]> pere.pagekite.me Git - text-free-culture-lessig.git/blob - freeculture.xml
Another index entry.
[text-free-culture-lessig.git] / freeculture.xml
1 <?xml version='1.0' encoding='UTF-8' ?>
2 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29 -->
3 <!--
4 TODO
5 * indexterm primary
6 * replace '. . .' with something else
7 * emphasis ?
8 * quotes ?
9 -->
10 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC "-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.2//EN"
11 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.2/docbookx.dtd"
12 [
13 <!ENTITY copy "©">
14 <!ENTITY translationblock "">
15 ]>
16 <!--
17 -->
18
19 <book id="index" lang="en">
20 <bookinfo>
21 <title>Free Culture</title>
22
23 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
24
25 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
26 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY</subtitle>
27
28 <pubdate>2004-03-25</pubdate>
29
30 <releaseinfo>Version 2004-02-10</releaseinfo>
31
32 <authorgroup>
33 <author>
34 <firstname>Lawrence</firstname>
35 <surname>Lessig</surname>
36 </author>
37 </authorgroup>
38
39 <copyright>
40 <year>2004</year>
41 <holder>
42 Lawrence Lessig. This version of Free Culture is licensed under a
43 Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
44 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
45 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
46 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/</ulink>
47 </holder>
48 </copyright>
49
50 <abstract>
51 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR</title>
52 <para>
53 LAWRENCE LESSIG
54 (<ulink url="http://www.lessig.org/">http://www.lessig.org</ulink>),
55 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
56 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
57 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
58 (<ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/">http://creativecommons.org</ulink>).
59 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) and Code: And
60 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), Lessig is a member of
61 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
62 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
63 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
64 twice listed in BusinessWeek's "e.biz 25," and named one of Scientific
65 American's "50 visionaries." A graduate of the University of
66 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
67 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
68 Appeals.
69 </para>
70 </abstract>
71 </bookinfo>
72
73 <colophon>
74 <!-- PAGE BREAK 1 -->
75
76 <para>
77 You can buy a copy of this book by clicking on one of the links below:
78 </para>
79 <itemizedlist mark="number" spacing="compact">
80 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.amazon.com/">Amazon</ulink></para></listitem>
81 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.barnesandnoble.com/">B&amp;N</ulink></para></listitem>
82 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.penguin.com/">Penguin</ulink></para></listitem>
83 <!-- <ulink url="">Local Bookstore</ulink> -->
84 </itemizedlist>
85 <!-- PAGE BREAK 2 -->
86
87 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
88 <para>
89 ALSO BY LAWRENCE LESSIG
90 </para>
91 <para>
92 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
93 </para>
94 <para>
95 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
96 </para>
97
98 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
99 <para>
100 THE PENGUIN PRESS
101 </para>
102 <para>
103 NEW YORK
104 </para>
105
106 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
107 <para>
108 FREE CULTURE
109 </para>
110
111 <para>
112 HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND
113 THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN CULTURE
114 AND CONTROL CREATIVITY
115 </para>
116
117 <para>
118 LAWRENCE LESSIG
119 </para>
120
121 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
122 <para>
123 THE PENGUIN PRESS
124 </para>
125 <para>
126 a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc. 375 Hudson Street New
127 York, New York
128 </para>
129 <para>
130 Copyright &copy; Lawrence Lessig,
131 </para>
132 <para>
133 All rights reserved
134 </para>
135 <para>
136 Excerpt from an editorial titled "The Coming of Copyright Perpetuity,"
137 The New York Times, January 16, 2003. Copyright &copy; 2003 by The New York Times Co.
138 Reprinted with permission.
139 </para>
140 <para>
141 Cartoon by Paul Conrad on page 159. Copyright Tribune Media Services, Inc.
142 </para>
143 <para>
144 All rights reserved. Reprinted with permission.
145 </para>
146 <para>
147 Diagram on page 164 courtesy of the office of FCC Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
148 </para>
149 <para>
150 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
151 </para>
152 <para>
153 Lessig, Lawrence.
154 Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law to lock down
155 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
156 </para>
157 <para>
158 p. cm.
159 </para>
160 <para>
161 Includes index.
162 </para>
163 <para>
164 ISBN 1-59420-006-8 (hardcover)
165 </para>
166 <para>
167 1. Intellectual property&mdash;United States. 2. Mass media&mdash;United States.
168 </para>
169 <para>
170 3. Technological innovations&mdash;United States. 4. Art&mdash;United States. I. Title.
171 </para>
172 <para>
173 KF2979.L47
174 </para>
175 <para>
176 343.7309'9&mdash;dc22
177 </para>
178 <para>
179 This book is printed on acid-free paper.
180 </para>
181 <para>
182 Printed in the United States of America
183 </para>
184 <para>
185 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4
186 </para>
187 <para>
188 Designed by Marysarah Quinn
189 </para>
190
191 <para>
192 &translationblock;
193 </para>
194
195 <para>
196 Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of
197 this publication may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a
198 retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means
199 (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise),
200 without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and
201 the above publisher of this book. The scanning, uploading, and
202 distribution of this book via the Internet or via any other means
203 without the permission of the publisher is illegal and punishable by
204 law. Please purchase only authorized electronic editions and do not
205 participate in or encourage electronic piracy of copyrighted
206 materials. Your support of the author's rights is appreciated.
207 </para>
208 </colophon>
209
210 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
211 <dedication>
212 <para>
213 To Eric Eldred&mdash;whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
214 it continues still.
215 </para>
216
217 <para>
218 <figure id="CreativeCommons">
219 <title>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved</title>
220 <graphic fileref="images/cc.png"></graphic>
221 </figure>
222 </para>
223 </dedication>
224
225 <toc id="toc"></toc>
226
227 <lot>
228 <title>List of figures</title>
229 </lot>
230
231 <!--
232 c PREFACE xiii
233 c INTRODUCTION
234 c "PIRACY"
235 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
236 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
237 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
238 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
239 2 Film
240 2 Recorded Music
241 2 Radio
242 2 Cable TV
243 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
244 2 Piracy I
245 2 Piracy II
246 c "PROPERTY"
247 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
248 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
249 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
250 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
251 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
252 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
253 2 Beginnings
254 2 Law: Duration
255 2 Law: Scope
256 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
257 2 Architecture and Law: Force
258 2 Market: Concentration
259 2 Together
260 c PUZZLES
261 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
262 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
263 2 Constraining Creators
264 2 Constraining Innovators
265 2 Corrupting Citizens
266 c BALANCES
267 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
268 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
269 c CONCLUSION
270 c AFTERWORD
271 1 Us, Now
272 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
273 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
274 1 Them, Soon
275 2 1. More Formalities
276 3 Registration and Renewal
277 3 Marking
278 2 2. Shorter Terms
279 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
280 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
281 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
282 c NOTES
283 c ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
284 c INDEX
285 -->
286
287 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
288
289 <preface id="preface">
290 <title>PREFACE</title>
291 <indexterm id="idxpoguedavid" class='startofrange'>
292 <primary>Pogue, David</primary>
293 </indexterm>
294 <para>
295 At the end of his review of my first book, Code: And Other Laws of
296 Cyberspace, David Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless
297 technical and computer-related texts, wrote this:
298 </para>
299 <blockquote>
300 <para>
301 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
302 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
303 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
304 system, you can always flip off the modem.<footnote id="preface01"><para>
305 David Pogue, "Don't Just Chat, Do Something," New York Times, 30 January 2000.
306 </para></footnote>
307 </para>
308 </blockquote>
309 <para>
310 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book&mdash;that
311 software, or "code," functioned as a kind of law&mdash;and his review
312 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
313 could always "drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome"-like simply flip a
314 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
315 any troubles that exist in that space wouldn't "affect" us anymore.
316 </para>
317 <para>
318 Pogue might have been right in 1999&mdash;I'm skeptical, but maybe.
319 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now: Free Culture
320 is about the troubles the Internet causes even after the modem is turned
321 <!-- PAGE BREAK 12 -->
322 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
323 on-line have fundamentally affected "people who aren't online." There
324 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
325 </para>
326 <indexterm startref="idxpoguedavid" class='endofrange'/>
327 <para>
328 But unlike Code, the argument here is not much about the Internet
329 itself. It is instead about the consequence of the Internet to a part of
330 our tradition that is much more fundamental, and, as hard as this is for
331 a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more important.
332 </para>
333 <para>
334 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
335 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of "free culture"&mdash;not
336 "free" as in "free beer" (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
337 free software movement<footnote>
338 <para>
339 Richard M. Stallman, Free Software, Free Societies 57 (Joshua Gay, ed. 2002).
340 </para></footnote>), but "free" as in "free speech," "free markets," "free
341 trade," "free enterprise," "free will," and "free elections." A free
342 culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does this
343 directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
344 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
345 follow-on creators and innovators remain as free as possible from the
346 control of the past. A free culture is not a culture without property,
347 just as a free market is not a market in which everything is free. The
348 opposite of a free culture is a "permission culture"&mdash;a culture in
349 which creators get to create only with the permission of the powerful,
350 or of creators from the past.
351 </para>
352 <para>
353 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not "we"
354 on the Left or "you" on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
355 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
356 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
357 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
358 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
359 culture deem fundamental.
360 </para>
361 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
362 <para>
363 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
364 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
365 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
366 generated more than 700,000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
367 As William Safire described marching "uncomfortably alongside CodePink
368 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
369 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens," he formulated perhaps
370 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
371 he asked,
372 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
373 </para>
374 <blockquote>
375 <para>
376 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
377 power&mdash;political, corporate, media, cultural&mdash;should be anathema to
378 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
379 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
380 the greatest expression of democracy.<footnote><para> William Safire,
381 "The Great Media Gulp," New York Times, 22 May 2003.
382 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
383 </para></footnote>
384 </para>
385 </blockquote>
386 <para>
387 This idea is an element of the argument of Free Culture, though my
388 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
389 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
390 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
391 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
392 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
393 you&mdash;whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
394 Safire's left or on his right. The inspiration for the title and for
395 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
396 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
397 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in Free Software, Free
398 Society, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
399 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
400 that this work is "merely" derivative.
401 </para>
402 <para>
403 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
404 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
405 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
406 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
407 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
408 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
409 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
410 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
411
412 <!-- PAGE BREAK 14 -->
413 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
414 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
415 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
416 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
417 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
418 what I advance here.
419 </para>
420 <para>
421 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
422 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
423 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
424 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
425 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
426 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
427 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
428 book is written.
429 </para>
430
431 </preface>
432 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
433
434 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
435 <chapter id="c-introduction">
436 <title>INTRODUCTION</title>
437 <para>
438 On December 17, 1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
439 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
440 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
441 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
442 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
443 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
444 </para>
445 <para>
446 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
447 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
448 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
449 and all the space above, to "an indefinite extent, upwards."<footnote><para>
450 St. George Tucker, Blackstone's Commentaries 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
451 Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18.
452 </para></footnote>
453 For many
454 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
455 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
456 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
457 </para>
458 <para>
459 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
460 law&mdash;deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
461 by the most important legal thinkers of our past&mdash;mattered. If
462 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
463 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
464 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
465 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
466 </para>
467 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
468 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
469 <para>
470 In 1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
471 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
472 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
473 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
474 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
475 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
476 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to "an indefinite
477 extent, upwards," then the government was trespassing on their
478 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
479 </para>
480 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
481 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
482 <para>
483 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
484 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
485 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
486 "taking" of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
487 that "it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
488 the land extended to the periphery of the universe." But Justice Douglas
489 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
490 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
491 </para>
492 <blockquote>
493 <para>
494 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
495 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
496 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
497 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
498 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
499 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
500 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
501 the public has a just claim.<footnote>
502 <para>
503 United States v. Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. The Court did find
504 that there could be a "taking" if the government's use of its land
505 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
506 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, "(Intellectual)
507 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
508 Authorship," Stanford Law Review 48 (1996): 1293, 1333. See also Paul
509 Goldstein, Real Property (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press, 1984),
510 1112&ndash;13.
511 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
512 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
513 </para></footnote>
514 </para>
515 </blockquote>
516 <para>
517 "Common sense revolts at the idea."
518 </para>
519 <para>
520 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
521 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
522 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 18 -->
524 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: "Common sense revolts
525 at the idea." But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
526 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
527 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
528 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
529 </para>
530 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
531 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
532 <para>
533 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
534 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
535 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
536 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
537 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
538 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
539 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
540 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
541 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by "what
542 seemed reasonable" given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
543 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
544 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
545 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
546 end, the force of what seems "obvious" to everyone else&mdash;the power of
547 "common sense"&mdash;would prevail. Their "private interest" would not be
548 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
549 </para>
550 <para>
551 Edwin Howard Armstrong is one of America's forgotten inventor
552 geniuses. He came to the great American inventor scene just after the
553 titans Thomas Edison and Alexander Graham Bell. But his work in
554 the area of radio technology was perhaps the most important of any
555 single inventor in the first fifty years of radio. He was better educated
556 than Michael Faraday, who as a bookbinder's apprentice had discovered
557 electric induction in 1831. But he had the same intuition about
558 how the world of radio worked, and on at least three occasions,
559 Armstrong invented profoundly important technologies that advanced our
560 understanding of radio.
561 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
562 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham</primary></indexterm>
563 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
564 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael</primary></indexterm>
565 </para>
566 <para>
567 On the day after Christmas, 1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
568 for his most significant invention&mdash;FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
569 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
570 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
571 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
572 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
573 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
574 much less transmitter power and static.
575 </para>
576 <para>
577 On November 5, 1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
578 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
579 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
580 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
581 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
582 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
583 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
584 "This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
585 frequency modulation at two and a half meters."
586 </para>
587 <para>
588 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
589 </para>
590 <blockquote>
591 <para>
592 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
593 sounded like a glass of water being poured. . . . A paper was crumpled
594 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
595 fire. . . . Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
596 and guitar number were performed. . . . The music was projected with a
597 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio "music
598 box."<footnote><para>
599 Lawrence Lessing, Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong
600 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209.
601 </para></footnote>
602 </para>
603 </blockquote>
604 <para>
605 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
606 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
607 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
608 AM radio market. By 1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
609 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
610 a handful of networks.
611 <!-- PAGE BREAK 20 -->
612 </para>
613 <para>
614 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
615 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
616 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
617 that removed static from "radio." But when Armstrong demonstrated
618 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
619 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
620 </para>
621 <blockquote>
622 <para>
623 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
624 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
625 revolution&mdash; start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
626 RCA.<footnote><para> See "Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
627 Electronic Era," First Electronic Church of America, at
628 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
629
630 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #1</ulink>.
631 </para></footnote>
632 </para>
633 </blockquote>
634 <para>
635 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
636 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
637 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
638 described,
639 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
640 </para>
641 <blockquote>
642 <para>
643 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
644 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
645 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
646 unrestrained, posed . . . a complete reordering of radio power
647 . . . and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
648 on which RCA had grown to power.<footnote><para>Lessing, 226.
649 </para></footnote>
650 </para>
651 </blockquote>
652 <para>
653 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
654 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
655 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
656 FM radio's deployment generally. In 1936, RCA hired the former head
657 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
658 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM&mdash;principally by moving FM
659 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
660 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
661 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
662 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
663 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
664 </para>
665 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
666 <blockquote>
667 <para>
668 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
669 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
670 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
671 deviousness.<footnote><para>
672 Lessing, 256.
673 </para></footnote>
674 </para>
675 </blockquote>
676 <indexterm><primary>AT&amp;T</primary></indexterm>
677 <para>
678 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
679 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
680 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
681 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
682 (This change was strongly supported by AT&amp;T, because the loss of
683 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
684 wired links from AT&amp;T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
685 least temporarily.
686 </para>
687 <para>
688 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
689 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
690 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
691 invalid&mdash;baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
692 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
693 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
694 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
695 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
696 now broke, in 1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
697 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
698 </para>
699 <para>
700 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
701 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
702 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
703 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
704 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
705 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
706 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
707 course always public spirited; the reality is something
708 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
709 to themselves, would crumble in
710 <!-- PAGE BREAK 22 -->
711 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
712 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
713 effect of technological change.
714 </para>
715 <para>
716 There's no single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
717 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
718 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
719 Internet and American Life Project, 58 percent of Americans had access
720 to the Internet in 2002, up from 49 percent two years
721 before.<footnote><para>
722 Amanda Lenhart, "The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
723 Internet Access and the Digital Divide," Pew Internet and American
724 Life Project, 15 April 2003: 6, available at
725 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #2</ulink>.
726 </para></footnote>
727 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
728 of 2004.
729 </para>
730 <para>
731 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
732 changed things. Some of these changes are technical&mdash;the Internet has
733 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
734 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
735 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
736 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
737 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
738 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
739 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
740 </para>
741 <para>
742 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
743 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
744 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
745 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
746 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
747 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
748 has introduced.
749 </para>
750 <para>
751 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
752 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
753 regulation of each. By "commercial culture" I mean that part of our
754 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
755 "noncommercial culture" I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
756 parks or on
757 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
758 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
759 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his "Reader," or
760 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
761 </para>
762 <para>
763 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
764 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
765 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
766 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
767 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
768 left this culture "free." The ordinary ways in which ordinary
769 individuals shared and transformed their culture&mdash;telling
770 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
771 clubs, sharing music, making tapes&mdash;were left alone by the law.
772 </para>
773 <para>
774 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
775 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
776 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
777 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
778 marketplace.<footnote>
779 <para>
780 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
781 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
782 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
783 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
784 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
785 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
786 D. Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy," Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193,
787 198&ndash;200.
