2263 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2264 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2265 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2266 cultures, it records private facts in a public way&mdash;it's a kind
2267 of electronic <citetitle>Jerry Springer</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2268 </para>
2269 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2270 <para>
2271 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2272 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2273 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2274 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2275 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2276 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2277 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2278 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2279 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2280 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2281 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2282 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2283 </para>
2284 <para>
2285 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2286 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2287 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2288 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2289 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2290 people vote
2291 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2292 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2293 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2294 </para>
2295 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de</primary></indexterm>
2296 <indexterm><primary>jury system</primary></indexterm>
2297 <para>
2298 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2299 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2300 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2301 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2302 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2303 most important account of early <quote>Democracy in America.</quote> It wasn't
2304 popular elections that fascinated him&mdash;it was the jury, an
2305 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2306 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2307 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2308 deliberated. Members argued about the <quote>right</quote> result; they tried to
2309 persuade each other of the <quote>right</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2310 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2311 come to an end.<footnote><para>
2312 <!-- f15 -->
2313 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, <citetitle>Democracy in America</citetitle>,
2314 bk. 1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16.
2315 </para></footnote>
2316 </para>
2317 <para>
2318 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2319 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2320 are pushing to create just such an institution.<footnote><para>
2321 <!-- f16 -->
2322 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, <quote>Deliberation Day,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2323 Political Philosophy</citetitle> 10 (2) (2002): 129.
2324 </para></footnote>
2325 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2326 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2327 place for <quote>democratic deliberation</quote> to occur.
2328 </para>
2329 <para>
2330 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2331 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2332 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2333 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2334 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2335 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.<footnote><para>
2336 <!-- f17 -->
2337 Cass Sunstein, <citetitle>Republic.com</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001),
2338 65&ndash;80, 175, 182, 183, 192.
2339 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2340 little beyond what our friends say.
2341 </para>
2342 <indexterm id='idxblogs1' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2343 <indexterm><primary>e-mail</primary></indexterm>
2344 <para>
2345 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2346 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2347 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2348 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2349 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2350
2351 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2352 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2353 place.
2354 </para>
2355 <para>
2356 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2357 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2358 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2359 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2360 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2361 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2362 </para>
2363 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard</primary></indexterm>
2364 <para>
2365 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2366 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race
2367 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2368 is having an effect.
2369 </para>
2370 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent</primary></indexterm>
2371 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom</primary></indexterm>
2372 <para>
2373 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2374 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2375 <quote>misspoke</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2376 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2377 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2378 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2379 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2380 more instances of the same <quote>misspeaking</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2381 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2382 resign as senate majority leader.<footnote><para>
2383 <!-- f18 -->
2384 Noah Shachtman, <quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,</quote> New
2385 York Times, 16 January 2003, G5.
2386 </para></footnote>
2387 </para>
2388 <para>
2389 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2390 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2391 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2392 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2393 on.
2394 </para>
2395 <para>
2396 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2397 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2398 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2399 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2400 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2401 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2402 peer-generated rankings.
2403 </para>
2404 <indexterm id="idxwinerdave" class='startofrange'><primary>Winer, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2405 <para>
2406 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2407 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2408 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2409 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2410 difference is the absence of a financial <quote>conflict of interest.</quote> <quote>I think you
2411 have to take the conflict of interest</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2412 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2413 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2414 get it out of the way.</quote>
2415 </para>
2416 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2417 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2418 <para>
2419 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2420 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2421 from the public than an unconcentrated media can&mdash;as CNN admitted
2422 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2423 its own employees.<footnote><para>
2424 <!-- f19 -->
2425 Telephone interview with David Winer, 16 April 2003.
2426 </para></footnote>
2427 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2428 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2429 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2430 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2431 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2432 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2433 told her that <emphasis>they</emphasis> were writing <quote>the story.</quote>)
2434 </para>
2435 <para> Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2436 debate&mdash;<quote>amateur</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced, but in the
2437 sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to give their
2438 reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a story, as
2439 reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds from across
2440 the southwest United States turned to the Internet to retell what they
2441 had seen.<footnote><para>
2442 <!-- f20 -->
2443 John Schwartz, <quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2444 Information Online,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci
2445 D. Kramer, <quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,</quote>
2446 Online Journalism Review, 2 February 2003, available at
2447 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #10</ulink>.
2448 </para></footnote>
2449 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2450 <quote>triangulate,</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2451 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2452 out of it</quote>&mdash;with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2453 </para>
2454 <para>
2455 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2456 with blogs. <quote>It's going to become an essential skill,</quote> Winer predicts,
2457 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2458 not clear that <quote>journalism</quote> is happy about this&mdash;some journalists
2459 have been told to curtail their blogging.<footnote>
2460 <para>
2461 <!-- f21 -->
2462 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2463 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2464 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve</primary></indexterm>
2465 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2466 See Michael Falcone, <quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?</quote> <citetitle>New
2467 York Times</citetitle>, 29 September 2003, C4. (<quote>Not all news organizations have
2468 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2469 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2470 war on March 9, stopped posting 12 days later at his bosses'
2471 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a <citetitle>Houston Chronicle</citetitle> reporter, was
2472 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2473 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.</quote>)
2474 </para></footnote>
2475 But it is clear that we are still in transition. <quote>A
2476
2477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2478 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,</quote> Winer told me.
2479 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2480 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2481 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, <quote>we will
2482 be the last thing that gets shut down.</quote>
2483 </para>
2484 <para>
2485 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because <quote>you
2486 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.</quote>
2487 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2488 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2489 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2490 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2491 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2492 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2493 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2494 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2495 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2496 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2497 extraordinary to report.
2498 </para>
2499 <indexterm startref='idxblogs1' class='endofrange'/>
2500 <indexterm startref="idxwinerdave" class='endofrange'/>
2501 <indexterm id="idxbrownjohnseely" class='startofrange'><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
2502 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2503 <para>
2504 <emphasis role='strong'>John Seely Brown</emphasis> is the chief
2505 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2506 describes it, is <quote>human learning and &hellip; the creation of
2507 knowledge ecologies for creating &hellip; innovation.</quote>
2508 </para>
2509 <para>
2510 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2511 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2512 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2513 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2514 affect learning.
2515 </para>
2516 <para>
2517 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When <quote>a lot of us grew up,</quote>
2518 he explains, that tinkering was done <quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2519 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.</quote> But digital technologies
2520 enable a different kind of tinkering&mdash;with abstract ideas though
2521 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2522 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2524 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2525 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2526 or <quote>free collage,</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2527 the tinkering of many others.
2528 </para>
2529 <para>
2530 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2531 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2532 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2533 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2534 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2535 </para>
2536 <para>
2537 This opportunity creates a <quote>completely new kind of learning platform,</quote>
2538 as Brown describes. <quote>As soon as you start doing that, you &hellip;
2539 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2540 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2541 if they can improve it.</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2542 apprenticeship. <quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.</quote>
2543 </para>
2544 <para>
2545 In this process, <quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2546 They are code.</quote> Kids are <quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2547 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2548 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2549 platform. &hellip; You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2550 you tinker the more you improve.</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2551 learn.
2552 </para>
2553 <para>
2554 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2555 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2556 it, <quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2557 intelligence.</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2558 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2559 text. <quote>The Web &hellip; says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2560 you are visual, if you are interested in film &hellip; [then] there is a
2561 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2562 these multiple forms of intelligence.</quote>
2563 </para>
2564 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'/>
2565 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2566 <para>
2567 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2568 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2569
2570 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2571 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2572 kind of recognition.
2573 </para>
2574 <para>
2575 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2576 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2577 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2578 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2579 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2580 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2581 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2582 </para>
2583 <para>
2584 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2585 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2586 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>)
2587 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the <quote>right to
2588 tinker</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2589 general.<footnote><para>
2590 <!-- f22 -->
2591 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, <quote>Technological Access
2592 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2593 of the Association for Computer Machinery</citetitle> 43 (2000): 9.
2594 </para></footnote>
2595 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2596 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2597 </para>
2598 <para>
2599 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,</quote> Brown
2600 explains. We need to <quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2601 and want to learn.</quote>
2602 </para>
2603 <para>
2604 <quote>Yet,</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2605 evince, <quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2606 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. &hellip; We're building an
2607 architecture that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2608 system that closes down that part of the brain.</quote>
2609 </para>
2610 <indexterm startref="idxbrownjohnseely" class='endofrange'/>
2611 <para>
2612 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2613 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2614 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2615 the law to close down that technology.
2616 </para>
2617 <para>
2618 <quote>No way to run a culture,</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2619 chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="collectors"/>,
2620 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2621 </para>
2622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2623 </chapter>
2624 <chapter label="3" id="catalogs">
2625 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs</title>
2626 <indexterm><primary>RPI</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</see></indexterm>
2627 <indexterm id="idxrensselaer" class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary></indexterm>
2628 <para>
2629 <emphasis role='strong'>In the fall</emphasis> of 2002, Jesse Jordan
2630 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2631 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2632 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2633 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2634 was available on the RPI network.
2635 </para>
2636 <para>
2637 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2638 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2639 to information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand
2640 undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school
2641 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2642 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2643 </para>
2644 <para>
2645 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2646 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2647 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2648 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2649 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2650 </para>
2651 <para>
2652 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2653 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2654 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2655 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2656 engines can do this even better. The idea of <quote>intranet</quote> search
2657 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2658 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2659 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2660 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2661 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2662 </para>
2663 <para>
2664 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2665 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2666 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2667 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2668 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2669 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2670 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2671 </para>
2672 <para>
2673 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2674 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2675 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2676 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2677 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2678 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2679 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2680 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2681 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2682 on-line.
2683 </para>
2684 <para>
2685 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2686 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2687 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2688 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2689 be on users' computers.
2690 </para>
2691 <para>
2692 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2693 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2694 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2695 might have created; university brochures&mdash;basically anything that
2696 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2697 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2698 computer.
2699 </para>
2700 <para>
2701 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2702 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2703 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and&mdash;so that this
2704 point is absolutely clear&mdash;Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2705 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2706 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2707 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2708 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2709 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2710 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2711 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2712 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2713 supposed to do.
2714 </para>
2715 <para>
2716 On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2717 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2718 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2719 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2720 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2721 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2722 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2723 </para>
2724 <para>
2725 <quote>It was absurd,</quote> he told me. <quote>I don't think I did anything
2726 wrong. &hellip; I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2727 engine that I ran or &hellip; what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2728 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2729 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2730 easier to use</quote>&mdash;again, a <emphasis>search engine</emphasis>,
2731 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2732 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2733 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2734 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2735 with music.
2736 </para>
2737 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages</primary></indexterm>
2738 <para>
2739 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2740 network and had therefore <quote>willfully</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2741 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2742 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2743 <quote>willful infringement,</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2744 call <quote>statutory damages.</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2745 claim $150,000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2746 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2747 Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000.
2748 </para>
2749 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University</primary></indexterm>
2750 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University</primary></indexterm>
2751 <para>
2752 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2753 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2754 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2755 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2756 huge demands for <quote>damages</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2757 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2758 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $100
2759 <emphasis>billion</emphasis>&mdash;six times the
2760 <emphasis>total</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2761 2001.<footnote><para>
2762
2763 <!-- f1 -->
2764 Tim Goral, <quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks:
2765 Suit Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages,</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC</citetitle> 6
2766 (2003): 5, available at 2003 WL 55179443.
2767 </para></footnote>
2768 </para>
2769 <indexterm startref="idxrensselaer" class='endofrange'/>
2770 <para>
2771 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2772 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2773 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2774 $12,000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2775 $12,000 to dismiss the case.
2776 </para>
2777 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt</primary></indexterm>
2778 <para>
2779 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2780 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2781 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2782 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2783 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2784 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2785 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, <quote>You don't want to pay another
2786 visit to a dentist like me.</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2787 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2788 </para>
2789 <para>
2790 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2791 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2792 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2793 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2794 at least $250,000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2795 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2796 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2797 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2798 </para>
2799 <para>
2800 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $250,000 and a chance at winning,
2801 or $12,000 and a settlement.
2802 </para>
2803 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
2804 <para>
2805 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2806 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2807 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2808 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2809 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $1 million a year.
2810 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2811 artist makes $45,900.<footnote><para>
2812 <!-- f2 -->
2813 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001)
2814 (27&ndash;2042&mdash;Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2815 the Arts, <citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon</citetitle> (2000).
2816 </para></footnote>
2817 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2818 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2819 student for running a search engine?<footnote><para>
2820 <!-- f3 -->
2821 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in <quote>KaZaA and Punishment,</quote>
2822 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, A24.
2823 </para></footnote>
2824 </para>
2825 <para>
2826 On June 23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2827 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2828 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $15 million lawsuit became an
2829 activist:
2830 </para>
2831 <blockquote>
2832 <para>
2833 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2834 an activist. &hellip; [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2835 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2836 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2837 </para>
2838 </blockquote>
2839 <para>
2840 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2841 his father told me, Jesse <quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
2842 I. &hellip; He's not a tree hugger. &hellip; I think it's bizarre that they would
2843 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2844 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.</quote>
2845 </para>
2846 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
2847 </chapter>
2848 <chapter label="4" id="pirates">
2849 <title>CHAPTER FOUR: <quote>Pirates</quote></title>
2850 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
2851 <para>
2852 <emphasis role='strong'>If <quote>piracy</quote> means</emphasis>
2853 using the creative property of others without their
2854 permission&mdash;if <quote>if value, then right</quote> is
2855 true&mdash;then the history of the content industry is a history of
2856 piracy. Every important sector of <quote>big media</quote>
2857 today&mdash;film, records, radio, and cable TV&mdash;was born of a
2858 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
2859 generation's pirates join this generation's country club&mdash;until
2860 now.
2861 </para>
2862 <section id="film">
2863 <title>Film</title>
2864 <para>
2865 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.<footnote><para>
2866 <!-- f1 -->
2867 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
2868 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
2869 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 87&ndash;93,
2870 which details Edison's <quote>adventures</quote> with copyright and patent.
2871 </para></footnote>
2872 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
2873 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
2874 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
2875 exercised through a monopoly <quote>trust,</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
2876 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
2877 property&mdash;patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
2878 this creative property
2879 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
2880 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
2881 </para>
2882 <para>
2883 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
2884 </para>
2885 <blockquote>
2886 <para>
2887 A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
2888 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
2889 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
2890 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
2891 summer of 1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
2892 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
2893 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
2894 </para>
2895 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William</primary></indexterm>
2896 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company</primary></indexterm>
2897 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
2898 <para>
2899 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
2900 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
2901 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
2902 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
2903 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
2904 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
2905 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
2906 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
2907 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
2908 license was revoked.<footnote><para>
2909 <!-- f2 -->
2910 J. A. Aberdeen, <citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
2911 Picture Producers</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts
2912 posted at <quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
2913 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,</quote> available at
2914 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #11</ulink>. For a
2915 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
2916 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, <quote>From
2917 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
2918 the Propertization of Copyright</quote> (September 2002), University of
2919 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
2920 Working Paper No. 159.
2921 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
2922 </para></footnote>
2923 </para>
2924 </blockquote>
2925 <para>
2926 The Napsters of those days, the <quote>independents,</quote> were companies like
2927 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
2928 resisted. <quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
2929 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
2930 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.</quote><footnote><para>
2931 <!-- f3 -->
2932 Marc Wanamaker, <quote>The First Studios,</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority</citetitle>, archived at
2933 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #12</ulink>.
2934 </para></footnote>
2935 That led the independents to flee the East
2936 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
2937 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
2938 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
2939 did just that.
2940 </para>
2941 <para>
2942 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
2943 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
2944 patent holder a truly <quote>limited</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
2945
2946 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
2947 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
2948 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
2949 Edison's creative property.
2950 </para>
2951 </section>
2952 <section id="recordedmusic">
2953 <title>Recorded Music</title>
2954 <para>
2955 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
2956 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
2957 </para>
2958 <indexterm id="idxfourneauxhenri" class='startofrange'><primary>Fourneaux, Henri</primary></indexterm>
2959 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil</primary></indexterm>
2960 <para>
2961 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
2962 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
2963 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
2964 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
2965 their music. In other words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
2966 1899 hit <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
2967 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
2968 right to perform it publicly.
2969 </para>
2970 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
2971 <para>
2972 But what if I wanted to record <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> using Edison's phonograph
2973 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
2974 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
2975 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
2976 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
2977 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
2978 <quote>public performance</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
2979 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
2980 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
2981 brain are not&mdash;yet&mdash; regulated by copyright law). So if I
2982 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
2983 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
2984 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
2985 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
2986 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
2987 its composer anything.
2988 </para>
2989 <indexterm startref="idxfourneauxhenri" class='endofrange'/>
2990 <para>
2991 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
2992 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
2993 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
2994 put it,
2995 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
2996 </para>
2997 <blockquote>
2998 <para>
2999 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3000 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3001 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3002 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3003 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3004 rights.<footnote><para>
3005 <!-- f4 -->
3006 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3007 S. 6330 and H.R. 19853 Before the ( Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th
3008 Cong. 59, 1st sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3009 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in <citetitle>Legislative History of the
3010 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3011 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3012 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3013 </para></footnote>
3014 </para>
3015 </blockquote>
3016 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip</primary></indexterm>
3017 <para>
3018 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3019 people's works were <quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3020 genius of American composers,</quote><footnote><para>
3021 <!-- f5 -->
3022 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223
3023 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3024 </para></footnote>
3025 and the <quote>music publishing industry</quote>
3026 was thereby <quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.</quote><footnote><para>
3027 <!-- f6 -->
3028 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226
3029 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3030 </para></footnote>
3031 As John Philip
3032 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, <quote>When they make money
3033 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.</quote><footnote><para>
3034 <!-- f7 -->
3035 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23
3036 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3037 </para></footnote>
3038 </para>
3039 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company</primary></indexterm>
3040 <indexterm><primary>player pianos</primary></indexterm>
3041 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
3042 <para>
3043 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3044 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3045 player piano argued that <quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3046 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3047 of anything he had before their introduction.</quote> Rather, the machines
3048 increased the sales of sheet music.<footnote><para>
3049 <!-- f8 -->
3050
3051 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283&ndash;84
3052 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3053 Perforating Company of New York).
3054 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3055 Congress was <quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3056 they represent, and whose servants they are.</quote> <quote>All talk about
3057 `theft,'</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3058 wrote, <quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3059 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3060 statute.</quote><footnote><para>
3061 <!-- f9 -->
3062 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared
3063 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3064 Graphophone Company Association).
3065 </para></footnote>
3066 </para>
3067 <para>
3068 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3069 <emphasis>and</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3070 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the <quote>mechanical
3071 reproductions</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3072 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3073 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3074 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3075 recorded once. This is the part of
3076
3077 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3078 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3079 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3080 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3081 </para>
3082 <para>
3083 American law ordinarily calls this a <quote>compulsory license,</quote> but I will
3084 refer to it as a <quote>statutory license.</quote> A statutory license is a license
3085 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3086 Copyright Act in 1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3087 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3088 the fee set by the statute.
3089 </para>
3090 <para>
3091 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3092 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3093 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3094 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3095 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3096 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3097 Grisham.
3098 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
3099 </para>
3100 <para>
3101 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3102 thus, in effect, the law <emphasis>subsidizes</emphasis> the recording
3103 industry through a kind of piracy&mdash;by giving recording artists a
3104 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3105 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3106 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3107 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3108 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3109 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3110 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3111 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3112 creativity.<footnote><para>
3113
3114 <!-- f10 -->
3115 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and
3116 H.R. 11794 Before the ( Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st
3117 sess., 217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3118 in <citetitle>Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3119 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3120 </para></footnote>
3121 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3122 </para>
3123 <para>
3124 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3125 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3126 records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3127 relates,
3128 </para>
3129 <blockquote>
3130 <para>
3131 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3132 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3133 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3134 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3135 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3136 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3137 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3138 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3139 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before 1909 and
3140 the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3141 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3142 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3143 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3144 choice.<footnote><para>
3145 <!-- f11 -->
3146 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee
3147 on the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8
3148 March 1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3149 this report.</para></footnote>
3150 </para>
3151 </blockquote>
3152 <para>
3153 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3154 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3155 </para>
3156 </section>
3157 <section id="radio">
3158 <title>Radio</title>
3159 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments1' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
3160 <para>
3161 Radio was also born of piracy.
3162 </para>
3163 <para>
3164 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3165 <quote>public performance</quote> of the composer's work.<footnote><para>
3166 <!-- f12 -->
3167 See 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning,
3168 record companies printed <quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast</quote> and other
3169 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3170 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3171 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3172 station. See <citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Whiteman</citetitle>, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd
3173 Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3174 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3175 Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 281.
3176 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned</primary></indexterm>
3177 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3178 </para></footnote>
3179 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3180 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3181 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3182 </para>
3183 <para>
3184 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3185 copy of the <emphasis>composer's</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3186 also performing a copy of the <emphasis>recording artist's</emphasis>
3187 work. It's one thing to have <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> sung on the radio by the
3188 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3189 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3190 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3191 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3192 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3193 music for his work.
3194 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
3195
3196 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3197 </para>
3198 <para>
3199 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3200 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3201 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3202 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3203 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3204 of playing the song.
3205 </para>
3206 <indexterm id="idxmadonna" class='startofrange'><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3207 <para>
3208 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3209 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3210 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3211 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3212 </para>
3213 <para>
3214 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3215 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3216 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3217 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3218 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3219 <quote>protected</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3220 <emphasis>pirate</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3221 her anything.
3222 </para>
3223 <indexterm startref="idxmadonna" class='endofrange'/>
3224 <para>
3225 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3226 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3227 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3228 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3229 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3230 to take something for nothing.
3231 </para>
3232 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments1' class='endofrange'/>
3233 </section>
3234 <section id="cabletv">
3235 <title>Cable TV</title>
3236 <indexterm id='idxcabletv1' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
3237 <para>
3238 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3239 </para>
3240 <para>
3241 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3242 television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3243 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3244 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3245 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3246 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3247 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3248 did&mdash; Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3249 give away.
3250 </para>
3251 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas</primary></indexterm>
3252 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin</primary></indexterm>
3253 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3254 <para>
3255 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3256 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3257 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.</quote><footnote><para>
3258 <!-- f13 -->
3259 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the
3260 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3261 Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966)
3262 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3263 Commission).
3264 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3265 </para></footnote>
3266 There may have been a <quote>public interest</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3267 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3268 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, <quote>Does public
3269 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?</quote><footnote><para>
3270 <!-- f14 -->
3271 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3272 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3273 </para></footnote>
3274 As another broadcaster put it,
3275 </para>
3276 <blockquote>
3277 <para>
3278 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3279 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3280 paid for.<footnote><para>
3281 <!-- f15 -->
3282 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3283 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3284 </para></footnote>
3285 </para>
3286 </blockquote>
3287 <para>
3288 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3289 </para>
3290 <blockquote>
3291 <para>
3292 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3293 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3294 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3295 think there are harsher words which would fit it.<footnote><para>
3296 <!-- f16 -->
3297 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3298 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3299 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3300 </para></footnote>
3301 </para>
3302 </blockquote>
3303 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3304 <para>
3305 These were <quote>free-ride[rs],</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3306 Heston said, who were <quote>depriving actors of
3307 compensation.</quote><footnote><para>
3308 <!-- f17 -->
3309 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3310 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3311 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3312 </para>
3313 </footnote>
3314 </para>
3315 <para>
3316 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3317 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3318 </para>
3319 <blockquote>
3320 <para>
3321 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3322 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3323 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3324 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. &hellip; The
3325
3326 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3327 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3328 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.<footnote><para>
3329 <!-- f18 -->
3330 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M.
3331 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3332 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3333 </para></footnote>
3334 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3335 </para>
3336 </blockquote>
3337 <para>
3338 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3339 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3340 </para>
3341 <para>
3342 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3343 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they <quote>pirated.</quote>
3344 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3345 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3346 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3347 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3348 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3349 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3350 companies thus built their empire in part upon a <quote>piracy</quote> of the value
3351 created by broadcasters' content.
3352 </para>
3353 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv1' class='endofrange'/>
3354 <para>
3355 <emphasis role='strong'>These separate stories</emphasis> sing a
3356 common theme. If <quote>piracy</quote> means using value from someone
3357 else's creative property without permission from that creator&mdash;as
3358 it is increasingly described today<footnote><para>
3359 <!-- f19 -->
3360 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, <citetitle>The Engine
3361 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet&mdash;The Myth of Free
3362 Information</citetitle>, available at
3363 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #13</ulink>. <quote>The
3364 threat of piracy&mdash;the use of someone else's creative work without
3365 permission or compensation&mdash;has grown with the Internet.</quote>
3366 </para></footnote>
3367 &mdash; then <emphasis>every</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3368 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3369 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV. &hellip; The list is long and
3370 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3371 last. Every generation&mdash;until now.
3372 </para>
3373 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3374 </section>
3375 </chapter>
3376 <chapter label="5" id="piracy">
3377 <title>CHAPTER FIVE: <quote>Piracy</quote></title>
3378 <para>
3379 <emphasis role='strong'>There is piracy</emphasis> of copyrighted
3380 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3381 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3382 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3383 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3384 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3385 </para>
3386 <para>
3387 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of <quote>taking</quote>
3388 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3389 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3390 taking <quote>piracy,</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3391 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3392 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3393 has so often done in the past.
3394 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3395 </para>
3396 <section id="piracy-i">
3397 <title>Piracy I</title>
3398 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3399 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3400 <para>
3401 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3402 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3403 content, copy it, and sell it&mdash;all without the permission of a copyright
3404 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion
3405 every year to physical piracy<footnote><para>
3406 <!-- f1 -->
3407 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), <citetitle>The
3408 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003</citetitle>, July 2003, available
3409 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #14</ulink>. See
3410 also Ben Hunt, <quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3411 Times</citetitle>, 14 February 2003, 11.
3412 </para></footnote>
3413 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3414 estimates that it loses $3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3415 </para>
3416 <para>
3417 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3418 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3419 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3420 This piracy is wrong.
3421 </para>
3422 <para>
3423 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3424 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3425 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3426 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3427 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3428 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3429 of our existence, treated as right.
3430 </para>
3431 <para>
3432 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3433 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3434 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3435 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3436 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3437 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3438 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3439 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3440 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3441 </para>
3442 <para>
3443 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3444 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3445 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3446 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3447 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3448 similar childhood.
3449 </para>
3450 <para>
3451 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3452 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3453 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3454 of intellectual property law.<footnote><para>
3455 <!-- f2 -->
3456 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3457 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The
3458 New Press, 2003), 10&ndash;13, 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3459 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3460 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3461 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3462 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3463 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3464 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3465 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3466 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3467 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3468 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3469 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3470 TRIPS framework.
3471 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents</primary></indexterm>
3472 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
3473 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3474 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3475 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3476 is wrong.
3477 </para>
3478 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3479 <para>
3480 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3481 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3482 to American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3483 bought those American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any
3484 less money than they otherwise would have had.<footnote><para>
3485 <!-- f3 -->
3486 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3487 Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002),
3488 144&ndash;90. <quote>In some instances &hellip; the impact of piracy on the
3489 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3490 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3491 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3492 pirating were not an option.</quote> Ibid., 149.
3493 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3494 </para></footnote>
3495 </para>
3496 <para>
3497 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3498 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3499 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3500 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3501 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes &amp; Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3502 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?</quote>
3503 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes &amp;
3504 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3505 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3506 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3507 piracy of the tangible.
3508 </para>
3509 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'/>
3510 <para>
3511 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3512 property right of a very special sort, it <emphasis>is</emphasis> a
3513 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3514 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3515 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3516 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3517 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3518 give people the right to <quote>take</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3519 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3520
3521 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3522 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3523 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3524 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3525 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3526 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what <quote>property</quote> means.
3527 </para>
3528 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3529 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
3530 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
3531 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3532 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3533 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of</secondary></indexterm>
3534 <indexterm><primary>Windows</primary></indexterm>
3535 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>international software piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3536 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of</secondary></indexterm>
3537 <para>
3538 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3539 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese <quote>steal</quote>
3540 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3541 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3542 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3543 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3544 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3545 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3546 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3547 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3548 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3549 </para>
3550 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
3551 <para>
3552 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3553 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3554 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3555 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3556 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3557 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3558 </para>
3559 <indexterm><primary>Netscape</primary></indexterm>
3560 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer</primary></indexterm>
3561 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3562 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3563 <para>
3564 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3565 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3566 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3567 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3568 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3569 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3570 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3571 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3572 what&mdash;at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3573 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3574 violating the law is still wrong.
3575 </para>
3576 <para>
3577 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3578 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3579 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3580 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3581 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3582 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3583 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3584 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3585 is flat out wrong.
3586 </para>
3587 <para>
3588 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3589 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is. Or
3590 at least, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3591 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of <quote>piracy</quote> are useful
3592 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3593 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3594 <quote>piracy</quote> in that sense of the term.
3595 </para>
3596 <para>
3597 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3598 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3599 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3600 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3601 </para>
3602 <para>
3603 For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3604 controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it
3605 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable
3606 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3607 </para>
3608 <para>
3609 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3610 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3611 sharing to survive.
3612 </para>
3613 </section>
3614 <section id="piracy-ii">
3615 <title>Piracy II</title>
3616 <para>
3617 The key to the <quote>piracy</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that <quote>rob[s]
3618 the author of [his] profit.</quote><footnote><para>
3619 <!-- f4 -->
3620 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777).
3621 </para></footnote>
3622 This means we must determine whether
3623 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3624 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3625 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3626 author of his profit.
3627 </para>
3628 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3629 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn</primary></indexterm>
3630 <para>
3631 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3632 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3633 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3634 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well<footnote><para>
3635 <!-- f5 -->
3636 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3637 See Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3638 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle> (New York:
3639 HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3640 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3641 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3642 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3643 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3644 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 89&ndash;92, 139.
3645
3646 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
3647 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3648 put together components that had been developed independently.
3649 </para>
3650 <para>
3651 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999,
3652 Napster amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After
3653 eighteen months, there were close to 80 million registered users of the
3654 system.<footnote><para>
3655 <!-- f6 -->
3656 See Carolyn Lochhead, <quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,</quote> <citetitle>San
3657 Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24 September 2002, A1; <quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,</quote>
3658 <citetitle>New Scientist</citetitle>, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Napster Names CEO,
3659 Secures New Financing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 23 May 2003, C1;
3660 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton,
3661 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet</quote> (London) <citetitle>Times</citetitle>, 26 July 2002, 18.
3662 </para></footnote>
3663 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3664 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3665 boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3666 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3667 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3668 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend&mdash;
3669 or your 20,000 best friends.
3670 </para>
3671 <para>
3672 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3673 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3674 September 2002 estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded
3675 music&mdash;28 percent of Americans older than 12.<footnote><para>
3676
3677 <!-- f7 -->
3678 See Ipsos-Insight, <citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution</citetitle>
3679 (September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3680 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have
3681 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3682 </para></footnote>
3683 A survey by the NPD group quoted in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>
3684 estimated that 43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3685 exchange content in May 2003.<footnote><para>
3686 <!-- f8 -->
3687 Amy Harmon, <quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,</quote> <citetitle>New
3688 York Times</citetitle>, 6 June 2003, A1.
3689 </para></footnote>
3690 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3691 massive quantity of content is being <quote>taken</quote> on these networks. The
3692 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3693 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3694 </para>
3695 <para>
3696 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3697 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3698 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3699 complicated than one might think. So consider&mdash;a bit more
3700 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3701 do&mdash;the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3702 of harm it entails.
3703 </para>
3704 <para>
3705 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3706 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3707 different kinds into four types.
3708 </para>
3709 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
3710 <listitem>
3711 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3712 <para>
3713 <!-- A. -->
3714 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3715 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3716 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3717 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3718 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3719 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3720 users who download instead of purchasing.
3721 </para></listitem>
3722 <listitem><para>
3723 <!-- B. -->
3724 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3725 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3726 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3727 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3728 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3729 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3730 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3731 music purchased.
3732 </para></listitem>
3733 <listitem><para>
3734 <!-- C. -->
3735 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3736 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3737 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3738 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3739 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3740 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3741 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend <quote>recalling</quote> old
3742 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3743 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3744 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3745 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero&mdash;the same
3746 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to
3747 a local collector.
3748 </para></listitem>
3749 <listitem><para>
3750 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3751 <!-- D. -->
3752 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3753 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3754 wants to give away.
3755 </para></listitem>
3756 </orderedlist>
3757 <para>
3758 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3759 </para>
3760 <para>
3761 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3762 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3763 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3764 harmful.<footnote><para>
3765 <!-- f9 -->
3766 See Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle>, 148&ndash;49.
3767 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3768 </para></footnote>
3769 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3770 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3771 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3772 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3773 answer&mdash;and certainly much more difficult than the current
3774 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3775 </para>
3776 <para>
3777 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3778 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3779 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3780 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3781 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of <quote>theft</quote> that is
3782 <quote>devastating</quote> the industry.