788 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
789 </para></footnote>
790 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
791 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
792 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
793 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
794 </para>
795 <para>
796 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
797 been erased.<footnote><para>
798 See Jessica Litman, Digital Copyright (New York: Prometheus Books,
799 2001), ch. 13.
800 </para></footnote>
801 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
802 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
803 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
804 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
805 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
806 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
807 the balance of our history&mdash;between uses of our culture that were
808 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission&mdash;has
809 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
810 culture, more and more a permission culture.
811 </para>
812 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
813 <para>
814 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
815 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
816 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
817 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
818 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
819 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
820 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
821 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
822 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
823 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
824 Causbys.
825 </para>
826 <para>
827 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
828 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
829 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
830 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
831 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
832 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
833 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
834 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
835 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
836 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
837 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
838 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
839 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
840 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
841 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
842 than creators do today&mdash;all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
843 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
844 </para>
845 <para>
846 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
847 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
848 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
849 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
850 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
851 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
852 remakes them.
853 </para>
854 <para>
855 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
856 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
857 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
858 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions&mdash;whether "piracy" will
859 be permitted, and whether "property" will be protected. The "war" that
860 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet&mdash;what
861 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
862 calls his "own terrorist war"<footnote><para>
863 Amy Harmon, "Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
864 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club," New York
865 Times, 17 January 2002.
866 </para></footnote>&mdash;has been framed as a battle about the
867 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
868 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
869 against it.
870 </para>
871 <para>
872 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
873 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
874 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
875 "creative property." I believe that "piracy" is wrong, and that the
876 law, properly tuned, should punish "piracy," whether on or off the
877 Internet.
878 </para>
879 <para>
880 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
881 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
882 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet "pirates" will also rid our
883 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
884 </para>
885 <para>
886 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first 180 years of
887 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
888 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
889 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
890 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,<footnote>
891 <para>
892 Neil W. Netanel, "Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society," Yale Law
893 Journal 106 (1996): 283.
894 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
895 </para></footnote>
896 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
897 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
898 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
899 could cultivate and extend our culture.
900 </para>
901 <para>
902 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
903 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
904 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
905 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist&ndash;like,
906 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
907 granted&mdash;but it is not often granted to the critical or the
908 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
909 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
910 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
911 </para>
912 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Should "Is it" be "It is" ? -->
913 <para>
914 The story that follows is about this war. Is it not about the
915 "centrality of technology" to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
916 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
917 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
918 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
919 against an industry.
920 </para>
921 <para>
922 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
923 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
924 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
925 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
926 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
927 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
928 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
929 </para>
930 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
931 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
932 <para>
933 Like the Causbys' battle, this war is, in part, about "property." The
934 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
935 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
936 this "property" are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
937 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
938 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
939 of "intellectual property" now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
940 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
941 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
942 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
943 "trespassing" upon legitimate claims of "property." It is as plain to
944 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
945 trespass.
946 </para>
947 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
948 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
949 <para>
950 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
951 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
952 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
953 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
954 war. Unlike
955 <!-- PAGE BREAK 27 -->
956 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
957 on its side.
958 </para>
959 <para>
960 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
961 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
962 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
963 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
964 our "culture" was as "owned" as it is now. And yet there has never
965 been a time when the concentration of power to control the uses of
966 culture has been as unquestioningly accepted as it is now.
967 </para>
968 <para>
969 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
970 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
971 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
972 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
973 </para>
974 <para>
975 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
976 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
977 </para>
978 <para>
979 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
980 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
981 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
982 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
983 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
984 </para>
985 <para>
986 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
987 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
988 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
989 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
990 view?
991 </para>
992 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
993 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
994 <para>
995 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
996 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
997 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
998 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of "intellectual
999 property." What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1000 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1001 this silliness will be much more profound.
1002 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1003 </para>
1004 <para>
1005 The struggle that rages just now centers on two ideas: "piracy" and
1006 "property." My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1007 ideas.
1008 </para>
1009 <para>
1010 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1011 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1012 obscure French theorists&mdash;however natural that is for the weird
1013 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1014 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1015 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1016 </para>
1017 <para>
1018 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1019 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1020 government, pushed by big media to respond to this "something new," is
1021 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1022 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let "common
1023 sense" resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1024 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1025 law&mdash;and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1026 fundamental about who we have always been.
1027 </para>
1028 <para>
1029 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1030 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1031 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1032 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1033 of one more consequence of this form of corruption&mdash;a consequence
1034 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1035 </para>
1036 </chapter>
1037 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1038 <chapter id="c-piracy">
1039 <title>"PIRACY"</title>
1040
1041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1042 <indexterm id="idxmansfield1" class='startofrange'>
1043 <primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary>
1044 </indexterm>
1045 <para>
1046 Since the inception of the law regulating creative property, there has
1047 been a war against "piracy." The precise contours of this concept,
1048 "piracy," are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1049 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1050 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1051 </para>
1052 <blockquote>
1053 <para>
1054 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1055 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1056 of them for his own use.<footnote><para>
1057 <!-- f1 -->
1058 Bach v. Longman, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield).
1059 </para></footnote>
1060 </para>
1061 <indexterm startref="idxmansfield1" class='endofrange'/>
1062 </blockquote>
1063 <para>
1064 Today we are in the middle of another "war" against "piracy." The
1065 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1066 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1067 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1068 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1069 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1070 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1071 </para>
1072 <para>
1073 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1074 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1075 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1076 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1077 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will "rob the author of the
1078 profit."
1079 </para>
1080 <para>
1081 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1082 increasingly to technology to defend their "property" against this
1083 "piracy." A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1084 raised to believe that "property" should be "free." Forget tattoos,
1085 never mind body piercing&mdash;our kids are becoming thieves!
1086 </para>
1087 <para>
1088 There's no doubt that "piracy" is wrong, and that pirates should be
1089 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1090 notion of "piracy" in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1091 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1092 </para>
1093 <para>
1094 The idea goes something like this:
1095 </para>
1096 <blockquote>
1097 <para>
1098 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1099 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1100 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1101 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1102 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1103 piracy.
1104 </para>
1105 </blockquote>
1106 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle</primary></indexterm>
1107 <para>
1108 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1109 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the "if value, then right"
1110 theory of creative property<footnote><para>
1111 <!-- f2 -->
1112 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, "Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1113 in the Pepsi Generation," Notre Dame Law Review 65 (1990): 397.
1114 </para></footnote>
1115 &mdash;if there is value, then someone must have a
1116 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1117 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1118 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.<footnote><para>
1119 <!-- f3 -->
1120 Lisa Bannon, "The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1121 Up," Wall Street Journal, 21 August 1996, available at
1122 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #3</ulink>; Jonathan
1123 Zittrain, "Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1124 Speech, No One Wins," Boston Globe, 24 November 2002.
1125 </para></footnote>
1126 There was "value" (the songs) so there must have been a
1127 "right"&mdash;even against the Girl Scouts.
1128 </para>
1129 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP</primary></indexterm>
1130 <para>
1131 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1132 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1133 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1134 of law protecting creative property. But the "if value, then right"
1135 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1136 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1137 </para>
1138 <para>
1139 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1140 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1141 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1142 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1143 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1144 </para>
1145 <para>
1146 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1147 takes care to draw&mdash;the distinction between republishing someone's
1148 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1149 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1150 copyright law today regulates both.
1151 </para>
1152 <para>
1153 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1154 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1155 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1156 entities could bear the burden of the law&mdash;even the burden of the
1157 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1158 more expense of doing business.
1159 </para>
1160 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1161 <para>
1162 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1163 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1164 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1165 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1166 "copying," when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1167 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1168 outweighs any original benefit&mdash;certainly as it affects
1169 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1170 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1171 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1172 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1173 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1174 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1175 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1176 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1177 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1178 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the "Rise of the Creative Class."<footnote>
1179 <para>
1180 <!-- f4 -->
1181 In The Rise of the Creative Class (New York: Basic Books, 2002),
1182 Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of labor toward a
1183 labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't directly address the
1184 legal conditions under which that creativity is enabled or stifled. I
1185 certainly agree with him about the importance and significance of this
1186 change, but I also believe the conditions under which it will be
1187 enabled are much more tenuous.
1188 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1189 </para></footnote>
1190 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1191 this creative class.
1192 </para>
1193 <para>
1194 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1195 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1196 context the current battles about behavior labeled "piracy."
1197 </para>
1198
1199 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1200 <sect1 id="creators">
1201 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators</title>
1202 <para>
1203 In 1928, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1204 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called Plane Crazy.
1205 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1206 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, Steamboat Willie brought
1207 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1208 </para>
1209 <para>
1210 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1211 movie The Jazz Singer. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1212 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1213 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1214 Disney ran a test in the summer of 1928, the results were unambiguous.
1215 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1216 </para>
1217 <blockquote>
1218 <para>
1219 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1220 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1221 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1222 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1223 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1224 </para>
1225 <para>
1226 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1227 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1228 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1229 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1230 synchronization was pretty close.
1231 </para>
1232 <para>
1233 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1234 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1235 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1236 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1237 it was something new!<footnote><para>
1238 <!-- f1 -->
1239 Leonard Maltin, Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1240 Cartoons (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34&ndash;35.
1241 </para></footnote>
1242 </para>
1243 </blockquote>
1244 <para>
1245 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1246 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: "I have never been so thrilled
1247 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it."
1248 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub</primary></indexterm>
1249 </para>
1250 <para>
1251 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1252 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1253 rarely&mdash;except in Disney's hands&mdash;been anything more than
1254 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1255 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1256 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1257 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1258 </para>
1259 <para>
1260 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that 1928 also
1261 marks another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed
1262 to cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1263 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was Steamboat Bill, Jr.
1264 </para>
1265 <para>
1266 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in 1895. In the era of
1267 silent film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to
1268 spark uncontrollable laughter from his audience. Steamboat Bill, Jr. was
1269 a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its incredible stunts.
1270 The film was classic Keaton&mdash;wildly popular and among the best of its
1271 genre.
1272 </para>
1273 <para>
1274 Steamboat Bill, Jr. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat Willie.
1275 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1276 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1277 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,<footnote><para>
1278 <!-- f2 -->
1279 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1280 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #4</ulink>.
1281 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1282 use the music for five songs in Steamboat Willie: "Steamboat Bill," "The
1283 Simpleton" (Delille), "Mischief Makers" (Carbonara), "Joyful Hurry No. 1"
1284 (Baron), and "Gawky Rube" (Lakay). A sixth song, "The Turkey in the
1285 Straw," was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1286 Harry Surden, 10 July 2003, on file with author.
1287 </para></footnote>
1288 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1289 the invention of synchronized sound in The Jazz Singer that we get
1290 Steamboat Willie. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1291 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song "Steamboat Bill,"
1292 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1293 Mouse.
1294 </para>
1295 <para>
1296 This "borrowing" was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1297 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1298 films of his day.<footnote><para>
1299 <!-- f3 -->
1300 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, "The Mouse
1301 that Ate the Public Domain," Findlaw, 5 March 2002, at
1302 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #5</ulink>.
1303 </para></footnote>
1304 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1305 knockoffs&mdash;slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1306 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1307 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1308 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1309 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1310 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1311 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1312 old.
1313 </para>
1314 <para>
1315 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1316 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1317 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1318 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1319 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1320 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1321 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1322 </para>
1323 <para>
1324 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1325 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1326 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1327 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1328 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1329 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1330 work of others is astonishing when set together: Snow White (1937),
1331 Fantasia (1940), Pinocchio (1940), Dumbo (1941), Bambi (1942), Song of
1332 the South (1946), Cinderella (1950), Alice in Wonderland (1951), Robin
1333 Hood (1952), Peter Pan (1953), Lady and the Tramp
1334 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1335 (1955), Mulan (1998), Sleeping Beauty (1959), 101 Dalmatians (1961),
1336 The Sword in the Stone (1963), and The Jungle Book (1967)&mdash;not to
1337 mention a recent example that we should perhaps quickly forget,
1338 Treasure Planet (2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney,
1339 Inc.) ripped creativity from the culture around him, mixed that
1340 creativity with his own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix
1341 into the soul of his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1342 </para>
1343 <para>
1344 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1345 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1346 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1347 its importance. We could call this "Disney creativity," though that
1348 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, "Walt Disney
1349 creativity"&mdash;a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1350 culture around us and makes it something different.
1351 </para>
1352 <para> In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1353 relatively fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was
1354 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1355 thirty years&mdash;for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1356 copyrighted.<footnote><para>
1357 <!-- f4 -->
1358 Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1359 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the "average" term by
1360 determining
1361 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1362 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in year
1363 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the
1364 average
1365 term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1366 Web site associated with this book, available at
1367 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #6</ulink>.
1368 </para></footnote>
1369 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1370 copyright holders of a creative work had an "exclusive right" to control
1371 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1372 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1373 </para>
1374 <para>
1375 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1376 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1377 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a "lawyer-free
1378 zone." Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1379 for Disney to use and build upon in 1928. It was free for
1380 anyone&mdash; whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1381 approved or not&mdash;to use and build upon.
1382 </para>
1383 <para>
1384 This is the ways things always were&mdash;until quite recently. For most
1385 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1386 until 1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1387 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1388
1389 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1390 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1391 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s
1392 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1393 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1394 content from before the Great Depression.
1395 </para>
1396 <para>
1397 Of course, Walt Disney had no monopoly on "Walt Disney creativity."
1398 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1399 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1400 universal.
1401 </para>
1402 <para>
1403 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1404 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: manga, or
1405 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of
1406 publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives
1407 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1408 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1409 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1410 </para>
1411 <para>
1412 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1413 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1414 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1415 the stories that these "graphic novels" tell. For the Japanese, manga
1416 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are "men in tights."
1417 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1418 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1419 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1420 interestingly different way.
1421 </para>
1422 <para>
1423 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1424 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1425 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1426 </para>
1427 <para>
1428 This is the phenomenon of doujinshi. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1429 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1430 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is just a copy; the artist must make a
1431 contribution to the art he copies, by transforming it either subtly or
1432 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1433 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1434 develop it differently&mdash;with a different story line. Or the comic can
1435 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1436 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently "different." But they
1437 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1438 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1439 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1440 </para>
1441 <para>
1442 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1443 huge. More than 33,000 "circles" of creators from across Japan produce
1444 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come
1445 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1446 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1447 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1448 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1449 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1450 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1451 </para>
1452 <para>
1453 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1454 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1455 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1456 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1457 one. Doujinshi are plainly "derivative works." There is no general
1458 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1459 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1460 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with Steamboat Bill, Jr. Under
1461 both Japanese and American law, that "taking" without the permission
1462 of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an infringement of
1463 the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative work without the
1464 original copyright owner's permission.
1465 </para>
1466 <para>
1467 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1468 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1469 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, "The
1470 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1471 in Japan now. . . . American comics were born out of copying each
1472
1473 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1474 other. . . . That's how [the artists] learn to draw&mdash;by going into comic
1475 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them"
1476 and building from them.<footnote><para>
1477 <!-- f5 -->
1478 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, Reinventing Comics (New
1479 York: Perennial, 2000).
1480 </para></footnote>
1481 </para>
1482 <para>
1483 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1484 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1485 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, "there are these rules
1486 and you have to stick to them." There are things Superman "cannot"
1487 do. "As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1488 which are fifty years old."
1489 </para>
1490 <para>
1491 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1492 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1493 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1494 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1495 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1496 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1497 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.<footnote><para>
1498 <!-- f6 -->
1499 See Salil K. Mehra, "Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1500 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?" Rutgers Law
1501 Review 55 (2002): 155, 182. "[T]here might be a collective economic
1502 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1503 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1504 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1505 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1506 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved."
1507 </para></footnote>
1508 </para>
1509 <para>
1510 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1511 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1512 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1513 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1514 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1515 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1516 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1517 a more general pattern of blocking this "free taking" by the doujinshi
1518 culture?
1519 </para>
1520 <para>
1521 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1522 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1523 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. "We don't have enough
1524 lawyers," he told me one afternoon. There "just aren't enough resources
1525 to prosecute cases like this."
1526 </para>
1527 <para>
1528 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1529 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1530 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1531 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1532 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1533 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1534 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1535 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1536 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1537 their clients or hurt them?
1538 Let's pause for a moment.
1539 </para>
1540 <para>
1541 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1542 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1543 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1544 </para>
1545 <para>
1546 We live in a world that celebrates "property." I am one of those
1547 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1548 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1549 "intellectual property."<footnote><para>
1550 <!-- f7 -->
1551 The term intellectual property is of relatively recent origin. See
1552 Siva Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs, 11 (New York: New York
1553 University Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, The Future of Ideas
1554 (New York: Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately
1555 describes a set of "property" rights&mdash;copyright, patents,
1556 trademark, and trade-secret&mdash;but the nature of those rights is
1557 very different.
1558 </para></footnote>
1559 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1560 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1561 property.
1562 </para>
1563 <para>
1564 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1565 plenty of value out there that "property" doesn't capture. I don't
1566 mean "money can't buy you love," but rather, value that is plainly
1567 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1568 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1569 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1570 condemning that taking as wrong&mdash; even though trivial, even if
1571 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1572 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1573 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1574 Disney's use would have been considered "fair." There was nothing
1575 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1576 the public domain.
1577 </para>
1578 <para>
1579 Thus, even though the things that Disney took&mdash;or more generally,
1580 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity&mdash;are
1581 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1582
1583 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1584 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1585 freedom is good.
1586 </para>
1587 <para>
1588 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1589 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1590 work&mdash;or even one copy&mdash;without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1591 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1592 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1593 form, whether large or small.
1594 </para>
1595 <para>
1596 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1597 say that the copycat comic artists are "stealing." This form of Walt
1598 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1599 particular find it hard to say why.
1600 </para>
1601 <para>
1602 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1603 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1604 without asking or paying for the privilege. ("Excuse me, Professor
1605 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1606 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?") Acting companies
1607 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1608 permission from anyone. (Does anyone believe Shakespeare would be
1609 better spread within our culture if there were a central Shakespeare
1610 rights clearinghouse that all productions of Shakespeare must appeal
1611 to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles with a certain kind of
1612 movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s; two volcano disaster
1613 films in 1997.
1614 </para>
1615 <para>
1616 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1617 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1618 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1619 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1620 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1621 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1622 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking&mdash;free
1623 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1624 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1625 </para>
1626 <para>
1627 The hard question is therefore not whether a culture is free. All
1628 cultures are free to some degree. The hard question instead is "How
1629 free is this culture?" How much, and how broadly, is the culture free
1630 for others to take and build upon? Is that freedom limited to party
1631 members? To members of the royal family? To the top ten corporations
1632 on the New York Stock Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To
1633 artists generally, whether affiliated with the Met or not? To
1634 musicians generally, whether white or not? To filmmakers generally,
1635 whether affiliated with a studio or not?
1636 </para>
1637 <para>
1638 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1639 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1640 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1641 </para>
1642
1643 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1644 </sect1>
1645 <sect1 id="mere-copyists">
1646 <title>CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"</title>
1647 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis</primary></indexterm>
1648 <para>
1649 In 1839, Louis Daguerre invented the first practical technology for
1650 producing what we would call "photographs." Appropriately enough, they
1651 were called "daguerreotypes." The process was complicated and
1652 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1653 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1654 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1655 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1656 </para>
1657 <para>
1658 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1659 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1660 "automatic pictures." William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1661 making "negatives." But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1662 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1663 the 1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1664 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1665 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1666 amateurs.
1667 </para>
1668 <indexterm id="idxeastmangeorge" class='startofrange'>
1669 <primary>Eastman, George</primary>
1670 </indexterm>
1671 <para>
1672 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1673 didn't happen until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1674 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1675 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1676 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1677 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1678 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1679 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1680 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1681 population of photographers.
1682 </para>
1683 <para>
1684 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1685 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1686 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. "You press the button and we
1687 do the rest."<footnote><para>
1688 <!-- f1 -->
1689 Reese V. Jenkins, Images and Enterprise (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975), 112.
1690 </para></footnote> As he described in The Kodak Primer:
1691 </para>
1692 <blockquote>
1693 <para>
1694 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1695 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1696 that only an expert can do. . . . We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1697 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1698 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1699 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1700 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1701 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1702 chemicals.<footnote>
1703 <para>
1704 <!-- f2 -->
1705 Brian Coe, The Birth of Photography (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1706 1977), 53.
1707 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1708 </para></footnote>
1709 </para>
1710 </blockquote>
1711 <para>
1712 For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1713 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1714 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1715 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1716 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1717 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in 1888; one
1718 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1719 From 1888 through 1909, while industrial production was rising by 4.7
1720 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by
1721 percent.<footnote><para>
1722 <!-- f3 -->
1723 Jenkins, 177.
1724 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1725 an average annual increase of over 17 percent.<footnote><para>
1726 <!-- f4 -->
1727 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p. 178.
1728 </para></footnote>
1729 </para>
1730 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1731 <para>
1732
1733 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1734 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1735 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1736 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1737 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1738 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, "For the
1739 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1740 permanent record of his family and its activities. . . . For the first
1741 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1742 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1743 interpretation or bias."<footnote><para>
1744 <!-- f5 -->
1745 Coe, 58.
1746 </para></footnote>
1747 </para>
1748 <para>
1749 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1750 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1751 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1752 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1753 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1754 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its "quality";
1755 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1756 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1757 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1758 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1759 have before.
1760 </para>
1761 <para>
1762 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1763 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1764 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1765 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1766 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1767 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1768 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1769 he wanted. Their answer was no.<footnote><para>
1770 <!-- f6 -->
1771 For illustrative cases, see, for example, Pavesich v. N.E. Life Ins. Co., 50 S.E.
1772 </para></footnote>
1773 </para>
1774 <para>
1775 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1776 familiar. The photographer was "taking" something from the person or
1777 building whose photograph he shot&mdash;pirating something of
1778 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1779 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1780 draw
1781 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1782 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1783 that they thought valuable.
1784 </para>
1785 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1786 <para>
1787 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1788 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1789 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1790 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1791 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.<footnote>
1792 <para>
1793 <!-- f7 -->
1794 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy,"
1795 Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193.
1796 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1797 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.</primary></indexterm>
1798 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1799 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1800 Steamboat Bill, Jr. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1801 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1802 </para>
1803 <para>
1804 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1805 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1806 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1807 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1808 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1809 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1810 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1811 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1812 clearing the rights to do the capturing.<footnote><para>
1813 <!-- f8 -->
1814 See Melville B. Nimmer, "The Right of Publicity," Law and Contemporary
1815 Problems 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, "Privacy," California Law
1816 Review 48 (1960) 398&ndash;407; White v. Samsung Electronics America,
1817 Inc., 971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951
1818 (1993).
1819 </para></footnote>)
1820 </para>
1821 <para>
1822 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1823 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1824 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1825 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1826 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1827 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1828 Kodak would be benefiting from the "theft" committed by the
1829 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1830 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1831 from the "image-right" infringement of its photographers. We could
1832 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1833 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1834 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1835 </para>
1836 <para>
1837
1838 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
1839 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
1840 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
1841 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
1842 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
1843 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
1844 technology as they did&mdash;since professionals could have more
1845 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
1846 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
1847 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
1848 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
1849 realized. If you drive through San Francisco's Presidio, you might
1850 see two gaudy yellow school buses painted over with colorful and
1851 striking images, and the logo "Just Think!" in place of the name of a
1852 school. But there's little that's "just" cerebral in the projects that
1853 these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies that
1854 teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even the
1855 film of your VCR. Rather the "film" of digital cameras. Just Think!
1856 is a project that enables kids to make films, as a way to understand
1857 and critique the filmed culture that they find all around them. Each
1858 year, these busses travel to more than thirty schools and enable three
1859 hundred to five hundred children to learn something about media by
1860 doing something with media. By doing, they think. By tinkering, they
1861 learn.
1862 </para>
1863 <indexterm startref="idxeastmangeorge" class='endofrange'/>
1864 <para>
1865 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
1866 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
1867 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, "Five years ago, a good
1868 real-time digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get
1869 professional quality for $595."<footnote><para>
1870 <!-- f9 -->
1871 H. Edward Goldberg, "Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
1872 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,"
1873 cadalyst, February 2002, available at
1874 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #7</ulink>.
1875 </para></footnote>
1876 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
1877 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
1878 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
1879 learning more and more of something teachers call "media literacy."
1880 </para>
1881 <para>
1882 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
1883 "Media literacy," as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
1884 Think!, puts it, "is the ability . . . to understand, analyze, and
1885 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
1886 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
1887 the way people access it."
1888 </para>
1889 <para>
1890 This may seem like an odd way to think about "literacy." For most
1891 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
1892 and noticing split infinitives are the things that "literate" people know
1893 about.
1894 </para>
1895 <para>
1896 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of
1897 television commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000
1898 commercials generally,<footnote><para>
1899 <!-- f10 -->
1900 Judith Van Evra, Television and Child Development (Hillsdale, N.J.:
1901 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990); "Findings on Family and TV
1902 Study," Denver Post, 25 May 1997, B6.
1903 </para></footnote>
1904 it is increasingly important to understand the "grammar" of media. For
1905 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
1906 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
1907 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
1908 (at least at first) terrible media.
1909 </para>
1910 <para>
1911 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
1912 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
1913 has written understands how difficult writing is&mdash;how difficult
1914 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
1915 language to be understandable&mdash;few of us have any real sense of
1916 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
1917 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
1918 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
1919 </para>
1920 <para>
1921 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
1922 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
1923 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
1924 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
1925 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
1926 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
1927 </para>
1928 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael</primary></indexterm>
1929 <para>
1930 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
1931 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
1932 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
1933
1934 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
1935 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
1936 about "the placement of objects, color, . . . rhythm, pacing, and
1937 texture."<footnote>
1938 <para>
1939 <!-- f11 -->
1940 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish, 13 December
1941 2002.
1942 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
1943 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
1944 </para></footnote>
1945 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
1946 "played" as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
1947 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
1948 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
1949 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
1950 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
1951 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
1952 to a wildly successful author.<footnote><para>
1953 <!-- f12 -->
1954 See Scott Steinberg, "Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs," E!online, 4
1955 November 2000, available at
1956 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #8</ulink>; "Timeline," 22 November 2000,
1957 available at
1958 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #9</ulink>.
1959 </para></footnote>
1960 </para>
1961 <indexterm><primary>computer games</primary></indexterm>
1962 <para>
1963 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
1964 describes, "people are very surprised about how they are led through a
1965 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
1966 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
1967 led." If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
1968 </para>
1969 <para>
1970 Yet the push for an expanded literacy&mdash;one that goes beyond text
1971 to include audio and visual elements&mdash;is not about making better
1972 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
1973 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
1974 </para>
1975 <blockquote>
1976 <para>
1977 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
1978 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
1979 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
1980 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
1981 being read-only.
1982 </para>
1983 </blockquote>
1984 <para>
1985 "Read-only." Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
1986 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
1987 twentieth century.
1988 </para>
1989 <para>
1990 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
1991 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
1992 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
1993 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
1994 literacy,
1995 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
1996 and this literacy in particular, is to "empower people to choose the
1997 appropriate language for what they need to create or
1998 express."<footnote>
1999 <para>
2000 <!-- f13 -->
2001 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2002 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2003 </para></footnote> It is to enable students "to communicate in the
2004 language of the twenty-first century."<footnote><para>
2005 <!-- f14 -->
2006 Ibid.
2007 </para></footnote>
2008 </para>
2009 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2010 <para>
2011 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2012 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2013 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2014 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2015 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2016 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2017 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2018 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2019 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2020 students know something about&mdash;gun violence.
2021 </para>
2022 <para>
2023 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2024 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2025 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2026 away. The "kids were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night,"
2027 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2028 what education should be about&mdash;learning how to express themselves.
2029 </para>
2030 <para>
2031 Using whatever "free web stuff they could find," and relatively simple
2032 tools to enable the kids to mix "image, sound, and text," Barish said
2033 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2034 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2035 close to the lives of these students. The project "gave them a tool
2036 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2037 it," Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2038 expression&mdash;far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2039 been created using only text. "If you had said to these students, `you
2040 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2041 gone and done something else," Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2042 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2043 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which these ideas can be
2044 expressed well. The power of this message depended upon its connection
2045 to this form of expression.
2046 </para>
2047 <para>
2048
2049 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2050 "But isn't education about teaching kids to write?" I asked. In part,
2051 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2052 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of "constructing
2053 meaning." To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2054 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2055 part&mdash;and increasingly, not the most powerful part&mdash;of
2056 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2057 our interview,
2058 </para>
2059 <blockquote>
2060 <para>
2061 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2062 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2063 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2064 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2065 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2066 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2067 you say, "Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters."
2068 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2069 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2070 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, "Well, with all these things that you
2071 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2072 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2073 for me something that reflects that." Not by giving a kid a video
2074 camera and . . . saying, "Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2075 make a little movie." But instead, really help you take these elements
2076 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2077 about the topic. . . .
2078 </para>
2079 <para>
2080 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2081 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2082 bump up against the fact, "I need to explain this and I really need
2083 to write something." And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2084 they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 times, till they got it right.
2085 </para>
2086 <para>
2087 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2088 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2089 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2090 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2091 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2092 had a lot of power with this language."
2093 </para>
2094 </blockquote>
2095 <para>
2096 When two planes crashed into the World Trade Center, another into the
2097 Pentagon, and a fourth into a Pennsylvania field, all media around the
2098 world shifted to this news. Every moment of just about every day for
2099 that week, and for weeks after, television in particular, and media
2100 generally, retold the story of the events we had just witnessed. The
2101 telling was a retelling, because we had seen the events that were
2102 described. The genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the
2103 delayed second attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole
2104 world would be watching.
2105 </para>
2106 <para>
2107 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2108 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2109 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was "balance,"
2110 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2111 increasingly come to expect it, "news as entertainment," even if the
2112 entertainment is tragedy.
2113 </para>
2114 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
2115 <indexterm><primary>CBS</primary></indexterm>
2116 <para>
2117 But in addition to this produced news about the "tragedy of September
2118 11," those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2119 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2120 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2121 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2122 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2123 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2124 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2125 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2126 the term in his book Cyber Rights, around a news event that had
2127 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2128 was also the Internet.
2129 </para>
2130 <para>
2131 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet&mdash;though I do think the
2132 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2133 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2134 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2135 movie
2136 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2137 by a student on the "Just Think!" bus, the visual images could be mixed
2138 with sound or text.
2139 </para>
2140 <para>
2141 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2142 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2143 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2144 tradition&mdash;not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2145 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2146 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2147 spread practically instantaneously.
2148 </para>
2149 <para>
2150 September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around
2151 the same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically
2152 was just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2153 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures, such
2154 as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those cultures, it
2155 records private facts in a public way&mdash;it's a kind of electronic Jerry
2156 Springer, available anywhere in the world.
2157 </para>
2158 <para>
2159 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2160 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2161 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2162 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2163 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2164 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2165 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2166 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2167 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2168 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2169 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2170 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2171 </para>
2172 <para>
2173 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2174 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2175 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2176 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2177 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2178 people vote
2179 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2180 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2181 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2182 </para>
2183 <para>
2184 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2185 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2186 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2187 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2188 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2189 most important account of early "Democracy in America." It wasn't
2190 popular elections that fascinated him&mdash;it was the jury, an
2191 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2192 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2193 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2194 deliberated. Members argued about the "right" result; they tried to
2195 persuade each other of the "right" result, and in criminal cases at
2196 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2197 come to an end.<footnote><para>
2198 <!-- f15 -->
2199 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, bk. 1, trans.
2200 Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16.
2201 </para></footnote>
2202 </para>
2203 <para>
2204 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2205 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2206 are pushing to create just such an institution.<footnote><para>
2207 <!-- f16 -->
2208 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, "Deliberation Day," Journal of
2209 Political Philosophy 10 (2) (2002): 129.
2210 </para></footnote>
2211 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2212 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2213 place for "democratic deliberation" to occur.
2214 </para>
2215 <para>
2216 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2217 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2218 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2219 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2220 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2221 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.<footnote><para>
2222 <!-- f17 -->
2223 Cass Sunstein, Republic.com (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001),
2224 65&ndash;80, 175, 182, 183, 192.
2225 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2226 little beyond what our friends say.
2227 </para>
2228 <para>
2229 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2230 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2231 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2232 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2233 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2234
2235 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2236 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2237 place.
2238 </para>
2239 <para>
2240 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2241 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2242 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2243 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2244 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2245 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2246 </para>
2247 <para>
2248 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2249 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race
2250 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2251 is having an effect.
2252 </para>
2253 <para>
2254 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2255 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2256 "misspoke" at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2257 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2258 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2259 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2260 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2261 more instances of the same "misspeaking" emerged. Finally, the story
2262 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2263 resign as senate majority leader.<footnote><para>
2264 <!-- f18 -->
2265 Noah Shachtman, "With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot," New
2266 York Times, 16 January 2003, G5.
2267 </para></footnote>
2268 </para>
2269 <para>
2270 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2271 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2272 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2273 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2274 on.
2275 </para>
2276 <para>
2277 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2278 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2279 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2280 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2281 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2282 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2283 peer-generated rankings.
2284 </para>
2285 <para>
2286 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2287 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2288 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2289 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2290 difference is the absence of a financial "conflict of interest." "I think you
2291 have to take the conflict of interest" out of journalism, Winer told me.
2292 "An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2293 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2294 get it out of the way."
2295 </para>
2296 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2297 <para>
2298 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2299 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2300 from the public than an unconcentrated media can&mdash;as CNN admitted
2301 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2302 its own employees.<footnote><para>
2303 <!-- f19 -->
2304 Telephone interview with David Winer, 16 April 2003.
2305 </para></footnote>
2306 It also needs to sustain a more coherent
2307 account. (In the middle of the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet
2308 from someone who was at that time listening to a satellite uplink with
2309 a reporter in Iraq. The New York headquarters was telling the reporter
2310 over and over that her account of the war was too bleak: She needed to
2311 offer a more optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't
2312 warranted, they told her that they were writing "the story.")
2313 </para>
2314 <para> Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2315 debate&mdash;"amateur" not in the sense of inexperienced, but in the
2316 sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to give their
2317 reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a story, as
2318 reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds from across
2319 the southwest United States turned to the Internet to retell what they
2320 had seen.<footnote><para>
2321 <!-- f20 -->
2322 John Schwartz, "Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2323 Information Online," New York Times, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci
2324 D. Kramer, "Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,"
2325 Online Journalism Review, 2 February 2003, available at
2326 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #10</ulink>.