3783 </para>
3784 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
3785 <para>
3786 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3787 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3788 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3789 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3790 &amp; Young put it, <quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3791 technology, the labels fought it.</quote><footnote><para>
3792 <!-- f10 -->
3793 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary></indexterm>
3794 See Cap Gemini Ernst &amp; Young, <citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
3795 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis</citetitle> (2003), 3. This report
3796 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3797 practice of cassette taping in the 1970s, including an advertising
3798 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption <quote>Home taping
3799 is killing music.</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3800 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3801 behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3802 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3803 Assessment, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law</citetitle>,
3804 OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3805 October 1989), 145&ndash;56. </para></footnote>
3806 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3807 when record sales fell by 11.4 percent in 1981, the industry claimed
3808 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3809 regulating technology was the answer.
3810 </para>
3811 <indexterm><primary>MTV</primary></indexterm>
3812 <para>
3813 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3814 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3815 turnaround. <quote>In the end,</quote> Cap Gemini concludes, <quote>the `crisis' &hellip; was
3816 not the fault of the tapers&mdash;who did not [stop after MTV came into
3817 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
3818 being]&mdash;but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
3819 innovation at the major labels.</quote><footnote><para>
3820 <!-- f11 -->
3821 U.S. Congress, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying</citetitle>, 4.
3822 </para></footnote>
3823 </para>
3824 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'/>
3825 <para>
3826 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
3827 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
3828 the industry in particular, and society in general&mdash;or at least
3829 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
3830 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
3831 VCR&mdash;the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
3832 harmful. The question is also <emphasis>how</emphasis> harmful type A
3833 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
3834 </para>
3835 <para>
3836 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
3837 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
3838 The <quote>net harm</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
3839 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
3840 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
3841 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
3842 therefore have little <emphasis>static</emphasis> reason to resist
3843 them.
3844
3845 </para>
3846 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>sales levels of</secondary></indexterm>
3847 <para>
3848 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
3849 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
3850 actually suggest it might be close.
3851 </para>
3852 <para>
3853 In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9 percent,
3854 from 882 million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7
3855 percent.<footnote><para>
3856 <!-- f12 -->
3857 See Recording Industry Association of America, <citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics</citetitle>,
3858 available at
3859 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #15</ulink>. A later
3860 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
3861 Association of America, <citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy</citetitle>, 25 June 2003,
3862 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
3863 #16</ulink>: <quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
3864 have fallen by 26 percent from 1.16 billion units in to 860 million
3865 units in 2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
3866 of sales, revenues are down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in to $12.6
3867 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
3868 industry worldwide has gone from a $39 billion industry in 2000 down
3869 to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
3870 shipments).</quote>
3871 </para></footnote>
3872 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
3873 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
3874 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
3875 than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That no
3876 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
3877 account for at least some of the loss. <quote>From 1999 to 2001, the average
3878 price of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19.</quote><footnote>
3879 <!-- f13 -->
3880 <para>
3881 Jane Black, <quote>Big Music's Broken Record,</quote> BusinessWeek online, 13
3882 February 2003, available at
3883 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #17</ulink>.
3884 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane</primary></indexterm>
3885 </para>
3886 </footnote>
3887 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
3888 the decline. As Jane Black of <citetitle>BusinessWeek</citetitle> notes, <quote>The
3889 soundtrack to the film <citetitle>High Fidelity</citetitle> has a list price of
3890 $18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
3891 $19.99.</quote><footnote><para>
3892 <!-- f14 -->
3893 Ibid.
3894 </para></footnote>
3895 </para>
3896 <para>
3897
3898 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
3899 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
3900 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
3901 that the RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
3902 estimates that 2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
3903 although 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
3904 free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 percent.
3905 </para>
3906 <para>
3907 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
3908 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
3909 The recording industry constantly asks, <quote>What's the difference between
3910 downloading a song and stealing a CD?</quote>&mdash;but their own numbers
3911 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
3912 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
3913 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
3914 downloads. If every download were a lost sale&mdash;if every use of
3915 Kazaa <quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit</quote>&mdash;then the industry
3916 would have suffered a 100 percent drop in sales last year, not a 7
3917 percent drop. If 2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
3918 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, then there is
3919 a huge difference between <quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.</quote>
3920 </para>
3921 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'/>
3922 <para>
3923 These are the harms&mdash;alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
3924 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
3925 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
3926 these costs?
3927 </para>
3928 <para>
3929 One benefit is type C sharing&mdash;making available content that
3930 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
3931 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
3932 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
3933 available.<footnote><para>
3934 <!-- f15 -->
3935 By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels
3936 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
3937 Law&mdash;Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
3938 Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April
3939 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
3940 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #18</ulink>.
3941 </para></footnote>
3942 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
3943 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
3944 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
3945 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
3946 sense <emphasis>to the company</emphasis> to make it available.
3947 </para>
3948 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
3949 <para>
3950 In real space&mdash;long before the Internet&mdash;the market had a simple
3951 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
3952 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
3953 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
3954 today.<footnote><para>
3955 <!-- f16 -->
3956 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
3957 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
3958 in existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the
3959 United States, an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter
3960 Press, <citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
3961 Market</citetitle> (2002), available at
3962 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #19</ulink>. Used
3963 records accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See National
3964 Association of Recording Merchandisers, <quote>2002 Annual Survey
3965 Results,</quote> available at
3966 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #20</ulink>.
3967 </para></footnote>
3968 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
3969 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
3970 content, <emphasis>even if the content is still under
3971 copyright</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
3972 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
3973 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
3974 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
3975 the content they sell.
3976 </para>
3977 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard</primary></indexterm>
3978 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
3979 <para>
3980 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
3981 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
3982 the content available isn't making money from making the content
3983 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
3984 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
3985 when someone shares my 1949 recording of Bernstein's <quote>Two Love Songs,</quote>
3986 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
3987 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
3988 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
3989 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
3990 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
3991 </para>
3992 <para>
3993 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
3994 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
3995 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
3996 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
3997 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
3998 shut as well?
3999 </para>
4000 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
4001 <para>
4002 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4003 type D sharing to occur&mdash;the sharing of content that copyright owners
4004 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4005 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4006 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
4007 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4008
4009 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4010 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4011 would be a great advertisement for the <quote>real</quote> book. People would read
4012 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4013 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4014 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4015 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4016 great book!)
4017 </para>
4018 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'/>
4019 <para>
4020 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4021 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4022 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4023 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4024 </para>
4025 <para>
4026 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4027 understandably says, <quote>This is how much we've lost,</quote> we must also ask,
4028 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4029 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4030 unavailable?</quote>
4031 </para>
4032 <para>
4033 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4034 chapter, much of the <quote>piracy</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4035 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4036 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="pirates"/>, much of
4037 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4038 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4039 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4040 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4041 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4042 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4043 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4044 found only with time.
4045 </para>
4046 <para>
4047 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4048 just what you call type A sharing?</quote>
4049 </para>
4050 <para>
4051 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The
4052 effect
4053 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4054 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4055 Napster
4056 case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4057 developed
4058 a technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of identified
4059 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4060 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4
4061 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4062 <quote>down to zero.</quote><footnote><para>
4063 <!-- f17 -->
4064 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34-
4065 35 (N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183
4066 MHP, available at
4067
4068 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #21</ulink>. For an
4069 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4070 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster</citetitle> (New
4071 York: Crown Business, 2003), 269&ndash;82.
4072 </para></footnote>
4073 </para>
4074 <para>
4075 If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4076 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4077 assure that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance
4078 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of
4079 VCRs or 100 percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns
4080 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4081 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4082 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4083 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4084 </para>
4085 <para>
4086 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4087 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4088 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4089 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4090 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4091 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4092 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4093 </para>
4094 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
4095 <para>
4096 So, as we've seen, when <quote>mechanical reproduction</quote> threatened the
4097 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4098 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4099 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4100 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4101 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4102 complained to Congress that their <quote>creative property</quote> was not being
4103 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4104 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4105 benefit was enough.
4106 </para>
4107 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
4108 <para>
4109 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4110 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4111 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4112 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4113 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4114 price.
4115 </para>
4116 <para>
4117
4118 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4119 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4120 pianos, served two important goals&mdash;indeed, the two central goals
4121 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4122 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4123 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4124 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4125 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4126 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4127 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4128 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4129 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4130 Congress chose a path that would assure
4131 <emphasis>compensation</emphasis> without giving the past
4132 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4133 </para>
4134 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'/>
4135 <indexterm><primary>Betamax</primary></indexterm>
4136 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
4137 <para>
4138 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4139 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4140 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4141 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4142 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4143 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4144 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4145 <quote>record</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4146 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4147 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4148 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4149 </para>
4150 <para>
4151 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4152 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4153 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4154 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4155 machine to copy only if there were a special <quote>copy me</quote> signal on the
4156 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4157 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4158 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4159 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4160 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4161 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4162 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4163 for the architecture it chose.
4164 </para>
4165 <para>
4166 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4167 champion. Valenti called VCRs <quote>tapeworms.</quote> He warned, <quote>When there are
4168 20, 30, 40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4169 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4170 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4171 copyright.</quote><footnote><para>
4172 <!-- f18 -->
4173 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4174 S. 1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st
4175 and 2nd sess., 459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4176 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4177 </para></footnote>
4178 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4179 creative judgment,</quote> he told Congress, <quote>to understand the devastation
4180 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4181 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4182 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4183 and plain common sense.</quote><footnote><para>
4184 <!-- f19 -->
4185 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475.
4186 </para></footnote>
4187 Indeed, as surveys would later show,
4188 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more<footnote><para>
4189 <!-- f20 -->
4190 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 480 F. Supp. 429,
4191 (C.D. Cal., 1979).
4192 </para></footnote>
4193 &mdash; a use the Court would later hold was not <quote>fair.</quote> By
4194 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4195 copyright infringementwithout creating a mechanism to compensate
4196 copyrightowners,</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would <quote>take from the
4197 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4198 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4199 profit from its reproduction.</quote><footnote><para>
4200 <!-- f21 -->
4201 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony
4202 of Jack Valenti).
4203 </para></footnote>
4204 </para>
4205 <para>
4206 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4207 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4208 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction&mdash;leading Judge Alex
4209 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the <quote>Hollywood
4210 Circuit</quote>&mdash;held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4211 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4212 rule, this totally familiar technology&mdash;which Jack Valenti had
4213 called <quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry</quote> (worse
4214 yet, it was a <emphasis>Japanese</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4215 American film industry)&mdash;was an illegal
4216 technology.<footnote><para>
4217 <!-- f22 -->
4218 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th Cir.
4219 1981).
4220 </para></footnote>
4221 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex</primary></indexterm>
4222 </para>
4223 <para>
4224 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4225
4226 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4227 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4228 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4229 Court wrote,
4230 </para>
4231 <blockquote>
4232 <para>
4233 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4234 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4235 market
4236 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4237 authority
4238 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4239 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4240 implicated
4241 by such new technology.<footnote><para>
4242 <!-- f23 -->
4243 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417, 431 (1984).
4244 </para></footnote>
4245 </para>
4246 </blockquote>
4247 <para>
4248 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4249 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4250 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4251 enough, this <quote>taking</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4252 together, a pattern is clear:
4253 </para>
4254
4255 <informaltable id="t1">
4256 <tgroup cols="4" align="left">
4257 <thead>
4258 <row>
4259 <entry>CASE</entry>
4260 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS <quote>PIRATED</quote></entry>
4261 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS</entry>
4262 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS</entry>
4263 </row>
4264 </thead>
4265 <tbody>
4266 <row>
4267 <entry>Recordings</entry>
4268 <entry>Composers</entry>
4269 <entry>No protection</entry>
4270 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4271 </row>
4272 <row>
4273 <entry>Radio</entry>
4274 <entry>Recording artists</entry>
4275 <entry>N/A</entry>
4276 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4277 </row>
4278 <row>
4279 <entry>Cable TV</entry>
4280 <entry>Broadcasters</entry>
4281 <entry>No protection</entry>
4282 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4283 </row>
4284 <row>
4285 <entry>VCR</entry>
4286 <entry>Film creators</entry>
4287 <entry>No protection</entry>
4288 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4289 </row>
4290 </tbody>
4291 </tgroup>
4292 </informaltable>
4293 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'/>
4294 <para>
4295 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4296 way content was distributed.<footnote><para>
4297 <!-- f24 -->
4298 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4299 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4300 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4301 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4302 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4303 1992 (Title 17 of the <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat.
4304 4237, codified at 17 U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4305 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4306 Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 71. See also Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,</quote>
4307 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 293&ndash;96.
4308 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
4309 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
4310 </para></footnote>
4311 In each case, throughout our history,
4312 that change meant that someone got a <quote>free ride</quote> on someone else's
4313 work.
4314 </para>
4315 <para>
4316 In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4317 Congress eliminate all free riding. In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of
4318 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4319 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4320 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of <quote>piracy.</quote>
4321 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4322 the behavior of the <quote>pirates.</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4323 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4324 interests at stake.
4325 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4326 </para>
4327 <para>
4328 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4329 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4330 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4331 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4332 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4333 regulated?
4334 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4335 to $15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4336 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4337 permission to record a song?
4338 </para>
4339 <para>
4340 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4341 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4342 copyright <quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4343 over all possible uses of his work.</quote><footnote><para>
4344 <!-- f25 -->
4345 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
4346 (1984).
4347 </para></footnote>
4348 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4349 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4350 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4351 balancing has historically been done <emphasis>after</emphasis> a
4352 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4353 facilitate the distribution of content.
4354 </para>
4355 <para>
4356 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4357 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4358 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4359 should not become a tool for <quote>stealing</quote> from artists. But neither
4360 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4361 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4362 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4363 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4364 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4365 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4366 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4367 public interest that innovation continue.
4368 </para>
4369 <para>
4370
4371 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4372 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4373 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4374 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4375 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4376 efficient. Yet these <quote>potential public benefits,</quote> as John Schwartz
4377 writes in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, <quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4378 fight.</quote><footnote><para>
4379 <!-- f26 -->
4380 John Schwartz, <quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4381 Echoes Past Efforts,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 September 2003, C3.
4382 </para></footnote>
4383 </para>
4384 <para>
4385 <emphasis role='strong'>Yet when anyone</emphasis> begins to talk
4386 about <quote>balance,</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4387 argument. <quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4388 incentives,</quote> they say, <quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4389 content,</quote> the warriors insist, <quote>is our
4390 <emphasis>property</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4391 `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4392 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4393 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether
4394 the car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?</quote>
4395 </para>
4396 <para>
4397 <quote>It is <emphasis>our property</emphasis>,</quote> the warriors
4398 insist. <quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4399 is protected.</quote>
4400 </para>
4401 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4402 </section>
4403 </chapter>
4404 </part>
4405 <part id="c-property">
4406 <title><quote>PROPERTY</quote></title>
4407 <partintro>
4408 <para>
4409
4410 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4411 <emphasis role='strong'>The copyright warriors</emphasis> are right: A
4412 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4413 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4414 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4415 that partially determine the price she can get.
4416 </para>
4417 <para>
4418 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a <quote>property</quote> right is a
4419 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4420 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4421 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4422 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4423 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4424 when I take the good <emphasis>idea</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4425 table in the backyard&mdash;by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4426 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4427 then?
4428 </para>
4429 <para>
4430 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4431 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4432 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4433 in the ordinary case&mdash;indeed, in practically every case except for a
4434 narrow
4435 range of exceptions&mdash;ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4436 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress&mdash;though I
4437 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4438 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4439 when I copy the way someone else dresses), <quote>He who receives an idea
4440 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4441 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.</quote><footnote><para>
4442 <!-- f1 -->
4443 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in
4444 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson</citetitle>, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4445 Ellery Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333&ndash;34.
4446 </para></footnote>
4447 </para>
4448 <para>
4449 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4450 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4451 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4452 expression
4453 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4454 property.
4455 </para>
4456 <para>
4457 But how, and to what extent, and in what form&mdash;the details,
4458 in other words&mdash;matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4459 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4460 <quote>property</quote> in its proper context.<footnote><para>
4461 <!-- f2 -->
4462 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4463 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4464 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4465 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4466 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4467 Adam Mossoff, <quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,</quote>
4468 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review</citetitle> 45 (2003): 373, 429 n. 241.
4469 </para></footnote>
4470 </para>
4471 <para>
4472 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4473 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4474 <quote>copyright material is property</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4475 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4476 these stories, the significance of this true
4477 statement&mdash;<quote>copyright material is property</quote>&mdash; will be a bit
4478 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4479 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4480 </para>
4481 </partintro>
4482
4483 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4484 <chapter label="6" id="founders">
4485 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders</title>
4486 <indexterm><primary>Henry V</primary></indexterm>
4487 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4488 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for</secondary></indexterm>
4489 <para>
4490 <emphasis role='strong'>William Shakespeare</emphasis> wrote
4491 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> in 1595. The play was first
4492 published in 1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4493 written. He would continue to write plays through 1613, and the plays
4494 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4495 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4496 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4497 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4498 Henry V: <quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4499 clichés.</quote>
4500 </para>
4501 <para>
4502 In 1774, almost 180 years after <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> was written, the
4503 <quote>copy-right</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4504 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.<footnote><para>
4505 <!-- f1 -->
4506 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben</primary></indexterm>
4507 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John</primary></indexterm>
4508 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4509 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4510 handsome <quote>definitive editions</quote> of classic works. In addition to <citetitle>Romeo and
4511 Juliet</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4512 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4513 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, <quote>Jacob Tonson,
4514 Bookseller,</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar</citetitle> 61:3 (1992): 424&ndash;31.
4515 </para></footnote>
4516 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4517 the Conger<footnote><para>
4518 <!-- f2 -->
4519 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle> (Nashville:
4520 Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 151&ndash;52.
4521 </para></footnote>
4522 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4523 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the <quote>copy</quote> of
4524 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4525 that no
4526 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4527 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4528 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4529 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4530 </para>
4531 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4532 <para>
4533 Now, there's something puzzling about the year 1774 to anyone who
4534 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4535 history of copyright is 1710, the year that the British Parliament
4536 adopted the first <quote>copyright</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4537 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4538 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4539 works already published by 1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4540 additional years.<footnote><para>
4541 <!-- f3 -->
4542 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4543 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4544 <quote>copyright law.</quote> See Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 40.
4545 </para></footnote> Under this law, <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> should have been
4546 free in 1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4547 Tonson's control in 1774?
4548 </para>
4549 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (1662)</primary></indexterm>
4550 <para>
4551 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a <quote>copyright</quote>
4552 was&mdash;indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4553 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4554 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of 1662, had
4555 expired in 1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4556 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4557 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4558 that the publishers, or <quote>Stationers,</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4559 books.
4560 </para>
4561 <para>
4562 There was no <emphasis>positive</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4563 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4564 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4565 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4566 from legislatures <quote>positive law.</quote> We call the words from judges
4567 <quote>common law.</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4568 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4569 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4570 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4571 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4572 </para>
4573 <para>
4574 This question was important to the publishers, or <quote>booksellers,</quote> as
4575 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4576 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4577 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4578
4579 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4580 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4581 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4582 ultimately
4583 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4584 </para>
4585 <para>
4586 The Statute of Anne granted the author or <quote>proprietor</quote> of a book an
4587 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4588 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4589 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4590 copyright <quote>expired,</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4591 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4592 believed.
4593 </para>
4594 <para>
4595 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4596 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4597 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4598 <emphasis>at all?</emphasis>
4599 </para>
4600 <para>
4601 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4602 strong claim. Take <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> as an example: That play
4603 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4604 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4605 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4606 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4607 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4608 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4609 reason is there to allow someone else to <quote>steal</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4610 </para>
4611 <para>
4612 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4613 about the notion of <quote>copyright</quote> that existed at the time of the
4614 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4615 <quote>booksellers.</quote>
4616 </para>
4617 <para>
4618 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4619 to apply the concept of <quote>copyright</quote> ever more broadly. But in 1710, it
4620 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4621 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4622 others from reprinting a book. In 1710, the <quote>copy-right</quote> was a right
4623 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4624 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4625 generally how
4626 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4627 a work could be <emphasis>used</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4628 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4629 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4630 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4631 </para>
4632 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4633 <para>
4634 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4635 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4636 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4637 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4638 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4639 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4640 allowed to make his films. The <quote>copy-right</quote> was only an exclusive
4641 right to print&mdash;no less, of course, but also no more.
4642 </para>
4643 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England</primary></indexterm>
4644 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (1656)</primary></indexterm>
4645 <para>
4646 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4647 They had had a long and ugly experience with <quote>exclusive rights,</quote>
4648 especially <quote>exclusive rights</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4649 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4650 monopolies&mdash;especially monopolies for works that already
4651 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4652 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4653 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In 1656, it passed the
4654 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4655 inventions. And by 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4656 monopoly in publishing.
4657 </para>
4658 <para>
4659 Thus the <quote>copy-right,</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4660 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4661 claim that <quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,</quote> try
4662 sounding convincing when uttering, <quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4663 have it forever.</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4664 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4665 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4666 </para>
4667 <indexterm id='idxbooksellers' class='startofrange'><primary>booksellers, English</primary></indexterm>
4668 <para>
4669 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4670 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4671 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4672 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4673 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4674
4675 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4676 kind&mdash;tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4677 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4678 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as <quote>old patentees
4679 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling</quote>; they were <quote>men who do
4680 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4681 indetted.</quote><footnote><para>
4682
4683 <!-- f4 -->
4684 Philip Wittenberg, <citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4685 Property</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31.
4686 </para></footnote>
4687 </para>
4688 <para>
4689 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4690 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4691 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4692 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4693 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4694 with that idea.
4695 </para>
4696 <para>
4697 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4698 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4699 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4700 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4701 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4702 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4703 compromise
4704 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4705 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4706 construction and spread of culture.
4707 </para>
4708 <para>
4709 When 1731 (1710 + 21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4710 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4711 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4712 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4713 to control publication. But in 1735 and 1737, they tried to persuade
4714 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4715 they said; they needed more time.
4716 </para>
4717 <para>
4718 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4719 words that echo today,
4720 </para>
4721 <blockquote>
4722 <para>
4723 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4724 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4725 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4726 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4727 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4728 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4729 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4730 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4731 Booksellers.<footnote><para>
4732 <!-- f5 -->
4733 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4734 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4735 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4736 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4737 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4738 mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4739 al., 8, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618).
4740 </para></footnote>
4741 </para>
4742 </blockquote>
4743 <para>
4744 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4745 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4746 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
4747 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
4748 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
4749 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
4750 creative <quote>property</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
4751 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
4752 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
4753 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
4754 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
4755 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
4756 way to protect authors.
4757 </para>
4758 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
4759 <para>
4760 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
4761 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
4762 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
4763 <quote>The publishers &hellip; had as much concern for authors as a cattle
4764 rancher has for cattle.</quote><footnote><para>
4765 <!-- f6 -->
4766 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
4767 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4768 Lyman Ray Patterson, <quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
4769 Law Review</citetitle> 40 (1987): 28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
4770 Vaidhyanathan, 37&ndash;48.
4771 </para></footnote>
4772 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
4773 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
4774 </para>
4775 <para>
4776 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
4777 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
4778 Donaldson.<footnote><para>
4779 <!-- f7 -->
4780 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, <citetitle>Authorship and Copyright</citetitle>
4781 (London: Routledge, 1992), 62&ndash;69.
4782 </para></footnote>
4783 </para>
4784 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James</primary></indexterm>
4785 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew</primary></indexterm>
4786 <para>
4787 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
4788 career in Edinburgh in 1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
4789 reprints <quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,</quote> at least
4790 under the Statute of Anne.<footnote><para>
4791 <!-- f8 -->
4792 Mark Rose, <citetitle>Authors and Owners</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
4793 1993), 92.
4794 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
4795 </para></footnote>
4796 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
4797 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
4798 and became <quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.</quote> <quote>[A]mong
4799 them,</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was <quote>the young James Boswell
4800 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
4801 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.</quote><footnote><para>
4802 <!-- f9 -->
4803 Ibid., 93.
4804 </para></footnote>
4805 </para>
4806 <para>
4807 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
4808 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
4809 inexpensive editions <quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
4810 of the supposed common law right of Literary
4811 Property.</quote><footnote><para>
4812 <!-- f10 -->
4813 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
4814 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle>, 167 (quoting
4815 Borwell).
4816 </para></footnote>
4817 His books undercut the Conger prices by 30 to 50 percent, and he
4818 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
4819 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
4820 </para>
4821 <para>
4822 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block <quote>piracy</quote> like
4823 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the <quote>pirates,</quote>
4824 the most important early victory being <citetitle>Millar</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Taylor</citetitle>.
4825 </para>
4826 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)</primary></indexterm>
4827 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert</primary></indexterm>
4828 <para>
4829 Millar was a bookseller who in 1729 had purchased the rights to James
4830 Thomson's poem <quote>The Seasons.</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
4831 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
4832 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
4833 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
4834 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.<footnote><para>
4835 <!-- f11 -->
4836 Howard B. Abrams, <quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
4837 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review</citetitle> 29
4838 (1983): 1152.
4839 </para></footnote>
4840 </para>
4841 <indexterm id="idxmansfield2" class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
4842 <para>
4843 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
4844 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
4845 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
4846 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
4847 law would protect the author against subsequent <quote>pirates.</quote>
4848 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
4849 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
4850 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
4851 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
4852 </para>
4853 <para>
4854 Considered as a matter of abstract justice&mdash;reasoning as if
4855 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
4856 principles&mdash;Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
4857 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
4858 with in 1710: How best to limit
4859 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
4860 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
4861 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in 1710, but
4862 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
4863 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
4864 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
4865 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
4866 </para>
4867 <indexterm startref="idxmansfield2" class='endofrange'/>
4868 <para>
4869 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
4870 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
4871 </para>
4872 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
4873 <para>
4874 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
4875 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
4876 Thomas Beckett.<footnote><para>
4877 <!-- f12 -->
4878 Ibid., 1156.
4879 </para></footnote>
4880 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
4881 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in <citetitle>Millar</citetitle>,
4882 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
4883 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
4884 Court. In February of 1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
4885 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
4886 </para>
4887 <para>
4888 As few legal cases ever do, <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle> drew an
4889 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
4890 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
4891 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
4892 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
4893 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
4894 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
4895 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
4896 </para>
4897 <para>
4898 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
4899 presented to the House and voted upon first by the <quote>law lords,</quote>
4900 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
4901 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
4902 House of Lords generally voted.
4903 </para>
4904 <para>
4905 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
4906 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
4907 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
4908 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
4909 (22 to 11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
4910 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
4911 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
4912 passed into the public domain.
4913 </para>
4914 <para>
4915 <quote>The public domain.</quote> Before the case of <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle>
4916 v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
4917 England. Before 1774, there was a strong argument that common law
4918 copyrights were perpetual. After 1774, the public domain was
4919 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
4920 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
4921 history&mdash;including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
4922 and Bunyan&mdash;were free of legal restraint.
4923 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis</primary></indexterm>
4924 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John</primary></indexterm>
4925 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel</primary></indexterm>
4926 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
4927 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4928 </para>
4929 <para>
4930 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
4931 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
4932 where most of the <quote>pirate publishers</quote> did their work, people
4933 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the <citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser</citetitle>
4934 reported, <quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
4935 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
4936 decision of which so many individuals were interested.</quote> <quote>Great
4937 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
4938 and illuminations.</quote><footnote><para>
4939 <!-- f13 -->
4940 Rose, 97.
4941 </para></footnote>
4942 </para>
4943 <para>
4944 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
4945 equally strong in the opposite direction. The <citetitle>Morning Chronicle</citetitle>
4946 reported:
4947 </para>
4948 <blockquote>
4949 <para>
4950 By the above decision &hellip; near 200,000 pounds worth of what was
4951 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
4952 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
4953 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
4954 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
4955 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
4956 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
4957 successors.<footnote><para>
4958 <!-- f14 -->
4959 Ibid.
4960 </para></footnote>
4961 </para>
4962 </blockquote>
4963 <para>
4964 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
4965 <quote>Ruined</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
4966 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
4967 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
4968 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
4969 <emphasis>free</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
4970 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
4971 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
4972 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
4973 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
4974 book from someone. But <emphasis>free</emphasis> in the sense that the
4975 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
4976 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
4977 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
4978 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
4979 develop&mdash; chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
4980 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a <emphasis>competitive
4981 context</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
4982 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
4983 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
4984 </para>
4985 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellers' class='endofrange'/>
4986 <para>
4987 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
4988 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
4989 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
4990 protected.
4991 </para>
4992 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'/>
4993 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishlaw' class='endofrange'/>
4994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
4995 </chapter>
4996 <chapter label="7" id="recorders">
4997 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders</title>
4998 <para>
4999 <emphasis role='strong'>Jon Else</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5000 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5001 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5002 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5003 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5004 </para>
5005 <para>
5006 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5007 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5008 today.
5009 </para>
5010 <para>
5011 In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5012 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5013 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5014 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5015 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5016 stage.
5017 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5018 </para>
5019 <para>
5020 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5021 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5022 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5023 and the opera company played Wagner, was <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. As Else judged
5024 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5025 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5026 about the scene.
5027 </para>
5028 <para>
5029 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5030 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>.
5031 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5032 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5033 unless <quote>fair use</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5034 </para>
5035 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5036 <para>
5037 Else called <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5038 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5039 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5040 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5041 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5042 </para>
5043 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5044 <para>
5045 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5046 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5047 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5048 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5049 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5050 </para>
5051 <para>
5052 Then, as Else told me, <quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5053 &hellip; that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation&mdash;or at
5054 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.</quote>
5055 And second, Fox <quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5056 to use this four-point-five seconds of &hellip; entirely unsolicited
5057 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.</quote>
5058 </para>
5059 <indexterm><primary>Herrera, Rebecca</primary></indexterm>
5060 <para>
5061 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5062 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5063 explained to her, <quote>There must be some mistake here. &hellip; We're
5064 asking for your educational rate on this.</quote> That was the educational
5065 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5066 confirm what he had been told.
5067 </para>
5068 <para>
5069 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,</quote> he told me. <quote>Yes, you
5070 have your facts straight,</quote> she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the
5071 clip of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5072 about
5073
5074 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5075 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, <quote>And
5076 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.</quote> As an assistant
5077 to Herrera told Else later on, <quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5078 the money.</quote>
5079 </para>
5080 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5081 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The</primary></indexterm>
5082 <para>
5083 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5084 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5085 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5086 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5087 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5088 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5089 </para>
5090 <para>
5091 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5092 copyright to <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5093 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5094 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5095 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5096 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5097 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5098 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5099 says the owner gets to control.
5100 </para>
5101 <para>
5102 For example, <quote>public performance</quote> is a use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> that the
5103 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5104 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see <quote>My
5105 Favorite <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>,</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5106 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5107 whatever she wants&mdash;$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set
5108 by the law.
5109 </para>
5110 <para>
5111 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5112 thought is <quote>fair use.</quote><footnote><para>
5113 <!-- f1 -->
5114 For an excellent argument that such use is <quote>fair use,</quote> but that
5115 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is <quote>fair use,</quote> see Richard
5116 A. Posner with William F. Patry, <quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5117 Wake of <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5118 Law School, 5 August 2003.
5119 </para></footnote>
5120 Else's use of just 4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>
5121 episode is clearly a fair use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>&mdash;and fair use does
5122 not require the permission of anyone.
5123 </para>
5124 <para>
5125 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5126 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon <quote>fair use.</quote> Here's his reply:
5127 </para>
5128 <blockquote>
5129 <para>
5130 The <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5131 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5132 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5133 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was <quote>clearly
5134 fair use</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5135 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5136 </para>
5137 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
5138 <listitem><para>
5139 <!-- 1. -->
5140 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5141 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5142 <quote>visual cue sheet</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5143 shot in the film. They take a dim view of <quote>fair use,</quote> and a claim of
5144 <quote>fair use</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5145 </para></listitem>
5146 <listitem>
5147 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5148 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George</primary></indexterm>
5149 <para>
5150 <!-- 2. -->
5151 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5152 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5153 tracking down and stopping unlicensed <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> usage, just as George
5154 Lucas had a very high profile litigating <citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5155 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5156 license to four seconds of <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5157 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5158 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5159 principle.
5160 </para></listitem>
5161 <listitem><para>
5162 <!-- 3. -->
5163 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5164 School &hellip; who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5165 that Fox would <quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5166 life,</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5167 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5168 pockets, me or them.
5169 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5170 </para></listitem>
5171 <listitem><para>
5172 <!-- 4. -->
5173 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5174 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5175 money.
5176 </para></listitem>
5177 </orderedlist>
5178 </blockquote>
5179 <para>
5180 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5181 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5182 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5183 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5184 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5185 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5186 </para>
5187 <para>
5188 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5189 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5190 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5191 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5192 not.
5193 </para>
5194 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5195 </chapter>
5196 <chapter label="8" id="transformers">
5197 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers</title>
5198 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul</primary></indexterm>
5199 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5200 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary></indexterm>
5201 <para>
5202 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5203 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5204 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5205 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5206 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5207 anticipation of the power of networks.
5208 </para>
5209 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on</secondary></indexterm>
5210 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in</primary></indexterm>
5211 <para>
5212 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5213 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology&mdash;not to distribute
5214 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5215 difficult. In 1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5216 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5217 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5218 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5219 important to his career.
5220 </para>
5221 <para>
5222 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5223 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5224 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5225 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5226 </para>
5227 <para>
5228 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5229 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5230 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5231 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5232 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5233 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5234 </para>
5235 <para>
5236 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. <quote>Our
5237 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5238 Eastwood's films,</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5239 arose. <quote>No one had ever really done this before,</quote> Alben explained. <quote>No
5240 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5241 actor's career.</quote>
5242 </para>
5243 <para>
5244 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5245 Slade asked, <quote>Well, what will it take?</quote>
5246 </para>
5247 <para>
5248 Alben replied, <quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5249 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5250 else that we want to use in these film clips.</quote> Slade said, <quote>Great! Go
5251 for it.</quote><footnote>
5252 <para>
5253 <!-- f1 -->
5254 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5255 publicity&mdash;rights an artist has to control the commercial
5256 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden <quote>Rip, Mix,
5257 Burn</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5258 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of</secondary></indexterm>
5259 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5260 </para></footnote>
5261 </para>
5262 <para>
5263 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5264 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5265 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5266 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5267 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5268 </para>
5269 <para>
5270 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5271 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5272 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5273 </para>
5274 <blockquote>
5275 <para>
5276 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5277 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include&mdash;of
5278 course we were going to use the <quote>Make my day</quote> clip from <citetitle>Dirty
5279 Harry</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5280 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5281 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5282 </para>
5283 <para>
5284 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5285 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5286 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5287 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5288 rate at the time was about $600. So we had to identify the
5289 people&mdash;some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5290 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5291 glass&mdash;is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5292 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5293 started calling people.
5294 </para>
5295 </blockquote>
5296 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald</primary></indexterm>
5297 <para>
5298 Some actors were glad to help&mdash;Donald Sutherland, for example,
5299 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5300 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5301 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5302 know, $1,200?</quote> And they would say, <quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5303 to get $1,200.</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5304 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5305 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5306 career.
5307 </para>
5308 <para>
5309 It was one <emphasis>year</emphasis> later&mdash;<quote>and even then we
5310 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.</quote>
5311 </para>
5312 <para>
5313 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5314 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5315 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5316 </para>
5317 <blockquote>
5318 <para>
5319 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5320 hands and said, <quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5321 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5322 actors.</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5323 constituent parts and said, <quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5324 directors, &hellip; this many musicians,</quote> and we just went at it very
5325 systematically and cleared the rights.
5326 </para>
5327 </blockquote>
5328 <para>
5329
5330 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5331 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5332 loved it, and it sold very well.
5333 </para>
5334 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter</primary></indexterm>
5335 <para>
5336 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5337 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5338 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, <quote>There is
5339 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5340 at all.</quote><footnote><para>
5341 <!-- f2 -->
5342 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, <citetitle>Seven
5343 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition</citetitle>, available at
5344 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #22</ulink>.
5345 </para></footnote>
5346 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5347 has to be made?
5348 </para>
5349 <para>
5350 For, as he acknowledged, <quote>very few &hellip; have the time and resources,
5351 and the will to do this,</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5352 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5353 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5354 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5355 </para>
5356 <blockquote>
5357 <para>
5358 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5359 he or she gets paid very well. &hellip; And then when 30 seconds of
5360 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5361 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person &hellip; should be
5362 compensated for that.
5363 </para>
5364 </blockquote>
5365 <para>
5366 Or at least, is this <emphasis>how</emphasis> the artist should be
5367 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5368 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5369 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5370 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5371 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5372 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5373 made to be more clean?
5374 </para>
5375 <blockquote>
5376 <para>
5377 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5378 mechanism&mdash;where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5379 subject to estranged former spouses&mdash;you'd see a lot more of this
5380 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5381 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5382 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5383 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5384 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5385 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5386 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5387 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5388 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5389 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5390 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, <quote>Oh, I
5391 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5392 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5393 money,</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5394 </para>
5395 </blockquote>
5396 <para>
5397 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5398 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5399 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5400 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5401 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5402 </para>
5403 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'/>
5404 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'/>
5405 <para>
5406 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5407 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5408 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5409 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5410 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5411 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5412 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5413 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5414 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5415 <quote>Does this still make sense?</quote>
5416 </para>
5417 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'/>
5418 <para>
5419 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5420 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5421 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5422 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5423
5424 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5425 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5426 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5427 </para>
5428 <para>
5429 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5430 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode.
5431 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5432 judges loved every minute of it.
5433 </para>
5434 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David</primary></indexterm>
5435 <para>
5436 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5437 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5438 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5439 room of over 250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5440 began his talk with a question: <quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5441 were just violated in this room?</quote>
5442 </para>
5443 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David</primary></indexterm>
5444 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5445 <para>
5446 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5447 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5448 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5449 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5450 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle
5451 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5452 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5453 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5454 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5455 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5456 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5457 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5458 couldn't easily do them legally.
5459 </para>
5460 <para>
5461 We live in a <quote>cut and paste</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5462 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5463 and paste architecture of the Internet created&mdash;in a second you can
5464 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5465 planted in your presentation.
5466 </para>
5467 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos</primary></indexterm>
5468 <para>
5469 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5470 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5471 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5472 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5473 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5474 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5475 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5476 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5477 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5478 </para>
5479 <para>
5480 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5481 wanted to be <quote>legal,</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5482 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5483 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5484 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5485 </para>
5486 <para>
5487 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5488 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5489 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5490 necessarily requiring that the <quote>free</quote> use be free as in <quote>free beer.</quote>
5491 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5492 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5493 along: a rule, for example, that says <quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5494 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5495 will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5496 copyright owner.</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5497 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5498 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5499 registers the work.
5500 </para>
5501 <para>
5502 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5503 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5504 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5505 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5506 </para>
5507 <para>
5508 <emphasis role='strong'>In February 2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5509 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5510 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live</citetitle> and
5511 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5512 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5513 would work together to form a <quote>unique filmmaking pact.</quote> Under the
5514 agreement, DreamWorks <quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5515 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and&mdash;with the use
5516 of stateof-the-art digital technology&mdash;insert Myers and other
5517 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5518 entertainment.</quote>
5519 </para>
5520 <para>
5521 The announcement called this <quote>film sampling.</quote> As Myers explained,
5522 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5523 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5524 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5525 to take that same concept and apply it to film.</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5526 quoted as saying, <quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5527 new audiences, it is Mike.</quote>
5528 </para>
5529 <para>
5530 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5531 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5532 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5533 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5534 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5535 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5536 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5537 privilege reserved for the funny and famous&mdash;and presumably rich.
5538 </para>
5539 <para>
5540 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5541 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of <quote>fair use.</quote>
5542 Much of <quote>sampling</quote> should be considered <quote>fair use.</quote> But few would
5543 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5544 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5545 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5546 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5547 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5548 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5549 process is a process of paying lawyers&mdash;again a privilege, or perhaps a
5550 curse, reserved for the few.
5551 </para>
5552 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5553 </chapter>
5554 <chapter label="9" id="collectors">
5555 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors</title>
5556 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
5557 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
5558 <para>
5559 <emphasis role='strong'>In April 1996</emphasis>, millions of
5560 <quote>bots</quote>&mdash;computer codes designed to
5561 <quote>spider,</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5562 content&mdash;began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5563 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5564 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5565 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5566 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5567 Internet and stored them.
5568 </para>
5569 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5570 <para>
5571 By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5572 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5573 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5574 the world. Using a technology called <quote>the Way Back Machine,</quote> you could
5575 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to 1996, as
5576 well as when those pages changed.
5577 </para>
5578 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Orwell, George</primary></indexterm>
5579 <para>
5580 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5581 appreciated. In the dystopia described in <citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5582 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5583 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5584 reports.
5585 </para>
5586 <para>
5587 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5588 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5589 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5590 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5591 </para>
5592 <para>
5593 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5594 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5595 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5596 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5597 library&mdash;constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5598 </para>
5599 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'/>
5600 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5601 <para>
5602 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5603 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5604 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5605 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5606 what others might prefer you forget.<footnote><para>
5607 <!-- f1 -->
5608 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
5609 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases</primary></indexterm>
5610 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5611 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003,
5612 press release stated, <quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.</quote> That was
5613 later changed, without notice, to <quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5614 Have Ended.</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003.
5615 </para></footnote>
5616 </para>
5617 <indexterm><primary>history, records of</primary></indexterm>
5618 <para>
5619 <emphasis role='strong'>We take it</emphasis> for granted that we can
5620 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5621 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5622 race riots in Watts in 1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in 1963,
5623 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5624 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5625 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
5626 remember&mdash;not just what it is convenient to remember, but
5627 remember something close to the truth.
5628 </para>
5629 <para>
5630 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5631 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We <emphasis>all</emphasis>
5632 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
5633 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
5634 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
5635 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
5636 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
5637 </para>
5638 <para>
5639 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5640 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5641 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5642 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5643 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5644 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5645 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5646 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet&mdash;the
5647 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5648 </para>
5649 <para>
5650 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5651 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5652 researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5653 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5654 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5655 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5656 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10
5657 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5658 </para>
5659 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
5660 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive</primary></indexterm>
5661 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University</primary></indexterm>
5662 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5663 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>archival function of</secondary></indexterm>
5664 <para>
5665 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
5666 human history. At the end of 2002, it held <quote>two hundred and thirty
5667 terabytes of material</quote>&mdash;and was <quote>ten times larger than the
5668 Library of Congress.</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
5669 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
5670 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
5671 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
5672 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
5673 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
5674 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University&mdash;thanks to a
5675 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
5676 is available to scholars for a very low fee. <quote>But other than that,
5677 [television] is almost unavailable,</quote> Kahle told me. <quote>If you were
5678 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
5679 just a graduate student?</quote> As Kahle put it,
5680 </para>
5681 <blockquote>
5682 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan</primary></indexterm>
5683 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes</primary></indexterm>
5684 <para>
5685 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
5686 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
5687 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
5688 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
5689 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
5690
5691 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
5692 <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode that came out after it &hellip; it would be almost
5693 impossible. &hellip; Those materials are almost unfindable. &hellip;
5694 </para>
5695 </blockquote>
5696 <indexterm><primary>newspapers</primary><secondary>archives of</secondary></indexterm>
5697 <para>
5698 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
5699 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
5700 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
5701 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
5702 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
5703 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
5704 </para>
5705 <para>
5706 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
5707 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
5708 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
5709 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
5710 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
5711 work.
5712 </para>
5713 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
5714 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
5715 <para>
5716 These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library
5717 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
5718 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
5719 borrow back the deposits&mdash;for an unlimited time at no cost. In
5720 1915 alone, there were more than 5,475 films deposited and <quote>borrowed
5721 back.</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
5722 held by any library. The copy exists&mdash;if it exists at
5723 all&mdash;in the library archive of the film company.<footnote><para>
5724 <!-- f2 -->
5725 Doug Herrick, <quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
5726 the Library of Congress,</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly</citetitle> 13 nos. 2&ndash;3
5727 (1980): 5; Anthony Slide, <citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
5728 Preservation in the United States</citetitle> ( Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland &amp;
5729 Co., 1992), 36.
5730 </para></footnote>
5731 </para>
5732 <para>
5733 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
5734 were originally not copyrighted&mdash;there was no way to capture the
5735 broadcasts, so there was no fear of <quote>theft.</quote> But as technology enabled
5736 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
5737 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
5738 <quote>copyrighted.</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
5739 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
5740 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
5741 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
5742 </para>
5743 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
5744 <para>
5745 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and
5746 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
5747 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
5748 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
5749 September 11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
5750 stations from around the world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made
5751 their coverage during the week of September 11 available free on-line.
5752 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
5753 events of that day.
5754 </para>
5755 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive</primary></indexterm>
5756 <indexterm><primary>archive.org</primary><seealso>Internet Archive</seealso></indexterm>
5757 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
5758 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive</primary></indexterm>
5759 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film</primary></indexterm>
5760 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films</primary></indexterm>
5761 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick</primary></indexterm>
5762 <para>
5763 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
5764 archive of film includes close to 45,000 <quote>ephemeral films</quote> (meaning
5765 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
5766 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
5767 1,300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
5768 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
5769 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
5770 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
5771 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
5772 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
5773 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
5774 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
5775 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the <quote>Duck and Cover</quote> film
5776 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
5777 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
5778 few minutes&mdash;for free.
5779 </para>
5780 <para>
5781 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
5782 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
5783 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
5784 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
5785 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
5786 to find them.
5787 </para>
5788 <para>
5789 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
5790 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
5791 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
5792 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
5793 property, but during a second life that all creative property
5794 has&mdash;a noncommercial life.
5795 </para>
5796 <para>
5797 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
5798 of creative property goes through different <quote>lives.</quote> In its first
5799 life, if the
5800
5801 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
5802 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
5803 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
5804 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
5805 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
5806 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
5807 </para>
5808 <para>
5809 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
5810 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
5811 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
5812 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
5813 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
5814 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
5815 longer sold.
5816 </para>
5817 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
5818 <para>
5819 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
5820 very quickly (the average today is after about a year<footnote><para>
5821 <!-- f3 -->
5822 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
5823 Dave Barns, <quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
5824 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>,
5825 5 September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927
5826 and 1946, only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese,
5827 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,</quote> <citetitle>Boston
5828 College Law Review</citetitle> 44 (2003): 593 n. 51.
5829 </para></footnote>). After
5830 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
5831 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
5832 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
5833 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
5834 important to the spread and stability of culture.
5835 </para>
5836 <para>
5837 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
5838 creative property does not hold true with the most important
5839 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
5840 centuries. For these&mdash;television, movies, music, radio, the
5841 Internet&mdash;there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
5842 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes &amp;
5843 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
5844 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
5845 disappears.
5846 </para>
5847 <para>
5848 <emphasis role='strong'>For most of</emphasis> the twentieth century,
5849 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
5850 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
5851 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
5852 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
5853 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
5854 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
5855 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
5856 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
5857 little practical effect.
5858 </para>
5859 <para>
5860 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
5861 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
5862 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
5863 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
5864 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
5865 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
5866 </para>
5867 <para>
5868 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
5869 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
5870 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
5871 Kahle describes,
5872 </para>
5873 <blockquote>
5874 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>total number of</secondary></indexterm>
5875 <para>
5876 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
5877 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
5878 movies, &hellip; and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
5879 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
5880 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
5881 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
5882 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
5883 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
5884 &hellip; thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
5885 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
5886 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
5887 </para>
5888 </blockquote>
5889 <para>
5890 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
5891 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
5892 libraries or archives could be. <emphasis>When</emphasis> the
5893 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
5894 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
5895 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
5896 will draw upon it to understand it;
5897 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
5898 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
5899 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
5900 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past&mdash;a
5901 future <emphasis>for</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
5902 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
5903 </para>
5904 <para>
5905 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
5906 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
5907 call these <quote>archives,</quote> as warm as the idea of a <quote>library</quote> might seem,
5908 the <quote>content</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
5909 someone's <quote>property.</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
5910 that Kahle and others would exercise.
5911 </para>
5912 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'/>
5913 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
5914 </chapter>
5915 <chapter label="10" id="property-i">
5916 <title>CHAPTER TEN: <quote>Property</quote></title>
5917 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon</primary></indexterm>
5918 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
5919 <para>
5920 <emphasis role='strong'>Jack Valenti</emphasis> has been the president
5921 of the Motion Picture Association of America since 1966. He first came
5922 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
5923 administration&mdash;literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
5924 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
5925 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
5926 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
5927 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
5928 </para>
5929 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
5930 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment</primary></indexterm>
5931 <indexterm><primary>MGM</primary></indexterm>
5932 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures</primary></indexterm>
5933 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox</primary></indexterm>
5934 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures</primary></indexterm>
5935 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
5936 <para>
5937 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
5938 Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal
5939 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
5940 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
5941 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
5942 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
5943 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
5944 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
5945 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
5946 Warner Brothers.
5947 </para>
5948 <para>
5949 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
5950 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
5951 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
5952 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
5953 political skill of a Southerner&mdash;the ability to appear simple and
5954 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
5955 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
5956 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
5957 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
5958 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
5959 Washingtonian way.
5960 </para>
5961 <para>
5962 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
5963 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
5964 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
5965 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
5966 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
5967 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
5968 redefine the meaning of <quote>creative property.</quote>
5969 </para>
5970 <para>
5971 In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
5972 perfectly:
5973 </para>
5974 <blockquote>
5975 <para>
5976 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
5977 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
5978 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
5979 theme which animates this entire debate: <emphasis>Creative property
5980 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
5981 other property owners in the nation</emphasis>. That is the issue.
5982 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
5983 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.<footnote><para>
5984 <!-- f1 -->
5985 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R.
5986 4794, H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the
5987 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
5988 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
5989 Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack
5990 Valenti).
5991 </para></footnote>
5992 </para>
5993 </blockquote>
5994 <para>
5995 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
5996 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
5997 <quote>central theme</quote> to which <quote>reasonable men and women</quote> will return is
5998 this:
5999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6000 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6001 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.</quote>
6002 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6003 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6004 </para>
6005 <para>
6006 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6007 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6008 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6009 extreme a claim made by <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> who is serious in
6010 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6011 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6012 it comes to the nature and scope of <quote>creative property.</quote> His views
6013 have <emphasis>no</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6014 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6015 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6016 </para>
6017 <para>
6018 While <quote>creative property</quote> is certainly <quote>property</quote> in a nerdy and
6019 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,<footnote><para>
6020 <!-- f2 -->
6021 Lawyers speak of <quote>property</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6022 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6023 object. Thus, my <quote>property right</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6024 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For
6025 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of <quote>property</quote> to
6026 <quote>lawyer talk,</quote> see Bruce Ackerman, <citetitle>Private Property and the
6027 Constitution</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 26&ndash;27.
6028 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6029 <quote>creative property owners</quote> have been <quote>accorded the same rights and
6030 protection resident in all other property owners.</quote> Indeed, if creative
6031 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6032 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6033 in our tradition.
6034 </para>
6035 <para>
6036 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6037 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6038 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6039 overturned in 1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6040 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6041 culture would develop.
6042 </para>
6043 <para>
6044 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6045 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6046 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6047 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6048 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6049 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6050 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6051 the same would be to
6052
6053 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6054 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6055 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6056 perfect control.
6057 </para>
6058 <para>
6059 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6060 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6061 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6062 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6063 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6064 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6065 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6066 </para>
6067 <para>
6068 <emphasis role='strong'>To get</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6069 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6070 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6071 </para>
6072 <para>
6073 The framers of our Constitution loved <quote>property.</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6074 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6075 important requirement. If the government takes your property&mdash;if
6076 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6077 farm&mdash;it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's <quote>Takings
6078 Clause,</quote> to pay you <quote>just compensation</quote> for that taking. The
6079 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6080 sacred. It cannot <emphasis>ever</emphasis> be taken from the property
6081 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6082 </para>
6083 <para>
6084 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6085 Valenti calls <quote>creative property.</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6086 power to create <quote>creative property,</quote> the Constitution
6087 <emphasis>requires</emphasis> that after a <quote>limited time,</quote> Congress
6088 take back the rights that it has granted and set the <quote>creative
6089 property</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6090 the expiration of a copyright term <quote>takes</quote> your copyright and turns it
6091 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6092 pay <quote>just compensation</quote> for this <quote>taking.</quote> Instead, the same
6093 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6094 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6095 requires that you lose your <quote>creative property</quote> right without any
6096 compensation at all.
6097 </para>
6098 <para>
6099 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6100 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6101 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6102 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6103 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6104 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6105 itself.
6106 </para>
6107 <para>
6108 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6109 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6110 The Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6111 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6112 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6113 president (as it did in 1800). The framers were no doubt
6114 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6115 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6116 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6117 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6118 </para>
6119 <para>
6120 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6121 least try to understand <emphasis>why</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6122 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6123 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6124 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6125 domain?
6126 </para>
6127 <para>
6128 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6129 history of these <quote>creative property</quote> rights, and the control that they
6130 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6131 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6132 should be at the core of this war: Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis>
6133 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6134 <emphasis>whether</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6135 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6136 ought to be. Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6137 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6138 also control how culture develops.
6139 </para>
6140 <para>
6141
6142 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6143 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6144 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6145 than the narrow language of the law allows. In <citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6146 Cyberspace</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6147 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6148 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6149 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6150 </para>
6151 <figure id="fig-1331">
6152 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.</title>
6153 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6154 </figure>
6155 <para>
6156 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6157 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6158 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6159 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6160 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6161 be regulated&mdash; either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6162 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6163 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6164 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6165 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6166 Web, you can be punished
6167 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6168 with a $150,000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6169 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6170 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6171 </para>
6172 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6173 <para>
6174 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6175 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6176 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6177 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6178 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6179 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6180 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6181 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6182 the source of the enforcement.
6183 </para>
6184 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6185 <para>
6186 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6187 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6188 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6189 norms&mdash;it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6190 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6191 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6192 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6193 individual or group might behave.
6194 </para>
6195 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6196 <para>
6197 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6198 <quote>architecture</quote>&mdash;the physical world as one finds it&mdash;is a
6199 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6200 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6201 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6202 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6203 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6204 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6205 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6206 theft, but by nature, by <quote>architecture.</quote> If a 500-pound boulder
6207 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6208 constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6209 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6210 </para>
6211 <para>
6212
6213 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6214 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6215 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6216 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6217 undermined by another.
6218 </para>
6219 <para>
6220 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6221 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6222 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6223 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6224 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6225 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6226 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6227 </para>
6228 <indexterm id="idxdrivespeed" class='startofrange'><primary>driving speed, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6229 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6230 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6231 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6232 <para>
6233 So, for example, consider the <quote>freedom</quote> to drive a car at a high
6234 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6235 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6236 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6237 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6238 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6239 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6240 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6241 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6242 the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own
6243 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6244 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6245 </para>
6246 <para>
6247 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6248 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6249 special role in affecting the three.<footnote><para>
6250 <!-- f3 -->
6251 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6252 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6253 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6254 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6255 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Code: And
6256 Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90&ndash;95;
6257 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>The New Chicago School,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies</citetitle>,
6258 June 1998.
6259 </para></footnote>
6260 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6261 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6262 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6263 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6264 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6265 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6266 used to require that other laws be more
6267 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6268 strict&mdash;a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6269 limit, for example&mdash;so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6270 driving.
6271 </para>
6272 <indexterm startref="idxdrivespeed" class='endofrange'/>
6273
6274 <figure id="fig-1361">
6275 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.</title>
6276 <graphic fileref="images/1361.png"></graphic>
6277 </figure>
6278 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6279 <para>
6280 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6281 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6282 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6283 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6284 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6285 another.<footnote>
6286 <para>
6287 <!-- f4 -->
6288 Some people object to this way of talking about <quote>liberty.</quote> They object
6289 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6290 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6291 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6292 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6293 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6294 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6295 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6296 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6297 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6298 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6299 of liberty. As I argued in <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, we come from a
6300 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6301 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6302 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6303 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6304 <citetitle>On Liberty</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6305 1978), 19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6306 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons, <quote>The
6307 Right to Work,</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6308 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays</citetitle> (London:
6309 Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6310 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6311 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6312 places easier; 42 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
6313 12101 (2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6314 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6315 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6316 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6317 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (1990)</primary></indexterm>
6318 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.</primary></indexterm>
6319 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6320 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6321 </para></footnote>
6322 </para>
6323 <section id="hollywood">
6324 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right</title>
6325 <para>
6326 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6327 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6328 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6329 rallying makes sense.
6330 </para>
6331 <para>
6332 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6333 Internet:
6334 </para>
6335 <figure id="fig-1371">
6336 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6337 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6338 </figure>
6339 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6340 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6341 <para>
6342 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6343 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6344 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6345 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6346 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6347 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6348 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6349 recognize&mdash;kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6350 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6351 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6352 this form of infringement.
6353 </para>
6354 <para>
6355 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6356 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6357 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6358 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6359 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6360 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6361 </para>
6362 <para>
6363 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6364 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6365 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6366 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6367 Iraq
6368 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6369 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6370 looting that results.
6371 </para>
6372 <figure id="fig-1381">
6373 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.</title>
6374 <graphic fileref="images/1381.png"></graphic>
6375 </figure>
6376 <para>
6377 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6378 warriors. Indeed, in a <quote>White Paper</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6379 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995,
6380 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6381 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6382 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should
6383 strengthen intellectual property law, (2) businesses should adopt
6384 innovative marketing techniques, (3) technologists should push to
6385 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (4) educators should
6386 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6387 </para>
6388 <indexterm><primary>steel industry</primary></indexterm>
6389 <para>
6390 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed&mdash;if it was to
6391 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6392 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6393 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6394 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6395 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6396 life. Homeowners living in a
6397
6398 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6399 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6400 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6401 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6402 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6403 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6404 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6405 </para>
6406 <para>
6407 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6408 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6409 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6410 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6411 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6412 Brown describes it, its <quote>architecture of revenue.</quote>
6413 </para>
6414 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry</primary></indexterm>
6415 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
6416 <indexterm><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
6417 <para>
6418 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6419 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6420 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6421 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6422 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20
6423 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6424 of digital cameras.<footnote><para>
6425 <!-- f5 -->
6426 See Geoffrey Smith, <quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?</quote>
6427 BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at
6428 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #23</ulink>. For a more
6429 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6430 R. Schoenberger, <quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?</quote> Forbes.com, 6
6431 October 2003, available at
6432 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #24</ulink>.
6433 </para></footnote>
6434
6435 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6436 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6437 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6438 <emphasis>for the purpose of</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6439 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6440 weakened the <quote>stickiness</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6441 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf ), and it
6442 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6443 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6444 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6445 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6446 </para>
6447 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
6448 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
6449 <para>
6450 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6451 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6452 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6453 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6454 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6455 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6456 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6457 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, <quote>established companies
6458 have an interest in excluding future competitors.</quote><footnote><para>
6459 <!-- f6 -->
6460 Fred Warshofsky, <citetitle>The Patent Wars</citetitle> (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170&ndash;71.
6461 </para></footnote>
6462 And relative to a
6463 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6464 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6465 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6466 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6467 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6468 Brezhnev.
6469 </para>
6470 <para>
6471 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6472 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6473 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6474 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6475 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6476 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6477 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6478 opportunities for innovation and change.
6479 </para>
6480 <para>
6481 In the context of laws regulating speech&mdash;which include,
6482 obviously, copyright law&mdash;that duty is even stronger. When the
6483 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6484 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6485 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6486 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6487 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6488 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: <quote>Congress
6489 shall make no law &hellip; abridging the freedom of speech.</quote> So when
6490 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would <quote>abridge</quote> the freedom
6491 of speech, it should ask&mdash; carefully&mdash;whether such
6492 regulation is justified.
6493 </para>
6494 <para>
6495 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6496 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6497 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6498 <quote>justified.</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6499 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6500 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6501 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6502 </para>
6503 <para>
6504 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6505 </para>
6506 <indexterm id="idxddt" class='startofrange'><primary>DDT</primary></indexterm>
6507 <indexterm><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann</primary></indexterm>
6508 <para>
6509 In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss
6510 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6511 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the
6512 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6513 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6514 </para>
6515 <para>
6516 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6517 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6518 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6519 </para>
6520 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6521 <indexterm><primary>Silent Sprint (Carson)</primary></indexterm>
6522 <para>
6523 But in 1962, Rachel Carson published <citetitle>Silent Spring</citetitle>, which argued that
6524 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6525 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6526 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6527 </para>
6528 <para>
6529 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6530 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6531 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6532 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6533 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6534 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6535 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6536 </para>
6537 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James</primary></indexterm>
6538 <para>
6539 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6540 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an <quote>environmentalism</quote> for
6541 culture.<footnote><para>
6542 <!-- f7 -->
6543 See, for example, James Boyle, <quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6544 Environmentalism for the Net?</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal</citetitle> 47 (1997): 87.
6545 </para></footnote>
6546 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6547 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6548 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6549 <quote>for free.</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6550 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6551 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6552 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6553 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6554 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6555 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6556 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6557 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6558 </para>
6559 <para>
6560 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6561 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6562 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6563 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6564 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6565 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6566 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6567 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6568 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6569 </para>
6570 <para>
6571 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6572 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6573 be lost.
6574 </para>
6575 <indexterm startref="idxddt" class='endofrange'/>
6576 </section>
6577 <section id="beginnings">
6578 <title>Beginnings</title>
6579 <para>
6580 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6581 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of <quote>creative
6582 property</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6583 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6584 </para>
6585 <para>
6586 The power to establish <quote>creative property</quote> rights is granted to
6587 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6588 odd. Article I, section 8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that:
6589 </para>
6590 <para>
6591 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6592 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6593 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
6594
6595 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
6596 We can call this the <quote>Progress Clause,</quote> for notice what this clause
6597 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
6598 <quote>creative property rights.</quote> It says that Congress has the power
6599 <emphasis>to promote progress</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
6600 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
6601 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
6602 </para>
6603 <para>
6604 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
6605 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="founders"/>,
6606 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
6607 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
6608 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
6609 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
6610 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
6611 copyrights extend <quote>to Authors</quote> only.
6612 </para>
6613 <para>
6614 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
6615 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
6616 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
6617 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
6618 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
6619 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
6620 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
6621 to reinforce the power of the states&mdash;including the Senate, whose
6622 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
6623 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
6624 case, a <emphasis>structure</emphasis> built checks and balances into
6625 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
6626 concentrations of power.
6627 </para>
6628 <para>
6629 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call <quote>copyright</quote>
6630 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
6631 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
6632 <quote>copyright</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210
6633 years since they first struck its design.
6634 </para>
6635 <para>
6636 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
6637 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
6638 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
6639 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
6640 started here:
6641 </para>
6642 <figure id="fig-1441">
6643 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6644 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6645 </figure>
6646 <para>
6647 We will end here:
6648 </para>
6649 <figure id="fig-1442">
6650 <title><quote>Copyright</quote> today.</title>
6651 <graphic fileref="images/1442.png"></graphic>
6652 </figure>
6653 <para>
6654 Let me explain how.
6655 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
6656 </para>
6657 </section>
6658 <section id="lawduration">
6659 <title>Law: Duration</title>
6660 <para>
6661 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
6662 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
6663 the English had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws
6664 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
6665 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
6666 authorship.<footnote>
6667 <para>
6668 <!-- f8 -->
6669 William W. Crosskey, <citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
6670 the United States</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press, 1953), vol. 1,
6671 485&ndash;86: <quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
6672 Law of the Land,' <emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
6673 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law</emphasis></quote>
6674 (emphasis added).
6675 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.</primary></indexterm>
6676 </para></footnote>
6677 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
6678 States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
6679 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
6680 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
6681 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
6682 domain to reprint and distribute works.
6683 </para>
6684 <para>
6685 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
6686 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
6687 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
6688 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
6689 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
6690 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
6691 </para>
6692 <para>
6693 In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
6694 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
6695 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
6696 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
6697 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
6698 </para>
6699 <para>
6700 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
6701 ten years of the Republic, only 5 percent of the works were actually
6702 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
6703 in the United States both before 1790 and from 1790 through 1800, 95
6704 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
6705 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
6706 likely within fourteen years.<footnote><para>
6707 <!-- f9 -->
6708 Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790
6709 to 1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, <citetitle>A
6710 History of Book Publishing in the United States</citetitle>, vol. 1, <citetitle>The Creation
6711 of an Industry, 1630&ndash;1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000
6712 imprints recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
6713 1790 act; William J. Maher, <citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
6714 and the Copyright Law of 1790 in Historical Context</citetitle>, 7&ndash;10 (2002),
6715 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
6716 #25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
6717 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
6718 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
6719 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
6720 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
6721 Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124. </para></footnote>
6722 </para>
6723 <para>
6724 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
6725 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
6726 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
6727 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
6728 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
6729 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
6730 copyright, either.
6731 </para>
6732 <para>
6733 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
6734 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
6735 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
6736 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
6737 domain.<footnote><para>
6738 <!-- f10 -->
6739 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
6740 instance, of the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were
6741 renewed in 1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
6742 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, <quote>Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright,</quote>
6743 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright</citetitle>, vol. 1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
6744 1963), 618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
6745 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote>
6746 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 471, 498&ndash;501, and
6747 accompanying figures. </para></footnote>
6748 </para>
6749 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6750 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
6751 <para>
6752 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
6753 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
6754 out of print after one year.<footnote><para>
6755 <!-- f11 -->
6756 See Ringer, ch. 9, n. 2. </para></footnote> When that happens, the
6757 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
6758 no longer <emphasis>effectively</emphasis> controlled by
6759 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
6760 is to sell the books as used books; that use&mdash;because it does not
6761 involve publication&mdash;is effectively free.
6762 </para>
6763 <para>
6764 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
6765 changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28
6766 years to a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
6767 from 14 years to 28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
6768 the term increased once again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal
6769 term of 14 years to 28 years, setting a maximum term of 56 years.
6770 </para>
6771 <para>
6772 Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
6773 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
6774 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
6775 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
6776 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
6777 In 1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
6778 And in 1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
6779 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
6780 </para>
6781 <para>
6782 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
6783 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
6784 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
6785 years, or 70 percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years
6786
6787 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
6788 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
6789 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
6790 of the expiration of a copyright term.
6791 </para>
6792 <para>
6793 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
6794 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
6795 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
6796 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
6797 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
6798 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
6799 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
6800 value.
6801 </para>
6802 <para>
6803 The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For
6804 all works created after 1978, there was only one copyright term&mdash;the
6805 maximum term. For <quote>natural</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
6806 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992,
6807 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
6808 before 1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
6809 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
6810 was ninety-five years.
6811 </para>
6812 <para>
6813 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
6814 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
6815 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
6816 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
6817 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
6818 that terms be <quote>limited,</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
6819 them.