2327 </para></footnote>
2328 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2329 "triangulate," as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2330 "communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2331 out of it"&mdash;with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2332 </para>
2333 <para>
2334 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2335 with blogs. "It's going to become an essential skill," Winer predicts,
2336 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2337 not clear that "journalism" is happy about this&mdash;some journalists
2338 have been told to curtail their blogging.<footnote>
2339 <para>
2340 <!-- f21 -->
2341 See Michael Falcone, "Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?" New
2342 York Times, 29 September 2003, C4. ("Not all news organizations have
2343 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2344 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2345 war on March 9, stopped posting 12 days later at his bosses'
2346 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a Houston Chronicle reporter, was
2347 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2348 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.")
2349 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2350 </para></footnote>
2351 But it is clear that we are still in transition. "A
2352
2353 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2354 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises," Winer told me.
2355 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2356 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2357 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, "we will
2358 be the last thing that gets shut down."
2359 </para>
2360 <para>
2361 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because "you
2362 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper."
2363 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2364 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2365 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2366 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2367 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2368 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2369 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2370 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2371 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2372 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2373 extraordinary to report.
2374 </para>
2375 <para>
2376 John Seely Brown is the chief scientist of the Xerox Corporation.
2377 His work, as his Web site describes it, is "human learning and . . . the
2378 creation of knowledge ecologies for creating . . . innovation."
2379 </para>
2380 <para>
2381 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2382 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2383 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2384 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2385 affect learning.
2386 </para>
2387 <para>
2388 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When "a lot of us grew up,"
2389 he explains, that tinkering was done "on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2390 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on." But digital technologies
2391 enable a different kind of tinkering&mdash;with abstract ideas though
2392 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2393 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2394 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2395 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2396 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2397 or "free collage," as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2398 the tinkering of many others.
2399 </para>
2400 <para>
2401 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2402 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2403 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2404 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2405 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2406 </para>
2407 <para>
2408 This opportunity creates a "completely new kind of learning platform,"
2409 as Brown describes. "As soon as you start doing that, you . . .
2410 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2411 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2412 if they can improve it." Each effort is a kind of
2413 apprenticeship. "Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform."
2414 </para>
2415 <para>
2416 In this process, "the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2417 They are code." Kids are "shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2418 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2419 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2420 platform. . . . You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2421 you tinker the more you improve." The more you improve, the more you
2422 learn.
2423 </para>
2424 <para>
2425 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2426 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2427 it, "the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2428 intelligence." Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2429 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2430 text. "The Web . . . says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2431 you are visual, if you are interested in film . . . [then] there is a
2432 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2433 these multiple forms of intelligence."
2434 </para>
2435 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2436 <para>
2437 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2438 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2439
2440 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2441 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2442 kind of recognition.
2443 </para>
2444 <para>
2445 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2446 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2447 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2448 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2449 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2450 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2451 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2452 </para>
2453 <para>
2454 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2455 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2456 10) has developed a powerful argument in favor of the "right to
2457 tinker" as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2458 general.<footnote><para>
2459 <!-- f22 -->
2460 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, "Technological Access
2461 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship," Communications
2462 of the Association for Computer Machinery 43 (2000): 9.
2463 </para></footnote>
2464 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2465 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2466 </para>
2467 <para>
2468 "This is where education in the twenty-first century is going," Brown
2469 explains. We need to "understand how kids who grow up digital think
2470 and want to learn."
2471 </para>
2472 <para>
2473 "Yet," as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2474 evince, "we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2475 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. . . . We're building an
2476 architecture that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2477 system that closes down that part of the brain."
2478 </para>
2479 <para>
2480 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2481 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2482 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2483 the law to close down that technology.
2484 </para>
2485 <para>
2486 "No way to run a culture," as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2487 chapter 9, quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2488 </para>
2489 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2490 </sect1>
2491 <sect1 id="catalogs">
2492 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs</title>
2493 <para>
2494 In the fall of 2002, Jesse Jordan of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as
2495 a freshman at Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York.
2496 His major at RPI was information technology. Though he is not a
2497 programmer, in October Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search
2498 engine technology that was available on the RPI network.
2499 </para>
2500 <para>
2501 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2502 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2503 to information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand
2504 undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school
2505 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2506 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2507 </para>
2508 <para>
2509 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2510 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2511 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2512 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2513 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2514 </para>
2515 <para>
2516 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2517 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2518 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2519 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2520 engines can do this even better. The idea of "intranet" search
2521 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2522 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2523 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2524 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2525 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2526 </para>
2527 <para>
2528 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2529 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2530 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2531 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2532 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2533 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2534 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2535 </para>
2536 <para>
2537 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2538 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2539 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2540 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2541 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2542 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2543 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2544 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2545 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2546 on-line.
2547 </para>
2548 <para>
2549 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2550 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2551 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2552 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2553 be on users' computers.
2554 </para>
2555 <para>
2556 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2557 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2558 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2559 might have created; university brochures&mdash;basically anything that
2560 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2561 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2562 computer.
2563 </para>
2564 <para>
2565 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2566 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2567 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and&mdash;so that this
2568 point is absolutely clear&mdash;Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2569 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2570 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2571 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2572 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2573 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2574 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2575 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2576 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2577 supposed to do.
2578 </para>
2579 <para>
2580 On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2581 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2582 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2583 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2584 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2585 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2586 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2587 </para>
2588 <para>
2589 "It was absurd," he told me. "I don't think I did anything
2590 wrong. . . . I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2591 engine that I ran or . . . what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2592 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2593 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2594 easier to use"&mdash;again, a search engine, which Jesse had not
2595 himself built, using the Windows filesharing system, which Jesse had
2596 not himself built, to enable members of the RPI community to get
2597 access to content, which Jesse had not himself created or posted, and
2598 the vast majority of which had nothing to do with music.
2599 </para>
2600 <para>
2601 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2602 network and had therefore "willfully" violated copyright laws. They
2603 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2604 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2605 "willful infringement," the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2606 call "statutory damages." These damages permit a copyright owner to
2607 claim $150,000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2608 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2609 Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000.
2610 </para>
2611 <para>
2612 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one
2613 other student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2614 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2615 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2616 huge demands for "damages" that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2617 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2618 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $100 billion&mdash;six
2619 times the total profit of the film industry in 2001.<footnote><para>
2620 <!-- f1 -->
2621 Tim Goral, "Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks:
2622 Suit Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages," Professional Media Group LCC 6
2623 (2003): 5, available at 2003 WL 55179443.
2624 </para></footnote>
2625 </para>
2626 <para>
2627 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2628 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2629 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2630 $12,000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2631 $12,000 to dismiss the case.
2632 </para>
2633 <para>
2634 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2635 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2636 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2637 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2638 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2639 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2640 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, "You don't want to pay another
2641 visit to a dentist like me.") And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2642 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2643 </para>
2644 <para>
2645 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2646 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2647 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2648 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2649 at least $250,000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2650 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2651 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2652 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2653 </para>
2654 <para>
2655 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $250,000 and a chance at winning,
2656 or $12,000 and a settlement.
2657 </para>
2658 <para>
2659 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2660 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2661 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2662 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2663 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $1 million a year.
2664 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2665 artist makes $45,900.<footnote><para>
2666 <!-- f2 -->
2667 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001)
2668 (27&ndash;2042&mdash;Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2669 the Arts, More Than One in a Blue Moon (2000).
2670 </para></footnote>
2671 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2672 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2673 student for running a search engine?<footnote><para>
2674 <!-- f3 -->
2675 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in "KaZaA and Punishment,"
2676 Wall Street Journal, 10 September 2003, A24.
2677 </para></footnote>
2678 </para>
2679 <para>
2680 On June 23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2681 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2682 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $15 million lawsuit became an
2683 activist:
2684 </para>
2685 <blockquote>
2686 <para>
2687 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2688 an activist. . . . [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2689 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2690 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2691 </para>
2692 </blockquote>
2693 <para>
2694 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2695 his father told me, Jesse "considers himself very conservative, and so do
2696 I. . . . He's not a tree hugger. . . . I think it's bizarre that they would
2697 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2698 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record."
2699 </para>
2700 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
2701 </sect1>
2702 <sect1 id="pirates">
2703 <title>CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"</title>
2704 <para>
2705 If "piracy" means using the creative property of others without
2706 their permission&mdash;if "if value, then right" is true&mdash;then the history of
2707 the content industry is a history of piracy. Every important sector of
2708 "big media" today&mdash;film, records, radio, and cable TV&mdash;was born of a
2709 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last generation's
2710 pirates join this generation's country club&mdash;until now.
2711 </para>
2712 <sect2 id="film">
2713 <title>Film</title>
2714 <para>
2715 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.<footnote><para>
2716 <!-- f1 -->
2717 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
2718 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs, 87&ndash;93,
2719 which details Edison's "adventures" with copyright and patent.
2720 </para></footnote>
2721 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
2722 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
2723 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
2724 exercised through a monopoly "trust," the Motion Pictures Patents
2725 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
2726 property&mdash;patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
2727 this creative property
2728 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
2729 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
2730 </para>
2731 <para>
2732 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
2733 </para>
2734 <blockquote>
2735 <para>
2736 A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
2737 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
2738 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
2739 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
2740 summer of 1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
2741 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
2742 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
2743 </para>
2744 <para>
2745 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
2746 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
2747 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
2748 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
2749 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
2750 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
2751 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
2752 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
2753 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
2754 license was revoked.<footnote><para>
2755 <!-- f2 -->
2756 J. A. Aberdeen, Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
2757 Picture Producers (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts
2758 posted at "The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
2759 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws," available at
2760 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #11</ulink>. For a
2761 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
2762 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, "From
2763 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
2764 the Propertization of Copyright" (September 2002), University of
2765 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
2766 Working Paper No. 159. </para></footnote>
2767 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company</primary></indexterm>
2768 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
2769 </para>
2770 </blockquote>
2771 <para>
2772 The Napsters of those days, the "independents," were companies like
2773 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
2774 resisted. "Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
2775 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
2776 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred."<footnote><para>
2777 <!-- f3 -->
2778 Marc Wanamaker, "The First Studios," The Silents Majority, archived at
2779 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #12</ulink>.
2780 </para></footnote>
2781 That led the independents to flee the East
2782 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
2783 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
2784 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
2785 did just that.
2786 </para>
2787 <para>
2788 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
2789 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
2790 patent holder a truly "limited" monopoly (just seventeen years at that
2791
2792 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
2793 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
2794 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
2795 Edison's creative property.
2796 </para>
2797 </sect2>
2798 <sect2 id="recordedmusic">
2799 <title>Recorded Music</title>
2800 <para>
2801 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
2802 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
2803 </para>
2804 <para>
2805 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
2806 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
2807 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
2808 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
2809 their music. In other words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
2810 1899 hit "Happy Mose," the law said I would have to pay for the right
2811 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
2812 right to perform it publicly.
2813 </para>
2814 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
2815 <para>
2816 But what if I wanted to record "Happy Mose," using Edison's phonograph
2817 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
2818 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
2819 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
2820 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
2821 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
2822 "public performance" if I recorded the song in my own house (even
2823 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
2824 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
2825 brain are not&mdash;yet&mdash; regulated by copyright law). So if I
2826 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
2827 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
2828 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
2829 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
2830 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
2831 its composer anything.
2832 </para>
2833 <para>
2834 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
2835 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
2836 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
2837 put it,
2838 </para>
2839 <blockquote>
2840 <para>
2841 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
2842 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
2843 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
2844 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
2845 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
2846 rights.<footnote><para>
2847 <!-- f4 -->
2848 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
2849 S. 6330 and H.R. 19853 Before the ( Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th
2850 Cong. 59, 1st sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
2851 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in Legislative History of the
2852 Copyright Act, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
2853 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
2854 </para></footnote>
2855 </para>
2856 </blockquote>
2857 <para>
2858 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
2859 people's works were "sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
2860 genius of American composers,"<footnote><para>
2861 <!-- f5 -->
2862 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223
2863 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
2864 </para></footnote>
2865 and the "music publishing industry"
2866 was thereby "at the complete mercy of this one pirate."<footnote><para>
2867 <!-- f6 -->
2868 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226
2869 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
2870 </para></footnote>
2871 As John Philip
2872 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, "When they make money
2873 out of my pieces, I want a share of it."<footnote><para>
2874 <!-- f7 -->
2875 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23
2876 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
2877 </para></footnote>
2878 </para>
2879 <para>
2880 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
2881 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
2882 player piano argued that "it is perfectly demonstrable that the
2883 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
2884 of anything he had before their introduction." Rather, the machines
2885 increased the sales of sheet music.<footnote><para>
2886 <!-- f8 -->
2887
2888 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283&ndash;84
2889 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
2890 Perforating Company of New York).
2891 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
2892 Congress was "to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
2893 they represent, and whose servants they are." "All talk about
2894 `theft,'" the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
2895 wrote, "is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
2896 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
2897 statute."<footnote><para>
2898 <!-- f9 -->
2899 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared
2900 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
2901 Graphophone Company Association).
2902 </para></footnote>
2903 </para>
2904 <para>
2905 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer and the
2906 recording artist. Congress amended the law to make sure that composers
2907 would be paid for the "mechanical reproductions" of their music. But
2908 rather than simply granting the composer complete control over the
2909 right to make mechanical reproductions, Congress gave recording
2910 artists a right to record the music, at a price set by Congress, once
2911 the composer allowed it to be recorded once. This is the part of
2912
2913 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
2914 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
2915 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
2916 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
2917 </para>
2918 <para>
2919 American law ordinarily calls this a "compulsory license," but I will
2920 refer to it as a "statutory license." A statutory license is a license
2921 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
2922 Copyright Act in 1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
2923 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
2924 the fee set by the statute.
2925 </para>
2926 <para>
2927 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
2928 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
2929 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
2930 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
2931 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
2932 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
2933 Grisham.
2934 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
2935 </para>
2936 <para>
2937 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
2938 thus, in effect, the law subsidizes the recording industry through a
2939 kind of piracy&mdash;by giving recording artists a weaker right than
2940 it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles have less control
2941 over their creative work than Grisham does. And the beneficiaries of
2942 this less control are the recording industry and the public. The
2943 recording industry gets something of value for less than it otherwise
2944 would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range of musical
2945 creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its reasons for
2946 granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of rights
2947 holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
2948 creativity.<footnote><para>
2949 <!-- f10 -->
2950 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and
2951 H.R. 11794 Before the ( Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st
2952 sess., 217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
2953 in Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act, E. Fulton Brylawski and
2954 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
2955 </para></footnote>
2956 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
2957 </para>
2958 <para>
2959 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
2960 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
2961 records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
2962 relates,
2963 </para>
2964 <blockquote>
2965 <para>
2966 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
2967 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
2968 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
2969 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
2970 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
2971 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
2972 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
2973 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
2974 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before 1909 and
2975 the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
2976 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
2977 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
2978 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
2979 choice.<footnote><para>
2980 <!-- f11 -->
2981 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee
2982 on the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8
2983 March 1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
2984 this report.</para></footnote>
2985 </para>
2986 </blockquote>
2987 <para>
2988 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
2989 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
2990 </para>
2991 </sect2>
2992 <sect2 id="radio">
2993 <title>Radio</title>
2994 <para>
2995 Radio was also born of piracy.
2996 </para>
2997 <para>
2998 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
2999 "public performance" of the composer's work.<footnote><para>
3000 <!-- f12 -->
3001 See 17 United States Code, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning,
3002 record companies printed "Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast" and other
3003 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3004 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3005 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3006 station. See RCA Manufacturing Co. v. Whiteman, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd
3007 Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, "From Edison to the Broadcast
3008 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3009 Copyright," University of Chicago Law Review 70 (2003): 281.
3010 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned</primary></indexterm>
3011 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3012 </para></footnote>
3013 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3014 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3015 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3016 </para>
3017 <para>
3018 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3019 copy of the composer's work. The radio station is also performing a
3020 copy of the recording artist's work. It's one thing to have "Happy
3021 Birthday" sung on the radio by the local children's choir; it's quite
3022 another to have it sung by the Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The
3023 recording artist is adding to the value of the composition performed
3024 on the radio station. And if the law were perfectly consistent, the
3025 radio station would have to pay the recording artist for his work,
3026 just as it pays the composer of the music for his work.
3027
3028 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3029 </para>
3030 <para>
3031 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3032 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3033 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3034 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3035 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3036 of playing the song.
3037 </para>
3038 <para>
3039 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3040 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3041 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3042 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3043 </para>
3044 <para>
3045 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3046 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3047 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you get
3048 some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3049 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3050 "protected" right. The radio station thus gets to pirate the value of
3051 Madonna's work without paying her anything.
3052 </para>
3053 <para>
3054 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3055 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3056 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3057 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3058 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3059 to take something for nothing.
3060 </para>
3061 </sect2>
3062 <sect2 id="cabletv">
3063 <title>Cable TV</title>
3064 <para>
3065
3066 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3067 </para>
3068 <para>
3069 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3070 television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3071 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3072 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3073 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3074 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3075 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3076 did&mdash; Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3077 give away.
3078 </para>
3079 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas</primary></indexterm>
3080 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin</primary></indexterm>
3081 <para>
3082 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3083 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3084 "unfair and potentially destructive competition."<footnote><para>
3085 <!-- f13 -->
3086 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the
3087 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3088 Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966)
3089 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3090 Commission).