6820 </para>
6821 <para>
6822 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
6823 dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to
6824 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
6825 in 1973 was just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
6826 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
6827 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95
6828 years.<footnote><para>
6829 <!-- f12 -->
6830 These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the
6831 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
6832 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
6833 Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote> loc. cit.
6834 </para></footnote>
6835 </para>
6836 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
6837 </section>
6838 <section id="lawscope">
6839 <title>Law: Scope</title>
6840 <para>
6841 The <quote>scope</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
6842 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
6843 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
6844 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
6845 </para>
6846 <para>
6847 In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only <quote>maps,
6848 charts, and books.</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
6849 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
6850 the author the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> copyrighted works. That
6851 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
6852 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
6853 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
6854 did not extend to what lawyers call <quote>derivative works.</quote> It would not,
6855 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
6856 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
6857 (such as a drama based on a published book).
6858 </para>
6859 <para>
6860 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
6861 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
6862 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
6863 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
6864 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
6865 work not only the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> the work, but also the
6866 exclusive right of control over any <quote>copies</quote> of that work. And most
6867 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
6868 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
6869 <quote>derivative work</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
6870 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
6871 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
6872 on the initial creative work.
6873 </para>
6874 <para>
6875 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
6876 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
6877 complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition
6878 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
6879 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
6880 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
6881 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
6882 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
6883 famous &copy; or the word <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>. And for most
6884 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
6885 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
6886 secured.
6887 </para>
6888 <para>
6889 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
6890 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
6891 in the first ten years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible
6892 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
6893 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
6894 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
6895 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
6896 copyrighted&mdash;that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
6897 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
6898 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
6899 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
6900 original author.
6901 </para>
6902 <para>
6903 All of these <quote>formalities</quote> were abolished in the American system when
6904 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
6905 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
6906 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
6907 a &copy;; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
6908 copy available for others to copy.
6909 </para>
6910 <para>
6911 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
6912 differences.
6913 </para>
6914 <para>
6915 If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who
6916 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
6917 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
6918 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
6919 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were
6920 174 publishers in the United States.<footnote><para>
6921 <!-- f13 -->
6922 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, <quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
6923 Creation of American Literature,</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
6924 International Law and Politics</citetitle> 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
6925 Federal Copyright Records, 1790&ndash;1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987).
6926
6927 </para></footnote>
6928 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
6929 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
6930 the United States&mdash;publishers.
6931 </para>
6932 <para>
6933 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
6934 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
6935 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
6936 was totally unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and made
6937 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
6938 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
6939 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
6940 were restrained.
6941 </para>
6942 <para>
6943 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
6944 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
6945 every note to your spouse, every doodle, <emphasis>every</emphasis>
6946 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form&mdash;all of this is
6947 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
6948 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
6949 protect it.
6950 </para>
6951 <para>
6952 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
6953 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
6954 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
6955 </para>
6956 <para>
6957 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
6958 control
6959 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
6960 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of <quote>derivative
6961 rights.</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
6962 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
6963 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
6964 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
6965 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
6966 exclusive
6967 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
6968 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
6969 </para>
6970 <para>
6971 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
6972 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
6973 expansion
6974 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
6975 copyright.
6976 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
6977 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
6978 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
6979 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
6980 </para>
6981 <para>
6982 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
6983 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
6984 within a free culture&mdash;at least, it's astonishing when you
6985 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
6986 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
6987 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
6988 <emphasis>that</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
6989 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
6990 all&mdash;they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
6991 not protect derivative rights at all.<footnote><para>
6992 <!-- f14 -->
6993 Jonathan Zittrain, <quote>The Copyright Cage,</quote> <citetitle>Legal
6994 Affairs</citetitle>, July/August 2003, available at
6995 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #26</ulink>.
6996 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
6997 </para></footnote>
6998 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
6999 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7000 the wrong of direct piracy.
7001 </para>
7002 <para>
7003 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7004 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7005 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7006 of my book.<footnote><para>
7007 <!-- f15 -->
7008 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7009 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7010 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere <quote>copies</quote> and
7011 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld, <quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7012 Copyright's Constitutionality,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7013 Journal</citetitle> 112 (2002): 1&ndash;60 (see especially
7014 pp. 53&ndash;59).
7015 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb</primary></indexterm>
7016 </para></footnote>
7017 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7018 </para>
7019 <para>
7020 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7021 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7022 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7023 called <quote>Mickey Mouse,</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7024 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7025 created?
7026 </para>
7027 <para>
7028 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7029 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7030 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7031 the rights originally granted.
7032 </para>
7033 </section>
7034 <section id="lawreach">
7035 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach</title>
7036 <para>
7037 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7038 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7039 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7040 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.<footnote><para>
7041 <!-- f16 -->
7042 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7043 certainly regulates more than <quote>copies</quote>&mdash;a public performance of a
7044 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7045 per se doesn't make a copy; 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7046 106(4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a <quote>copy</quote>; 17
7047 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section 112(a). But the presumption under the
7048 existing law (which regulates <quote>copies;</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7049 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7050 </para></footnote>
7051 </para>
7052 <para>
7053 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7054 <quote>Copies.</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7055 <emphasis>copy</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7056 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that <quote>creative
7057 property</quote> deserves the <quote>same rights</quote> as all other property, it is the
7058 <emphasis>obvious</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7059 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7060 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7061 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7062 copies should <emphasis>not</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7063 law. More precisely, they should not <emphasis>always</emphasis> be
7064 the trigger for copyright law.
7065 </para>
7066 <para>
7067 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7068 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7069 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7070 the law of copyright automatically applies,<footnote><para>
7071 <!-- f17 -->
7072 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7073 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7074 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7075 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7076 technology.
7077 </para></footnote>
7078 because it is clear that the
7079 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7080 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7081 </para>
7082 <para>
7083 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7084 empty circle.
7085 </para>
7086 <figure id="fig-1521">
7087 <title>All potential uses of a book.</title>
7088 <graphic fileref="images/1521.png"></graphic>
7089 </figure>
7090 <indexterm id='idxbooksusetypes' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>three types of uses of</secondary></indexterm>
7091 <para>
7092 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7093 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7094 all its potential <emphasis>uses</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7095 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7096 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7097 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7098 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7099 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7100 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7101 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7102 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7103 acts do not make a copy.
7104 </para>
7105 <figure id="fig-1531">
7106 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.</title>
7107 <graphic fileref="images/1531.png"></graphic>
7108 </figure>
7109 <para>
7110 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7111 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7112 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7113 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7114 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see first
7115 diagram on next page).
7116 </para>
7117 <para>
7118 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7119 that remain unregulated because the law considers these <quote>fair uses.</quote>
7120 </para>
7121 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7122 <figure id="fig-1541">
7123 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.</title>
7124 <graphic fileref="images/1541.png"></graphic>
7125 </figure>
7126 <para>
7127 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7128 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7129 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7130 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7131 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7132 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7133 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such <quote>fair uses</quote>
7134 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7135 </para>
7136 <figure id="fig-1542">
7137 <title>Unregulated copying considered <quote>fair uses.</quote></title>
7138 <graphic fileref="images/1542.png"></graphic>
7139 </figure>
7140 <para> </para>
7141 <figure id="fig-1551">
7142 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.</title>
7143 <graphic fileref="images/1551.png"></graphic>
7144 </figure>
7145 <para>
7146 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7147 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7148 sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that
7149 are nonetheless deemed <quote>fair</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7150 </para>
7151 <indexterm startref='idxbooksusetypes' class='endofrange'/>
7152 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7153 <para>
7154 Enter the Internet&mdash;a distributed, digital network where every use
7155 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.<footnote><para>
7156 <!-- f18 -->
7157 I don't mean <quote>nature</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7158 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7159 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7160 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7161 of copies remain.
7162 </para></footnote>
7163 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7164 digital network, the scope of category 1 changes dramatically. Uses
7165 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7166 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7167 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7168 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7169 a copy&mdash;category 1 gets sucked into category 2. And those who
7170 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7171 exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7172 shift.
7173 </para>
7174 <para>
7175 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7176 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7177 be no plausible <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>-related argument that
7178 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7179 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7180 the book once, ten times, or every
7181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7182 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7183 use&mdash;reading&mdash; could be regulated by copyright law because
7184 none of those uses produced a copy.
7185 </para>
7186 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7187 <para>
7188 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7189 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7190 only once or only once a month, then <emphasis>copyright
7191 law</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7192 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7193 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7194 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7195 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7196 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7197 copyright owner's wish.
7198 </para>
7199 <para>
7200 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7201 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7202 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7203 points also become clear:
7204 </para>
7205 <para>
7206 First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7207 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7208 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7209 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7210 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7211 part of free culture before the Internet.
7212 </para>
7213 <para>
7214 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7215 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7216 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7217 <emphasis>any</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7218 using a machine. <quote>Copy and paste</quote> and <quote>cut and paste</quote> become
7219 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7220 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7221 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7222 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7223 creative work.
7224 </para>
7225 <para>
7226 Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary
7227
7228 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7229 burden on category 3 (<quote>fair use</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7230 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7231 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7232 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7233 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7234 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7235 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7236 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7237 regulated.
7238 </para>
7239 <para>
7240 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7241 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7242 depend upon fair use&mdash;never even addressing the earlier question
7243 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7244 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7245 <emphasis>unregulated</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7246 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7247 enough.
7248 </para>
7249 <indexterm id='idxadvertising2' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
7250 <para>
7251 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7252 in the business of making <quote>trailer</quote> advertisements for movies available
7253 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7254 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7255 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7256 </para>
7257 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7258 <para>
7259 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it began
7260 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7261 previews. The idea was to expand their <quote>selling by sampling</quote>
7262 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7263 <quote>browsing.</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7264 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7265 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7266 </para>
7267 <para>
7268 In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7269 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7270 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7271 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7272 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7273 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter&mdash;he had built a
7274 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7275 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7276 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7277 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7278 <quote>fair use</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7279 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7280 their rights.
7281 </para>
7282 <para>
7283 Disney countersued&mdash;for $100 million in damages. Those damages
7284 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had <quote>willfully
7285 infringed</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7286 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7287 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7288 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7289 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7290 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $100 million.
7291 </para>
7292 <para>
7293 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7294 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7295 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7296 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7297 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7298 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7299 Disney's permission.
7300 </para>
7301 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising2' class='endofrange'/>
7302 <para>
7303 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7304 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7305 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7306 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7307 was in the marketplace, the <quote>first-sale doctrine</quote> would free the
7308 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7309 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7310 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7311 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7312 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7313 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7314 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7315 </para>
7316 <indexterm><primary>Barnes &amp; Noble</primary></indexterm>
7317 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7318 <para>
7319 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7320 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7321 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes &amp; Noble has the
7322 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7323 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7324 abuse. If Barnes &amp; Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7325 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7326 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7327 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7328 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7329 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7330 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7331 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7332 happening are quite slight.
7333 </para>
7334 <para>
7335 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7336 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7337 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7338 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7339 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7340 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7341 </para>
7342 </section>
7343 <section id="lawforce">
7344 <title>Architecture and Law: Force</title>
7345 <para>
7346 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7347 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7348 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7349 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7350 </para>
7351 <para>
7352 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7353 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7354 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7355 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7356 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7357 your freedom.
7358 </para>
7359 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca</primary></indexterm>
7360 <indexterm id="idxmarxbrothers" class='startofrange'><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7361 <indexterm id="idxwarnerbrothers" class='startofrange'><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7362 <para>
7363 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7364 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7365 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7366 <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7367 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7368 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7369 plan.<footnote><para>
7370 <!-- f19 -->
7371 See David Lange, <quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7372 Contemporary Problems</citetitle> 44 (1981): 172&ndash;73.
7373 </para></footnote>
7374 </para>
7375 <para>
7376 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7377 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers <quote>were brothers long before
7378 you were.</quote><footnote><para>
7379 <!-- f20 -->
7380 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
7381 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and
7382 Copywrongs</citetitle>, 1&ndash;3.
7383 </para></footnote>
7384 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7385 <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7386 trying to control <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>, then the Marx
7387 Brothers would insist on control over <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>.
7388 </para>
7389 <para>
7390 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7391 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7392 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7393 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7394 </para>
7395 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7396 <para>
7397 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7398 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7399 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7400 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7401 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7402 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7403 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7404 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7405 </para>
7406 <indexterm startref="idxwarnerbrothers" class='endofrange'/>
7407 <indexterm startref="idxmarxbrothers" class='endofrange'/>
7408
7409 <indexterm id="idxadobeebookreader" class='startofrange'><primary>Adobe eBook Reader</primary></indexterm>
7410 <para>
7411 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7412 </para>
7413 <para>
7414 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7415 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7416 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7417 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7418 technology.
7419 </para>
7420 <para>
7421 On the next page is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook
7422 Reader.
7423 </para>
7424 <para>
7425 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7426 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7427 public domain: <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, for example, is in
7428 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7429 public domain: My own book <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
7430 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7431 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7432 copy of
7433 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7434 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7435 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
7436 </para>
7437 <figure id="fig-1611">
7438 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader</title>
7439 <graphic fileref="images/1611.png"></graphic>
7440 </figure>
7441 <para>
7442 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7443 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7444 </para>
7445 <figure id="fig-1612">
7446 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.</title>
7447 <graphic fileref="images/1612.png"></graphic>
7448 </figure>
7449 <para>
7450 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7451 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
7452 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
7453 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
7454 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
7455 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>
7456 read aloud through the computer.
7457 </para>
7458 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle</primary></indexterm>
7459 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics</citetitle>, (Aristotle)</primary></indexterm>
7460 <para>
7461 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7462 translation): Aristotle's <citetitle>Politics</citetitle>.
7463 </para>
7464 <figure id="fig-1621">
7465 <title>E-book of Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote></title>
7466 <graphic fileref="images/1621.png"></graphic>
7467 </figure>
7468 <para>
7469 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7470 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
7471 the book.
7472 </para>
7473 <figure id="fig-1622">
7474 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote>.</title>
7475 <graphic fileref="images/1622.png"></graphic>
7476 </figure>
7477 <para>
7478 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
7479 original e-book version of my last book, <citetitle>The Future of
7480 Ideas</citetitle>:
7481 </para>
7482 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
7483 <figure id="fig-1631">
7484 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>The Future of Ideas</quote>.</title>
7485 <graphic fileref="images/1631.png"></graphic>
7486 </figure>
7487 <para>
7488 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
7489 </para>
7490 <para>
7491 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
7492 <quote>permissions</quote>&mdash; as if the publisher has the power to control how
7493 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
7494 certainly does have the power&mdash;up to the limits of the copyright
7495 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
7496 power.<footnote><para>
7497 <!-- f21 -->
7498 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
7499 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
7500 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
7501 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
7502 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
7503 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
7504 subsequently acquired the book.
7505 </para></footnote>
7506 When my e-book of <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> says I have the
7507 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
7508 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
7509 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
7510 control that the law would enable.
7511 </para>
7512 <para>
7513 The control comes instead from the code&mdash;from the technology
7514 within which the e-book <quote>lives.</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
7515 permissions, they are not the sort of <quote>permissions</quote> that most of us
7516 deal with. When a teenager gets <quote>permission</quote> to stay out till
7517 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
7518 till 2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
7519 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
7520 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
7521 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
7522 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
7523 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
7524 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
7525 aloud&mdash;it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
7526 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
7527 won't read aloud.
7528 </para>
7529 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7530 <para>
7531 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
7532 These are <emphasis>controls</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
7533 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
7534 you tried to type <quote>Warner Brothers,</quote> erased <quote>Brothers</quote> from the
7535 sentence.
7536 </para>
7537 <para>
7538 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
7539 <emphasis>law</emphasis> as copyright <emphasis>code</emphasis>. The
7540 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
7541 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
7542 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
7543 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
7544 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
7545 </para>
7546 <para>
7547 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
7548 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
7549 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
7550 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
7551 to defeat these protections as well?
7552 </para>
7553 <para>
7554 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
7555 eBook Reader.
7556 </para>
7557 <indexterm><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)</primary></indexterm>
7558 <para>
7559 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
7560 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
7561 on the Adobe site was a copy of <citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
7562 Wonderland</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
7563 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
7564 following report:
7565 </para>
7566 <figure id="fig-1641">
7567 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>Alice's Adventures in
7568 Wonderland</quote>.</title>
7569 <graphic fileref="images/1641.png"></graphic>
7570 </figure>
7571 <beginpage pagenum="164"/>
7572 <para>
7573 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
7574 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
7575 <quote>permissions</quote> indicated, not allowed to <quote>read aloud</quote>!
7576 </para>
7577 <para>
7578 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
7579 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
7580 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
7581 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
7582 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
7583 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
7584 </para>
7585 <para>
7586 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
7587 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
7588 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
7589 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
7590 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
7591 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
7592 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
7593 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
7594 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
7595 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
7596 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
7597 </para>
7598 <para>
7599 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
7600 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
7601 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
7602 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
7603 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
7604 often crazy.
7605 </para>
7606 <indexterm startref="idxadobeebookreader" class='endofrange'/>
7607 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'/>
7608 <para>
7609 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
7610 story of mine that makes the same point.
7611 </para>
7612 <indexterm id="idxaibo1" class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7613 <indexterm id="idxroboticdog1" class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7614 <indexterm id="idxsonyaibo1" class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
7615 <para>
7616 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named <quote>Aibo.</quote> The Aibo
7617 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
7618 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
7619 </para>
7620 <para>
7621 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
7622 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
7623 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
7624 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
7625 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
7626 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
7627 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
7628 </para>
7629 <para>
7630 <quote>Teach</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
7631 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
7632 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
7633 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
7634 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
7635 their computer <quote>dog</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
7636 </para>
7637 <indexterm><primary>hacks</primary></indexterm>
7638 <para>
7639 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
7640 <citetitle>hack</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
7641 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
7642 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
7643 them, <citetitle>hack</citetitle> is a much more positive
7644 term. <citetitle>Hack</citetitle> just means code that enables the
7645 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
7646 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
7647 old computer doesn't run, or <quote>drive,</quote> the printer. If you discovered
7648 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
7649 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
7650 you just bought.
7651 </para>
7652 <para>
7653 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
7654 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
7655 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
7656 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
7657 ethically.
7658 </para>
7659 <para>
7660 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
7661 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
7662 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
7663 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
7664 than Sony had built.
7665 </para>
7666 <indexterm startref="idxsonyaibo1" class='endofrange'/>
7667 <indexterm startref="idxroboticdog1" class='endofrange'/>
7668 <indexterm startref="idxaibo1" class='endofrange'/>
7669 <para>
7670 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
7671 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
7672 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
7673 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
7674 the
7675
7676 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
7677 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
7678 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
7679 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
7680 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
7681 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
7682 thought, <emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
7683 a robot dog to dance?</emphasis>
7684 </para>
7685 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>government case against</secondary></indexterm>
7686 <para>
7687 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show&mdash;
7688 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
7689 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
7690 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
7691 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
7692 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
7693 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
7694 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
7695 into being silent about something he knew very well.
7696 </para>
7697 <para>
7698 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.<footnote><para>
7699 <!-- f22 -->
7700 See Pamela Samuelson, <quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,</quote>
7701 <citetitle>Science</citetitle> 293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, <quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
7702 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect</citetitle>,
7703 January 2002; <quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
7704 DMCA,</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter</citetitle>, 11 December 2001; Bill
7705 Holland, <quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,</quote> <citetitle>Billboard</citetitle>,
7706 May 2001; Janelle Brown, <quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?</quote> Salon.com,
7707 April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, <quote>Frequently Asked
7708 Questions about <citetitle>Felten and USENIX</citetitle> v. <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> Legal Case,</quote> available at
7709 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #27</ulink>.
7710 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
7711 </para></footnote>
7712 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
7713 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
7714 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
7715 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
7716 </para>
7717 <para>
7718 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
7719 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
7720 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
7721 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
7722 <quote>this music cannot be copied,</quote> and have a computer respect that
7723 command. The technology was to be part of a <quote>trusted system</quote> of
7724 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
7725 Internet much more.
7726 </para>
7727 <para>
7728 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
7729 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
7730 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
7731 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
7732 </para>
7733 <para>
7734 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
7735 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
7736 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
7737 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
7738 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
7739 </para>
7740 <para>
7741 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
7742 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
7743 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
7744 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
7745 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
7746 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
7747 </para>
7748 <para>
7749 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
7750 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
7751 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
7752 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
7753 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
7754 constituted, succeed.
7755 </para>
7756 <indexterm id="idxaibo2" class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7757 <indexterm id="idxroboticdog2" class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7758 <indexterm id="idxsonyaibo2" class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
7759 <para>
7760 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
7761 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
7762 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
7763 wrote:
7764 </para>
7765 <blockquote>
7766 <para>
7767 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
7768 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
7769 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
7770 </para>
7771 </blockquote>
7772 <indexterm startref="idxsonyaibo2" class='endofrange'/>
7773 <indexterm startref="idxroboticdog2" class='endofrange'/>
7774 <indexterm startref="idxaibo2" class='endofrange'/>
7775 <para>
7776 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
7777 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
7778 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
7779 </para>
7780 <blockquote>
7781 <para>
7782 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
7783 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
7784 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
7785 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
7786 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (<quote>DMCA</quote>).
7787 </para>
7788 </blockquote>
7789 <para>
7790 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
7791 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
7792 spreading such information an offense.
7793 </para>
7794 <para>
7795 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
7796 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
7797 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
7798 These new technologies would be copyright protection
7799 technologies&mdash; technologies to control the replication and
7800 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
7801 <emphasis>code</emphasis> to modify the original
7802 <emphasis>code</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
7803 protection for copyright owners.
7804 </para>
7805 <para>
7806 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
7807 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
7808 <emphasis>legal code</emphasis> intended to buttress
7809 <emphasis>software code</emphasis> which itself was intended to
7810 support the <emphasis>legal code of copyright</emphasis>.
7811 </para>
7812 <para>
7813 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
7814 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
7815 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
7816 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
7817 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
7818 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
7819 have been a copyright violation.
7820 </para>
7821 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7822 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7823 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
7824 <para>
7825 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
7826 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
7827 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
7828 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
7829 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
7830 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
7831 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
7832 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
7833 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
7834 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
7835 </para>
7836 <para>
7837 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
7838 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
7839 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
7840 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
7841 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
7842 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
7843 </para>
7844 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
7845 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
7846 <para>
7847 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
7848 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
7849 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
7850 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
7851 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
7852 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka <quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers</citetitle>,</quote>
7853 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
7854 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
7855 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
7856 </para>
7857 <blockquote>
7858 <para>
7859 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
7860 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
7861 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
7862 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
7863 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
7864 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the <quote>Neighborhood</quote>
7865 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
7866 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
7867 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
7868 broadcasting has always been <quote>You are an important person just the way
7869 you are. You can make healthy decisions.</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
7870 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
7871 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
7872 important.<footnote><para>
7873 <!-- f23 -->
7874 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
7875 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
7876 455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
7877 James Lardner, <citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
7878 the VCR</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270&ndash;71.
7879 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
7880 </para></footnote>
7881 </para>
7882 </blockquote>
7883 <para>
7884 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
7885 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
7886 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
7887 the VCR responsible.
7888 </para>
7889 <para>
7890 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
7891 the DMCA.
7892 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
7893 </para>
7894 <para>
7895 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
7896 </para>
7897 <para>
7898 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
7899 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
7900 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
7901 pirating of copyrighted material&mdash;a bad end. Or they can be used
7902 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
7903 would be considered fair use&mdash;a good end.
7904 </para>
7905 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'><primary>handguns</primary></indexterm>
7906 <para>
7907 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
7908 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
7909 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
7910 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
7911 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
7912 and bad uses.
7913 </para>
7914 <figure id="fig-1711">
7915 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.</title>
7916 <graphic fileref="images/1711.png"></graphic>
7917 </figure>
7918 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
7919 <para>
7920 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
7921 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
7922 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: <emphasis>No one ever
7923 died from copyright circumvention</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
7924 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
7925 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
7926 </para>
7927 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'/>
7928 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'/>
7929 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7930 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7931 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
7932 <para>
7933 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
7934 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
7935 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
7936 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
7937 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
7938 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
7939 </para>
7940 <para>
7941 This is how <emphasis>code</emphasis> becomes
7942 <emphasis>law</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
7943 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
7944 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
7945 law&mdash;increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
7946 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
7947 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
7948 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect&mdash;at
7949 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
7950 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
7951 </para>
7952 <para>
7953 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
7954 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
7955 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
7956 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
7957 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
7958 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
7959 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
7960 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
7961 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
7962 </para>
7963 <para>
7964
7965 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
7966 For example, imagine you were part of a <citetitle>Star Trek</citetitle> fan club. You
7967 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
7968 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
7969 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
7970 simply continue it.<footnote><para>
7971 <!-- f24 -->
7972 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, <quote>Legal Fictions,
7973 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
7974 Entertainment Law Journal</citetitle> 17 (1997): 651.
7975 </para></footnote>
7976 </para>
7977 <para>
7978 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
7979 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
7980 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
7981 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
7982 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
7983 </para>
7984 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
7985 <para>
7986 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
7987 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
7988 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
7989 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
7990 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
7991 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
7992 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
7993 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
7994 </para>
7995 <para>
7996 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
7997 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
7998 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
7999 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8000 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8001 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8002 </para>
8003 </section>
8004 <section id="marketconcentration">
8005 <title>Market: Concentration</title>
8006 <para>
8007 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically&mdash;tripled in
8008 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8009 well&mdash;from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8010 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8011 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8012 find better ways
8013 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8014 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8015 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8016 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8017 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8018 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8019 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8020 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8021 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8022 control.
8023 </para>
8024 <para>
8025 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8026 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8027 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8028 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8029 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8030 </para>
8031 <para>
8032 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8033 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8034 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8035 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8036 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8037 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8038 announced in June 2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8039 live in a world where just three companies control more than percent
8040 of the media.
8041 </para>
8042 <para>
8043 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8044 nature.
8045 </para>
8046 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8047 <indexterm><primary>BMG</primary></indexterm>
8048 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
8049 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John</primary></indexterm>
8050 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8051 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8052 <para>
8053 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8054 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8055 ownership, <quote>five companies control 85 percent of our media sources.</quote><footnote><para>
8056 <!-- f25 -->
8057 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8058 Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003)
8059 (statement of Senator John McCain). </para></footnote>
8060 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8061 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 percent of the
8062 U.S. music market.<footnote><para>
8063 <!-- f26 -->
8064 Lynette Holloway, <quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8065 Slide,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 23 December 2002.
8066 </para></footnote>
8067 The <quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8068 programming to 74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.</quote><footnote><para>
8069 <!-- f27 -->
8070 Molly Ivins, <quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette</citetitle>,
8071 31 May 2003.
8072 </para></footnote>
8073 </para>
8074 <para>
8075 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8076 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8077 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8078 seventy-five stations. Today <emphasis>one</emphasis> company owns
8079 more than 1,200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8080 total number of radio owners dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most
8081 markets, the two largest broadcasters control 74 percent of that
8082 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control 90 percent of
8083 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8084 </para>
8085 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8086 <para>
8087 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8088 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8089 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8090 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8091 the United States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all
8092 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent
8093 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8094 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8095 protected&mdash; by the market.
8096 </para>
8097 <para>
8098 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8099 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8100 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8101 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8102 </para>
8103 <blockquote>
8104 <para>
8105 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8106 unmatched in its integration. They supply content&mdash;Fox movies
8107 &hellip; Fox TV shows &hellip; Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8108 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8109 advertisers&mdash;in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8110 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8111 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8112 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8113 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8114 the same function in the United States.<footnote><para>
8115 <!-- f28 -->
8116 James Fallows, <quote>The Age of Murdoch,</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly</citetitle> (September
8117 2003): 89.
8118 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8119 </para></footnote>
8120 </para>
8121 </blockquote>
8122 <para>
8123 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8124 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8125 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8126 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8127 </para>
8128 <figure id="fig-1761">
8129 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.</title>
8130 <graphic fileref="images/1761.png"></graphic>
8131 </figure>
8132 <para>
8133 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8134 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8135 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8136 distribute content?
8137 </para>
8138 <para>
8139 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8140 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8141 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8142 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8143 </para>
8144 <para>
8145 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8146 integration may matter.
8147 </para>
8148 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman</primary></indexterm>
8149 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8150 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8151 <para>
8152 In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle>. He took
8153 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8154 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8155 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8156 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8157 </para>
8158 <para>
8159 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8160 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8161 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8162 control.<footnote><para>
8163 <!-- f29 -->
8164 Leonard Hill, <quote>The Axis of Access,</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8165 Forum, <quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,</quote> St. Louis,
8166 Missouri, 3 April 2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8167 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #28</ulink>;
8168 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8169 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #29</ulink>).
8170 </para></footnote>
8171 </para>
8172 <para>
8173
8174 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8175 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8176 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8177 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8178 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992,
8179 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8180 television&mdash;75 percent of it&mdash;was <quote>independent</quote> of the
8181 networks.
8182 </para>
8183 <para>
8184 In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8185 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985,
8186 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8187 2002, only five independent television studios remained. <quote>In 1992,
8188 only 15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8189 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8190 controlled companies more than quintupled to 77 percent.</quote> <quote>In 1992, 16
8191 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8192 year there was one.</quote><footnote><para>
8193 <!-- f30 -->
8194 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8195 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st
8196 sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8197 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8198 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8199 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8200 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February
8201 2003.
8202 </para></footnote>
8203 In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8204 that ran it. <quote>In the ten-year period between 1992 and 2002, the number
8205 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8206 increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8207 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8208 63%.</quote><footnote><para>
8209 <!-- f31 -->
8210 Ibid.
8211 </para></footnote>
8212 </para>
8213 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8214 <para>
8215 Today, another Norman Lear with another <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle> would
8216 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8217 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8218 owned by the network.
8219 </para>
8220 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry</primary></indexterm>
8221 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill</primary></indexterm>
8222 <para>
8223 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8224 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8225 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8226 </para>
8227 <blockquote>
8228 <para>
8229 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8230 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8231 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8232 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8233 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8234 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8235 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8236 handful.<footnote><para>
8237 <!-- f32 -->
8238 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers</citetitle>, Bill
8239 Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at
8240 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #31</ulink>.
8241 </para></footnote>
8242 </para>
8243 </blockquote>
8244 <para>
8245 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8246 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8247 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8248 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8249 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8250 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8251 question without risk of consequence&mdash;not necessarily banishment
8252 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8253 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8254 democracy.
8255 </para>
8256 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.</primary></indexterm>
8257 <para>
8258 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8259 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the <quote>Innovator's
8260 Dilemma</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8261 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8262 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8263 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.<footnote><para>
8264 <!-- f33 -->
8265 Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8266 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle>
8267 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press, 1997). Christensen
8268 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8269 Kim B. Clark, <quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8270 Concepts in Technological Evolution,</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy</citetitle> 14 (1985):
8271 235&ndash;51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8272 Kaplan, <citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8273 Underperform the Market&mdash;and How to Successfully Transform Them</citetitle>
8274 (New York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001). </para></footnote>
8275
8276 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8277 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8278 sprinting.
8279 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
8280 </para>
8281 <para>
8282 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8283 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8284 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8285 measure.
8286 </para>
8287 <para>
8288 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8289 suggest the concern.
8290 </para>
8291 <para>
8292 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8293 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8294 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8295 </para>
8296 <para>
8297 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8298 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8299 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8300
8301 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8302 wrecked by drugs&mdash;though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8303 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8304 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8305 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8306 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8307 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8308 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8309 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8310 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8311 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8312 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8313 outweigh these costs.
8314 </para>
8315 <para>
8316 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8317 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8318 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8319 these issues.
8320 </para>
8321 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8322 <para>
8323 Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8324 a media campaign as part of the <quote>war on drugs.</quote> The campaign produced
8325 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8326 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8327 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8328 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8329 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8330 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8331 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8332 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8333 </para>
8334 <para>
8335 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8336 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8337 </para>
8338 <para>
8339 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8340 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8341 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8342 war. Can you do it?
8343 </para>
8344 <para>
8345 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8346 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8347 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8348 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8349 message will be heard then?
8350 </para>
8351 <para>
8352 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8353 <quote>controversial</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8354 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8355 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8356 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8357 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8358 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8359 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8360 rights of the stations to be this biased.<footnote><para>
8361 <!-- f34 -->
8362 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads
8363 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8364 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as <quote>against
8365 [their] policy.</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8366 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8367 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8368 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8369 Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8370 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, <quote>On the Issue of
8371 an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV Networks,</quote> <citetitle>New
8372 York Times</citetitle>, 13 March 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time
8373 there is very little that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to
8374 even the playing field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, <quote>Ad
8375 Hoc Access: The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8376 Radio,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review</citetitle> 6 (1988): 449&ndash;79, and for a
8377 more recent summary of the stance of the FCC and the courts, see
8378 <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors Association</citetitle> v. <citetitle>FCC</citetitle>, 184 F. 3d 872
8379 (D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8380 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8381 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8382 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, <quote>Antidiesel Group Fuming
8383 After Muni Rejects Ad,</quote> SFGate.com, 16 June 2003, available at
8384 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #32</ulink>. The ground
8385 was that the criticism was <quote>too controversial.</quote>
8386 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8387 <indexterm><primary>Comcast</primary></indexterm>
8388 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project</primary></indexterm>
8389 <indexterm><primary>NBC</primary></indexterm>
8390 <indexterm><primary>WJOA</primary></indexterm>
8391 <indexterm><primary>WRC</primary></indexterm>
8392 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8393 </para></footnote>
8394 </para>
8395 <para>
8396 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well&mdash;if we lived
8397 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8398 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8399 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8400 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8401 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8402 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8403 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8404 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8405 </para>
8406 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'/>
8407 </section>
8408 <section id="together">
8409 <title>Together</title>
8410 <para>
8411 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8412 copyright warriors that the government should <quote>protect my property.</quote>
8413 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8414 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8415 </para>
8416 <para>
8417 But when we see how dramatically this <quote>property</quote> has changed&mdash;
8418 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8419 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8420 cultivate our culture is dramatically different&mdash;the claim begins
8421 to seem
8422
8423 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8424 less innocent and obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to
8425 supplement the law's control, and (2) the power of concentrated
8426 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8427 the massively expanded <quote>property</quote> rights granted by copyright
8428 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8429 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8430 be redefined.
8431 </para>
8432 <para>
8433 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8434 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8435 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8436 our culture today.
8437 </para>
8438 <para>
8439 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8440 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8441 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8442 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8443 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8444 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8445 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8446 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8447 traditionally defined copyright's regulation&mdash;a weakening of that
8448 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
8449 </para>
8450 <para>
8451 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
8452 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
8453 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
8454 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
8455 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
8456 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
8457 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
8458 future. And these changes have to be <emphasis>reductions</emphasis>
8459 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
8460 in control that technology and the market enable.
8461 </para>
8462 <para>
8463 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
8464 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
8465 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
8466 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
8467 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
8468 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
8469 more of the development of our culture than now</emphasis>.
8470 </para>
8471 <para>
8472 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
8473 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
8474 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
8475 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
8476 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
8477 were independent of the networks. <emphasis>Never</emphasis> has
8478 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
8479 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
8480 regulation&mdash;a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
8481 energy of a nation at the founding&mdash;is now a massive regulation
8482 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
8483 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
8484 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
8485 known.<footnote><para>
8486 <!-- f35 -->
8487 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
8488 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his <quote>four surrenders</quote> of
8489 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan, 159&ndash;60.
8490 </para></footnote>
8491 </para>
8492 <para>
8493 <emphasis role='strong'>This has been</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
8494 point can now be briefly stated.
8495 </para>
8496 <para>
8497 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
8498 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
8499 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
8500 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
8501 that copyright law has undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this:
8502 </para>
8503
8504 <informaltable id="t2">
8505 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
8506 <thead>
8507 <row>
8508 <entry></entry>
8509 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
8510 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8511 </row>
8512 </thead>
8513 <tbody>
8514 <row>
8515 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8516 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8517 <entry>Free</entry>
8518 </row>
8519 <row>
8520 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8521 <entry>Free</entry>
8522 <entry>Free</entry>
8523 </row>
8524 </tbody>
8525 </tgroup>
8526 </informaltable>
8527
8528 <para>
8529 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
8530 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
8531 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
8532
8533 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
8534 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
8535 noncommercial work was also free.
8536 </para>
8537 <para>
8538 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
8539 </para>
8540
8541 <informaltable id="t3">
8542 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
8543 <thead>
8544 <row>
8545 <entry></entry>
8546 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
8547 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8548 </row>
8549 </thead>
8550 <tbody>
8551 <row>
8552 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8553 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8554 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8555 </row>
8556 <row>
8557 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8558 <entry>Free</entry>
8559 <entry>Free</entry>
8560 </row>
8561 </tbody>
8562 </tgroup>
8563 </informaltable>
8564
8565 <para>
8566 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law&mdash;if
8567 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
8568 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
8569 transformation were still essentially free.
8570 </para>
8571 <para>
8572 In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
8573 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
8574 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
8575 expanded. Thus by 1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
8576 we could say the law began to look like this:
8577 </para>
8578
8579 <informaltable id="t4">
8580 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
8581 <thead>
8582 <row>
8583 <entry></entry>
8584 <entry>COPY</entry>
8585 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8586 </row>
8587 </thead>
8588 <tbody>
8589 <row>
8590 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8591 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8592 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8593 </row>
8594 <row>
8595 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8596 <entry>&copy;/Free</entry>
8597 <entry>Free</entry>
8598 </row>
8599 </tbody>
8600 </tgroup>
8601 </informaltable>
8602
8603 <para>
8604 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
8605 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
8606 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
8607 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
8608 that the law now looks like this:
8609 </para>
8610
8611 <informaltable id="t5">
8612 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
8613 <thead>
8614 <row>
8615 <entry></entry>
8616 <entry>COPY</entry>
8617 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8618 </row>
8619 </thead>
8620 <tbody>
8621 <row>
8622 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8623 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8624 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8625 </row>
8626 <row>
8627 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8628 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8629 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8630 </row>
8631 </tbody>
8632 </tgroup>
8633 </informaltable>
8634
8635 <para>
8636 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
8637 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
8638 creativity&mdash;
8639 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
8640 commercial or not, transformative or not&mdash;with the same rules
8641 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
8642 </para>
8643 <para>
8644 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
8645 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
8646 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
8647 these domains actually does any good.
8648 </para>
8649 <para>
8650 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
8651 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
8652 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
8653 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
8654 reasons sketched especially in chapters
8655 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/> and
8656 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>, one
8657 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
8658 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
8659 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
8660 </para>
8661 <para>
8662 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
8663 course copyright is a kind of <quote>property,</quote> and of course, as with any
8664 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
8665 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
8666 property rights<footnote><para>
8667 <!-- f36 -->
8668 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
8669 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
8670 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, <quote>The
8671 Disintegration of Property,</quote> in <citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property</citetitle>, J. Roland
8672 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
8673 Press, 1980).
8674 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement</primary></indexterm>
8675 </para></footnote>)
8676 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
8677 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
8678 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
8679 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the <quote>copyright</quote>
8680 did not control <emphasis>at all</emphasis> the freedom of others to
8681 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
8682 free, and for almost 180 years our country consistently protected a
8683 vibrant and rich free culture.
8684 </para>
8685 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
8686 <para>
8687 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
8688 limits on the scope of the interests protected by <quote>property.</quote> The very
8689 birth of <quote>copyright</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
8690 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
8691 story of chapter 6). The tradition of <quote>fair use</quote> is animated by a
8692 similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the costs of
8693 exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the story of
8694 chapter 7). Adding
8695 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
8696 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
8697 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter
8698 8). And granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect,
8699 claims of property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing
8700 the soul of a culture (chapter 9). Free cultures, like free markets,
8701 are built with property. But the nature of the property that builds a
8702 free culture is very different from the extremist vision that
8703 dominates the debate today.
8704 </para>
8705 <para>
8706 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
8707 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
8708 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
8709 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
8710 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
8711 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
8712 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
8713 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
8714 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
8715 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
8716 lawyer.
8717 </para>
8718 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
8719 </section>
8720 </chapter>
8721 </part>
8722 <part id="c-puzzles">
8723 <title>PUZZLES</title>
8724
8725 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
8726 <chapter label="11" id="chimera">
8727 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera</title>
8728 <indexterm id="idxchimera" class='startofrange'><primary>chimeras</primary></indexterm>
8729 <indexterm id="idxwells" class='startofrange'><primary>Wells, H. G.</primary></indexterm>
8730 <indexterm id="idxtcotb" class='startofrange'><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The</quote> (Wells)</primary></indexterm>
8731
8732 <para>
8733 <emphasis role='strong'>In a well-known</emphasis> short story by
8734 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
8735 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
8736 Andes.<footnote><para>
8737 <!-- f1. -->
8738 H. G. Wells, <quote>The Country of the Blind</quote> (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells,
8739 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
8740 York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
8741 </para></footnote>
8742 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with <quote>sweet water, pasture,
8743 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
8744 that bore an excellent fruit.</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
8745 takes this as an opportunity. <quote>In the Country of the Blind,</quote> he tells
8746 himself, <quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.</quote> So he resolves to live with the
8747 villagers to explore life as a king.
8748 </para>
8749 <para>
8750 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
8751 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
8752 <quote>blind.</quote> They don't have the word <citetitle>blind</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
8753 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
8754 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
8755 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. <quote>`You
8756 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
8757 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
8758 alone!'</quote>
8759 </para>
8760 <para>
8761 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
8762 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
8763 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
8764 affection, a young woman who to him seems <quote>the most beautiful thing in
8765 the whole of creation,</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
8766 description of what he sees <quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
8767 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
8768 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
8769 indulgence.</quote> <quote>She did not believe,</quote> Wells tells us, and <quote>she could
8770 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.</quote>
8771 </para>
8772 <para>
8773 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his <quote>mysteriously delighted</quote>
8774 love, the father and the village object. <quote>You see, my dear,</quote> her
8775 father instructs, <quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
8776 anything right.</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
8777 </para>
8778 <para>
8779 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. <quote>His brain
8780 is affected,</quote> he reports.
8781 </para>
8782 <para>
8783 <quote>What affects it?</quote> the father asks. <quote>Those queer things that are
8784 called the eyes &hellip; are diseased &hellip; in such a way as to affect
8785 his brain.</quote>
8786 </para>
8787 <para>
8788 The doctor continues: <quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
8789 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
8790 simple and easy surgical operation&mdash;namely, to remove these
8791 irritant bodies [the eyes].</quote>
8792 </para>
8793 <para>
8794 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
8795 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
8796 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
8797 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
8798 </para>
8799 <para>
8800 <emphasis role='strong'>It sometimes</emphasis> happens that the eggs
8801 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
8802 <quote>chimera.</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
8803 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
8804 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
8805
8806 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
8807 plot for murder mysteries. <quote>But the DNA shows with 100 percent
8808 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
8809 scene. &hellip;</quote>
8810 </para>
8811 <indexterm startref="idxtcotb" class='endofrange'/>
8812 <indexterm startref="idxwells" class="endofrange"/>
8813 <para>
8814 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
8815 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
8816 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
8817 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
8818 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
8819 understanding of a <quote>person</quote> should reflect this reality.
8820 </para>
8821 <para>
8822 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
8823 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
8824 unfairly enough, <quote>the copyright wars,</quote> the more I think we're dealing
8825 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question <quote>What is
8826 p2p file sharing?</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
8827 wrong. One side says, <quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
8828 others' records&mdash;the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
8829 thirty years without any question at all.</quote> That's true, at least in
8830 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
8831 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
8832 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
8833 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
8834 </para>
8835 <para>
8836 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
8837 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
8838 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
8839 <quote>friends</quote> beyond recognition to say <quote>my ten thousand best friends</quote> can
8840 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
8841 what <quote>we have always been allowed to do,</quote> we have not always been
8842 allowed to share music with <quote>our ten thousand best friends.</quote>
8843 </para>
8844 <para>
8845 Likewise, when the other side says, <quote>File sharing is just like walking
8846 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
8847 with it,</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
8848 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
8849 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
8850 from Tower.
8851 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
8852 </para>
8853 <para>
8854
8855 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
8856 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
8857 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
8858 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
8859 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
8860 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
8861 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
8862 $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
8863 CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.)
8864 </para>
8865 <para>
8866 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
8867 that it is both&mdash;both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
8868 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
8869 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
8870 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
8871 </para>
8872 <para>
8873 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
8874 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
8875 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
8876 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
8877 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
8878 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
8879 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
8880 implemented.<footnote><para>
8881 <!-- f2. -->
8882 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
8883 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
8884 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
8885 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003,
8886 available at
8887 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
8888 #33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
8889 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
8890 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
8891 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, <quote>House Bill Aims to Up
8892 Stakes on Piracy,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 17 July 2003, available at
8893 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #34</ulink>. Civil
8894 penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied song. For a recent
8895 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
8896 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 songs
8897 through a family computer, see <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
8898 re. Verizon Internet Services)</citetitle>, 240 F. Supp. 2d 24
8899 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $90
8900 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
8901 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
8902 $12,000 to $17,500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
8903 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $98
8904 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
8905 Elizabeth Young, <quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,</quote> redandblack.com,
8906 August 2003, available at
8907 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #35</ulink>. For an
8908 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
8909 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
8910 identities, see James Collins, <quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
8911 Name Students,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 8 August 2003, D3, available at
8912 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #36</ulink>.
8913 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
8914 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
8915 </para></footnote>
8916
8917 </para>
8918 <indexterm startref="idxchimera" class='endofrange'/>
8919 <para>
8920 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
8921 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
8922 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
8923 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
8924 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
8925 </para>
8926 <para>
8927 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
8928 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
8929 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
8930 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
8931 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
8932 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe <emphasis>either</emphasis> extreme
8933 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
8934 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
8935 </para>
8936 <para>
8937
8938 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
8939 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
8940 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
8941 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
8942 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
8943 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
8944 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
8945 </para>
8946 <para>
8947 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to <quote>steal</quote> music. My
8948 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
8949 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
8950 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
8951 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
8952 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
8953 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
8954 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
8955 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
8956 protection for copyrighted material,
8957 </para>
8958 <blockquote>
8959 <para>
8960 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
8961 material, and we want to protect those rights.
8962 </para>
8963 <para>
8964 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
8965 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
8966 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
8967 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
8968 produce a totally different industry model.
8969 </para>
8970 <para>
8971 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
8972 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
8973 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
8974 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
8975 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
8976 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
8977 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
8978 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
8979 interests.<footnote><para>
8980 <!-- f3. -->
8981 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
8982 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
8983 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
8984 House Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement of Peter
8985 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
8986 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
8987 Congressional Testimony File. </para></footnote>
8988 </para>
8989 </blockquote>
8990 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
8991 <para>
8992 In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
8993 one of <quote>the major labels.</quote> Its position on these matters has now
8994 changed.
8995 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
8996 </para>
8997 <para>
8998 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
8999 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9000 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9001 </para>
9002
9003 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9004 </chapter>
9005 <chapter label="12" id="harms">
9006 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms</title>
9007 <para>
9008 <emphasis role='strong'>To fight</emphasis> <quote>piracy,</quote> to
9009 protect <quote>property,</quote> the content industry has launched a
9010 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9011 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9012 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9013 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9014 </para>
9015 <para>
9016 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9017 particular, the consequences for <quote>free culture.</quote> But my aim now is to
9018 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9019 justified?
9020 </para>
9021 <para>
9022 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9023 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9024 power of the property called <quote>intellectual property</quote> is at its greatest in
9025 our history.
9026 </para>
9027 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
9028 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
9029 <para>
9030 Yet <quote>common sense</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9031 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9032 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9033 rejection of <quote>piracy</quote> still has play.
9034 </para>
9035 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9036 <para>
9037 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9038 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9039 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9040 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9041 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9042 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9043 </para>
9044 <section id="constrain">
9045 <title>Constraining Creators</title>
9046 <para>
9047 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9048 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9049 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9050 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9051 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9052 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9053 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9054 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9055 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9056 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9057 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9058 weave together a string&mdash;a mash-up&mdash; of songs from your
9059 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9060 </para>
9061 <para>
9062 This digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> is in part an extension of the
9063 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9064 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9065 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9066 of digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9067 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9068 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9069 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9070 the culture all around.
9071 </para>
9072 <para>
9073 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9074 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9075
9076 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9077
9078 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9079 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9080 storytelling extended across the globe.
9081 </para>
9082 <para>
9083 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9084 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9085 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9086 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9087 that catalog cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9088 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9089 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9090 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9091 work is presumptively illegal.
9092 </para>
9093 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom</primary></indexterm>
9094 <para>
9095 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9096 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9097 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9098 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9099 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9100 by the RIAA ( Jesse Jordan of chapter 3 was just one) were threatened
9101 with a $98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted
9102 songs to be copied. Yet World-Com&mdash;which defrauded investors of
9103 $11 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization
9104 of over $200 billion&mdash;received a fine of a mere $750
9105 million.<footnote><para>
9106 <!-- f1. -->
9107 See Lynne W. Jeter, <citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom</citetitle>
9108 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley &amp; Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of
9109 the settlement, see MCI press release, <quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9110 Approval for SEC Settlement</quote> (7 July 2003), available at
9111 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #37</ulink>.
9112 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom</primary></indexterm>
9113 </para></footnote>
9114 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9115 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9116 no more than $250,000 in damages for pain and
9117 suffering.<footnote>
9118 <para>
9119 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9120 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For
9121 an overview, see Tanya Albert, <quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9122 Say Tort Reformers,</quote> amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at
9123 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #38</ulink>,
9124 and <quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,</quote> CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003,
9125 available at
9126 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9127 recent months.
9128 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.</primary></indexterm>
9129 </para></footnote>
9130 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9131 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9132 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9133 </para>
9134 <indexterm><primary>art, underground</primary></indexterm>
9135 <para>
9136 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9137 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9138 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9139 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9140 Disneys <quote>pirates.</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9141 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9142 designed to
9143
9144 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9145 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9146 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9147 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9148 we will begin to see a world of underground art&mdash;not because the
9149 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9150 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9151 fraught. Already, exhibits of <quote>illegal art</quote> tour the United
9152 States.<footnote><para>
9153 <!-- f3. -->
9154
9155 See Danit Lidor, <quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,</quote> <citetitle>Wired</citetitle>, 7 July
9156 2003, available at
9157 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9158 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #41</ulink>.
9159 </para></footnote>
9160 In what does their <quote>illegality</quote> consist?
9161 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9162 critical or reflective.
9163 </para>
9164 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9165 <para>
9166 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9167 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9168 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. But an
9169 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9170 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9171 discovered in 2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9172 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9173 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9174 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9175 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9176 </para>
9177 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
9178 <para>
9179 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9180 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9181 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9182 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9183 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9184 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9185 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9186 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9187 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9188 </para>
9189 <para>
9190 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9191 described in chapter
9192 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/>, in
9193 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9194 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9195 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9196 use.
9197 </para>
9198 <para>
9199
9200 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9201 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9202 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9203 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad&mdash;in
9204 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9205 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9206 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9207 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9208 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9209 </para>
9210 <para>
9211 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9212 <quote>breathing room</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9213 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9214 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9215 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9216 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9217 journalists&mdash; these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9218 these rules have little relationship to the <quote>law</quote> with which judges
9219 comfort themselves.
9220 </para>
9221 <para>
9222 For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful
9223 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9224 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9225 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9226 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak&mdash;in that
9227 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9228 <quote>copyright</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9229 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9230 culture that is free.
9231 </para>
9232 <para>
9233 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9234 </para>
9235 <blockquote>
9236 <para>
9237 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9238 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9239 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9240 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made &hellip; you're not
9241 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9242 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9243 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, <quote>This has been
9244 cleared.</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9245 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9246 </para>
9247 </blockquote>
9248 </section>
9249 <section id="innovators">
9250 <title>Constraining Innovators</title>
9251 <para>
9252 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9253 story&mdash;creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9254 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9255 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9256 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9257 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9258 </para>
9259 <para>
9260 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9261 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9262 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9263 one at that, 188 pages into a book like this), then you can see this
9264 other aspect by substituting <quote>free market</quote> every place I've spoken of
9265 <quote>free culture.</quote> The point is the same, even if the interests
9266 affecting culture are more fundamental.
9267 </para>
9268 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9269 <para>
9270 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9271 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9272 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary&mdash;at
9273 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9274 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9275 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9276 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9277 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9278 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9279 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9280 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9281 </para>
9282 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9283 <para>
9284 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9285 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9286 strategy that I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9287 labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9288 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9289 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9290 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9291 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9292 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9293 lesson. That lesson&mdash;what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9294 <quote>nuclear pall</quote> that has fallen over the Valley&mdash;has been learned.
9295 </para>
9296 <para>
9297 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9298 I told in <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9299 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9300 </para>
9301 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael</primary></indexterm>
9302 <para>
9303 In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9304 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9305 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9306 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9307 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9308 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9309 </para>
9310 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9311 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>preference data on</secondary></indexterm>
9312 <para>
9313 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9314 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9315 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9316 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9317 Raitt. And so on.
9318 </para>
9319 <para>
9320 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9321 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9322 preference data. In January 2000, the company launched a service
9323 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9324 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9325 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9326 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9327 wherever you were&mdash;at work or at home&mdash;you could get access
9328 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9329 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9330 </para>
9331 <para>
9332 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9333 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9334
9335 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9336 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9337 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9338 the kind of content the users liked.
9339 </para>
9340 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'/>
9341 <para>
9342 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000
9343 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9344 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9345 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9346 therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9347 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9348 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9349 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was 50,000
9350 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers something
9351 they had already bought.
9352 </para>
9353 <indexterm id="idxvivendiuniversal" class='startofrange'><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9354 <para>
9355 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9356 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9357 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9358 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9359 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9360 MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9361 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $54 million. Vivendi
9362 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9363 </para>
9364 <para>
9365 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9366 </para>
9367 <para>
9368 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9369 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9370 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9371 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9372 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9373 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9374 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9375 demanded.
9376 </para>
9377 <para>
9378 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9379 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9380 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9381 clients in this
9382 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9383 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9384 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9385 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9386 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9387 </para>
9388 <indexterm startref="idxvivendiuniversal" class='endofrange'/>
9389 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John</primary></indexterm>
9390 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9391 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad</primary></indexterm>
9392 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
9393 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
9394 <para>
9395 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003,
9396 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9397 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9398 its development, its cofounder ( John Hummer), and general partner
9399 (Hank Barry).<footnote><para>
9400 <!-- f4. -->
9401 See Joseph Menn, <quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9402 Times</citetitle>, 23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9403 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, <quote>The Music
9404 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,</quote> Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available
9405 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #42</ulink>.
9406 See also Jon Healey, <quote>Online Music Services Besieged,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9407 Times</citetitle>, 28 May 2001.
9408 </para></footnote>
9409 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
9410 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
9411 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
9412 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
9413 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
9414 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
9415 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
9416 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
9417 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
9418 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
9419 <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
9420 discussion with BMW:
9421 </para>
9422 <blockquote>
9423 <indexterm><primary>BMW</primary></indexterm>
9424 <indexterm><primary>cars, MP3 sound system in</primary></indexterm>
9425 <para>
9426 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
9427 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
9428 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
9429 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
9430 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
9431 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
9432 United States with bona fide MP3 players. &hellip; <footnote>
9433 <para>
9434 <!-- f5. -->
9435 Rafe Needleman, <quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,</quote> <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, 16 June
9436 2003, available at
9437 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #43</ulink>. I am grateful
9438 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
9439 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
9440 </para></footnote>
9441 </para>
9442 </blockquote>
9443 <para>
9444 This is the world of the mafia&mdash;filled with <quote>your money or your
9445 life</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
9446 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
9447 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
9448 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
9449 constantly threatened by litigation.
9450 </para>
9451 <para>
9452
9453 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
9454 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
9455 enterprises. The point is the definition of <quote>illegal.</quote> The law is a
9456 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
9457 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
9458 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
9459 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
9460 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
9461 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
9462 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
9463 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
9464 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
9465 much less creativity.
9466 </para>
9467 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9468 <para>
9469 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
9470 use. Whatever the <quote>real</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
9471 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
9472 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
9473 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
9474 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
9475 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
9476 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
9477 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
9478 produce an overregulatedregulated market.
9479 </para>
9480 <para>
9481 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
9482 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
9483 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
9484 culture&mdash;a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
9485 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
9486 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
9487 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
9488 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
9489 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
9490 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
9491 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
9492 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
9493 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
9494 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
9495 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
9496 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
9497 result.
9498 </para>
9499 <para>
9500 <emphasis role='strong'>The uncertainty</emphasis> of the law is one
9501 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
9502 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
9503 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
9504 better protects their content.
9505 </para>
9506 <para>
9507 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
9508 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
9509 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
9510 this feature is a <quote>bug.</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
9511 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
9512 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
9513 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables <quote>piracy,</quote> then,
9514 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
9515 </para>
9516 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
9517 <para>
9518 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
9519 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
9520 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
9521 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.<footnote><para>
9522 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> GartnerG2 and
9523 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
9524 (2003), 33&ndash;35, available at
9525 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
9526 </para></footnote>
9527 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
9528 <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
9529 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
9530 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
9531 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
9532 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
9533 copyright violators and disable their machines.<footnote><para>
9534 <!-- f7. -->
9535 GartnerG2, 26&ndash;27.
9536 </para></footnote>
9537 </para>
9538 <para>
9539 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
9540 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
9541 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
9542 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
9543 and costs on
9544 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
9545 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
9546 those requirements.
9547 </para>
9548 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
9549 <para>
9550 In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
9551 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
9552 would impose.<footnote><para>
9553 <!-- f8. -->
9554 See David McGuire, <quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,</quote> Newsbytes,
9555 February 2002 (Entertainment).
9556 </para></footnote>
9557 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
9558 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
9559 harm than good.
9560 </para>
9561 <para>
9562 <emphasis role='strong'>There is one</emphasis> more obvious way in
9563 which this war has harmed innovation&mdash;again, a story that will be
9564 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
9565 </para>
9566 <para>
9567 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
9568 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
9569 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
9570 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
9571 </para>
9572 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
9573 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
9574 <para>
9575 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9576 linkend="property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
9577 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
9578 Jessica Litman in her book <citetitle>Digital
9579 Copyright</citetitle>,<footnote><para>
9580 <!-- f9. -->
9581 Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (Amherst,
9582 N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 2001).
9583 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
9584 </para></footnote>
9585 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter 10 details,
9586 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
9587 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
9588 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
9589 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
9590 </para>
9591 <para>
9592 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
9593 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
9594 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
9595 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
9596 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
9597 </para>
9598 <para>
9599 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.<footnote><para>
9600 <!-- f10. -->
9601 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.</primary></indexterm>
9602 The only circuit court exception is found in <citetitle>Recording Industry
9603 Association of America (RIAA)</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems</citetitle>, 180 F. 3d
9604 1072 (9th Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
9605 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
9606 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
9607 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
9608 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
9609 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
9610 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Grokster, Ltd</citetitle>., 259 F. Supp. 2d
9611 1029 (C.D. Cal., 2003), where the court found the link between the
9612 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
9613 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
9614 liability.
9615 </para></footnote>
9616 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
9617 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
9618 here.<footnote><para>
9619 <!-- f11. -->
9620 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy</primary></indexterm>
9621 For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
9622 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize
9623 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
9624 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
9625 August 2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
9626 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
9627 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that
9628 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
9629 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
9630 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
9631 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, <quote>Copyright and
9632 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003, 33&ndash;34,
9633 available at
9634 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
9635 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
9636 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz</primary></indexterm>
9637 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
9638 </para></footnote>
9639 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
9640 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
9641 </para>
9642 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
9643 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
9644 <para>
9645
9646 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
9647 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9648 linkend="pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
9649 artist doesn't get paid for that <quote>radio performance</quote> unless he or she
9650 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
9651 version of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote>&mdash;to memorialize her famous
9652 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden&mdash;
9653 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
9654 copyright owners of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> would get some money, whereas
9655 Marilyn Monroe would not.
9656 </para>
9657 <para>
9658 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
9659 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
9660 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
9661 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
9662 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
9663 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
9664 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
9665 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
9666 recording artists.
9667 </para>
9668 <para>
9669 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
9670 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
9671 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
9672 spectrum. Thus, I can <quote>tune in</quote> to an Internet radio station in
9673 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
9674 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
9675 metropolitan area.
9676 </para>
9677 <para>
9678 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
9679 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
9680 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
9681 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
9682 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
9683 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
9684 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
9685 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
9686 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
9687 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
9688 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
9689 </para>
9690 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9691 <para>
9692
9693 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
9694 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
9695 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
9696 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
9697 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
9698 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
9699 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
9700 FM radio,
9701 </para>
9702 <blockquote>
9703 <para>
9704 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
9705 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
9706 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
9707 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
9708 than by technical restrictions. &hellip; Armstrong likened the situation
9709 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
9710 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
9711 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
9712 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
9713 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
9714 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
9715 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
9716 shackles.<footnote><para>
9717 <!-- f12. -->
9718 Lessing, 239.
9719 </para></footnote>
9720 </para>
9721 </blockquote>
9722 <para>
9723 This potential for FM radio was never realized&mdash;not
9724 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
9725 underestimated the power of <quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
9726 legislation</quote><footnote><para>
9727 <!-- f13. -->
9728 Ibid., 229.
9729 </para></footnote>
9730 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
9731 </para>
9732 <para>
9733 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
9734 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
9735 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
9736 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
9737 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
9738 radio?
9739 </para>
9740 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments2' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
9741 <para>
9742 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
9743 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
9744
9745 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
9746 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
9747 of Internet radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
9748 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
9749 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
9750 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
9751 of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> on the air, <emphasis>Internet radio
9752 does</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
9753 radio&mdash;the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
9754 burdens terrestrial radio.
9755 </para>
9756 <para>
9757 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
9758 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
9759 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
9760 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
9761 over $1 million a year.<footnote>
9762 <para>
9763 <!-- f14. -->
9764 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
9765 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
9766 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
9767 iLaw (Stanford), 3 July 2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
9768 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
9769 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
9770 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP
9771 DTRA 1 and 2, available at
9772 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #45</ulink>.
9773 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
9774 C. Picker, <quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
9775 Distribution,</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin</citetitle> (Summer/Fall 2002): 461: <quote>This was
9776 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
9777 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
9778 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
9779 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
9780 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.</quote>
9781 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)</primary></indexterm>
9782 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
9783 </para></footnote>
9784 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
9785 equivalent fee.
9786 </para>
9787 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments2' class='endofrange'/>
9788 <para>
9789 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
9790 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
9791 station) would have to collect the following data from <emphasis>every
9792 listening transaction</emphasis>:
9793 </para>
9794 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
9795 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
9796 <listitem><para>
9797 name of the service;
9798 </para></listitem>
9799 <listitem><para>
9800 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
9801 </para></listitem>
9802 <listitem><para>
9803 type of program (archived/looped/live);
9804 </para></listitem>
9805 <listitem><para>
9806 date of transmission;
9807 </para></listitem>
9808 <listitem><para>
9809 time of transmission;
9810 </para></listitem>
9811 <listitem><para>
9812 time zone of origination of transmission;
9813 </para></listitem>
9814 <listitem><para>
9815 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
9816 </para></listitem>
9817 <listitem><para>
9818 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
9819 </para></listitem>
9820 <listitem><para>
9821 sound recording title;
9822 </para></listitem>
9823 <listitem><para>
9824 ISRC code of the recording;
9825 </para></listitem>
9826 <listitem><para>
9827 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
9828 </para></listitem>
9829 <listitem><para>
9830 featured recording artist;
9831 </para></listitem>
9832 <listitem><para>
9833 retail album title;
9834 </para></listitem>
9835 <listitem><para>
9836 recording label;
9837 </para></listitem>
9838 <listitem><para>
9839 UPC code of the retail album;
9840 </para></listitem>
9841 <listitem><para>
9842 catalog number;
9843 </para></listitem>
9844 <listitem><para>
9845 copyright owner information;
9846 </para></listitem>
9847 <listitem><para>
9848 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
9849 </para></listitem>
9850 <listitem><para>
9851 name of the service or entity;
9852 </para></listitem>
9853 <listitem><para>
9854 channel or program;
9855 </para></listitem>
9856 <listitem><para>
9857 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
9858 </para></listitem>
9859 <listitem><para>
9860 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
9861 </para></listitem>
9862 <listitem><para>
9863 time zone where the signal was received (user);
9864 </para></listitem>
9865 <listitem><para>
9866 unique user identifier;
9867 </para></listitem>
9868 <listitem><para>
9869 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
9870 </para></listitem>
9871 </orderedlist>
9872
9873 <para>
9874 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
9875 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
9876 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
9877 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
9878 Internet radio has to pay a <emphasis>type of copyright fee</emphasis>
9879 that terrestrial radio does not.
9880 </para>
9881 <para>
9882 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
9883 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
9884 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
9885 </para>
9886 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
9887 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
9888 <para>
9889 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
9890 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
9891 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
9892 </para>
9893 <blockquote>
9894 <para>
9895 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
9896 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
9897 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
9898 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
9899 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
9900 webcasters asked the RIAA, &hellip; <quote>How do you come up with a
9901
9902 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
9903 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
9904 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
9905 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
9906 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
9907 business. &hellip;</quote>
9908 </para>
9909 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
9910 <para>
9911 And the RIAA experts said, <quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
9912 industry with thousands of webcasters, <emphasis>we think it should be
9913 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
9914 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market</emphasis>.</quote> (Emphasis
9915 added.)
9916 </para>
9917 </blockquote>
9918 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'/>
9919 <para>
9920 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
9921 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
9922 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
9923 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
9924 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
9925 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
9926 effective to prevent it.
9927 </para>
9928 </section>
9929 <section id="corruptingcitizens">
9930 <title>Corrupting Citizens</title>
9931 <para>
9932 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
9933 dinosaurs
9934 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
9935 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
9936 </para>
9937 <para>
9938 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
9939 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
9940 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
9941 </para>
9942 <para>
9943 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
9944 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
9945 large number of citizens. According to <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, 43 million
9946 Americans downloaded music in May 2002.<footnote><para>
9947 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, <quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,</quote> Pew
9948 Internet and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at
9949 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #46</ulink>.
9950 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that 37 million
9951 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early 2001.