3091 </para></footnote>
3092 There may have been a "public interest" in spreading the reach of cable
3093 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3094 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, "Does public
3095 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?"<footnote><para>
3096 <!-- f14 -->
3097 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3098 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3099 </para></footnote>
3100 As another broadcaster put it,
3101 </para>
3102 <blockquote>
3103 <para>
3104 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3105 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3106 paid for.<footnote><para>
3107 <!-- f15 -->
3108 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3109 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3110 </para></footnote>
3111 </para>
3112 </blockquote>
3113 <para>
3114 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3115 </para>
3116 <blockquote>
3117 <para>
3118 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3119 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3120 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3121 think there are harsher words which would fit it.<footnote><para>
3122 <!-- f16 -->
3123 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3124 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3125 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3126 </para></footnote>
3127 </para>
3128 </blockquote>
3129 <para>
3130 These were "free-ride[rs]," Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3131 Heston said, who were "depriving actors of
3132 compensation."<footnote><para>
3133 <!-- f17 -->
3134 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3135 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3136 </para></footnote>
3137 </para>
3138 <para>
3139 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3140 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3141 </para>
3142 <blockquote>
3143 <para>
3144 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3145 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3146 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3147 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. . . . The
3148
3149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3150 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3151 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.<footnote><para>
3152 <!-- f18 -->
3153 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M.
3154 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3155 </para></footnote>
3156 </para>
3157 </blockquote>
3158 <para>
3159 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3160 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3161 </para>
3162 <para>
3163 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3164 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they "pirated."
3165 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3166 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3167 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3168 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3169 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3170 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3171 companies thus built their empire in part upon a "piracy" of the value
3172 created by broadcasters' content.
3173 </para>
3174 <para>
3175 These separate stories sing a common theme. If "piracy" means
3176 using value from someone else's creative property without permission
3177 from that creator&mdash;as it is increasingly described
3178 today<footnote><para>
3179 <!-- f19 -->
3180 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, The Engine
3181 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet&mdash;The Myth of Free
3182 Information, available at
3183 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #13</ulink>. "The
3184 threat of piracy&mdash;the use of someone else's creative work without
3185 permission or compensation&mdash;has grown with the Internet."
3186 </para></footnote>
3187 &mdash; then every industry affected by copyright today is the product
3188 and beneficiary of a certain kind of piracy. Film, records, radio,
3189 cable TV. . . . The list is long and could well be expanded. Every
3190 generation welcomes the pirates from the last. Every
3191 generation&mdash;until now.
3192 </para>
3193 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3194 </sect2>
3195 </sect1>
3196 <sect1 id="piracy">
3197 <title>CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"</title>
3198 <para>
3199 There is piracy of copyrighted material. Lots of it. This piracy comes
3200 in many forms. The most significant is commercial piracy, the
3201 unauthorized taking of other people's content within a commercial
3202 context. Despite the many justifications that are offered in its
3203 defense, this taking is wrong. No one should condone it, and the law
3204 should stop it.
3205 </para>
3206 <para>
3207 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of "taking"
3208 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3209 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3210 taking "piracy," however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3211 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3212 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3213 has so often done in the past.
3214 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3215 </para>
3216 <sect2 id="piracy-i">
3217 <title>Piracy I</title>
3218 <para>
3219 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3220 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3221 content, copy it, and sell it&mdash;all without the permission of a copyright
3222 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion
3223 every year to physical piracy<footnote><para>
3224 <!-- f1 -->
3225 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), The
3226 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003, July 2003, available at
3227
3228 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #14</ulink>. See also Ben Hunt, "Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,"
3229 Financial Times, 14 February 2003, 11.
3230 </para></footnote>
3231 (that works out to one in three CDs sold
3232 worldwide). The MPAA estimates that it loses $3 billion annually
3233 worldwide to piracy.
3234 </para>
3235 <para>
3236 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3237 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3238 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3239 This piracy is wrong.
3240 </para>
3241 <para>
3242 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3243 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3244 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor
3245 foreign
3246 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3247 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3248 developing
3249 nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years of our
3250 existence, treated as right.
3251 </para>
3252 <para>
3253 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3254 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3255 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3256 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3257 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian law
3258 does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3259 violate
3260 that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not just a
3261 moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally legal
3262 wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3263 </para>
3264 <para>
3265 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3266 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3267 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77 -->
3268 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3269 pirate
3270 nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a similar
3271 childhood.
3272 </para>
3273 <para>
3274 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3275 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3276 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3277 of intellectual property law.<footnote><para>
3278 <!-- f2 -->
3279 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism: Who
3280 Owns the Knowledge Economy? (New York: The New Press, 2003), 10&ndash;13,
3281 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights
3282 (TRIPS) agreement obligates member nations to create administrative
3283 and enforcement mechanisms for intellectual property rights, a costly
3284 proposition for developing countries. Additionally, patent rights may
3285 lead to higher prices for staple industries such as
3286 agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the disparity between burdens
3287 imposed upon developing countries and benefits conferred to
3288 industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit governments to use patents
3289 for public, noncommercial uses without first obtaining the patent
3290 holder's permission. Developing nations may be able to use this to
3291 gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower prices. This is a
3292 promising strategy for developing nations within the TRIPS framework.
3293 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
3294 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3295 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3296 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3297 is wrong.
3298 </para>
3299 <para>
3300 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3301 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3302 to American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3303 bought those American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any
3304 less money than they otherwise would have had.<footnote><para>
3305 <!-- f3 -->
3306 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3307 Liebowitz, Rethinking the Network Economy (New York: Amacom, 2002),
3308 144&ndash;90. "In some instances . . . the impact of piracy on the
3309 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3310 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3311 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3312 pirating were not an option." Ibid., 149.
3313 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3314 </para></footnote>
3315 </para>
3316 <para>
3317 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3318 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3319 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3320 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3321 "You wouldn't go into Barnes &amp; Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3322 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?"
3323 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes &amp;
3324 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3325 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3326 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3327 piracy of the tangible.
3328 </para>
3329 <para>
3330 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3331 property right of a very special sort, it is a property right. Like all
3332 property
3333 rights, the copyright gives the owner the right to decide the terms
3334 under which content is shared. If the copyright owner doesn't want to
3335 sell, she doesn't have to. There are exceptions: important statutory
3336 licenses
3337 that apply to copyrighted content regardless of the wish of the
3338 copyright owner. Those licenses give people the right to "take"
3339 copyrighted
3340 content whether or not the copyright owner wants to sell. But
3341
3342 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3343 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3344 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3345 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3346 technology
3347 of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the permission
3348 of a property owner. That is exactly what "property" means.
3349 </para>
3350 <para>
3351 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that
3352 the piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese
3353 "steal" Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft.
3354 Microsoft loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains
3355 users who are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the
3356 nation
3357 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software
3358 rather than steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will
3359 benefit
3360 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3361 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3362 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3363 Microsoft.
3364 Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3365 </para>
3366 <para>
3367 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a
3368 good one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3369 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3370 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will
3371 become
3372 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3373 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3374 </para>
3375 <para>
3376 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3377 alcoholic
3378 a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that will
3379 make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3380 ordinarily
3381 allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best to give
3382 their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of GNU/Linux,
3383 then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for example, with
3384 Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right means
3385 giving
3386 the property owner the right to say who gets access to what&mdash;at
3387 least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the rights of the
3388 copyright
3389 owner with the rights of access, then violating the law is still
3390 wrong.
3391 </para>
3392 <para>
3393 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3394 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3395 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3396 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3397 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3398 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3399 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3400 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3401 is flat out wrong.
3402 </para>
3403 <para>
3404 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3405 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all "piracy" is. Or
3406 at least, not all "piracy" is wrong if that term is understood in the
3407 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of "piracy" are useful
3408 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3409 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3410 "piracy" in that sense of the term.
3411 </para>
3412 <para>
3413 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3414 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3415 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3416 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3417 </para>
3418 <para>
3419 For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3420 controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it
3421 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable
3422 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3423 </para>
3424 <para>
3425 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3426 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3427 sharing
3428 to survive.
3429 </para>
3430 </sect2>
3431 <sect2 id="piracy-ii">
3432 <title>Piracy II</title>
3433 <para>
3434 The key to the "piracy" that the law aims to quash is a use that "rob[s]
3435 the author of [his] profit."<footnote><para>
3436 <!-- f4 -->
3437 Bach v. Longman, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777).
3438 </para></footnote>
3439 This means we must determine whether
3440 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3441 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3442 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3443 author of his profit.
3444 </para>
3445 <para>
3446 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3447 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3448 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3449 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well<footnote><para>
3450 <!-- f5 -->
3451 See Clayton M. Christensen, The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3452 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business (New York:
3453 HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3454 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3455 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3456 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3457 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3458 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, Future, 89&ndash;92, 139.
3459 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
3460 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3461 put together components that had been developed independently.
3462 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn</primary></indexterm>
3463 </para>
3464 <para>
3465 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999,
3466 Napster amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After
3467 eighteen months, there were close to 80 million registered users of the
3468 system.<footnote><para>
3469 <!-- f6 -->
3470 See Carolyn Lochhead, "Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare," San
3471 Francisco Chronicle, 24 September 2002, A1; "Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,"
3472 New Scientist, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, "Napster Names CEO,
3473 Secures New Financing," San Francisco Chronicle, 23 May 2003, C1;
3474 "Napster's Wake-Up Call," Economist, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton,
3475 "Hollywood at War with the Internet" (London) Times, 26 July 2002, 18.
3476 </para></footnote>
3477 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3478 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3479 boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3480 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3481 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3482 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend&mdash;
3483 or your 20,000 best friends.
3484 </para>
3485 <para>
3486 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of
3487 Americans
3488 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3489 September 2002 estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded
3490 music&mdash;28 percent of Americans older than 12.<footnote><para>
3491 <!-- f7 -->
3492 See Ipsos-Insight, TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution
3493 (September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3494 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have
3495 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3496 </para></footnote>
3497 A survey by the NPD
3498 group quoted in The New York Times estimated that 43 million citizens
3499 used file-sharing networks to exchange content in May 2003.<footnote><para>
3500 <!-- f8 -->
3501 Amy Harmon, "Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight," New
3502 York Times, 6 June 2003, A1.
3503 </para></footnote>
3504 The vast
3505 majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a massive
3506 quantity of content is being "taken" on these networks. The ease and
3507 inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired millions to
3508 enjoy
3509 music in a way that they hadn't before.
3510 </para>
3511 <para>
3512 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it
3513 does not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3514 infringement,
3515 calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3516 complicated than one might think. So consider&mdash;a bit more carefully
3517 than the polarized voices around this debate usually do&mdash;the kinds of
3518 sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds of harm it entails.
3519 </para>
3520 <para>
3521 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3522 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3523 different kinds into four types.
3524 </para>
3525 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
3526 <listitem><para>
3527 <!-- A. -->
3528 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for
3529 purchasing
3530 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released,
3531 rather than buying the CD, these users simply take it. We might
3532 quibble about whether everyone who takes it would actually
3533 have bought it if sharing didn't make it available for free. Most
3534 probably wouldn't have, but clearly there are some who would.
3535 The latter are the target of category A: users who download
3536 instead
3537 of purchasing.
3538 </para></listitem>
3539 <listitem><para>
3540 <!-- B. -->
3541 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3542 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an
3543 artist he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that
3544 artist. This is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to
3545 succeed.
3546 If the friend recommending the album gains nothing from
3547 a bad recommendation, then one could expect that the
3548 recommendations
3549 will actually be quite good. The net effect of this
3550 sharing could increase the quantity of music purchased.
3551 </para></listitem>
3552 <listitem><para>
3553 <!-- C. -->
3554 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to
3555 copyrighted
3556 content that is no longer sold or that they would not
3557 have purchased because the transaction costs off the Net are too
3558 high. This use of sharing networks is among the most
3559 rewarding
3560 for many. Songs that were part of your childhood but have
3561 long vanished from the marketplace magically appear again on
3562 the network. (One friend told me that when she discovered
3563 Napster, she spent a solid weekend "recalling" old songs. She
3564 was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3565 available.)
3566 For content not sold, this is still technically a violation of
3567 copyright, though because the copyright owner is not selling the
3568 content anymore, the economic harm is zero&mdash;the same harm
3569 that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to
3570 a local collector.
3571 </para></listitem>
3572 <listitem><para>
3573 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3574 <!-- D. -->
3575 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3576 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3577 wants to give away.
3578 </para></listitem>
3579 </orderedlist>
3580 <para>
3581 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3582 </para>
3583 <para>
3584 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3585 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3586 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3587 harmful.<footnote><para>
3588 <!-- f9 -->
3589 See Liebowitz, Rethinking the Network Economy,148&ndash;49.
3590 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3591 </para></footnote>
3592 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3593 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3594 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3595 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3596 answer&mdash;and certainly much more difficult than the current
3597 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3598 </para>
3599 <para>
3600 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3601 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3602 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3603 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3604 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of "theft" that is
3605 "devastating" the industry.
3606 </para>
3607 <para>
3608 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3609 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3610 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3611 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3612 &amp; Young put it, "Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3613 technology, the labels fought it."<footnote><para>
3614 <!-- f10 -->
3615 See Cap Gemini Ernst &amp; Young, Technology Evolution and the
3616 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis (2003), 3. This report
3617 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3618 practice of cassette taping in the 1970s, including an advertising
3619 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption "Home taping
3620 is killing music." At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3621 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3622 behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3623 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3624 Assessment, Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law,
3625 OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3626 October 1989), 145&ndash;56. </para></footnote>
3627 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3628 when record sales fell by 11.4 percent in 1981, the industry claimed
3629 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3630 regulating technology was the answer.
3631 </para>
3632 <para>
3633 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3634 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3635 turnaround. "In the end," Cap Gemini concludes, "the `crisis' . . . was
3636 not the fault of the tapers&mdash;who did not [stop after MTV came into
3637 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
3638 being]&mdash;but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
3639 innovation at the major labels."<footnote><para>
3640 <!-- f11 -->
3641 U.S. Congress, Copyright and Home Copying, 4.
3642 </para></footnote>
3643 </para>
3644 <para>
3645 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
3646 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
3647 the industry in particular, and society in general&mdash;or at least
3648 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
3649 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
3650 VCR&mdash;the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
3651 harmful. The question is also how harmful type A sharing is, and how
3652 beneficial the other types of sharing are.
3653 </para>
3654 <para>
3655 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from
3656 the standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
3657 The "net harm" to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
3658 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
3659 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
3660 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They
3661 would therefore have little static reason to resist them.
3662 </para>
3663 <para>
3664 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining
3665 because
3666 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD
3667 sales actually suggest it might be close.
3668 </para>
3669 <para>
3670 In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9
3671 percent,
3672 from 882 million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7 percent.<footnote><para>
3673 <!-- f12 -->
3674 See Recording Industry Association of America, 2002 Yearend Statistics,
3675 available at
3676 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #15</ulink>. A later report indicates even greater losses. See
3677 Recording Industry Association of America, Some Facts About Music Piracy,
3678 25 June 2003, available at
3679 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #16</ulink>: "In the past four years, unit shipments
3680 of recorded music have fallen by 26 percent from 1.16 billion units in
3681 to 860 million units in 2002 in the United States (based on units shipped).
3682 In terms of sales, revenues are down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in
3683 to $12.6 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The
3684 music
3685 industry worldwide has gone from a $39 billion industry in 2000 down
3686 to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments)."
3687 </para></footnote>
3688 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
3689 Internet
3690 piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
3691 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
3692 than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That
3693 no doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
3694 account for at least some of the loss. "From 1999 to 2001, the average
3695 price of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19."<footnote>
3696 <!-- f13 -->
3697 <para>
3698 Jane Black, "Big Music's Broken Record," BusinessWeek online, 13
3699 February 2003, available at
3700 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #17</ulink>.
3701 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane</primary></indexterm>
3702 </para>
3703 </footnote>
3704 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of the
3705 decline. As Jane Black of BusinessWeek notes, "The soundtrack to the film
3706 High Fidelity has a list price of $18.98. You could get the whole movie
3707 [on DVD] for $19.99."<footnote><para>
3708 <!-- f14 -->
3709 Ibid.
3710 </para></footnote>
3711 </para>
3712 <para>
3713
3714 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
3715 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD
3716 sales is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
3717 that the RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
3718 estimates that 2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
3719 although
3720 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
3721 free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 percent.
3722 </para>
3723 <para>
3724 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
3725 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
3726 The recording industry constantly asks, "What's the difference
3727 between
3728 downloading a song and stealing a CD?"&mdash;but their own
3729 numbers
3730 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
3731 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
3732 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
3733 downloads. If every download were a lost sale&mdash;if every use of Kazaa
3734 "rob[bed] the author of [his] profit"&mdash;then the industry would have
3735 suffered a 100 percent drop in sales last year, not a 7 percent drop. If 2.6
3736 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for free, and yet sales
3737 revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, then there is a huge difference
3738 between
3739 "downloading a song and stealing a CD."
3740 </para>
3741 <para>
3742 These are the harms&mdash;alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
3743 assume,
3744 real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on the
3745 recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to these
3746 costs?
3747 </para>
3748 <para>
3749 One benefit is type C sharing&mdash;making available content that is
3750 technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
3751 available.
3752 This is not a small category of content. There are millions of
3753 tracks that are no longer commercially available.<footnote><para>
3754 <!-- f15 -->
3755 By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels is no
3756 longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright Law&mdash;Coming
3757 Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the Senate
3758 Committee
3759 on the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April 2001) (prepared
3760 statement
3761 of the Future of Music Coalition), available at
3762 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #18</ulink>.
3763 </para></footnote>
3764 And while it's
3765 conceivable
3766 that some of this content is not available because the artist
3767 producing the content doesn't want it to be made available, the vast
3768 majority of it is unavailable solely because the publisher or the
3769 distributor
3770 has decided it no longer makes economic sense to the company to
3771 make it available.
3772 </para>
3773 <para>
3774 In real space&mdash;long before the Internet&mdash;the market had a simple
3775 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
3776 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
3777 thousands
3778 of used book and used record stores in America today.<footnote><para>
3779 <!-- f16 -->
3780 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores in
3781 existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the United States,
3782 an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter Press, The Quiet
3783 Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book Market (2002), available at
3784 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #19</ulink>. Used records accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See
3785 National
3786 Association of Recording Merchandisers, "2002 Annual Survey
3787 Results,"
3788 available at
3789 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #20</ulink>.
3790 </para></footnote>
3791 These
3792 stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they buy. And
3793 under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this content,
3794 even if the content is still under copyright, the copyright owner doesn't get
3795 a dime. Used book and record stores are commercial entities; their
3796 owners make money from the content they sell; but as with cable
3797 companies
3798 before statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright
3799 owner for the content they sell.
3800 </para>
3801 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard</primary></indexterm>
3802 <para>
3803 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
3804 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
3805 the content available isn't making money from making the content
3806 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
3807 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
3808 when someone shares my 1949 recording of Bernstein's "Two Love Songs,"
3809 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
3810 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
3811 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
3812 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
3813 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
3814 </para>
3815 <para>
3816 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
3817 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
3818 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
3819 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
3820 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
3821 shut as well?
3822 </para>
3823 <para>
3824 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
3825 type D sharing to occur&mdash;the sharing of content that copyright owners
3826 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
3827 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
3828 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, Down and Out in
3829 the Magic Kingdom, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
3830
3831 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
3832 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
3833 would be a great advertisement for the "real" book. People would read
3834 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
3835 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
3836 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
3837 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
3838 great book!)
3839 </para>
3840 <para>
3841 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
3842 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
3843 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
3844 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
3845 </para>
3846 <para>
3847 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
3848 understandably says, "This is how much we've lost," we must also ask,
3849 "How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
3850 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
3851 unavailable?"
3852 </para>
3853 <para>
3854 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
3855 chapter, much of the "piracy" that file sharing enables is plainly
3856 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter 4, much of
3857 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
3858 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
3859 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
3860 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
3861 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
3862 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
3863 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
3864 found only with time.
3865 </para>
3866 <para>
3867 "But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
3868 just what you call type A sharing?"
3869 </para>
3870 <para>
3871 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The
3872 effect
3873 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
3874 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
3875 Napster
3876 case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
3877 developed
3878 a technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of identified
3879 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
3880 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4
3881 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
3882 "down to zero."<footnote><para>
3883 <!-- f17 -->
3884 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34-
3885 35 (N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183
3886 MHP, available at
3887 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #21</ulink>. For an account of the litigation and its toll on
3888 Napster, see Joseph Menn, All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn
3889 Fanning's
3890 Napster (New York: Crown Business, 2003), 269&ndash;82.
3891 </para></footnote>
3892 </para>
3893 <para>
3894 If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
3895 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
3896 assure that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance
3897 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of
3898 VCRs or 100 percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns
3899 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
3900 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
3901 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
3902 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
3903 </para>
3904 <para>
3905 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
3906 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
3907 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way
3908 content
3909 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
3910 technology.
3911 In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the legitimate rights
3912 of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes this has meant
3913 more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
3914 </para>
3915 <para>
3916 So, as we've seen, when "mechanical reproduction" threatened the
3917 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
3918 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
3919 composers,
3920 but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be paid, but
3921 at a price set by Congress. But when radio started broadcasting the
3922 recordings made by these recording artists, and they complained to
3923 Congress that their "creative property" was not being respected (since
3924 the radio station did not have to pay them for the creativity it
3925 broadcast),
3926 Congress rejected their claim. An indirect benefit was enough.
3927 </para>
3928 <para>
3929 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
3930 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
3931 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
3932 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
3933 companies
3934 the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory price.
3935 </para>
3936 <para>
3937
3938 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
3939 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
3940 pianos, served two important goals&mdash;indeed, the two central goals of
3941 any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new innovators
3942 would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver content.
3943 Second,
3944 the law assured that copyright holders would be paid for the
3945 content
3946 that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress simply
3947 required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they demanded
3948 for their content, then copyright holders associated with broadcasters
3949 would use their power to stifle this new technology, cable. But if
3950 Congress
3951 had permitted cable to use broadcasters' content for free, then it
3952 would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus Congress chose a path that
3953 would assure compensation without giving the past (broadcasters)
3954 control
3955 over the future (cable).
3956 </para>
3957 <indexterm><primary>Betamax</primary></indexterm>
3958 <para>
3959 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
3960 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
3961 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
3962 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
3963 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
3964 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
3965 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
3966 "record" button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
3967 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
3968 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
3969 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
3970 </para>
3971 <para>
3972 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
3973 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
3974 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
3975 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
3976 machine to copy only if there were a special "copy me" signal on the
3977 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
3978 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
3979 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
3980 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
3981 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
3982 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
3983 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
3984 for the architecture it chose.
3985 </para>
3986 <para>
3987 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
3988 champion. Valenti called VCRs "tapeworms." He warned, "When there are
3989 20, 30, 40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
3990 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
3991 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
3992 copyright."<footnote><para>
3993 <!-- f18 -->
3994 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
3995 S. 1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st
3996 and 2nd sess., 459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
3997 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
3998 </para></footnote>
3999 "One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4000 creative judgment," he told Congress, "to understand the devastation
4001 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4002 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4003 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4004 and plain common sense."<footnote><para>
4005 <!-- f19 -->
4006 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475.
4007 </para></footnote>
4008 Indeed, as surveys would later show,
4009 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more<footnote><para>
4010 <!-- f20 -->
4011 Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Sony Corp. of America, 480 F. Supp. 429,
4012 (C.D. Cal., 1979).
4013 </para></footnote>
4014 &mdash; a use the Court would later hold was not "fair." By
4015 "allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4016 copyright infringementwithout creating a mechanism to compensate
4017 copyrightowners," Valenti testified, Congress would "take from the
4018 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4019 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4020 profit from its reproduction."<footnote><para>
4021 <!-- f21 -->
4022 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony
4023 of Jack Valenti).
4024 </para></footnote>
4025 </para>
4026 <para>
4027 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4028 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4029 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction&mdash;leading Judge Alex Kozinski,
4030 who sits on that court, refers to it as the "Hollywood Circuit"&mdash;held
4031 that Sony would be liable for the copyright infringement made possible
4032 by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's rule, this totally familiar
4033 technology&mdash;which Jack Valenti had called "the Boston Strangler of the
4034 American film industry" (worse yet, it was a Japanese Boston Strangler
4035 of the American film industry)&mdash;was an illegal
4036 technology.<footnote><para>
4037 <!-- f22 -->
4038 Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Sony Corp. of America, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th Cir.
4039 1981).
4040 </para></footnote>
4041 </para>
4042 <para>
4043 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4044
4045 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4046 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4047 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4048 Court wrote,
4049 </para>
4050 <blockquote>
4051 <para>
4052 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4053 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4054 market
4055 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4056 authority
4057 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4058 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4059 implicated
4060 by such new technology.<footnote><para>
4061 <!-- f23 -->
4062 Sony Corp. of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 431 (1984).
4063 </para></footnote>
4064 </para>
4065 </blockquote>
4066 <para>
4067 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision.
4068 But as with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts,
4069 Congress
4070 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film
4071 got enough, this "taking" notwithstanding.
4072 If we put these cases together, a pattern is clear:
4073 </para>
4074
4075 <table id="t1">
4076 <title>Table</title>
4077 <tgroup cols="4" align="char">
4078 <thead>
4079 <row>
4080 <entry>CASE</entry>
4081 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS "PIRATED"</entry>
4082 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS</entry>
4083 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS</entry>
4084 </row>
4085 </thead>
4086 <tbody>
4087 <row>
4088 <entry>Recordings</entry>
4089 <entry>Composers</entry>
4090 <entry>No protection</entry>
4091 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4092 </row>
4093 <row>
4094 <entry>Radio</entry>
4095 <entry>Recording artists</entry>
4096 <entry>N/A</entry>
4097 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4098 </row>
4099 <row>
4100 <entry>Cable TV</entry>
4101 <entry>Broadcasters</entry>
4102 <entry>No protection</entry>
4103 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4104 </row>
4105 <row>
4106 <entry>VCR</entry>
4107 <entry>Film creators</entry>
4108 <entry>No protection</entry>
4109 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4110 </row>
4111 </tbody>
4112 </tgroup>
4113 </table>
4114
4115 <para>
4116 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4117 way content was distributed.<footnote><para>
4118 <!-- f24 -->
4119 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4120 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4121 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4122 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4123 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4124 1992 (Title 17 of the United States Code), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat.
4125 4237, codified at 17 U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4126 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4127 Lessig, Future, 71. See also Picker, "From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,"
4128 University of Chicago Law Review 70 (2003): 293&ndash;96.
4129 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
4130 </para></footnote>
4131 In each case, throughout our history,
4132 that change meant that someone got a "free ride" on someone else's
4133 work.
4134 </para>
4135 <para>
4136 In none of these cases did either the courts or Congress eliminate all
4137 free riding. In none of these cases did the courts or Congress insist that
4138 the law should assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his
4139 copyright created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of
4140 "piracy." In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the
4141 legitimacy
4142 in the behavior of the "pirates." In each case, Congress allowed
4143 some new technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced
4144 the interests at stake.
4145 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4146 </para>
4147 <para>
4148 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4149 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4150 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4151 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4152 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4153 regulated?
4154 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4155 to $15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4156 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4157 permission to record a song?
4158 </para>
4159 <para>
4160 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4161 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4162 copyright "has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4163 over all possible uses of his work."<footnote><para>
4164 <!-- f25 -->
4165 Sony Corp. of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417,
4166 (1984).
4167 </para></footnote>
4168 Instead, the particular uses that the
4169 law regulates have been defined by balancing the good that comes from
4170 granting an exclusive right against the burdens such an exclusive right
4171 creates. And this balancing has historically been done after a
4172 technology
4173 has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that facilitate
4174 the distribution of content.
4175 </para>
4176 <para>
4177 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4178 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4179 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4180 should not become a tool for "stealing" from artists. But neither should
4181 the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which artists
4182 (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in some detail
4183 in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing income to artists
4184 while we allow the market to secure the most efficient way to promote
4185 and distribute content. This will require changes in the law, at least
4186 in the interim. These changes should be designed to balance the
4187 protection
4188 of the law against the strong public interest that innovation
4189 continue.
4190 </para>
4191 <para>
4192
4193 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4194 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4195 superior
4196 mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4197 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4198 network.
4199 Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4200 efficient.
4201 Yet these "potential public benefits," as John Schwartz writes in
4202 The New York Times, "could be delayed in the P2P fight."<footnote><para>
4203 <!-- f26 -->
4204 John Schwartz, "New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4205 Echoes Past Efforts," New York Times, 22 September 2003, C3.
4206 </para></footnote>
4207 Yet when anyone begins to talk about "balance," the copyright
4208 warriors
4209 raise a different argument. "All this hand waving about balance
4210 and incentives," they say, "misses a fundamental point. Our content,"
4211 the warriors insist, "is our property. Why should we wait for Congress
4212 to `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4213 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4214 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether the
4215 car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?"
4216 </para>
4217 <para>
4218 "It is our property," the warriors insist. "And it should be protected
4219 just as any other property is protected."
4220 </para>
4221 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4222 </sect2>
4223 </sect1>
4224 </chapter>
4225 <chapter id="c-property">
4226 <title>"PROPERTY"</title>
4227 <para>
4228
4229 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4230 The copyright warriors are right: A copyright is a kind of
4231 property. It can be owned and sold, and the law protects against its
4232 theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to hold out for any price he
4233 wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand that partially determine
4234 the price she can get.
4235 </para>
4236 <para>
4237 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a "property" right is a
4238 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of property.
4239 Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any expression is very
4240 odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the picnic table you
4241 put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic table, and after I
4242 take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking when I take the good
4243 idea you had to put a picnic table in the backyard&mdash;by, for example,
4244 going
4245 to Sears, buying a table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the
4246 thing I am taking then?
4247 </para>
4248 <para>
4249 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4250 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4251 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4252 in the ordinary case&mdash;indeed, in practically every case except for a
4253 narrow
4254 range of exceptions&mdash;ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4255 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress&mdash;though I
4256 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4257 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4258 when I copy the way someone else dresses), "He who receives an idea
4259 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4260 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me."<footnote><para>
4261 <!-- f1 -->
4262 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in
4263 The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4264 Ellery Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333&ndash;34.
4265 </para></footnote>
4266 </para>
4267 <para>
4268 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4269 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4270 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4271 expression
4272 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4273 property.
4274 </para>
4275 <para>
4276 But how, and to what extent, and in what form&mdash;the details, in
4277 other words&mdash;matter. To get a good sense of how this practice of
4278 turning
4279 the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4280 "property"
4281 in its proper context.<footnote><para>
4282 <!-- f2 -->
4283 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4284 intangible.
4285 A property right is simply a right that an individual has against the
4286 world to do or not do certain things that may or may not attach to a
4287 physical
4288 object. The right itself is intangible, even if the object to which it is
4289 (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See Adam Mossoff, "What Is
4290 Property?
4291 Putting the Pieces Back Together," Arizona Law Review 45 (2003):
4292 373, 429 n. 241.
4293 </para></footnote>
4294 </para>
4295 <para>
4296 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4297 preceding
4298 part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of "copyright
4299 material
4300 is property" in context. Where did the idea come from? What are
4301 its limits? How does it function in practice? After these stories, the
4302 significance of this true statement&mdash;"copyright material is property"&mdash;
4303 will be a bit more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite
4304 different from the implications that the copyright warriors would have
4305 us draw.
4306 </para>
4307
4308 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4309 <sect1 id="founders">
4310 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders</title>
4311 <para>
4312 William Shakespeare wrote Romeo and Juliet in 1595. The play
4313 was first published in 1597. It was the eleventh major play that
4314 Shakespeare
4315 had written. He would continue to write plays through 1613,
4316 and the plays that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American
4317 culture ever since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer
4318 seeped into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source.
4319 I once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's
4320 adaptation
4321 of Henry V: "I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of clichés."
4322 </para>
4323 <para>
4324 In 1774, almost 180 years after Romeo and Juliet was written, the
4325 "copy-right" for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4326 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.<footnote><para>
4327 <!-- f1 -->
4328 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4329 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4330 handsome "definitive editions" of classic works. In addition to Romeo and
4331 Juliet, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4332 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4333 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, "Jacob Tonson,
4334 Bookseller," American Scholar 61:3 (1992): 424&ndash;31.
4335 </para></footnote>
4336 Tonson was the
4337 most prominent of a small group of publishers called the Conger<footnote><para>
4338 <!-- f2 -->
4339 Lyman Ray Patterson, Copyright in Historical Perspective (Nashville:
4340 Vanderbilt
4341 University Press, 1968), 151&ndash;52.
4342 </para></footnote>
4343 who
4344 controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth century. The
4345 Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the "copy" of books that
4346 they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant that no
4347 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4348 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4349 copyright.
4350 Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4351 produce
4352 better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4353 </para>
4354 <para>
4355 Now, there's something puzzling about the year 1774 to anyone who
4356 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the history
4357 of copyright is 1710, the year that the British Parliament adopted the
4358 first "copyright" act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the act stated that
4359 all published works would get a copyright term of fourteen years,
4360 renewable
4361 once if the author was alive, and that all works already
4362 published
4363 by 1710 would get a single term of twenty-one additional years.<footnote><para>
4364 <!-- f3 -->
4365 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4366 "copyright
4367 law." See Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs, 40.
4368 </para></footnote>
4369 Under this law, Romeo and Juliet should have been free in 1731. So why
4370 was there any issue about it still being under Tonson's control in 1774?
4371 </para>
4372 <para>
4373 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a
4374 "copyright"
4375 was&mdash;indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4376 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4377 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of 1662, had
4378 expired
4379 in 1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing, as
4380 a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was published.
4381 But after it expired, there was no positive law that said that the
4382 publishers,
4383 or "Stationers," had an exclusive right to print books.
4384 </para>
4385 <para>
4386 There was no positive law, but that didn't mean that there was no
4387 law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to both the words of
4388 legislatures and the words of judges to know the rules that are to
4389 govern
4390 how people are to behave. We call the words from legislatures
4391 "positive
4392 law." We call the words from judges "common law." The common
4393 law sets the background against which legislatures legislate; the
4394 legislature,
4395 ordinarily, can trump that background only if it passes a law to
4396 displace it. And so the real question after the licensing statutes had
4397 expired
4398 was whether the common law protected a copyright,
4399 independent
4400 of any positive law.
4401 </para>
4402 <para>
4403 This question was important to the publishers, or "booksellers," as
4404 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4405 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4406 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4407
4408 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4409 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4410 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4411 ultimately
4412 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4413 </para>
4414 <para>
4415 The Statute of Anne granted the author or "proprietor" of a book
4416 an exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4417 however,
4418 and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the bookseller
4419 that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the copyright
4420 "expired,"
4421 and the work would then be free and could be published by
4422 anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have believed.