9952 </para></footnote>
9953 According to the RIAA,
9954 the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
9955 set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As the
9956
9957 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
9958 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
9959 the world, but against students building search engines, and
9960 increasingly
9961 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
9962 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
9963 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
9964 extreme
9965 response by the other.
9966 </para>
9967 <para>
9968 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
9969 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
9970 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
9971 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
9972 ($15,000,000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
9973 paying all the money in the world in damages ($250,000 in legal fees)
9974 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
9975 ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
9976 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September 2003, the RIAA
9977 sued 261 individuals&mdash;including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
9978 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
9979 was.<footnote><para>
9980 <!-- f16. -->
9981 Alex Pham, <quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,</quote> <citetitle>Los
9982 Angeles Times</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, Business.
9983 </para></footnote>
9984 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
9985 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
9986 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000
9987 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
9988 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
9989 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
9990 they oppose.
9991 </para>
9992 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition</primary></indexterm>
9993 <para>
9994 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
9995 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
9996 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
9997 consumption of alcohol was 1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
9998 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just 30 percent
9999 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10000 consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition
10001 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10002 number were criminals.<footnote><para>
10003 <!-- f17. -->
10004 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, <quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10005 Prohibition,</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review</citetitle> 81, no. 2 (1991): 242.
10006 </para></footnote>
10007 We have
10008 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10009 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10010 narcotics that 7 percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.<footnote><para>
10011 <!-- f18. -->
10012 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10013 Reform Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of
10014 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10015 </para></footnote>
10016 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of
10017 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10018 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10019 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10020 cheat.<footnote><para>
10021 <!-- f19. -->
10022 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, <quote>Tax
10023 Compliance,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature</citetitle> 36 (1998): 818 (survey of
10024 compliance literature).
10025 </para></footnote>
10026 We pride ourselves on our <quote>free society,</quote> but an endless array of
10027 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10028 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10029 </para>
10030 <indexterm><primary>law schools</primary></indexterm>
10031 <para>
10032 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10033 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10034 students about the importance of <quote>ethics.</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10035 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10036 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10037 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10038 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10039 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10040 teach them how to behave ethically&mdash;how to say no to bribes, or
10041 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10042 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10043 Americans&mdash;more significantly in some parts of America than in
10044 others, but still, everywhere in America today&mdash;can't live their
10045 lives both normally and legally, since <quote>normally</quote> entails a certain
10046 degree of illegality.
10047 </para>
10048 <para>
10049 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10050 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10051 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10052 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10053 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10054 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10055 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10056 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10057 to consider the alternative.
10058 </para>
10059 <para>
10060
10061 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10062 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10063 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10064 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10065 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10066 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10067 </para>
10068 <para>
10069 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10070 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10071 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10072 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10073 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10074 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10075 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10076 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10077 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10078 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10079 introduced this different idea of <quote>sharing.</quote> We need to be able to
10080 call these twenty million Americans <quote>citizens,</quote> not <quote>felons.</quote>
10081 </para>
10082 <para>
10083 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10084 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10085 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10086 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10087 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10088 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10089 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10090 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10091 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10092 a nation of felons?
10093 </para>
10094 <para>
10095 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10096 </para>
10097 <para>
10098 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10099 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10100 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10101 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10102 used
10103
10104 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10105 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That <quote>use</quote> of the
10106 recordings is free.
10107 </para>
10108 <para>
10109 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10110 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10111 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am <quote>free</quote> to copy,
10112 or <quote>rip,</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10113 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that <quote>freedom</quote> was a
10114 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the <quote>Rip, Mix, Burn</quote>
10115 capacities of digital technologies.
10116 </para>
10117 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda</primary></indexterm>
10118 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>mix technology and</secondary></indexterm>
10119 <para>
10120 This <quote>use</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10121 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10122 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10123 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10124 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10125 Others&mdash;the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10126 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10127 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10128 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10129 </para>
10130 <para>
10131 This use is enabled by unprotected media&mdash;either CDs or records.
10132 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10133 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10134 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10135 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10136 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10137 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10138 on people's machines.
10139 </para>
10140 <para>
10141 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10142 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10143 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10144 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10145 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10146 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10147
10148 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10149 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10150 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10151 plastic or were part of a massively complex <quote>digital rights
10152 management</quote> system.
10153 </para>
10154 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'/>
10155 <para>
10156 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10157 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10158 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10159 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10160 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10161 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10162 freedom to move content easily?
10163 </para>
10164 <para>
10165 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10166 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10167 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10168 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10169 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10170 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10171 alternative&mdash;namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10172 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10173 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10174 </para>
10175 <para>
10176 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10177 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10178 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10179 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10180 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10181 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10182 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10183 </para>
10184 <para>
10185 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10186 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10187 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10188 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10189 </para>
10190 <para>
10191 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10192 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10193
10194 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10195
10196 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10197 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10198 </para>
10199 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
10200 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
10201 <para>
10202 <emphasis role='strong'>There's one more</emphasis> aspect to this
10203 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10204 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10205 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10206 <quote>collateral damage</quote> that <quote>arises whenever you turn
10207 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.</quote> This
10208 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10209 </para>
10210 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10211 <para>
10212 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,</quote> von Lohmann
10213 explains,
10214 </para>
10215 <blockquote>
10216 <para>
10217 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10218 evaporate to one degree or another. &hellip; If you're a copyright
10219 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10220 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10221 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10222 access? &hellip; Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, <quote>Oh, well,
10223 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.</quote> Well, what this campaign
10224 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10225 American Internet-using population into <quote>lawbreakers.</quote>
10226 </para>
10227 </blockquote>
10228 <para>
10229 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10230 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10231 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10232 </para>
10233 <para>
10234 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA
10235 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10236 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10237 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10238 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10239 an Internet user is revealed.
10240 </para>
10241 <para>
10242 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10243 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10244 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10245 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10246 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10247 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10248 the family could be liable for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10249 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10250 Jesse Jordan.<footnote><para>
10251 <!-- f20. -->
10252 See Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10253 Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,</quote>
10254 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, <quote>Worried Parents
10255 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10256 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10257 Being Sued,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson
10258 Graham, <quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 15 September
10259 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, <quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10260 Fan, Either,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 25 September 2003, C1; Margo Varadi, <quote>Is
10261 Brianna a Criminal?</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star</citetitle>, 18 September 2003, P7.
10262 </para></footnote>
10263
10264 </para>
10265 <para>
10266 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10267 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10268 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.<footnote><para>
10269 <!-- f21. -->
10270 See <quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10271 Some Methods Used,</quote> CNN.com, available at
10272 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #47</ulink>.
10273 </para></footnote>
10274 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10275 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10276 one of those MP3s will have the same <quote>fingerprint.</quote>
10277 </para>
10278 <para>
10279 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10280 friend gives a CD to your daughter&mdash;a collection of songs just
10281 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10282 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10283 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10284 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10285 network is <quote>cooperating</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10286 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10287 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10288 as a <quote>criminal.</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10289 to deploy,<footnote><para>
10290 <!-- f22. -->
10291 See Jeff Adler, <quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,</quote>
10292 <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, <quote>Four
10293 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10294 Colleges,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10295 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10296 Monitor</citetitle>, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, <quote>Music
10297 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10298 Lawsuit Possible,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 16 July 2003, 1C; Beth Cox, <quote>RIAA
10299 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,</quote> <citetitle>Internet News</citetitle>, 30 January
10300 2003, available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10301 #48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Download Warning 101: Freshman
10302 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10303 Sharing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 11 August 2003, E11; <quote>Raid, Letters
10304 Are Weapons at Universities,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 26 September 2000, 3D.
10305 </para></footnote>
10306 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10307 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10308 </para>
10309 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'/>
10310 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10311 <para>
10312 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10313 a lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10314 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10315 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10316 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10317 this <quote>contraband</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10318 college students
10319
10320 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10321 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10322 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10323 Says von Lohmann,
10324 </para>
10325 <blockquote>
10326 <para>
10327 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10328 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10329 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10330 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10331 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10332 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10333 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10334 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10335 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10336 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10337 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10338 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10339 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10340 larger number of Americans than drug use. &hellip; If forty to sixty
10341 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10342 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10343 million of them.
10344 </para>
10345 </blockquote>
10346 <para>
10347 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered <quote>criminals</quote> under
10348 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective&mdash;
10349 securing rights to authors&mdash;without these millions being
10350 considered <quote>criminals,</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10351 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10352 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10353 </para>
10354
10355 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10356 </section>
10357 </chapter>
10358 </part>
10359 <part id="c-balances">
10360 <title>BALANCES</title>
10361 <partintro>
10362
10363 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10364 <para>
10365 <emphasis role='strong'>So here's</emphasis> the picture: You're
10366 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
10367 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
10368 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
10369 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10370 </para>
10371 <para>
10372 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10373 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10374 stop&mdash;or before she understands just why she should
10375 stop&mdash;the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10376 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10377 everything around.
10378 </para>
10379 <para>
10380 <emphasis role='strong'>A war</emphasis> about copyright rages all
10381 around&mdash;and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
10382 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
10383 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
10384 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
10385 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
10386 that if let alone would burn itself out.
10387 </para>
10388 <para>
10389 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
10390 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
10391 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
10392 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
10393 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
10394 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
10395 made that is happening all around.
10396 </para>
10397 <para>
10398 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
10399 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
10400 gasoline onto this fire.
10401 </para>
10402 <para>
10403 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
10404 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
10405 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
10406 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
10407 </para>
10408 <para>
10409 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
10410 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
10411 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
10412 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
10413 success will require.
10414 </para>
10415 </partintro>
10416
10417 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
10418 <chapter label="13" id="eldred">
10419 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred</title>
10420 <indexterm id="idxhawthornenathaniel" class='startofrange'><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel</primary></indexterm>
10421 <para>
10422 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
10423 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
10424 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
10425 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
10426 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
10427 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
10428 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
10429 </para>
10430 <para>
10431 It didn't work&mdash;at least for his daughters. They didn't find
10432 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
10433 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
10434 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
10435 them available for free.
10436 </para>
10437 <para>
10438 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
10439 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
10440 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
10441 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
10442 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
10443 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
10444 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
10445 many others, into a form more accessible&mdash;technically
10446 accessible&mdash;today.
10447 </para>
10448 <para>
10449 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
10450 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's <citetitle>Scarlet Letter</citetitle> had passed into the
10451 public domain in 1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
10452 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
10453 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
10454 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
10455 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
10456 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (<citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle>), sometimes not
10457 (<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame</citetitle>, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>). These are all
10458 commercial publications of public domain works.
10459 </para>
10460 <indexterm startref="idxhawthornenathaniel" class='endofrange'/>
10461 <para>
10462 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
10463 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
10464 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
10465 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
10466 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
10467 call the <quote>noncommercial publishing industry,</quote> which before the
10468 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
10469 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
10470 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
10471 generally.<footnote><para>
10472 <!-- f1. -->
10473 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
10474 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
10475 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers&mdash;people who
10476 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
10477 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
10478 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
10479 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
10480 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
10481 Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on
10482 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
10483 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
10484 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
10485 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
10486 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
10487 protect noncommercial pornographers.</para></footnote>
10488 </para>
10489 <para>
10490 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's
10491 collection of poems <citetitle>New Hampshire</citetitle> was slated to
10492 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
10493 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
10494 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10495 linkend="property-i"/>, in 1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
10496 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights&mdash;this time by
10497 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
10498 than 1923 to his collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
10499 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
10500 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
10501 more than 1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
10502 </para>
10503 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
10504 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
10505 <para>
10506
10507 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
10508 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
10509 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
10510 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
10511 <quote>copyrights should be forever.</quote><footnote><para>
10512 <!-- f2. -->
10513 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
10514 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
10515 The full text is: <quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
10516 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
10517 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
10518 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
10519 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
10520 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
10521 Congress,</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998).
10522 </para></footnote>
10523
10524 </para>
10525 <para>
10526 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
10527 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
10528 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
10529 second law passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
10530 of publishing would make Eldred a felon&mdash;whether or not anyone
10531 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
10532 to undertake.
10533 </para>
10534 <para>
10535 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
10536 constitutional
10537 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
10538 interpretation.
10539 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
10540 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
10541 importantly
10542 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
10543 </para>
10544 <blockquote>
10545 <para>
10546 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science &hellip;
10547 by securing for limited Times to Authors &hellip; exclusive Right to
10548 their &hellip; Writings. &hellip;
10549 </para>
10550 </blockquote>
10551 <para>
10552 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
10553 clause of Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
10554 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
10555 something&mdash;for example, to regulate <quote>commerce among the several
10556 states</quote> or <quote>declare War.</quote> But here, the <quote>something</quote> is something quite
10557 specific&mdash;to <quote>promote &hellip; Progress</quote>&mdash;through means that
10558 are also specific&mdash; by <quote>securing</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights</quote> (i.e.,
10559 copyrights) <quote>for limited Times.</quote>
10560 </para>
10561 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
10562 <para>
10563 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
10564 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
10565 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
10566 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be <quote>limited</quote> will have
10567 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
10568 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
10569 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
10570 what the Constitution plainly forbids&mdash;perpetual terms <quote>on the
10571 installment plan,</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
10572 </para>
10573 <para>
10574 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
10575 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
10576 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
10577 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
10578 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
10579 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
10580 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
10581 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
10582 this gravy train going.
10583 </para>
10584 <para>
10585 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
10586 government. <quote>Corruption</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
10587 bribed. Rather, <quote>corruption</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
10588 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
10589 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
10590 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
10591 do&mdash;and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
10592 </para>
10593 <para>
10594 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
10595 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
10596 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
10597 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry
10598 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
10599 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
10600 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
10601 published by anyone for free.
10602 </para>
10603 <para>
10604 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from
10605 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
10606 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
10607 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
10608 report:
10609 </para>
10610 <para>
10611 <quote>Next year,</quote> the adviser announces, <quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
10612
10613 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
10614 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
10615 receiving the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of
10616 those works.</quote>
10617 </para>
10618 <para>
10619 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,</quote> she continues, <quote>that
10620 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
10621 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
10622 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.</quote>
10623 </para>
10624 <para>
10625 <quote>Hope?</quote> a fellow board member says. <quote>Can't we be doing something
10626 about it?</quote>
10627 </para>
10628 <para>
10629 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>We could contribute
10630 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
10631 they support the bill.</quote>
10632 </para>
10633 <para>
10634 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
10635 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. <quote>How much
10636 would we get if this extension were passed?</quote> you ask the adviser. <quote>How
10637 much is it worth?</quote>
10638 </para>
10639 <para>
10640 <quote>Well,</quote> the adviser says, <quote>if you're confident that you will continue
10641 to get at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
10642 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent),
10643 then this law would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate.</quote>
10644 </para>
10645 <para>
10646 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
10647 correct conclusion:
10648 </para>
10649 <para>
10650 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
10651 $1,000,000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
10652 contributions
10653 would assure that the bill was passed?</quote>
10654 </para>
10655 <para>
10656 <quote>Absolutely,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>It is worth it to you to
10657 contribute
10658 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
10659 copyrights. Which for us means over $1,000,000.</quote>
10660 </para>
10661 <para>
10662 You quickly get the point&mdash;you as the member of the board and, I
10663 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
10664 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
10665 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
10666 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
10667 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
10668 copyrights
10669 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
10670 the copyright term extended.
10671 </para>
10672 <para>
10673 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
10674 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
10675 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
10676 </para>
10677 <para>
10678 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
10679 Copyright
10680 Term Extension Act, this <quote>theory</quote> about incentives was proved
10681 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
10682 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
10683 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
10684 contributions.<footnote><para>
10685 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, <quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
10686 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years,</quote>
10687 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 17 October 1998, 22.
10688 </para></footnote>
10689 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
10690 $1.5 million lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more
10691 than $200,000 in campaign contributions.<footnote><para>
10692 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, <quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
10693 Age,</quote> available at
10694 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #49</ulink>.
10695 </para></footnote>
10696 Disney is estimated to have
10697 contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in the
10698 cycle.<footnote><para>
10699 <!-- f5. -->
10700 Alan K. Ota, <quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,</quote>
10701 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week</citetitle>, 8 August 1990, available at
10702 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #50</ulink>.
10703 </para></footnote>
10704
10705 </para>
10706 <para>
10707 <emphasis role='strong'>Constitutional law</emphasis> is not oblivious
10708 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
10709 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
10710 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
10711 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
10712 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
10713 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
10714 constitutional requirement that terms be <quote>limited.</quote> If
10715 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
10716 again.
10717 </para>
10718 <para>
10719 It was also my judgment that <emphasis>this</emphasis> Supreme Court
10720 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
10721 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
10722 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
10723 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
10724 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
10725 Supreme Court's
10726
10727 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
10728 decision in 1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
10729 guns near schools.
10730 </para>
10731 <para>
10732 Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
10733 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
10734 power to regulate only <quote>commerce among the several states</quote> (aka
10735 <quote>interstate
10736 commerce</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
10737 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
10738 interstate
10739 commerce.
10740 </para>
10741 <para>
10742 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
10743 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
10744 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
10745 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
10746 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
10747 </para>
10748 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
10749 <para>
10750 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
10751 that in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The government had
10752 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
10753 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
10754 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
10755 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
10756 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
10757 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
10758 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
10759 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
10760 position to second-guess Congress.
10761 </para>
10762 <para>
10763 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,</quote>
10764 the Chief Justice wrote.<footnote><para>
10765 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995).
10766 </para></footnote>
10767 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
10768 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
10769 Congress's power. The decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
10770 later in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>.<footnote><para>
10771 <!-- f7. -->
10772 <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>, 529 U.S. 598 (2000).
10773 </para></footnote>
10774 </para>
10775 <para>
10776 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
10777 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.<footnote><para>
10778 <!-- f8. -->
10779 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
10780 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
10781 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
10782 by the government would allow the government unending power to
10783 regulate commerce&mdash;the limitation to interstate commerce
10784 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
10785 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
10786 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights&mdash;the
10787 limitation to <quote>limited times</quote> notwithstanding.
10788 </para></footnote>
10789 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
10790 yield the conclusion that Congress
10791 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
10792 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
10793 term, then there would be no <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power over
10794 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
10795 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
10796 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
10797 term of existing copyrights.
10798 </para>
10799 <para>
10800 <emphasis>If</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
10801 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> stood for
10802 politics&mdash;a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
10803 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
10804 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
10805 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
10806 demonstrating the <quote>fidelity</quote> in such an interpretation of the
10807 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
10808 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
10809 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
10810 were going to be petty politicians.
10811 </para>
10812 <para>
10813 <emphasis role='strong'>Now let's pause</emphasis> for a moment to
10814 make sure we understand what the argument in
10815 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
10816 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
10817 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
10818 piracy&mdash;piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
10819 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
10820 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
10821 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
10822 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
10823 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
10824 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
10825 power&mdash;expressed through the power of lobbyists' money&mdash;to
10826 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
10827 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
10828 piracy that affects us all.
10829 </para>
10830 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association</primary></indexterm>
10831 <para>
10832 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
10833
10834 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
10835 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
10836 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than <quote>legal piracy.</quote><footnote><para>
10837 <!-- f9. -->
10838 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
10839 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available
10840 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #51</ulink>.
10841 </para></footnote>
10842 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
10843 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
10844 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
10845 charter.
10846 </para>
10847 <para>
10848 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
10849 copyright
10850 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
10851 influence
10852 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
10853 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
10854 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
10855 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
10856 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
10857 bought to extend them again.
10858 </para>
10859 <para>
10860 <emphasis role='strong'>It is valuable</emphasis> copyrights that are
10861 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
10862 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.</quote> These works are too valuable for
10863 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
10864 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
10865 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
10866 the 1920s and 1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
10867 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
10868 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
10869 and no longer available as a result.
10870 </para>
10871 <para>
10872 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to
10873 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
10874 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
10875 copyright holders for that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
10876 But the law and its effect were not limited to that 2 percent. The law
10877 extended the terms of copyright generally.<footnote><para>
10878 <!-- f10. --> The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
10879 Congressional
10880 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
10881 of Petitioners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 7, available at
10882 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #52</ulink>.
10883 </para></footnote>
10884
10885 </para>
10886 <para>
10887 Think practically about the consequence of this
10888 extension&mdash;practically,
10889 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
10890
10891 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
10892 work. In 1930, 10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those
10893 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
10894 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
10895 remaining
10896 9,873. What would you have to do?
10897 </para>
10898 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
10899 <para>
10900 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were
10901 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
10902 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
10903 titles and authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration
10904 and renewal records for works published in 1930. That will produce a
10905 list of books still under copyright.
10906 </para>
10907 <para>
10908 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
10909 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
10910 </para>
10911 <para>
10912 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
10913 owners
10914 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
10915 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
10916 being at least a list?
10917 </para>
10918 <para>
10919 But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in
10920 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
10921 practically
10922 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
10923 thousands
10924 of such records&mdash;especially since the person who registered is
10925 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930!
10926 </para>
10927 <para>
10928 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,</quote> the
10929 apologists for the system respond. <quote>Why should there be a list of
10930 copyright owners?</quote>
10931 </para>
10932 <para>
10933 Well, actually, if you think about it, there <emphasis>are</emphasis>
10934 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
10935 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
10936 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
10937 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
10938 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
10939 what tangible property.
10940 </para>
10941 <para>
10942 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
10943 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
10944 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
10945
10946 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
10947 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
10948 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
10949 happen
10950 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
10951 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
10952 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
10953 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
10954 know quite well who owns what property.
10955 </para>
10956 <para>
10957 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
10958 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
10959 already
10960 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
10961 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
10962 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
10963 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
10964 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
10965 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
10966 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
10967 </para>
10968 <para>
10969 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
10970 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
10971 consequence
10972 for other creative works is much more dire.
10973 </para>
10974 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'><primary>Agee, Michael</primary></indexterm>
10975 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
10976 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films</primary></indexterm>
10977 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The</primary></indexterm>
10978 <para>
10979 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
10980 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
10981 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
10982 made between 1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, <citetitle>The Lucky Dog</citetitle>, is
10983 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923
10984 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
10985 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
10986 money. According to one estimate, <quote>Roach has sold about 60,000
10987 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's silent
10988 films.</quote><footnote><para>
10989 <!-- f11. -->
10990 See David G. Savage, <quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,</quote>
10991 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, <quote>Classic Movies,
10992 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
10993 Down Copyright Extension,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 9 October 2002.
10994 </para></footnote>
10995 </para>
10996 <para>
10997 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
10998 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
10999 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11000 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11001 </para>
11002 <para>
11003 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11004
11005 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11006 any continuing commercial value. The rest&mdash;to the extent it
11007 survives at all&mdash;sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11008 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11009 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11010 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11011 work available for distribution.
11012 </para>
11013 <para>
11014 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11015 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11016 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11017 it cost more than $10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11018 film in 1993, it can now cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of
11019 mm film.<footnote><para>
11020 <!-- f12. -->
11021 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11022 Supporting the Petitoners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11023 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01- 618), 12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11024 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11025 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, available at
11026 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #53</ulink>.
11027 </para></footnote>
11028
11029 </para>
11030 <para>
11031 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11032 important.
11033 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11034 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11035 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11036 locate the copyright owner.
11037 </para>
11038 <para>
11039 Or more accurately, <emphasis>owners</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11040 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11041 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11042 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11043 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11044 to these films is exceptionally high.
11045 </para>
11046 <para>
11047 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11048 copyright owner when she shows up?</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11049 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11050 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11051 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11052 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11053 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11054 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11055 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11056 </para>
11057 <para>
11058 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11059
11060 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11061 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11062 benefit
11063 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11064 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11065 the copyright expires.
11066 </para>
11067 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'/>
11068 <para>
11069 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11070 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11071 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11072 canisters
11073 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11074 than dust.
11075 </para>
11076 <para>
11077 <emphasis role='strong'>Of all the</emphasis> creative work produced
11078 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11079 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11080 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11081 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11082 the copyright acts as an <quote>engine of free expression.</quote>
11083 </para>
11084 <para>
11085 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11086 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11087 indicated,
11088 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11089 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11090 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11091 distributors,
11092 the commercial life ends.
11093 </para>
11094 <para>
11095 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11096 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes &amp; Noble, and
11097 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11098 between
11099 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11100 Friday
11101 night watching a 1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11102 of culture is important and valuable&mdash;for entertainment but also, and
11103 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11104 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11105 have, we need to have access to this history.
11106 </para>
11107 <para>
11108 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11109
11110 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11111 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11112 this context do no good.
11113 </para>
11114 <para>
11115 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11116 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11117 <emphasis>copyright-related use</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11118 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11119 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11120 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11121 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11122 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11123 was independent of copyright law.
11124 </para>
11125 <para>
11126 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11127 a film&mdash;the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs&mdash;were
11128 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11129 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11130 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11131 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11132 market didn't have more to offer.
11133 </para>
11134 <para>
11135 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11136 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11137 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11138 would not have interfered with anything.
11139 </para>
11140 <para>
11141 But this situation has now changed.
11142 </para>
11143 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11144 <para>
11145 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11146 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11147 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11148 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11149 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11150 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11151 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11152 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11153 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11154 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11155 </para>
11156 <para>
11157 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11158 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11159 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11160 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11161 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11162 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11163 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11164 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11165 written for a radically different context.
11166 </para>
11167 <para>
11168 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11169 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11170 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11171 <emphasis>copyright</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11172 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11173 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11174 context, copyright is serving no purpose <emphasis>at all</emphasis>
11175 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11176 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11177 </para>
11178 <para>
11179 You may well ask, <quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11180 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11181 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11182 culture widely?</quote>
11183 </para>
11184 <para>
11185 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11186 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes &amp; Noble
11187 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11188 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11189 of a library is to serve what <quote>the market</quote> would demand. But if you
11190 think the role of a library is bigger than this&mdash;if you think its
11191 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11192 particular bit of that culture or not&mdash;then we can't count on the
11193 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11194 </para>
11195 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'/>
11196 <para>
11197 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11198 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11199 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11200 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11201
11202 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11203 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11204 culture, 94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11205 and 1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11206 commercial market, if access is a value, then 6 percent is a failure
11207 to provide that value.<footnote><para>
11208 <!-- f13. -->
11209 Jason Schultz, <quote>The Myth of the 1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,</quote> 20
11210 December 2002, available at
11211 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #54</ulink>.
11212 </para></footnote>
11213
11214 </para>
11215 <para>
11216 <emphasis role='strong'>In January 1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11217 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11218 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11219 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (1)
11220 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11221 <quote>limited Times</quote> requirement, and (2) that extending terms
11222 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11223 </para>
11224 <para>
11225 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11226 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11227 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11228 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11229 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11230 </para>
11231 <para>
11232 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11233 copyrights be for <quote>limited Times</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11234 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11235 <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11236 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11237 terms that are <quote>limited.</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11238 to interpret the term <quote>limited Times</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11239 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11240 power to extend existing terms.
11241 </para>
11242 <para>
11243 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11244 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11245 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11246 whole, where the court will sit <quote>en banc</quote> to hear the case.
11247 </para>
11248 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David</primary></indexterm>
11249 <para>
11250 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11251 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11252
11253 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11254 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11255 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11256 overstepped its bounds.
11257 </para>
11258 <para>
11259 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11260 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11261 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11262 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11263 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11264 </para>
11265 <para>
11266 But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11267 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11268 was set for October of 2002. The summer would be spent writing
11269 briefs and preparing for argument.
11270 </para>
11271 <para>
11272 <emphasis role='strong'>It is over</emphasis> a year later as I write
11273 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
11274 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
11275 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
11276 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
11277 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
11278 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
11279 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
11280 client, Eric Eldred.
11281 </para>
11282 <para>
11283 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11284 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11285 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11286 mistake lost it.
11287 </para>
11288 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11289 <para>
11290 <emphasis role='strong'>The mistake</emphasis> was made early, though
11291 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
11292 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
11293 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
11294 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
11295 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11296 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11297 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11298 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11299 </para>
11300 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11301 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan</primary></indexterm>
11302 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11303 <para>
11304 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11305 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11306 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11307 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11308 told me, if we could make the issue seem <quote>important</quote> to the Supreme
11309 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11310 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against <quote>the
11311 most powerful media companies in the world.</quote>
11312 </para>
11313 <para>
11314 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
11315 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
11316 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
11317 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
11318 <quote>right</quote> as in <quote>true,</quote> I thought, but it is <quote>wrong</quote> as in <quote>it just shouldn't be
11319 that way.</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
11320 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
11321 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
11322 interpretation
11323 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
11324 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
11325 unconstitutional,
11326 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
11327 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
11328 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
11329 Constitution,
11330 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
11331 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
11332 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
11333 </para>
11334 <para>
11335 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
11336 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
11337 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
11338 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
11339 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
11340 why it was unconstitutional.
11341 </para>
11342 <para>
11343 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
11344
11345 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
11346 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
11347 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
11348 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
11349 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
11350 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
11351 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
11352 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
11353 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
11354 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
11355 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
11356 <emphasis>law</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
11357 the widest range of credible critics&mdash;credible not because they
11358 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
11359 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
11360 </para>
11361 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11362 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis</primary></indexterm>
11363 <para>
11364 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
11365 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
11366 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
11367 Congress. In November 1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
11368 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
11369 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
11370 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
11371 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
11372 to get bogged down?</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
11373 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
11374 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
11375 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
11376 </para>
11377 <para>
11378 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
11379 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
11380 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
11381 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
11382 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
11383 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
11384 </para>
11385 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
11386 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
11387 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
11388 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11389 <para>
11390 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
11391 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
11392
11393 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
11394 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/ Linux
11395 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
11396 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
11397 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
11398 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
11399 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
11400 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
11401 </para>
11402 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries</primary></indexterm>
11403 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union</primary></indexterm>
11404 <para>
11405 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
11406 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
11407 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
11408 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
11409 </para>
11410 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
11411 <para>
11412 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
11413 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
11414 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
11415 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
11416 clear.
11417 </para>
11418 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George</primary></indexterm>
11419 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
11420 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James</primary></indexterm>
11421 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11422 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton</primary></indexterm>
11423 <para>
11424 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
11425 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
11426 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
11427 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
11428 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
11429 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
11430 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
11431 nothing more than <quote>rent-seeking</quote>&mdash;the fancy term economists use
11432 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
11433 </para>
11434 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11435 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan</primary></indexterm>
11436 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen</primary></indexterm>
11437 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11438 <para>
11439 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
11440 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
11441 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
11442 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
11443 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
11444 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
11445 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
11446 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
11447
11448 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
11449 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
11450 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
11451 </para>
11452 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11453 <para>
11454 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
11455 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
11456 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
11457 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
11458 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
11459 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
11460 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
11461 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
11462 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
11463 confidence in our argument.
11464 </para>
11465 <para>
11466 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
11467 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these <quote>friends</quote> included
11468 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
11469 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
11470 copyright holders.
11471 </para>
11472 <para>
11473 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
11474 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either&mdash;they
11475 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
11476 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
11477 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
11478 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
11479 wanted to control.
11480 </para>
11481 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George</primary></indexterm>
11482 <para>
11483 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
11484 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
11485 Dr. Seuss's work&mdash; better than allowing it to fall into the
11486 public domain&mdash;because if this creativity were in the public
11487 domain, then people could use it to <quote>glorify drugs or to create
11488 pornography.</quote><footnote><para>
11489 <!-- f14. -->
11490 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11491 U.S. (2003) (No. 01-618), 19.
11492 </para></footnote>
11493 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
11494 <quote>protection</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
11495 to license <citetitle>Porgy and Bess</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
11496 Americans in the cast.<footnote><para>
11497 <!-- f15. -->
11498 Dinitia Smith, <quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
11499 Mouse Joins the Fray,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 28 March 1998, B7.
11500 </para></footnote>
11501 That's
11502 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
11503 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
11504 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
11505 </para>
11506 <para>
11507 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
11508 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
11509 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
11510 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
11511 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, <quote>Give us twenty years
11512 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
11513 better with them than anyone else.</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
11514 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
11515 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
11516 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
11517 </para>
11518 <para>
11519 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
11520 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
11521 copyrights&mdash;extensions that would further concentrate the market;
11522 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
11523 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
11524 </para>
11525 <para>
11526 <emphasis role='strong'>Between February</emphasis> and October, there
11527 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
11528 I set the strategy.
11529 </para>
11530 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
11531 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
11532 <para>
11533 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
11534 called <quote>the Conservatives.</quote> The other we called <quote>the Rest.</quote> The
11535 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
11536 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
11537 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
11538 five who had supported the <citetitle>Lopez/Morrison</citetitle> line
11539 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
11540 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
11541 </para>
11542 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11543 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
11544 <para>
11545 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
11546 Congress's power. These four&mdash;Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
11547 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer&mdash;had repeatedly argued that
11548 the Constitution
11549 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
11550 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
11551 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
11552 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
11553 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
11554 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
11555 </para>
11556 <para>
11557 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
11558 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
11559 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
11560 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
11561 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
11562 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
11563 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
11564 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
11565 sense.
11566 </para>
11567 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11568 <para>
11569 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
11570 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
11571 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
11572 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
11573 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
11574 these retrospective extensions.
11575 </para>
11576 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'/>
11577 <para>
11578 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
11579 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
11580 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
11581 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
11582 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
11583 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
11584 </para>
11585 <para>
11586 This analysis of <quote>the Rest</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
11587 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
11588 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
11589 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
11590 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation&mdash;the
11591 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
11592 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
11593 powers have limits.