4423 </para>
4424 <para>
4425 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4426 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to the
4427 particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right at all?
4428 </para>
4429 <para>
4430 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a
4431 very strong claim. Take Romeo and Juliet as an example: That play was
4432 written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4433 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4434 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating this
4435 play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So why is it
4436 that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and take
4437 Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4438 reason
4439 is there to allow someone else to "steal" Shakespeare's work?
4440 </para>
4441 <para>
4442 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something
4443 special
4444 about the notion of "copyright" that existed at the time of the
4445 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4446 "booksellers."
4447 </para>
4448 <para>
4449 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have
4450 come to apply the concept of "copyright" ever more broadly. But in
4451 1710, it wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4452 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4453 others
4454 from reprinting a book. In 1710, the "copy-right" was a right to use
4455 a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not go
4456 beyond
4457 that very narrow right. It did not control any more generally how
4458 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4459 a work could be used. Today the right includes a large collection of
4460 restrictions
4461 on the freedom of others: It grants the author the exclusive
4462 right to copy, the exclusive right to distribute, the exclusive right to
4463 perform, and so on.
4464 </para>
4465 <para>
4466 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4467 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4468 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4469 permission
4470 of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4471 anything,
4472 for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4473 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4474 allowed to make his films. The "copy-right" was only an exclusive right
4475 to print&mdash;no less, of course, but also no more.
4476 </para>
4477 <para>
4478 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4479 They had had a long and ugly experience with "exclusive rights,"
4480 especially
4481 "exclusive rights" granted by the Crown. The English had fought
4482 a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4483 monopolies&mdash;especially
4484 monopolies for works that already existed. King Henry
4485 VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a monopoly to Darcy to
4486 print playing cards. The English Parliament began to fight back
4487 against this power of the Crown. In 1656, it passed the Statute of
4488 Monopolies,
4489 limiting monopolies to patents for new inventions. And by
4490 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing monopoly in
4491 publishing.
4492 </para>
4493 <para>
4494 Thus the "copy-right," when viewed as a monopoly right, was
4495 naturally
4496 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing
4497 the claim that "it's my property, and I should have it forever," try
4498 sounding convincing when uttering, "It's my monopoly, and I should
4499 have it forever.") The state would protect the exclusive right, but only
4500 so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4501 specialinterest
4502 favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4503 </para>
4504 <para>
4505 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4506 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4507 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4508 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4509 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4510 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst kind&mdash;tools of the
4511 Crown's repression, selling the liberty of England to guarantee
4512 themselves
4513 a monopoly profit. The attacks against these monopolists were
4514 harsh: Milton described them as "old patentees and monopolizers in
4515 the trade of book-selling"; they were "men who do not therefore labour
4516 in an honest profession to which learning is indetted."<footnote><para>
4517 <!-- f4 -->
4518 Philip Wittenberg, The Protection and Marketing of Literary Property (New
4519 York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31.
4520 </para></footnote>
4521 </para>
4522 <para>
4523 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread
4524 of knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the
4525 Enlightenment
4526 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4527 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of the
4528 time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering with
4529 that idea.
4530 </para>
4531 <para>
4532 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4533 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4534 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4535 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4536 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4537 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4538 compromise
4539 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4540 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4541 construction and spread of culture.
4542 </para>
4543 <para>
4544 When 1731 (1710 + 21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4545 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4546 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4547 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4548 to control publication. But in 1735 and 1737, they tried to persuade
4549 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4550 they said; they needed more time.
4551 </para>
4552 <para>
4553 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4554 words that echo today,
4555 </para>
4556 <blockquote>
4557 <para>
4558 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4559 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4560 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4561 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4562 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4563 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4564 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4565 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4566 Booksellers.<footnote><para>
4567 <!-- f5 -->
4568 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4569 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4570 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4571 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4572 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4573 mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4574 al., 8, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618).
4575 </para></footnote>
4576 </para>
4577 </blockquote>
4578 <para>
4579 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4580 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4581 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
4582 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
4583 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
4584 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
4585 creative "property" and use it without his permission. The Statute of
4586 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
4587 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
4588 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
4589 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
4590 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
4591 way to protect authors.
4592 </para>
4593 <para>
4594 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
4595 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
4596 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
4597 "The publishers . . . had as much concern for authors as a cattle
4598 rancher has for cattle."<footnote><para>
4599 <!-- f6 -->
4600 Lyman Ray Patterson, "Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use," Vanderbilt
4601 Law Review 40 (1987): 28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
4602 Vaidhyanathan, 37&ndash;48.
4603 </para></footnote>
4604 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
4605 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
4606 </para>
4607 <para>
4608 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
4609 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
4610 Donaldson.<footnote><para>
4611 <!-- f7 -->
4612 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, Authorship and Copyright
4613 (London: Routledge, 1992), 62&ndash;69.
4614 </para></footnote>
4615 </para>
4616 <para>
4617 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
4618 career in Edinburgh in 1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
4619 reprints "of standard works whose copyright term had expired," at least
4620 under the Statute of Anne.<footnote><para>
4621 <!-- f8 -->
4622 Mark Rose, Authors and Owners (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
4623 1993), 92.
4624 </para></footnote>
4625 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
4626 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
4627 and became "something of a center for literary Scotsmen." "[A]mong
4628 them," Professor Mark Rose writes, was "the young James Boswell
4629 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
4630 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson."<footnote><para>
4631 <!-- f9 -->
4632 Ibid., 93.
4633 </para></footnote>
4634 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew</primary></indexterm>
4635 </para>
4636 <para>
4637 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
4638 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
4639 inexpensive editions "of the most popular English books, in defiance
4640 of the supposed common law right of Literary
4641 Property."<footnote><para>
4642 <!-- f10 -->
4643 Lyman Ray Patterson, Copyright in Historical Perspective, 167 (quoting
4644 Borwell).
4645 </para></footnote>
4646 His books undercut the Conger prices by 30 to 50 percent, and he
4647 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
4648 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
4649 </para>
4650 <para>
4651 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block "piracy" like
4652 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the "pirates,"
4653 the most important early victory being Millar v. Taylor.
4654 </para>
4655 <para>
4656 Millar was a bookseller who in 1729 had purchased the rights to James
4657 Thomson's poem "The Seasons." Millar complied with the requirements of
4658 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
4659 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
4660 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
4661 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.<footnote><para>
4662 <!-- f11 -->
4663 Howard B. Abrams, "The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
4664 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright," Wayne Law Review 29
4665 (1983): 1152.
4666 </para></footnote>
4667 </para>
4668 <indexterm id="idxmansfield2" class='startofrange'>
4669 <primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary>
4670 </indexterm>
4671 <para>
4672 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
4673 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
4674 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
4675 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
4676 law would protect the author against subsequent "pirates."
4677 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
4678 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
4679 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
4680 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
4681 </para>
4682 <para>
4683 Considered as a matter of abstract justice&mdash;reasoning as if
4684 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
4685 principles&mdash;Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
4686 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
4687 with in 1710: How best to limit
4688 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
4689 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
4690 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in 1710, but
4691 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
4692 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
4693 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
4694 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
4695 </para>
4696 <indexterm startref="idxmansfield2" class='endofrange'/>
4697 <para>
4698 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
4699 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
4700 </para>
4701 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
4702 <para>
4703 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
4704 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
4705 Thomas Beckett.<footnote><para>
4706 <!-- f12 -->
4707 Ibid., 1156.
4708 </para></footnote>
4709 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
4710 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in Millar,
4711 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
4712 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
4713 Court. In February of 1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
4714 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
4715 </para>
4716 <para>
4717 As few legal cases ever do, Donaldson v. Beckett drew an enormous
4718 amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers argued
4719 that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the Statute
4720 of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute of Anne,
4721 the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control publication
4722 came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term specified in
4723 the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been protected by the
4724 statute were no longer protected.
4725 </para>
4726 <para>
4727 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
4728 presented to the House and voted upon first by the "law lords,"
4729 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
4730 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
4731 House of Lords generally voted.
4732 </para>
4733 <para>
4734 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
4735 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
4736 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
4737 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
4738 (22 to 11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
4739 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
4740 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
4741 passed into the public domain.
4742 </para>
4743 <para>
4744 "The public domain." Before the case of Donaldson v. Beckett, there
4745 was no clear idea of a public domain in England. Before 1774, there
4746 was a strong argument that common law copyrights were perpetual.
4747 After 1774, the public domain was born. For the first time in
4748 Anglo-American history, the legal control over creative works expired,
4749 and the greatest works in English history&mdash;including those of
4750 Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson, and Bunyan&mdash;were free of
4751 legal restraint.
4752 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis</primary></indexterm>
4753 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John</primary></indexterm>
4754 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel</primary></indexterm>
4755 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
4756 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4757 </para>
4758 <para>
4759 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
4760 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
4761 where most of the "pirate publishers" did their work, people
4762 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the Edinburgh Advertiser
4763 reported, "No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
4764 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
4765 decision of which so many individuals were interested." "Great
4766 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
4767 and illuminations."<footnote><para>
4768 <!-- f13 -->
4769 Rose, 97.
4770 </para></footnote>
4771 </para>
4772 <para>
4773 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
4774 equally strong in the opposite direction. The Morning Chronicle
4775 reported:
4776 </para>
4777 <blockquote>
4778 <para>
4779 By the above decision . . . near 200,000 pounds worth of what was
4780 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
4781 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
4782 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
4783 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
4784 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
4785 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
4786 successors.<footnote><para>
4787 <!-- f14 -->
4788 Ibid.
4789 </para></footnote>
4790 </para>
4791 </blockquote>
4792 <para>
4793 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
4794 "Ruined" is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
4795 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
4796 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
4797 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
4798 free. Not in the sense that copyrights would not be respected, for of
4799 course, for a limited time after a work was published, the bookseller
4800 had an exclusive right to control the publication of that book. And
4801 not in the sense that books could be stolen, for even after a
4802 copyright expired, you still had to buy the book from someone. But
4803 free in the sense that the culture and its growth would no longer be
4804 controlled by a small group of publishers. As every free market does,
4805 this free market of free culture would grow as the consumers and
4806 producers chose. English culture would develop as the many English
4807 readers chose to let it develop&mdash; chose in the books they bought
4808 and wrote; chose in the memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a
4809 competitive context, not a context in which the choices about what
4810 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
4811 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
4812 </para>
4813 <para>
4814 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
4815 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
4816 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
4817 protected.
4818 </para>
4819 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
4820 </sect1>
4821 <sect1 id="recorders">
4822 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders</title>
4823 <para>
4824 Jon Else is a filmmaker. He is best known for his documentaries and
4825 has been very successful in spreading his art. He is also a teacher, and
4826 as a teacher myself, I envy the loyalty and admiration that his students
4827 feel for him. (I met, by accident, two of his students at a dinner party.
4828 He was their god.)
4829 </para>
4830 <para>
4831 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
4832 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
4833 today.
4834 </para>
4835 <para>
4836 In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
4837 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
4838 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
4839 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
4840 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
4841 stage.
4842 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
4843 </para>
4844 <para>
4845 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
4846 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
4847 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
4848 and the opera company played Wagner, was The Simpsons. As Else judged
4849 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
4850 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
4851 about the scene.
4852 </para>
4853 <para>
4854 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
4855 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of The Simpsons.
4856 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
4857 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
4858 unless "fair use" or some other privilege applies.
4859 </para>
4860 <para>
4861 Else called Simpsons creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
4862 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
4863 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
4864 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
4865 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
4866 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
4867 </para>
4868 <para>
4869 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
4870 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
4871 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
4872 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
4873 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
4874 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
4875 </para>
4876 <para>
4877 Then, as Else told me, "two things happened. First we discovered
4878 . . . that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation&mdash;or at
4879 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation."
4880 And second, Fox "wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
4881 to use this four-point-five seconds of . . . entirely unsolicited
4882 Simpsons which was in the corner of the shot."
4883 </para>
4884 <para>
4885 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
4886 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
4887 explained to her, "There must be some mistake here. . . . We're
4888 asking for your educational rate on this." That was the educational
4889 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
4890 confirm what he had been told.
4891 </para>
4892 <para>
4893 "I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight," he told me. "Yes, you
4894 have your facts straight," she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the
4895 clip of The Simpsons in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
4896 about
4897
4898 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
4899 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, "And
4900 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys." As an assistant
4901 to Herrera told Else later on, "They don't give a shit. They just want
4902 the money."
4903 </para>
4904 <para>
4905 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
4906 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
4907 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
4908 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
4909 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
4910 The Day After Trinity, from ten years before.
4911 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
4912 </para>
4913 <para>
4914 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
4915 copyright to The Simpsons. That copyright is their property. To use
4916 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
4917 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
4918 Simpsons copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
4919 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
4920 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
4921 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
4922 says the owner gets to control.
4923 </para>
4924 <para>
4925 For example, "public performance" is a use of The Simpsons that the
4926 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
4927 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see "My
4928 Favorite Simpsons," then you need to get permission from the copyright
4929 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
4930 whatever she wants&mdash;$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set
4931 by the law.
4932 </para>
4933 <para>
4934 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
4935 thought is "fair use."<footnote><para>
4936 <!-- f1 -->
4937 For an excellent argument that such use is "fair use," but that
4938 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is "fair use," see Richard
4939 A. Posner with William F. Patry, "Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
4940 Wake of Eldred " (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
4941 Law School, 5 August 2003.
4942 </para></footnote>
4943 Else's use of just 4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a Simpsons
4944 episode is clearly a fair use of The Simpsons&mdash;and fair use does
4945 not require the permission of anyone.
4946 </para>
4947 <para>
4948 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
4949 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon "fair use." Here's his reply:
4950 </para>
4951 <blockquote>
4952 <para>
4953 The Simpsons fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
4954 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
4955 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
4956 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was "clearly
4957 fair use" in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
4958 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
4959 </para>
4960 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
4961 <listitem><para>
4962 <!-- 1. -->
4963 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
4964 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
4965 "visual cue sheet" listing the source and licensing status of each
4966 shot in the film. They take a dim view of "fair use," and a claim of
4967 "fair use" can grind the application process to a halt.
4968 </para></listitem>
4969 <listitem><para>
4970 <!-- 2. -->
4971 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
4972 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
4973 tracking down and stopping unlicensed Simpsons usage, just as George
4974 Lucas had a very high profile litigating Star Wars usage. So I decided
4975 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
4976 license to four seconds of Simpsons. As a documentary producer working
4977 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
4978 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
4979 principle.
4980 </para></listitem>
4981 <listitem><para>
4982 <!-- 3. -->
4983 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
4984 School . . . who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
4985 that Fox would "depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
4986 life," regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
4987 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
4988 pockets, me or them.
4989 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
4990 </para></listitem>
4991 <listitem><para>
4992 <!-- 4. -->
4993 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
4994 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
4995 money.
4996 </para></listitem>
4997 </orderedlist>
4998 </blockquote>
4999 <para>
5000 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5001 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5002 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5003 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5004 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5005 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5006 </para>
5007 <para>
5008 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5009 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5010 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5011 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5012 not.
5013 </para>
5014 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5015 </sect1>
5016 <sect1 id="transformers">
5017 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers</title>
5018 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul</primary></indexterm>
5019 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5020 <para>
5021 In 1993, Alex Alben was a lawyer working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave
5022 was an innovative company founded by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to
5023 develop digital entertainment. Long before the Internet became
5024 popular, Starwave began investing in new technology for delivering
5025 entertainment in anticipation of the power of networks.
5026 </para>
5027 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5028 <para>
5029 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5030 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology&mdash;not to distribute
5031 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5032 difficult. In 1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5033 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5034 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5035 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5036 important to his career.
5037 </para>
5038 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5039 <para>
5040 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5041 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5042 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5043 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5044 </para>
5045 <para>
5046 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5047 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5048 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5049 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5050 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5051 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5052 </para>
5053 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5054 <para>
5055 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. "Our
5056 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5057 Eastwood's films," Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5058 arose. "No one had ever really done this before," Alben explained. "No
5059 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5060 actor's career."
5061 </para>
5062 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5063 <para>
5064 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5065 Slade asked, "Well, what will it take?"
5066 </para>
5067 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5068 <para>
5069 Alben replied, "Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5070 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5071 else that we want to use in these film clips." Slade said, "Great! Go
5072 for it."<footnote>
5073 <para>
5074 <!-- f1 -->
5075 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5076 publicity&mdash;rights an artist has to control the commercial
5077 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden "Rip, Mix,
5078 Burn" creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5079 <indexterm>
5080 <primary>artists</primary>
5081 <secondary>publicity rights on images of</secondary>
5082 </indexterm>
5083 </para></footnote>
5084 </para>
5085 <para>
5086 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5087 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5088 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5089 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5090 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5091 </para>
5092 <para>
5093 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5094 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5095 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5096 </para>
5097 <blockquote>
5098 <para>
5099 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5100 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include&mdash;of
5101 course we were going to use the "Make my day" clip from Dirty
5102 Harry. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5103 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5104 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5105 </para>
5106 <para>
5107 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5108 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5109 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5110 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5111 rate at the time was about $600. So we had to identify the
5112 people&mdash;some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5113 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5114 glass&mdash;is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5115 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5116 started calling people.
5117 </para>
5118 </blockquote>
5119 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5120 <para>
5121 Some actors were glad to help&mdash;Donald Sutherland, for example,
5122 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5123 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5124 "Hey, can I pay you $600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5125 know, $1,200?" And they would say, "Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5126 to get $1,200." And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5127 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5128 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5129 career.