11594 </para>
11595 <para>
11596 This then was the core of our strategy&mdash;a strategy for which I am
11597 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
11598 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
11599 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
11600 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
11601 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
11602 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
11603 supposed to be <quote>limited.</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
11604 reconcile <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> with
11605 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
11606 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
11607 be limited.
11608 </para>
11609 <para>
11610 <emphasis role='strong'>The argument</emphasis> on the government's
11611 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
11612 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
11613 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
11614 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
11615 that practice is unconstitutional.
11616 </para>
11617 <para>
11618 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
11619 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in 1831
11620 and in 1909. And of course, in 1962, Congress began extending
11621 existing
11622 terms regularly&mdash;eleven times in forty years.
11623 </para>
11624 <para>
11625 But this <quote>consistency</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
11626 extended
11627 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
11628 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
11629 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
11630 existing
11631 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
11632 restraint
11633 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
11634 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
11635 hesitated
11636 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
11637 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
11638 </para>
11639 <para>
11640 <emphasis role='strong'>Oral argument</emphasis> was scheduled for the
11641 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
11642 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
11643 <quote>mooted</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
11644
11645 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
11646 help in the case. Such <quote>moots</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
11647 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
11648 </para>
11649 <para>
11650 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
11651 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
11652 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
11653 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
11654 Congress
11655 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
11656 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
11657 this central idea.
11658 </para>
11659 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11660 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11661 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11662 <para>
11663 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
11664 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
11665 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
11666 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
11667 </para>
11668 <para>
11669 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
11670 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
11671 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
11672 the harm&mdash;passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
11673 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.</quote>
11674 </para>
11675 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11676 <para>
11677 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
11678 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
11679 right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
11680 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
11681 does the right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it is right. As
11682 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
11683 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
11684 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
11685 </para>
11686 <para>
11687 <emphasis role='strong'>The night before</emphasis> the argument, a
11688 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
11689 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
11690 culture. Hundreds stood in line
11691
11692 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
11693 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
11694 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
11695 </para>
11696 <para>
11697 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
11698 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
11699 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
11700 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
11701 congressmen
11702 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
11703 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
11704 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
11705 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
11706 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
11707 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
11708 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
11709 family of the Justices.
11710 </para>
11711 <para>
11712 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
11713 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
11714 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
11715 those enumerated powers had any limit.
11716 </para>
11717 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
11718 <para>
11719 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
11720 The history was bothering her.
11721 </para>
11722 <blockquote>
11723 <para>
11724 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
11725 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
11726 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
11727 practice that began with the very first act.
11728 </para>
11729 </blockquote>
11730 <para>
11731 She was quite willing to concede <quote>that this flies directly in the face
11732 of what the framers had in mind.</quote> But my response again and again
11733 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
11734 </para>
11735 <blockquote>
11736 <para>
11737 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
11738 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
11739 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
11740 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
11741 is yes.
11742 </para>
11743 </blockquote>
11744 <para>
11745 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
11746 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
11747 Kennedy, who observed,
11748 </para>
11749 <blockquote>
11750 <para>
11751 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
11752 the '76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
11753 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
11754 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
11755 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
11756 </para>
11757 </blockquote>
11758 <para>
11759 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
11760 student,
11761 I answered,
11762 </para>
11763 <blockquote>
11764 <para>
11765 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
11766 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
11767 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
11768 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
11769 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
11770 </para>
11771 </blockquote>
11772 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11773 <para>
11774 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
11775 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
11776 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
11777 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
11778 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
11779 </para>
11780 <para>
11781 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
11782 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> ruling,
11783 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
11784 </para>
11785 <para>
11786 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
11787 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
11788
11789 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
11790 </para>
11791 <blockquote>
11792 <para>
11793 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
11794 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
11795 </para>
11796 <para>
11797 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
11798 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
11799 domain
11800 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
11801 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
11802 into the Copyright Clause.
11803 </para>
11804 </blockquote>
11805 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.</primary></indexterm>
11806 <para>
11807 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
11808 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
11809 asked Solicitor General Olson,
11810 </para>
11811 <blockquote>
11812 <para>
11813 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11814 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
11815 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
11816 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11817 time.
11818 </para>
11819 </blockquote>
11820 <para>
11821 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
11822 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
11823 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
11824 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
11825 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
11826 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
11827 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
11828 Patent Clause&mdash; indeed, the very first case striking a law of
11829 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
11830 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
11831 Court to my side.
11832 </para>
11833 <para>
11834 <emphasis role='strong'>As I left</emphasis> the court that day, I
11835 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
11836 hundred questions I wished I had
11837
11838 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
11839 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
11840 optimistic.
11841 </para>
11842 <para>
11843 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
11844 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
11845 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
11846 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
11847 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
11848 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
11849 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
11850 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
11851 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
11852 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
11853 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court&mdash;in particular,
11854 the Conservatives&mdash;would feel itself constrained by the rule of
11855 law that it had established elsewhere.
11856 </para>
11857 <para>
11858 <emphasis role='strong'>The morning</emphasis> of January 15, 2003, I
11859 was five minutes late to the office and missed the 7:00 A.M. call from
11860 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
11861 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
11862 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
11863 majority. There were two dissents.
11864 </para>
11865 <para>
11866 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
11867 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
11868 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
11869 </para>
11870 <para>
11871 My <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
11872 money in the world against <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. And here
11873 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
11874 reasoning.
11875 </para>
11876 <para>
11877 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
11878 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
11879 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
11880 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
11881 even appear in the Court's opinion.
11882 </para>
11883 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
11884 <para>
11885
11886 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
11887 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
11888 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
11889 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
11890 </para>
11891 <para>
11892 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable&mdash;for her, and for Justice
11893 Souter. Neither believes in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
11894 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
11895 they had worked so hard to defeat.
11896 </para>
11897 <para>
11898 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
11899 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
11900 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
11901 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
11902 reconcile the two simply <emphasis>by not addressing the
11903 argument</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
11904 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
11905 followed from the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
11906 be limited, but in this context it would not.
11907 </para>
11908 <para>
11909 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
11910 they would respect? By what right did they&mdash;the silent
11911 five&mdash;get to select the part of the Constitution they would
11912 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
11913 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
11914 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
11915 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
11916 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
11917 the system we have.
11918 </para>
11919 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11920 <para>
11921 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
11922 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
11923 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
11924 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
11925 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
11926 the Court discounted the parallel&mdash;without explaining how the
11927 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
11928 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
11929 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
11930 </para>
11931 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11932 <para>
11933 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
11934 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
11935 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
11936 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
11937 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8
11938 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
11939 that the actual number was 99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
11940 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
11941 <quote>limited,</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
11942 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
11943 </para>
11944 <para>
11945 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
11946 because neither believed in the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
11947 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
11948 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
11949 Sentelle. It was <citetitle>Hamlet</citetitle> without the Prince.
11950 </para>
11951 <para>
11952 <emphasis role='strong'>Defeat brings depression</emphasis>. They say
11953 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
11954 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
11955 sorts.
11956 </para>
11957 <indexterm><primary>originalism</primary></indexterm>
11958 <para>
11959 It was first anger with the five <quote>Conservatives.</quote> It would have been
11960 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> didn't
11961 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
11962 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
11963 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
11964 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
11965 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is <quote>originalism</quote>&mdash;to
11966 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
11967 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
11968 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> and many other <quote>originalist</quote> rulings. Where was their
11969 <quote>originalism</quote> now?
11970 </para>
11971 <para>
11972 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
11973 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
11974 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
11975 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
11976
11977 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
11978 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
11979 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
11980 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
11981 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
11982 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
11983 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
11984 own principles.
11985 </para>
11986 <para>
11987 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
11988 myself.
11989 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
11990 the law as it is.
11991 </para>
11992 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11993 <para>
11994 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
11995 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
11996 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
11997 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
11998 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
11999 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12000 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12001 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12002 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12003 </para>
12004 <para>
12005 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12006 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12007 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12008 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12009 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12010 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12011 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12012 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12013 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12014 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12015 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12016 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12017 effort to persuade; but I
12018 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12019 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12020 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12021 should decide the issue.
12022 </para>
12023 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12024 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12025 <para>
12026 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12027 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12028 Kathleen Sullivan?
12029 </para>
12030 <para>
12031 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12032 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12033 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12034 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12035 </para>
12036 <para>
12037 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12038 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12039 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12040 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12041 have persuaded.
12042 </para>
12043 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12044 <para>
12045 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12046 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12047 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12048 case was a mistake. <quote>The Court is not ready,</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12049 issue should not be raised until it is.
12050 </para>
12051 <para>
12052 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12053 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12054 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12055 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12056 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12057 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12058 this case&mdash;a decision I had made four years before&mdash;was wrong.
12059 </para>
12060 <para>
12061 <emphasis role='strong'>While the reaction</emphasis> to the Sonny
12062 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12063 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12064 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12065 that battle over ideas. Where
12066
12067 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12068 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12069 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12070 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12071 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12072 harmful law. <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12073 </para>
12074 <blockquote>
12075 <para>
12076 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12077 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12078 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12079 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12080 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12081 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12082 </para>
12083 </blockquote>
12084 <para>
12085 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12086 hilarious images&mdash;of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12087 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced on the next page
12088 (<xref linkend="fig-18"/>). The <quote>powerful and wealthy</quote> line is a bit
12089 unfair. But the punch in the face felt exactly like that.
12090 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12091 </para>
12092 <figure id="fig-18">
12093 <title>Tom the Dancing Bug cartoon</title>
12094 <graphic fileref="images/18.png"></graphic>
12095 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12096 </figure>
12097 <para>
12098 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12099 quote from <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>. That <quote>grand experiment</quote> we call the
12100 <quote>public domain</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think, <quote>Honey,
12101 I shrunk the Constitution.</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12102 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12103 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12104 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12105 </para>
12106 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12107 </chapter>
12108 <chapter label="14" id="eldred-ii">
12109 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II</title>
12110 <para>
12111 <emphasis role='strong'>The day</emphasis>
12112 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12113 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12114 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was denied&mdash;meaning the case was
12115 really finally over&mdash;fate would have it that I was giving a
12116 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12117 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12118 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12119 wrote an op-ed piece.
12120 </para>
12121 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12122 <para>
12123 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12124 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12125 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12126 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12127 Justice Kennedy: <quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12128 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12129 that.</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12130 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12131 </para>
12132 <para>
12133 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12134 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12135 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12136 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12137 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12138 the work passed into the public domain.
12139 </para>
12140 <para>
12141 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12142 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12143 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12144 </para>
12145 <para>
12146 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12147 is either the <quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act</quote> or the <quote>Copyright
12148 Term Deregulation Act.</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12149 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12150 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12151 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $1. But for
12152 everything else, let the content go.
12153 </para>
12154 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12155 <para>
12156 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12157 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12158 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12159 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12160 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12161 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12162 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12163 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12164 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12165 the stupid harm of the present system.
12166 </para>
12167 <para>
12168 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12169 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12170 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12171 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12172 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12173 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12174 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12175 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12176 where copyright owners could be identified.
12177 </para>
12178 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12179 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12180 <para>
12181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12182 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
12183 linkend="property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12184 removed in 1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12185 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.<footnote><para>
12186 <!-- f1. -->
12187 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law</primary></indexterm>
12188 Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12189 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12190 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12191 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act,
12192 every text of the Convention has provided that <quote>the enjoyment and the
12193 exercise</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention <quote>shall not be subject
12194 to any formality.</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12195 embodied in Article 5(2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12196 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12197 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12198 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12199 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12200 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12201 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12202 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12203 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>International
12204 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12205 Press, 2001), 153&ndash;54. </para></footnote>
12206 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a <quote>natural right.</quote> Natural
12207 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12208 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12209 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12210 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12211 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12212 </para>
12213 <para>
12214 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12215 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12216 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12217 <quote>Walt Disney creativity</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12218 know what's protected and what's not.
12219 </para>
12220 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12221 <para>
12222 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12223 Berlin in 1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12224 Convention in 1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12225 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12226 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12227 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12228 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an <citetitle>i</citetitle> or cross a
12229 <citetitle>t</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12230 </para>
12231 <para>
12232 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12233 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12234 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12235 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12236 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12237 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12238 </para>
12239 <para>
12240 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12241 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12242 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12243 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12244 burden
12245 imposed upon creators.
12246 </para>
12247 <para>
12248 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was
12249 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12250
12251 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12252 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12253 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12254 the government. He has a property right over the table <quote>naturally,</quote>
12255 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12256 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12257 table.
12258 </para>
12259 <para>
12260 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12261 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12262 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12263 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12264 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12265 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12266 spread.
12267 </para>
12268 <para>
12269 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12270 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12271 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12272 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12273 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12274 important reason to secure registration&mdash;both because it makes
12275 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12276 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12277 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12278 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12279 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12280 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12281 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12282 system of protection for property generally.
12283 </para>
12284 <para>
12285 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12286 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12287 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12288 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12289 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12290 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12291 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12292 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12293
12294 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12295 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12296 <emphasis>lawyer</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12297 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
12298 </para>
12299 <para>
12300 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12301 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12302 didn't <quote>get.</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
12303 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
12304 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, <quote>short,</quote> then this
12305 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
12306 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
12307 be presumptively uncontrolled.
12308 </para>
12309 <para>
12310 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
12311 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
12312 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
12313 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
12314 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
12315 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
12316 seen before <emphasis>because there are no formalities</emphasis>.
12317 </para>
12318 <para>
12319 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
12320 it is worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
12321 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
12322 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
12323 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
12324 </para>
12325 <para>
12326 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
12327 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
12328 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
12329 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
12330 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you.
12331 </para>
12332 <para>
12333 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
12334 registering the work mean that the $1 is really misleading? Isn't the
12335 hassle worth more than $1? Isn't that the real problem with
12336 registration?
12337 </para>
12338 <para>
12339 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
12340 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
12341 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
12342
12343 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
12344 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
12345 address the real problem of <emphasis>governments</emphasis> standing
12346 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
12347 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
12348 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
12349 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
12350 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
12351 upon historical data, that system would move up to 98 percent of
12352 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
12353 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
12354 </para>
12355 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12356 <para>
12357 <emphasis role='strong'>When Steve Forbes</emphasis> endorsed the
12358 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
12359 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
12360 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
12361 willing to take the first step.
12362 </para>
12363 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe</primary></indexterm>
12364 <para>
12365 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
12366 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
12367 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
12368 possible. In May 2003, it looked as if the bill would be
12369 introduced. On May 16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, <quote>we are
12370 close.</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
12371 something good might happen here.
12372 </para>
12373 <para>
12374 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
12375 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
12376 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
12377 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
12378 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
12379 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
12380 </para>
12381 <para>
12382 The MPAA argued first that Congress had <quote>firmly rejected the central
12383 concept in the proposed bill</quote>&mdash;that copyrights be renewed. That
12384 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's <quote>firm rejection</quote> had occurred
12385 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
12386 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
12387 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
12388 owners&mdash;apparently those who could not afford the $1 fee. Third,
12389 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
12390 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
12391 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
12392 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
12393 off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
12394 argued that the bill would impose <quote>enormous</quote> costs, since a
12395 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
12396 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
12397 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
12398 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
12399 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
12400 film is a valid derivative use.
12401 </para>
12402 <para>
12403 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
12404 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
12405 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
12406 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
12407 or not&mdash;a controversial claim in any case&mdash;unless they know
12408 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
12409 </para>
12410 <para>
12411 <emphasis role='strong'>At the beginning</emphasis> of this book, I
12412 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
12413 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
12414 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
12415 opposition&mdash;the power of the side that fought to defend the
12416 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
12417 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
12418 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
12419 </para>
12420 <para>
12421 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
12422 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
12423 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
12424 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
12425 sense?
12426 </para>
12427 <para>
12428
12429 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
12430 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
12431 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
12432 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
12433 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
12434 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
12435 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
12436 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
12437 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
12438 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
12439 </para>
12440 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin</primary></indexterm>
12441 <para>
12442 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
12443 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
12444 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
12445 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
12446 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
12447 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the <quote>Dark
12448 Content</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
12449 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
12450 </para>
12451 <para>
12452 What does this industry really want?
12453 </para>
12454 <para>
12455 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
12456 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
12457 protecting <emphasis>their</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
12458 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
12459 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
12460 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
12461 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
12462 content that doesn't require <emphasis>their</emphasis> permission
12463 first.
12464 </para>
12465 <para>
12466 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
12467 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
12468 its aim not the protection of <quote>property</quote> but the rejection of a
12469 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
12470 theirs. <emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
12471 theirs</emphasis>.
12472 </para>
12473 <para>
12474 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
12475 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
12476
12477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
12478 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
12479 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
12480 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
12481 and to share its own creation.
12482 </para>
12483 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
12484 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
12485 <para>
12486 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
12487 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
12488 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
12489 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
12490 block the progress of others.
12491 </para>
12492 <para>
12493 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
12494 <quote>property</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
12495 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
12496 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing <quote>permission
12497 society.</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
12498 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
12499 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
12500 </para>
12501 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
12502 </chapter>
12503 </part>
12504 <chapter label="15" id="c-conclusion">
12505 <title>CONCLUSION</title>
12506 <indexterm id="idxantiretroviraldrugs" class='startofrange'><primary>antiretroviral drugs</primary></indexterm>
12507 <indexterm id="idxhivaidstherapies" class='startofrange'><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies</primary></indexterm>
12508 <indexterm id="idxafricahivmed" class='startofrange'><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in</primary></indexterm>
12509 <para>
12510 <emphasis role='strong'>There are more</emphasis> than 35 million
12511 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
12512 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
12513 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
12514 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
12515 </para>
12516 <para>
12517 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
12518 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
12519 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
12520 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
12521 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
12522 the disease almost invisible.
12523 </para>
12524 <para>
12525 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
12526 United States, they cost between $10,000 and $15,000 per person per
12527 year. Today, some cost $25,000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
12528 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
12529 population:
12530 $15,000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
12531 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.<footnote><para>
12532 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, <quote>Final Report: Integrating
12533 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy</quote> (London, 2002),
12534 available at
12535 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
12536 release
12537 issued 9 July 2002, only 230,000 of the 6 million who need drugs in
12538 the developing world receive them&mdash;and half of them are in Brazil.
12539 </para></footnote>
12540 </para>
12541 <para>
12542 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
12543 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
12544 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
12545 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
12546 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
12547 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
12548 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
12549 </para>
12550 <para>
12551 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
12552 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
12553 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
12554 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
12555 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
12556 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
12557 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
12558 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
12559 changes.
12560 </para>
12561 <para>
12562 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
12563 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
12564 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
12565 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
12566 costs significantly below the market price.
12567 </para>
12568 <para>
12569 In 1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
12570 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
12571 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
12572 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
12573 Africa from India. This is called <quote>parallel importation,</quote> and it is
12574 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
12575 permitted within the European Union.<footnote>
12576 <para>
12577 <!-- f2. -->
12578 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
12579 Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37.
12580 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
12581 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12582 </para></footnote>
12583 </para>
12584 <para>
12585 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
12586 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
12587 characterized it, <quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa &hellip;
12588 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
12589 imports.</quote><footnote><para>
12590 <!-- f3. -->
12591 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
12592 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12593 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12594 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 14, available at
12595 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #56</ulink>. For a
12596 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
12597 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
12598 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess.,
12599 Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150&ndash;57 (statement of James
12600 Love).
12601 </para></footnote>
12602 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
12603 government asked South Africa to change the law&mdash;and to add
12604 pressure to that request, in 1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
12605 possible trade sanctions.
12606 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
12607 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
12608 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
12609 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
12610 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
12611 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
12612 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
12613 patent&mdash; pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
12614 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
12615 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
12616 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.<footnote><para>
12617 <!-- f4. -->
12618 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
12619 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12620 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12621 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 15. </para></footnote>
12622 </para>
12623 <para>
12624 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
12625 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
12626 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
12627 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
12628 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
12629 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
12630 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
12631 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
12632 </para>
12633 <para>
12634 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
12635 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
12636 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
12637 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
12638 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
12639 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save 15 to 30 million lives.
12640 </para>
12641 <para>
12642 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
12643 profits of United States drug companies&mdash;at least, not substantially. It
12644 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
12645 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
12646 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
12647 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
12648 by U.S. companies.
12649 </para>
12650 <para>
12651 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
12652 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
12653 argument
12654 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
12655 about the sanctity of property.<footnote><para>
12656 <!-- f5. -->
12657 See Sabin Russell, <quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
12658 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24
12659 May 1999, A1, available at
12660 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #57</ulink>
12661 (<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
12662 system of intellectual property protection</quote>); Robert Weissman, <quote>AIDS
12663 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
12664 Medicines,</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus</citetitle> 4:23 (August 1999), available at
12665 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #58</ulink>
12666 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, <quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
12667 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
12668 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
12669 Symposium Journal</citetitle> (Spring 2001): 175.
12670 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
12671 </para></footnote>
12672 It was because <quote>intellectual property</quote> would be violated that these
12673 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
12674 importance of <quote>intellectual property</quote> that led these government actors
12675 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
12676 </para>
12677 <para>
12678 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
12679 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
12680 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
12681 direct cost would be to speed the death of 15 to 30 million Africans,
12682 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the <quote>sanctity</quote> of an
12683 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
12684 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
12685 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
12686 </para>
12687 <para>
12688 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
12689 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
12690 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
12691 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
12692 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system&mdash;
12693 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
12694 </para>
12695 <para>
12696 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
12697 drug companies would love&mdash;they say, and I believe them&mdash;to
12698 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
12699 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
12700 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
12701 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
12702 </para>
12703 <para>
12704 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
12705 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
12706 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, <quote>How
12707 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $1 a pill, but the same
12708 drug would cost an American $1,500?</quote> Because there is no <quote>sound
12709 bite</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
12710 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
12711 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
12712 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
12713 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
12714 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
12715 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal&mdash;the sanctity of an
12716 idea called <quote>intellectual property.</quote>
12717 </para>
12718 <para>
12719 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
12720 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
12721 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
12722 What is the argument?
12723 </para>
12724 <para>
12725 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
12726 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
12727 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
12728 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
12729 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
12730 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
12731 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
12732 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
12733 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
12734 were balanced in just this sense.
12735 </para>
12736 <para>
12737 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
12738 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
12739 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
12740 our tradition, now reigns in this culture&mdash;bizarrely, and with
12741 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
12742 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
12743 </para>
12744 <indexterm startref="idxafricahivmed" class='endofrange'/>
12745 <indexterm startref="idxhivaidstherapies" class='endofrange'/>
12746 <indexterm startref="idxantiretroviraldrugs" class='endofrange'/>
12747 <para>
12748 <emphasis role='strong'>A simple idea</emphasis> blinds us, and under
12749 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
12750 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
12751 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
12752 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
12753 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
12754 control of that property removes our
12755 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
12756 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
12757 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
12758 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
12759 this common sense open its eyes.
12760 </para>
12761 <para>
12762 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
12763 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
12764 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
12765 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
12766 to fight <quote>piracy,</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
12767 the idea of <quote>creative property,</quote> while transforming real creators into
12768 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
12769 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
12770 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
12771 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
12772 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
12773 produce the <quote>perfect storm</quote> for free culture.
12774 </para>
12775 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>public projects in</secondary></indexterm>
12776 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)</primary></indexterm>
12777 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust</primary></indexterm>
12778 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web</primary></indexterm>
12779 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System</primary></indexterm>
12780 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12781 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
12782 <para>
12783 <emphasis role='strong'>In August 2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
12784 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
12785 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.<footnote><para>
12786 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>,
12787 August 2003, E1, available at
12788 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #59</ulink>; William New, <quote>Global Group's
12789 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
12790 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
12791 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #60</ulink>; William New, <quote>U.S. Official
12792 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
12793 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
12794 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #61</ulink>.
12795 </para></footnote>
12796 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
12797 a meeting to discuss <quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
12798 goods.</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
12799 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
12800 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
12801 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
12802 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
12803 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
12804 that I describe in the Afterword. It included a project to develop
12805 single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs), which are thought to have
12806 great significance in biomedical research. (That nonprofit project
12807 comprised a consortium of the Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and
12808 technological companies, including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
12809 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
12810 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
12811 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
12812 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
12813 in the early 1980s. And it included <quote>open source and free software.</quote>
12814 <indexterm><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
12815 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
12816 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
12817 </para>
12818 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'/>
12819 <para>
12820 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
12821 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
12822 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
12823 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
12824 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
12825 </para>
12826 <para>
12827 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.<footnote><para>
12828 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
12829 meeting.
12830 </para></footnote>
12831 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
12832 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
12833 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
12834 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
12835 property issues.
12836 </para>
12837 <para>
12838 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
12839 about WIPO. In February 2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
12840 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
12841 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
12842 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
12843 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
12844 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
12845 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
12846 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
12847 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
12848 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
12849 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
12850 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
12851 talk about an <quote>Information Society</quote> unless one also talked about the
12852 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
12853 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
12854 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
12855 stuff of
12856 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
12857 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
12858 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
12859 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
12860 </para>
12861 <para>
12862 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
12863 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
12864 thus the meeting about <quote>open and collaborative projects to create
12865 public goods</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
12866 </para>
12867 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
12868 <para>
12869 But there is one project within that list that is highly
12870 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is <quote>open source
12871 and free software.</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
12872 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
12873 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
12874 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
12875 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
12876 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
12877 rather than <quote>proprietary software,</quote> for their own internal uses.
12878 </para>
12879 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft</quote> licenses</primary></indexterm>
12880 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12881 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12882 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
12883 <para>
12884 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
12885 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
12886 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
12887 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
12888 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
12889 operating system, the most famous bit of <quote>free software</quote>&mdash;and IBM
12890 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support <quote>open source and
12891 free software</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
12892 to support a mode of software development that is different from
12893 Microsoft's.<footnote><para>
12894 <!-- f8. -->
12895 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
12896 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
12897 <quote>open source</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
12898 principal opposition is to <quote>free software</quote> licensed under a <quote>copyleft</quote>
12899 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
12900 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, <quote>The Future
12901 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
12902 Toward Open Source Software</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
12903 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
12904 Public Policy Research, 2002), 69, available at
12905 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #62</ulink>. See also
12906 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, <citetitle>The Commercial Software
12907 Model</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (3
12908 May 2001), available at
12909 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #63</ulink>.
12910 </para></footnote>
12911 </para>
12912 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)</primary></indexterm>
12913 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)</primary></indexterm>
12914 <para>
12915 More important for our purposes, to support <quote>open source and free
12916 software</quote> is not to oppose copyright. <quote>Open source and free software</quote>
12917 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
12918 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
12919 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
12920 by
12921 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
12922 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
12923 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
12924 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
12925 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
12926 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
12927 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
12928 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
12929 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
12930 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
12931 </para>
12932 <indexterm><primary>Krim, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
12933 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by</secondary></indexterm>
12934 <para>
12935 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
12936 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
12937 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
12938 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
12939 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
12940 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
12941 States government to veto the meeting.<footnote><para>
12942 <!-- f9. -->
12943 Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> available at <ulink
12944 url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #64</ulink>.
12945 </para></footnote>
12946 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
12947 </para>
12948 <para>
12949 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
12950 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
12951 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
12952 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
12953 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
12954 its lobbying efforts.
12955 </para>
12956 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
12957 <para>
12958 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
12959 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
12960 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
12961 Office, explained that <quote>open-source software runs counter to the
12962 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.</quote>
12963 She is quoted as saying, <quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
12964 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
12965 goals of WIPO.</quote>
12966 </para>
12967 <para>
12968 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
12969 </para>
12970 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
12971 <para>
12972 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
12973 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
12974 right called <quote>copyright</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
12975 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it <quote>runs counter</quote> to the mission
12976 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
12977 in understanding&mdash;the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
12978 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
12979 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
12980 </para>
12981 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs</primary></indexterm>
12982 <para>
12983 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to <quote>promote</quote>
12984 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
12985 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
12986 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
12987 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
12988 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
12989 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
12990 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
12991 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
12992 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
12993 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
12994 </para>
12995 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
12996 <para>
12997 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
12998 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
12999 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13000 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13001 <emphasis>their</emphasis> rights. If they want to <quote>waive</quote> or
13002 <quote>disclaim</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13003 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $20 billion to do
13004 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13005 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13006 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13007 to do with <emphasis>their</emphasis> property.
13008 </para>
13009 <indexterm id='idxboland' class='startofrange'><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13010 <para>
13011 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13012 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,</quote> she's
13013 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13014 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13015 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13016 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from <quote>waiving</quote> or
13017 <quote>disclaiming</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13018 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13019 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13020 way possible.
13021 </para>
13022 <para>
13023 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13024 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called <quote>feudalism.</quote> Under
13025 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13026 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13027 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13028 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13029 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13030 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13031 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13032 that control.
13033 </para>
13034 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13035 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13036 <para>
13037 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13038 choice we are now making about intellectual property.<footnote><para>
13039 <!-- f10. -->
13040 See Drahos with Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism</citetitle>, 210&ndash;20.
13041 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13042 </para></footnote>
13043 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13044 choice now is whether that information society will be
13045 <emphasis>free</emphasis> or <emphasis>feudal</emphasis>. The trend is
13046 toward the feudal.
13047 </para>
13048 <para>
13049 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13050 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13051 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13052 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13053 </para>
13054 <blockquote>
13055 <para>
13056 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13057 it should be (<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13058 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13059 not simply to promote intellectual property rights</quote>), not as it is. If
13060 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13061 say anything wrong. But in the world
13062 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13063 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13064 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13065 </para>
13066 </blockquote>
13067 <para>
13068 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13069 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13070 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13071 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13072 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13073 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13074 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13075 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13076 </para>
13077 <indexterm startref='idxboland' class='endofrange'/>
13078 <para>
13079 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13080 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13081 <quote>goal</quote> of a government should be <quote>to promote the right balance</quote> of
13082 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13083 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. <quote>Typical for
13084 an academic,</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13085 </para>
13086 <para>
13087 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13088 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13089 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13090 our own country's history).
13091 </para>
13092 <para>
13093 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13094 government should be to <quote>seek balance,</quote> then count me with the silly,
13095 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13096 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13097 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13098 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13099 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13100 not lies is just na&iuml;ve, then who have we, the most powerful
13101 democracy in the world, become?
13102 </para>
13103 <para>
13104 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13105 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13106 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13107 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13108 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13109 been part of our tradition for most of our history&mdash;free culture.
13110 </para>
13111 <para>
13112 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13113 </para>
13114 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
13115 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
13116 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted</primary></indexterm>
13117 <para>
13118 <emphasis role='strong'>There are moments</emphasis> of hope in this
13119 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13120 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13121 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13122 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13123 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13124 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13125 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing 700,000 letters were
13126 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13127 </para>
13128 <para>
13129 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13130 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13131 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13132 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13133 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13134 concentration in the media.
13135 </para>
13136 <para>
13137 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13138 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13139 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13140 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13141 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13142 </para>
13143 <para>
13144 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13145 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13146 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13147 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13148 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13149 range of rights&mdash;property rights of a historically extreme
13150 form&mdash;that makes their bigness bad.
13151 </para>
13152 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13153 <para>
13154 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13155 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13156 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13157 Americans have a long history of fighting <quote>big,</quote> wisely or not. That
13158 we could be motivated to fight <quote>big</quote> again is not something new.
13159 </para>
13160 <para>
13161 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13162 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13163 the idea of <quote>intellectual property.</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13164 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13165 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13166 called <quote>property</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13167 </para>
13168 <para>
13169 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13170 of our tragedy.
13171 </para>
13172 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob</primary></indexterm>
13173 <para>
13174 <emphasis role='strong'>As I write</emphasis> these final words, the
13175 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
13176 three hundred individuals.<footnote><para>
13177 <!-- f11. -->
13178 John Borland, <quote>RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers,</quote> CNET News.com, September
13179 2003, available at
13180 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #65</ulink>; Paul
13181 R. La Monica, <quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,</quote> CNN/Money, 8 September
13182 2003, available at
13183 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #66</ulink>; Soni
13184 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, <quote>Sued for a Song,
13185 N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among 261 Cited as Sharers,</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News</citetitle>, 9
13186 September 2003, 3; Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13187 Targets; Single Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13188 Defendants,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13189 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,</quote> <citetitle>Wired News</citetitle>, 10 September 2003,
13190 available at
13191 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #67</ulink>.
13192 </para></footnote>
13193 Eminem has just been sued for <quote>sampling</quote> someone else's
13194 music.<footnote><para>
13195 <!-- f12. -->
13196 Jon Wiederhorn, <quote>Eminem Gets Sued &hellip; by a Little Old Lady,</quote>
13197 mtv.com, 17 September 2003, available at
13198 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #68</ulink>.
13199 </para></footnote>
13200 The story about Bob Dylan <quote>stealing</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13201 finished making the rounds.<footnote><para>
13202 <!-- f13. -->
13203 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, <quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13204 Dylan Songs,</quote> Kansascity.com, 9 July 2003, available at
13205 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #69</ulink>.
13206 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13207 </para></footnote>
13208 An insider from Hollywood&mdash;who insists he must remain
13209 anonymous&mdash;reports <quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13210 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13211 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13212 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13213 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.</quote> Congressmen are
13214 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13215 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13216 kids who use a computer to share content.
13217 </para>
13218 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13219 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13220 <indexterm><primary>BBC</primary></indexterm>
13221 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in</primary></indexterm>
13222 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
13223 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto</primary></indexterm>
13224 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>public creative archive in</secondary></indexterm>
13225 <para>
13226 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13227 that it will build a <quote>Creative Archive,</quote> from which British citizens can
13228 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.<footnote><para>
13229 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,</quote> BBC press release,
13230 24 August 2003, available at
13231 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #70</ulink>.
13232 </para></footnote>
13233 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13234 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13235 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13236 country.<footnote><para>
13237 <!-- f15. -->
13238 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,</quote> Creative Commons Weblog, 6 August 2003,
13239 available at
13240 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #71</ulink>.
13241 </para></footnote>
13242 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13243 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13244 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13245 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13246 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13247 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13248 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13249 day into the Causbys.
13250 </para>
13251 <para>
13252 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
13253 potential is ever to be realized.
13254
13255 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
13256
13257 </para>
13258 </chapter>
13259 <chapter label="16" id="c-afterword">
13260 <title>AFTERWORD</title>
13261 <para>
13262
13263 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
13264 <emphasis role='strong'>At least some</emphasis> who have read this
13265 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
13266 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
13267 </para>
13268 <para>
13269 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
13270 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
13271 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
13272 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
13273 </para>
13274 <para>
13275 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
13276 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
13277 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists&mdash;all to tell this
13278 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
13279 is so important.
13280 </para>
13281 <para>
13282 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
13283 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
13284 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
13285 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
13286 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
13287 </para>
13288 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
13289
13290 <section id="usnow">
13291 <title>US, NOW</title>
13292 <para>
13293 <emphasis role='strong'>Common sense</emphasis> is with the copyright
13294 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
13295 extremes&mdash;as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
13296 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
13297 choice, then the warriors should win.
13298 </para>
13299 <para>
13300 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
13301 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
13302 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright&mdash;<quote>All Rights
13303 Reserved</quote>&mdash; and those who reject copyright&mdash;<quote>No Rights
13304 Reserved.</quote> The <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
13305 permission before you <quote>use</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The <quote>No
13306 Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
13307 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
13308 </para>
13309 <para>
13310 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
13311 tilted in the <quote>no rights reserved</quote> direction. Content could be copied
13312 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
13313 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
13314 the
13315
13316 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
13317 original design of the Internet was <quote>no rights reserved.</quote> Content was
13318 <quote>taken</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
13319 unprotected.
13320 </para>
13321 <para>
13322 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
13323 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
13324 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
13325 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
13326 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
13327 architecture made the effective default <quote>no rights reserved,</quote> the
13328 future architecture will make the effective default <quote>all rights
13329 reserved.</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
13330 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
13331 content requires permission. The <quote>cut and paste</quote> world that defines
13332 the Internet today will become a <quote>get permission to cut and paste</quote>
13333 world that is a creator's nightmare.
13334 </para>
13335 <para>
13336 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle&mdash;neither
13337 <quote>all rights reserved</quote> nor <quote>no rights reserved</quote> but <quote>some rights
13338 reserved</quote>&mdash; and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
13339 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
13340 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
13341 before.
13342 </para>
13343
13344 <section id="examples">
13345 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples</title>
13346 <indexterm id='browsing' class='startofrange'><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
13347 <para>
13348 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
13349 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
13350 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
13351 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
13352 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
13353 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
13354 to your neighbors or boss. The <quote>privacy</quote> of your browsing habits was
13355 assured.
13356 </para>
13357 <para>
13358 What made it assured?
13359 </para>
13360 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
13361 <para>
13362 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
13363 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>, your
13364 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
13365 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
13366 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
13367 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
13368 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
13369 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
13370 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
13371 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
13372 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
13373 (there is no law protecting <quote>privacy</quote> in public places), and in many
13374 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
13375 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
13376 </para>
13377 <indexterm><primary>Amazon</primary></indexterm>
13378 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet</primary></indexterm>
13379 <para>
13380 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
13381 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
13382 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
13383 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
13384 <quote>recently viewed</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
13385 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
13386 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any <quote>privacy</quote>
13387 protected by the friction disappears, too.
13388 </para>
13389 <para>
13390 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
13391 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
13392 people should have the <quote>right</quote> to browse in a library without the
13393 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
13394 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
13395 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
13396 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
13397 disappears.
13398 </para>
13399 <indexterm startref='browsing' class='endofrange'/>
13400 <para>
13401 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define <quote>privacy</quote>
13402 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
13403 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
13404 friction did.<footnote><para>
13405 <!-- f1. -->
13406
13407 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, <quote>Fair Information Practices and the
13408 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
13409 Law Review</citetitle> 1 (2001): par. 6&ndash;18, available at
13410
13411 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>
13412 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
13413 also Jeffrey Rosen, <citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
13414 in an Anxious Age</citetitle> (New York: Random House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs
13415 between technology and privacy).</para></footnote>
13416 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
13417 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
13418
13419 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
13420 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
13421 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
13422 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
13423 </para>
13424 <para>
13425 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
13426 movement. When computers with software were first made available
13427 commercially, the software&mdash;both the source code and the
13428 binaries&mdash; was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
13429 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
13430 care much about controlling their software.
13431 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13432 </para>
13433 <indexterm><primary>Stallman, Richard</primary></indexterm>
13434 <para>
13435 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
13436 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
13437 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
13438 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
13439 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
13440 people's work.
13441 </para>
13442 <para>
13443 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
13444 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
13445 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
13446 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
13447 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
13448 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
13449 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
13450 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
13451 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
13452 anything else?
13453 </para>
13454 <para>
13455 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
13456 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
13457 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
13458 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
13459 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
13460 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
13461 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
13462 </para>
13463 <para>
13464 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
13465 early 1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
13466 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
13467 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
13468 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
13469 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
13470 fundamentally weakened.
13471 </para>
13472 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus</primary></indexterm>
13473 <para>
13474 Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
13475 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
13476 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's <quote>Linux</quote>
13477 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
13478 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13479 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13480 </para>
13481 <para>
13482 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
13483 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
13484 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
13485 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
13486 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
13487 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
13488 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
13489 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
13490 byproduct.
13491 </para>
13492 <para>
13493 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
13494 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
13495 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
13496 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
13497 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
13498 what before had been passively guaranteed.
13499 </para>
13500 <para>
13501 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
13502 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
13503 scientific journals are produced.
13504 </para>
13505 <indexterm id="idxacademocjournals" class='startofrange'><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
13506 <para>
13507 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
13508 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
13509 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
13510 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
13511 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
13512 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
13513 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
13514 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
13515 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
13516 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
13517 and Westlaw are also free
13518 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
13519 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
13520 Court opinion through their respective services.
13521 </para>
13522 <para>
13523 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
13524 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
13525 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
13526 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
13527 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
13528 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
13529 access to material that is not in the public domain.
13530 </para>
13531 <para>
13532 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
13533 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
13534 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
13535 </para>
13536 <para>
13537 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
13538 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
13539 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
13540 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
13541 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
13542 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
13543 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
13544 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
13545 the technology of paper journals (architecture)&mdash;namely, that it
13546 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
13547 </para>
13548 <para>
13549 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
13550 that libraries not give the general public access to the
13551 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
13552 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
13553 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
13554 granted before.
13555 </para>
13556 <para>
13557 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
13558 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
13559 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
13560 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
13561 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
13562 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
13563 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
13564 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
13565 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
13566 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
13567 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
13568 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
13569 </para>
13570 <para>
13571 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
13572 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
13573 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
13574 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
13575 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
13576 presumptively a good&mdash;especially when it helps spread knowledge
13577 and science.
13578 </para>
13579 <indexterm startref="idxacademocjournals" class='endofrange'/>
13580
13581 </section>
13582 <section id="oneidea">
13583 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea</title>
13584 <indexterm id="idxcc" class='startofrange'><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
13585 <para>
13586 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
13587 increasing control effected through law and technology.
13588 </para>
13589 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University</primary></indexterm>
13590 <para>
13591 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
13592 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
13593 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
13594 <emphasis>reasonable</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
13595 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
13596 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
13597 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
13598 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
13599 make this possible.
13600 </para>
13601 <para>
13602 <emphasis>Simple</emphasis>&mdash;which means without a middleman, or
13603 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
13604 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
13605 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
13606 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
13607 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
13608 shared. These three expressions together&mdash;a legal license, a
13609 human-readable description, and
13610 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
13611 machine-readable tags&mdash;constitute a Creative Commons license. A
13612 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
13613 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
13614 that the person associated with the license believes in something
13615 different than the <quote>All</quote> or <quote>No</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
13616 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
13617 certain freedoms are given.
13618 </para>
13619 <para>
13620 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
13621 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
13622 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
13623 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
13624 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
13625 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (<quote>share and share
13626 alike</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
13627 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
13628 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
13629 </para>
13630 <para>
13631 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
13632 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
13633 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
13634 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
13635 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
13636 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
13637 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
13638 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
13639 a public domain.
13640 </para>
13641 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia</primary></indexterm>
13642 <para>
13643 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
13644 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
13645 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
13646 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
13647 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
13648 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
13649 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
13650 of content (<quote>content conducers,</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
13651 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
13652 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
13653 </para>
13654 <para>
13655 The aim is not to fight the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts. The aim is to
13656 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
13657 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
13658 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
13659 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
13660 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
13661 the background of digital technologies. New rules&mdash;with different
13662 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
13663 them&mdash;are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
13664 to begin to build those rules.
13665 </para>
13666 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
13667 <para>
13668 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
13669 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
13670 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
13671 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
13672 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
13673 </para>
13674 <para>
13675 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
13676 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1)
13677 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
13678 and (2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
13679 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (1) will download
13680 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2)
13681 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
13682 them (2)-goods. If there are more (2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the
13683 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
13684 <emphasis>increase</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
13685 </para>
13686 <para>
13687 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
13688 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
13689 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
13690 was a total success.
13691 </para>
13692 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)</primary></indexterm>
13693 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13694 <para>
13695 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
13696 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
13697 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
13698 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled <citetitle>Free for All</citetitle>,
13699 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
13700 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
13701 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
13702 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
13703 well.
13704 </para>
13705 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'/>
13706 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy</primary></indexterm>
13707 <indexterm><primary>rap music</primary></indexterm>
13708 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter</primary></indexterm>
13709 <para>
13710 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
13711 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
13712 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
13713 reasons. Many who use the <quote>sampling license</quote> do so because anything
13714 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
13715 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
13716 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
13717 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
13718 art&mdash;they, too, sample from others. Because the
13719 <emphasis>legal</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
13720 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
13721 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not <quote>allow</quote>
13722 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
13723 high<footnote><para>
13724 <!-- f2. -->
13725 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
13726 Culture Wars</citetitle> (2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
13727 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
13728 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>.
13729 </para></footnote>),
13730 these artists release into the creative environment content
13731 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
13732 </para>
13733 <para>
13734 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
13735 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
13736 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
13737 you are effectively saying you believe in the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote>
13738 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
13739 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
13740 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
13741 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
13742 this notion of <quote>Some Rights Reserved,</quote> and gives many the chance to
13743 say it to others.
13744 </para>
13745 <para>
13746 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
13747 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
13748 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
13749 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
13750
13751 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
13752 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
13753 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
13754 </para>
13755 <para>
13756 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
13757 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
13758 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
13759 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
13760 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
13761 steps are possible.
13762 </para>
13763 <para>
13764 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
13765 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
13766 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
13767 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
13768 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
13769 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
13770 creativity to spread more easily.
13771 </para>
13772 <indexterm startref="idxcc" class='endofrange'/>
13773
13774 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
13775 </section>
13776 </section>
13777 <section id="themsoon">
13778 <title>THEM, SOON</title>
13779 <para>
13780 <emphasis role='strong'>We will</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
13781 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
13782 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
13783 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
13784 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
13785 </para>
13786 <para>
13787 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
13788 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
13789 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
13790 to our end.
13791 </para>
13792
13793 <section id="formalities">
13794 <title>1. More Formalities</title>
13795 <para>
13796 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
13797 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
13798 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
13799 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
13800 </para>
13801 <para>
13802 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
13803 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
13804 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
13805 protected.
13806 </para>
13807 <para>
13808 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
13809 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
13810 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
13811 default is control, and <quote>formalities</quote> are banished.
13812 </para>
13813 <para>
13814 Why?
13815 </para>
13816 <para>
13817 As I suggested in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
13818 linkend="property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
13819 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
13820 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
13821 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
13822 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
13823 formalities were getting in the way.
13824 </para>
13825 <para>
13826 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
13827 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
13828 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
13829 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
13830 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
13831 trace&mdash; there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
13832 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
13833 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
13834 past. And thus, the <emphasis>lack</emphasis> of formalities forces
13835 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
13836 </para>
13837 <para>
13838 The law should therefore change this requirement<footnote><para>
13839 <!-- f1. -->
13840 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
13841 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
13842 adopted by other countries as well.</para></footnote>&mdash;but it
13843 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
13844 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
13845 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
13846 </para>
13847 <para>
13848 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
13849 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
13850 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
13851 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
13852 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
13853 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
13854 developed by others.
13855 </para>
13856
13857 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
13858
13859 <section id="registration">
13860 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL</title>
13861 <para>
13862 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
13863 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
13864 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
13865 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
13866 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
13867 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
13868 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
13869 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
13870 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
13871 panic&mdash;nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
13872 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
13873 </para>
13874 <para>
13875 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
13876 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
13877 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
13878 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
13879 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
13880 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
13881 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
13882 </para>
13883 <para>
13884 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
13885 There are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world.
13886 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
13887 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
13888 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
13889 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
13890 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
13891 with which registration occurs up.
13892 </para>
13893 <para>
13894 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
13895 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
13896 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
13897 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
13898 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
13899 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
13900 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
13901 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
13902 formality&mdash;while producing a database
13903 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
13904 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
13905 </para>
13906
13907 </section>
13908 <section id="marking">
13909 <title>MARKING</title>
13910 <para>
13911 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
13912 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
13913 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule&mdash;akin to
13914 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
13915 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
13916 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
13917 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
13918 uniformly across all media.
13919 </para>
13920 <para>
13921 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
13922 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
13923 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
13924 use the work.
13925 </para>
13926 <para>
13927 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
13928 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
13929 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
13930 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
13931 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
13932 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
13933 signal from the failure to mark&mdash;not the loss of the copyright, but the
13934 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
13935 </para>
13936 <para>
13937 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
13938 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
13939 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
13940 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
13941 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
13942 doesn't give permission.<footnote><para>
13943 <!-- f2. -->
13944 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
13945 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
13946 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
13947 </para></footnote>
13948 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be <quote>use unless someone
13949 complains.</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
13950 stop using the work in any new
13951 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
13952 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
13953 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
13954 their work.
13955 </para>
13956 <para>
13957 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
13958 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
13959 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
13960 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
13961 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
13962 </para>
13963 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>copyright marking of</secondary></indexterm>
13964 <para>
13965 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
13966 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
13967 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
13968 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
13969 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
13970 <emphasis>solely</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
13971 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
13972 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
13973 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
13974 other important functions.
13975 </para>
13976 <para>
13977 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
13978 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
13979 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
13980 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
13981 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
13982 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
13983 </para>
13984 <para>
13985 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
13986 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
13987 make things unclear.
13988 </para>
13989 <para>
13990 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
13991 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
13992 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
13993 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
13994 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
13995 that assertion at the appropriate time.
13996 </para>
13997
13998 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
13999 </section>
14000 </section>
14001 <section id="shortterms">
14002 <title>2. Shorter Terms</title>
14003 <para>
14004 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14005 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14006 natural authors.
14007 </para>
14008 <para>
14009 In <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14010 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14011 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14012 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14013 radical. <citetitle>The Economist</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14014 copyright term.<footnote><para>
14015
14016 <!-- f3. -->
14017 <quote>A Radical Rethink,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 366:8308 (25 January 2003): 15,
14018 available at
14019 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #74</ulink>.
14020 </para></footnote>
14021 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14022 </para>
14023 <para>
14024 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14025 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14026 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14027 terms.
14028 </para>
14029 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14030 <listitem><para>
14031 <!-- (1) -->
14032 <emphasis>Keep it short:</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14033 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14034 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14035 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14036 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14037 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14038 </para></listitem>
14039 <listitem><para>
14040 <!-- (2) -->
14041 <emphasis>Keep it simple:</emphasis> The line between the public
14042 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14043 fuzziness of <quote>fair use,</quote> and the distinction between <quote>ideas</quote> and
14044 <quote>expression.</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14045 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14046 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14047 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14048 <quote>lawyer-free zone</quote> makes the complexities of <quote>fair use</quote> and
14049 <quote>idea/expression</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14050 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14051 </para></listitem>
14052 <listitem>
14053 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions</primary></indexterm>
14054 <para>
14055 <!-- (3) -->
14056 <emphasis>Keep it alive:</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14057 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14058 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14059 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14060 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14061 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14062 pension.<footnote><para>
14063 <!-- f4. -->
14064 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14065 and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001),
14066 available at
14067 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #75</ulink>.
14068 </para></footnote>
14069 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14070 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14071 single form.
14072 </para></listitem>
14073 <listitem><para>
14074 <!-- (4) -->
14075 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14076 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14077 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14078 in 1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14079 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14080 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in 1923 than we
14081 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14082 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14083 the number of authors who wrote in 1923. Of course, we can increase
14084 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14085 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14086 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14087 creativity in 1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14088 we can do about that now. </para></listitem>
14089 </orderedlist>
14090 <para>
14091 These changes together should produce an <emphasis>average</emphasis>
14092 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until 1976,
14093 the average term was just 32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14094 same.
14095 </para>
14096 <para>
14097 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas <quote>radical.</quote> (After all, I
14098 call them <quote>extremists.</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14099 than the term under Richard Nixon. How <quote>radical</quote> can it be to ask for
14100 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14101 </para>
14102
14103 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14104
14105 </section>
14106 <section id="freefairuse">
14107 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use</title>
14108 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
14109 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
14110 <para>
14111 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14112 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14113 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14114 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14115 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14116 the emergence of that new technology.
14117 </para>
14118 <para>
14119 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors <quote>exclusive
14120 right</quote> to <quote>their writings.</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14121 right to <quote>their writings</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14122 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14123 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14124 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14125 though that movie is not <quote>my writing.</quote>
14126 </para>
14127 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin</primary></indexterm>
14128 <para>
14129 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it
14130 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14131 control translations and dramatizations of a work.<footnote><para>
14132 <!-- f5. -->
14133 Benjamin Kaplan, <citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14134 University Press, 1967), 32.
14135 </para></footnote>
14136 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14137 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14138 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14139 </para>
14140 <blockquote>
14141 <para>
14142 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14143 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14144 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14145 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.<footnote><para>
14146 <!-- f6. --> Ibid., 56.
14147 </para></footnote>
14148 </para>
14149 </blockquote>
14150 <para>
14151 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14152 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14153 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14154 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14155 Consider each limitation in turn.
14156 </para>
14157 <para>
14158 <emphasis>Term:</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14159 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14160 sense to protect John
14161
14162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14163 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14164 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14165 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14166 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14167 after the creative work is done.
14168 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
14169 </para>
14170 <para>
14171 <emphasis>Scope:</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14172 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14173 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14174 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14175 material. When all <quote>reuse</quote> of creative material was within the control
14176 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14177 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14178 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14179 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14180 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14181 the creative process. Smothers it.
14182 </para>
14183 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
14184 <para>
14185 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14186 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14187 foreseeable derivative rights&mdash;turning a book into a movie, or a
14188 poem into a musical score&mdash;it doesn't make sense to require
14189 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14190 much more sense.
14191 </para>
14192 <para>
14193 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14194 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14195 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14196 Paul Goldstein.<footnote>
14197 <para>
14198 <!-- f7. -->
14199 Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14200 Jukebox</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187&ndash;216.
14201 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul</primary></indexterm>
14202 </para></footnote>
14203 His view is that the law should be written so that
14204 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14205 </para>
14206 <para>
14207 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14208 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14209 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14210 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14211 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14212 </para>
14213 <para>
14214 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14215 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
14216 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
14217 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
14218 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
14219 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
14220 </para>
14221 </section>
14222
14223 <section id="liberatemusic">
14224 <title>4. Liberate the Music&mdash;Again</title>
14225 <para>
14226 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
14227 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
14228 is, to most people, most pressing&mdash;music. There is no other
14229 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
14230 battles around the sharing of music.
14231 </para>
14232 <para>
14233 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
14234 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
14235 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
14236 killer app&mdash;possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
14237 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
14238 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
14239 innovation on the network.
14240 </para>
14241 <para>
14242 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
14243 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
14244 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
14245 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
14246 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
14247 </para>
14248 <para>
14249 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
14250 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
14251 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
14252 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="piracy"/>, they enable
14253 four different kinds of sharing:
14254 </para>
14255 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
14256 <listitem><para>
14257 <!-- A. -->
14258 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
14259 for purchasing CDs.
14260 </para></listitem>
14261 <listitem><para>
14262 <!-- B. -->
14263 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
14264 on the way to purchasing CDs.
14265 </para></listitem>
14266 <listitem><para>
14267 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
14268 <!-- C. -->
14269 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14270 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
14271 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
14272 </para></listitem>
14273 <listitem><para>
14274 <!-- D. -->
14275 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14276 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
14277 owner plainly endorses.
14278 </para></listitem>
14279 </orderedlist>
14280 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
14281 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
14282 <para>
14283 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
14284 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
14285 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
14286 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
14287 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
14288 significantly weakened.
14289 </para>
14290 <para>
14291 As I said in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
14292 linkend="piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
14293 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
14294 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
14295 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
14296 networks.
14297 </para>
14298 <para>
14299 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
14300 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
14301 should respond.
14302 </para>
14303 <para>
14304 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
14305 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
14306 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
14307 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
14308 is cumbersome and slow&mdash;we in the United States are lucky to have
14309 broadband service at 1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
14310 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
14311 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
14312 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
14313 Internet is mainly just an idea.
14314 </para>
14315 <para>
14316 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
14317 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
14318 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
14319 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
14320 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
14321 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
14322 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
14323 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
14324 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
14325 where everywhere you are&mdash;except maybe the desert or the
14326 Rockies&mdash;you can instantaneously be connected to the
14327 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
14328 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
14329 </para>
14330 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over</primary></indexterm>
14331 <para>
14332 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
14333 give you access to content on the fly&mdash;such as Internet radio,
14334 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
14335 then, is the critical point: When it is <emphasis>extremely</emphasis>
14336 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
14337 <emphasis>easier</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
14338 access to content than it will be to download and store content
14339 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
14340 content</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
14341 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
14342 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
14343 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
14344 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
14345 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
14346 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
14347 paying for this content even though <quote>free</quote> content is available in the
14348 form of MP3s across the Web.<footnote><para>
14349 <!-- f8. -->
14350 See, for example, <quote>Music Media Watch,</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3
14351 April 2002, available at
14352 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #76</ulink>.
14353 </para></footnote>
14354
14355 </para>
14356 <para>
14357 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
14358 present: It is emphatically temporary. The <quote>problem</quote> with file
14359 sharing&mdash;to the extent there is a real problem&mdash;is a problem
14360 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
14361 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
14362 makers today to be <quote>solving</quote> this problem in light of a technology
14363 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
14364 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
14365 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
14366 artists get paid, during
14367
14368 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
14369 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
14370 and twenty-first-century technologies.
14371 </para>
14372 <para>
14373 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different <quote>problems</quote>
14374 here to solve. Let's start with type D content&mdash;uncopyrighted
14375 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
14376 <quote>problem</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
14377 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
14378 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
14379 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
14380 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
14381 order to eliminate kidnapping.
14382 </para>
14383 <para>
14384 Type C content raises a different <quote>problem.</quote> This is content that was,
14385 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
14386 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
14387 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
14388 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
14389 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
14390 way that returns something to the artist.
14391 </para>
14392 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
14393 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
14394 <para>
14395 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
14396 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
14397 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
14398 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
14399 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
14400 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
14401 from the author's perspective, this <quote>sharing</quote> of his content without
14402 his being compensated is less than ideal.
14403 </para>
14404 <para>
14405 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
14406 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
14407 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
14408 providers would be free, under this rule, to <quote>share</quote> that content,
14409 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
14410 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
14411 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
14412 </para>
14413 <para>
14414
14415 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
14416 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
14417 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
14418 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
14419 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
14420 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
14421 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
14422 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
14423 trade.
14424 </para>
14425 <para>
14426 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
14427 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
14428 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
14429 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
14430 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
14431 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
14432 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
14433 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
14434 </para>
14435 <para>
14436 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
14437 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
14438 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
14439 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
14440 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
14441 delivering and accessing content.
14442 </para>
14443 <para>
14444 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
14445 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
14446 </para>
14447 <para>
14448 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
14449 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
14450 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
14451 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
14452 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
14453 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
14454 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
14455 harmed the interests of the content industry.
14456 </para>
14457 <para>
14458 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
14459 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
14460 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
14461 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
14462 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
14463 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
14464 way to compensate those who are harmed.
14465 </para>
14466 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
14467 <para>
14468 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
14469 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.<footnote>
14470 <para>
14471 <!-- f9. -->
14472 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
14473 William Fisher, <citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities</citetitle> (last
14474 revised: 10 October 2000), available at
14475 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #77</ulink>; William
14476 Fisher, <citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
14477 Entertainment</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
14478 2004), ch. 6, available at
14479 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #78</ulink>. Professor
14480 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
14481 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
14482 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, <quote>Impose a
14483 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,</quote> available at
14484 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Who's Holding Back
14485 Broadband?</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
14486 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
14487 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, 26 February 2002,
14488 available at
14489 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, <citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
14490 Use Fee (IPUF)</citetitle>, 3 March 2002, available at
14491 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
14492 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 13 May
14493 2002, available at
14494 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, <quote>Getting Copyright Right,</quote>
14495 IEEE Spectrum Online, 1 July 2002, available at
14496 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #83</ulink>; Declan
14497 McCullagh, <quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,</quote> CNET News.com, 27 August
14498 2002, available at
14499 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #84</ulink>.
14500 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
14501 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
14502 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
14503 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
14504 debate by about a decade. See
14505 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #85</ulink>.
14506 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William</primary></indexterm>
14507 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
14508 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
14509 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'/>
14510 </para></footnote>
14511 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
14512 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
14513 would (1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
14514 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
14515 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
14516 develop (2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
14517 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (3) artists would be
14518 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (4) an appropriate
14519 tax.
14520 </para>
14521 <para>
14522 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
14523 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
14524 <citetitle>Promises to Keep</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
14525 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
14526 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
14527 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
14528 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
14529 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
14530 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
14531 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
14532 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
14533 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
14534 controlling access.
14535 </para>
14536 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'/>
14537 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
14538 <para>
14539 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
14540 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
14541 the system supports the widest range of <quote>semiotic democracy</quote>
14542 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
14543 other changes I described were accomplished&mdash;in particular, the
14544 limits on derivative
14545
14546 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
14547 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
14548 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
14549 allowed to do with the content itself.
14550 </para>
14551 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
14552 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore</primary></indexterm>
14553 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
14554 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>prices of</secondary></indexterm>
14555 <para>
14556 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
14557 <quote>harm</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
14558 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
14559 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
14560 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
14561 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat <quote>free</quote> by being
14562 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
14563 of songs at even the very high price of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents,
14564 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
14565 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
14566 Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a song. And no doubt
14567 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
14568 on-line.
14569 </para>
14570 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
14571 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast</secondary></indexterm>
14572 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
14573 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
14574 <indexterm><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in</secondary></indexterm>
14575 <para>
14576 This competition has already occurred against the background of <quote>free</quote>
14577 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
14578 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
14579 that, there is nothing impossible at all about <quote>competing with free.</quote>
14580 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
14581 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
14582 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
14583 theaters are often luxurious&mdash;with <quote>first class</quote> seats, and meals
14584 served while you watch a movie&mdash;as they struggle and succeed in
14585 finding ways to compete with <quote>free.</quote>
14586 </para>
14587 <para>
14588 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
14589 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
14590 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
14591 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
14592 innovators&mdash;ones who would have a right to the content, and would
14593 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
14594 the law.
14595 </para>
14596 <para>
14597 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
14598 </para>
14599 <para>
14600
14601 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
14602 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
14603 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
14604 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
14605 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
14606 create.
14607 </para>
14608 <para>
14609 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
14610 by
14611 </para>
14612 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14613 <listitem><para>
14614 <!-- 1. -->
14615 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
14616 </para></listitem>
14617 <listitem><para>
14618 <!-- 2. -->
14619 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
14620 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
14621 statute;
14622 </para></listitem>
14623 <listitem><para>
14624 <!-- 3. -->
14625 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
14626 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
14627 </para></listitem>
14628 </orderedlist>
14629 <para>
14630 But what if <quote>piracy</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
14631 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
14632 consumers continue to <quote>take</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
14633 something then?
14634 </para>
14635 <para>
14636 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
14637 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
14638 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
14639 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
14640 technology that is 95 percent secure and produces a market of size <citetitle>x</citetitle>,
14641 or (b) to have a technology that is 50 percent secure but produces a
14642 market of five times <citetitle>x</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
14643 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
14644 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
14645 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
14646 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
14647 pirates.
14648 </para>
14649 <para>
14650 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
14651 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
14652 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
14653
14654 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
14655 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
14656 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
14657 </para>
14658 </section>
14659
14660 <section id="firelawyers">
14661 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers</title>
14662 <para>
14663 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
14664 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
14665 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
14666 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
14667 </para>
14668 <para>
14669 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
14670 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
14671 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
14672 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
14673 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
14674 strong view queers the law.
14675 </para>
14676 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville</primary></indexterm>
14677 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of</secondary></indexterm>
14678 <para>
14679 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
14680 <quote>radical</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
14681 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
14682 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
14683 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
14684 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
14685 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
14686 Nimmer, thought it obvious.<footnote><para>
14687 <!-- f10. -->
14688 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Copyright's First Amendment</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
14689 Memorial Lecture), <citetitle>UCLA Law Review</citetitle> 48 (2001): 1057, 1069&ndash;70.
14690 </para></footnote>
14691
14692 </para>
14693 <para>
14694 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
14695 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
14696 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
14697 </para>
14698 <para>
14699 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
14700 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
14701 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
14702 the legal system are slight.<footnote><para>
14703 <!-- f11. -->
14704 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
14705 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
14706 leading him to question his own publicly stated
14707 position&mdash;twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
14708 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
14709 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
14710 J. Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
14711 Drive the Digital Marketplace</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002), (reviewing his
14712 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
14713 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?</quote> working paper, June 2003,
14714 available at
14715 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #86</ulink>.
14716 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
14717 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
14718 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
14719 <citetitle>Rethinking</citetitle>, 174&ndash;76.
14720 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
14721 </para></footnote>
14722 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
14723 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
14724 them it works.
14725 </para>
14726 <para>
14727 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
14728 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
14729 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
14730 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
14731 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
14732 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
14733 practically never be done.
14734 </para>
14735 <para>
14736 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
14737 billed at the largest firms at more than $400 per hour. How much time
14738 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
14739 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
14740 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
14741 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
14742 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
14743 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
14744 </para>
14745 <para>
14746 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
14747 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
14748 their duty to change the way the law works&mdash;or better, to change the
14749 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
14750 top 1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
14751 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
14752 </para>
14753 <para>
14754 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
14755 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
14756 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
14757 its review.
14758 </para>
14759 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
14760 <para>
14761 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
14762 technology&mdash;the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
14763 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
14764 technology&mdash;a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
14765 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
14766 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
14767 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
14768 </para>
14769 <para>
14770 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture&mdash;but it should
14771 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
14772
14773 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311 -->
14774 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
14775 simple pragmatic question: <quote>Will it do good?</quote> When challenged about
14776 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, <quote>Why not?</quote>
14777 </para>
14778 <para>
14779 We should ask, <quote>Why?</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
14780 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
14781 keep your lawyers away.
14782 </para>
14783 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
14784 </section>
14785 </section>
14786 </chapter>
14787 <chapter label="17" id="c-notes">
14788 <title>NOTES</title>
14789 <para>
14790 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
14791 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
14792 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
14793 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
14794 this book. For each link below, you can go to
14795 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
14796 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
14797 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
14798 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
14799 the material.
14800 </para>
14801
14802 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
14803 <?latex \theendnotes ?>
14804
14805 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
14806
14807 </chapter>
14808 <chapter label="18" id="c-acknowledgments">
14809 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS</title>
14810 <para>
14811 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
14812 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
14813 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
14814 to him that this book is dedicated.
14815 </para>
14816 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
14817 <para>
14818 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
14819 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
14820 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
14821 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
14822 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
14823 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
14824 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
14825 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
14826 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
14827 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
14828 critical eye on much of this.
14829 </para>
14830 <para>
14831 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
14832 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
14833 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
14834 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
14835 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
14836 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
14837 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
14838 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
14839 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
14840 </para>
14841 <para>
14842 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
14843 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
14844 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
14845 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
14846 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
14847 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
14848 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
14849 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
14850 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
14851 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
14852 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
14853 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
14854 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
14855 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
14856 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, <quote>Wink,</quote> Roger Wood, <quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,</quote>
14857 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
14858 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
14859 a bunch of great replies.)
14860 </para>
14861 <para>
14862 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
14863 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
14864 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
14865 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
14866 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
14867 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
14868 throughout this book.
14869 </para>
14870 <para>
14871 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
14872 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
14873 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
14874 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
14875 </para>
14876 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->
14877
14878 </chapter>
14879 <index></index>
14880 </book>