5130 </para>
5131 <para>
5132 It was one year later&mdash;"and even then we weren't sure whether we
5133 were totally in the clear."
5134 </para>
5135 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5136 <para>
5137 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5138 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5139 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5140 </para>
5141 <blockquote>
5142 <para>
5143 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5144 hands and said, "Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5145 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5146 actors." But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5147 constituent parts and said, "Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5148 directors, . . . this many musicians," and we just went at it very
5149 systematically and cleared the rights.
5150 </para>
5151 </blockquote>
5152 <para>
5153
5154 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5155 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5156 loved it, and it sold very well.
5157 </para>
5158 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5159 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter</primary></indexterm>
5160 <para>
5161 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5162 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5163 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, "There is
5164 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5165 at all."<footnote><para>
5166 <!-- f2 -->
5167 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, Seven
5168 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition, available at
5169 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #22</ulink>.
5170 </para></footnote>
5171 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5172 has to be made?
5173 </para>
5174 <para>
5175 For, as he acknowledged, "very few . . . have the time and resources,
5176 and the will to do this," and thus, very few such works would ever be
5177 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5178 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5179 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5180 </para>
5181 <blockquote>
5182 <para>
5183 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5184 he or she gets paid very well. . . . And then when 30 seconds of
5185 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5186 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person . . . should be
5187 compensated for that.
5188 </para>
5189 </blockquote>
5190 <para>
5191 Or at least, is this how the artist should be compensated? Would it
5192 make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind of statutory license
5193 that someone could pay and be free to make derivative use of clips
5194 like this? Did it really make sense that a follow-on creator would
5195 have to track down every artist, actor, director, musician, and get
5196 explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a lot more be created if the
5197 legal part of the creative process could be made to be more clean?
5198 </para>
5199 <blockquote>
5200 <para>
5201 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5202 mechanism&mdash;where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5203 subject to estranged former spouses&mdash;you'd see a lot more of this
5204 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5205 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5206 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5207 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5208 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5209 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5210 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5211 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5212 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5213 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5214 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, "Oh, I
5215 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5216 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5217 money," then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5218 </para>
5219 </blockquote>
5220 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5221 <para>
5222 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5223 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5224 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5225 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5226 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5227 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5228 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5229 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5230 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5231 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5232 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5233 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5234 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5235 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5236 "Does this still make sense?"
5237 </para>
5238 <para>
5239 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5240 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5241 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5242 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5243
5244 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5245 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5246 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5247 </para>
5248 <para>
5249 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5250 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a 60 Minutes episode.
5251 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5252 judges loved every minute of it.
5253 </para>
5254 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David</primary></indexterm>
5255 <para>
5256 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5257 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5258 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5259 room of over 250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5260 began his talk with a question: "Do you know how many federal laws
5261 were just violated in this room?"
5262 </para>
5263 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David</primary></indexterm>
5264 <para>
5265 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5266 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5267 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5268 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5269 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle
5270 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5271 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5272 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5273 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5274 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5275 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5276 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5277 couldn't easily do them legally.
5278 </para>
5279 <para>
5280 We live in a "cut and paste" culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5281 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5282 and paste architecture of the Internet created&mdash;in a second you can
5283 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5284 planted in your presentation.
5285 </para>
5286 <para>
5287 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5288 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5289 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5290 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5291 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5292 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5293 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5294 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5295 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5296 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos</primary></indexterm>
5297 </para>
5298 <para>
5299 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5300 wanted to be "legal," the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5301 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5302 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5303 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5304 </para>
5305 <para>
5306 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5307 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5308 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5309 necessarily requiring that the "free" use be free as in "free beer."
5310 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5311 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5312 along: a rule, for example, that says "the royalty owed the copyright
5313 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5314 will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5315 copyright owner." Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5316 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5317 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5318 registers the work.
5319 </para>
5320 <para>
5321 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5322 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5323 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5324 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5325 </para>
5326 <para>
5327 In February 2003, DreamWorks studios announced an agreement with Mike
5328 Myers, the comic genius of Saturday Night Live and
5329 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5330 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5331 would work together to form a "unique filmmaking pact." Under the
5332 agreement, DreamWorks "will acquire the rights to existing motion
5333 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and&mdash;with the use
5334 of stateof-the-art digital technology&mdash;insert Myers and other
5335 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5336 entertainment."
5337 </para>
5338 <para>
5339 The announcement called this "film sampling." As Myers explained,
5340 "Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5341 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5342 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5343 to take that same concept and apply it to film." Steven Spielberg is
5344 quoted as saying, "If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5345 new audiences, it is Mike."
5346 </para>
5347 <para>
5348 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5349 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5350 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5351 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5352 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5353 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5354 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5355 privilege reserved for the funny and famous&mdash;and presumably rich.
5356 </para>
5357 <para>
5358 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5359 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of "fair use."
5360 Much of "sampling" should be considered "fair use." But few would
5361 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5362 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5363 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5364 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5365 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5366 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5367 process is a process of paying lawyers&mdash;again a privilege, or perhaps a
5368 curse, reserved for the few.
5369 </para>
5370 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5371 </sect1>
5372 <sect1 id="collectors">
5373 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors</title>
5374 <para>
5375 In April 1996, millions of "bots"&mdash;computer codes designed to
5376 "spider," or automatically search the Internet and copy content&mdash;began
5377 running across the Net. Page by page, these bots copied Internet-based
5378 information onto a small set of computers located in a basement in San
5379 Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots finished the whole of the Internet,
5380 they started again. Over and over again, once every two months, these
5381 bits of code took copies of the Internet and stored them.
5382 </para>
5383 <para>
5384 By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5385 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5386 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5387 the world. Using a technology called "the Way Back Machine," you could
5388 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to 1996, as
5389 well as when those pages changed.
5390 </para>
5391 <para>
5392 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5393 appreciated. In the dystopia described in 1984, old newspapers were
5394 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5395 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5396 reports.
5397 </para>
5398 <para>
5399 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5400 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5401 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5402 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5403 </para>
5404 <para>
5405 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5406 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5407 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5408 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5409 library&mdash;constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5410 </para>
5411 <para>
5412 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5413 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5414 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5415 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5416 what others might prefer you forget.<footnote><para>
5417 <!-- f1 -->
5418 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5419 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003,
5420 press release stated, "Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended." That was
5421 later changed, without notice, to "Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5422 Have Ended." E-mail from Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003.
5423 </para></footnote>
5424 </para>
5425 <para>
5426 We take it for granted that we can go back to see what we remember
5427 reading. Think about newspapers. If you wanted to study the reaction
5428 of your hometown newspaper to the race riots in Watts in 1965, or to
5429 Bull Connor's water cannon in 1963, you could go to your public
5430 library and look at the newspapers. Those papers probably exist on
5431 microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in paper, too. Either way, you
5432 are free, using a library, to go back and remember&mdash;not just what
5433 it is convenient to remember, but remember something close to the
5434 truth.
5435 </para>
5436 <para>
5437 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5438 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We all forget history. The key is
5439 whether we have a way to go back to rediscover what we forget. More
5440 directly, the key is whether an objective past can keep us
5441 honest. Libraries help do that, by collecting content and keeping it,
5442 for schoolchildren, for researchers, for grandma. A free society
5443 presumes this knowedge.
5444 </para>
5445 <para>
5446 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5447 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5448 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5449 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5450 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5451 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5452 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5453 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet&mdash;the
5454 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5455 </para>
5456 <para>
5457 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5458 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5459 researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5460 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5461 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5462 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5463 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10
5464 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5465 </para>
5466 <para>
5467 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
5468 human history. At the end of 2002, it held "two hundred and thirty
5469 terabytes of material"&mdash;and was "ten times larger than the
5470 Library of Congress." And this was just the first of the archives that
5471 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
5472 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
5473 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
5474 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
5475 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
5476 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University&mdash;thanks to a
5477 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
5478 is available to scholars for a very low fee. "But other than that,
5479 [television] is almost unavailable," Kahle told me. "If you were
5480 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
5481 just a graduate student?" As Kahle put it,
5482 </para>
5483 <blockquote>
5484 <para>
5485 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
5486 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
5487 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
5488 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
5489 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
5490
5491 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
5492 60 Minutes episode that came out after it . . . it would be almost
5493 impossible. . . . Those materials are almost unfindable. . . .
5494 </para>
5495 </blockquote>
5496 <para>
5497 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
5498 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
5499 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
5500 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
5501 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
5502 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
5503 </para>
5504 <para>
5505 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
5506 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
5507 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
5508 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
5509 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
5510 work.
5511 </para>
5512 <para>
5513 These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library
5514 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
5515 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
5516 borrow back the deposits&mdash;for an unlimited time at no cost. In
5517 1915 alone, there were more than 5,475 films deposited and "borrowed
5518 back." Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
5519 held by any library. The copy exists&mdash;if it exists at
5520 all&mdash;in the library archive of the film company.<footnote><para>
5521 <!-- f2 -->
5522 Doug Herrick, "Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
5523 the Library of Congress," Film Library Quarterly 13 nos. 2&ndash;3
5524 (1980): 5; Anthony Slide, Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
5525 Preservation in the United States ( Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland &amp;
5526 Co., 1992), 36.
5527 </para></footnote>
5528 </para>
5529 <para>
5530 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
5531 were originally not copyrighted&mdash;there was no way to capture the
5532 broadcasts, so there was no fear of "theft." But as technology enabled
5533 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
5534 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
5535 "copyrighted." But those copies were simply kept by the
5536 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
5537 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
5538 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
5539 </para>
5540 <para>
5541 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and
5542 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
5543 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
5544 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
5545 September 11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
5546 stations from around the world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made
5547 their coverage during the week of September 11 available free on-line.
5548 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
5549 events of that day.
5550 </para>
5551 <para>
5552 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
5553 archive of film includes close to 45,000 "ephemeral films" (meaning
5554 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
5555 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
5556 1,300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
5557 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
5558 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
5559 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
5560 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
5561 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
5562 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
5563 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
5564 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the "Duck and Cover" film
5565 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
5566 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
5567 few minutes&mdash;for free.
5568 </para>
5569 <para>
5570 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
5571 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
5572 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
5573 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
5574 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
5575 to find them.
5576 </para>
5577 <para>
5578 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
5579 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
5580 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
5581 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
5582 property, but during a second life that all creative property
5583 has&mdash;a noncommercial life.
5584 </para>
5585 <para>
5586 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
5587 of creative property goes through different "lives." In its first
5588 life, if the
5589
5590 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
5591 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
5592 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
5593 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
5594 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
5595 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
5596 </para>
5597 <para>
5598 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
5599 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
5600 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
5601 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
5602 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
5603 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
5604 longer sold.
5605 </para>
5606 <para>
5607 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
5608 very quickly (the average today is after about a year<footnote><para>
5609 <!-- f3 -->
5610 Dave Barns, "Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
5611 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business," Chicago Tribune,
5612 5 September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927
5613 and 1946, only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese,
5614 "The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks," Boston
5615 College Law Review 44 (2003): 593 n. 51.
5616 </para></footnote>). After
5617 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
5618 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
5619 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
5620 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
5621 important to the spread and stability of culture.
5622 </para>
5623 <para>
5624 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
5625 creative property does not hold true with the most important
5626 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
5627 centuries. For these&mdash;television, movies, music, radio, the
5628 Internet&mdash;there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
5629 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes &amp;
5630 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
5631 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
5632 disappears.
5633 </para>
5634 <para>
5635 For most of the twentieth century, it was economics that made this
5636 so. It would have been insanely expensive to collect and make
5637 accessible all television and film and music: The cost of analog
5638 copies is extraordinarily high. So even though the law in principle
5639 would have restricted the ability of a Brewster Kahle to copy culture
5640 generally, the
5641 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
5642 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
5643 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
5644 little practical effect.
5645 </para>
5646 <para>
5647 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
5648 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
5649 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
5650 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
5651 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
5652 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
5653 </para>
5654 <para>
5655 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
5656 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
5657 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
5658 Kahle describes,
5659 </para>
5660 <blockquote>
5661 <para>
5662 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
5663 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
5664 movies, . . . and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
5665 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
5666 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
5667 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
5668 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
5669 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
5670 . . . thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
5671 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
5672 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
5673 </para>
5674 </blockquote>
5675 <para>
5676 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
5677 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
5678 libraries or archives could be. When the commercial life of creative
5679 property ends, I don't know. But it does. And whenever it does, Kahle
5680 and his archive hint at a world where this knowledge, and culture,
5681 remains perpetually available. Some will draw upon it to understand
5682 it;
5683 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
5684 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
5685 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
5686 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past&mdash;a
5687 future for our past. The technology of digital arts could make the
5688 dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
5689 </para>
5690 <para>
5691 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
5692 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
5693 call these "archives," as warm as the idea of a "library" might seem,
5694 the "content" that is collected in these digital spaces is also
5695 someone's "property." And the law of property restricts the freedoms
5696 that Kahle and others would exercise.
5697 </para>
5698 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
5699 </sect1>
5700 <sect1 id="property-i">
5701 <title>CHAPTER TEN: "Property"</title>
5702 <para>
5703 Jack Valenti has been the president of the Motion Picture Association
5704 of America since 1966. He first came to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon
5705 Johnson's administration&mdash;literally. The famous picture of
5706 Johnson's swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of
5707 President Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty
5708 years of running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps
5709 the most prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
5710 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon</primary></indexterm>
5711 </para>
5712 <para>
5713 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
5714 Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal
5715 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
5716 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
5717 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
5718 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
5719 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
5720 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
5721 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
5722 Warner Brothers.
5723 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
5724 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment</primary></indexterm>
5725 <indexterm><primary>MGM</primary></indexterm>
5726 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures</primary></indexterm>
5727 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox</primary></indexterm>
5728 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures</primary></indexterm>
5729 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
5730 </para>
5731 <para>
5732 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
5733 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
5734 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
5735 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
5736 political skill of a Southerner&mdash;the ability to appear simple and
5737 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
5738 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
5739 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
5740 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
5741 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
5742 Washingtonian way.
5743 </para>
5744 <para>
5745 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
5746 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
5747 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
5748 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
5749 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
5750 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
5751 redefine the meaning of "creative property."
5752 </para>
5753 <para>
5754 In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
5755 perfectly:
5756 </para>
5757 <blockquote>
5758 <para>
5759 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
5760 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
5761 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
5762 theme which animates this entire debate: Creative property owners must
5763 be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all other
5764 property owners in the nation. That is the issue. That is the
5765 question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire hearing and the
5766 debates to follow must rest.<footnote><para>
5767 <!-- f1 -->
5768 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R.
5769 4794, H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the
5770 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
5771 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
5772 Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack
5773 Valenti).
5774 </para></footnote>
5775 </para>
5776 </blockquote>
5777 <para>
5778 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
5779 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
5780 "central theme" to which "reasonable men and women" will return is
5781 this:
5782 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
5783 "Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
5784 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation."
5785 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
5786 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
5787 </para>
5788 <para>
5789 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
5790 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
5791 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
5792 extreme a claim made by anyone who is serious in this debate than this
5793 claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet and however brilliant,
5794 is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when it comes to the nature
5795 and scope of "creative property." His views have no reasonable
5796 connection to our actual legal tradition, even if the subtle pull of
5797 his Texan charm has slowly redefined that tradition, at least in
5798 Washington.
5799 </para>
5800 <para>
5801 While "creative property" is certainly "property" in a nerdy and
5802 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,<footnote><para>
5803 <!-- f2 -->
5804 Lawyers speak of "property" not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
5805 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
5806 object. Thus, my "property right" to my car gives me the right to
5807 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For
5808 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of "property" to
5809 "lawyer talk," see Bruce Ackerman, Private Property and the
5810 Constitution (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 26&ndash;27.
5811 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
5812 "creative property owners" have been "accorded the same rights and
5813 protection resident in all other property owners." Indeed, if creative
5814 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
5815 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
5816 in our tradition.
5817 </para>
5818 <para>
5819 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
5820 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
5821 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
5822 overturned in 1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
5823 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
5824 culture would develop.
5825 </para>
5826 <para>
5827 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
5828 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
5829 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
5830 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
5831 differently from the rights resident in all other property
5832 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
5833 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
5834 the same would be to
5835
5836 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
5837 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
5838 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
5839 perfect control.
5840 </para>
5841 <para>
5842 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
5843 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
5844 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
5845 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
5846 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
5847 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
5848 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old. To
5849 get just a hint that there is something fundamentally wrong in
5850 Valenti's argument, we need look no further than the United States
5851 Constitution itself.
5852 </para>
5853 <para>
5854 The framers of our Constitution loved "property." Indeed, so strongly
5855 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
5856 important requirement. If the government takes your property&mdash;if
5857 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
5858 farm&mdash;it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's "Takings
5859 Clause," to pay you "just compensation" for that taking. The
5860 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
5861 sacred. It cannot ever be taken from the property owner unless the
5862 government pays for the privilege.
5863 </para>
5864 <para>
5865 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
5866 Valenti calls "creative property." In the clause granting Congress the
5867 power to create "creative property," the Constitution requires that
5868 after a "limited time," Congress take back the rights that it has
5869 granted and set the "creative property" free to the public domain. Yet
5870 when Congress does this, when the expiration of a copyright term
5871 "takes" your copyright and turns it over to the public domain,
5872 Congress does not have any obligation to pay "just compensation" for
5873 this "taking." Instead, the same Constitution that requires
5874 compensation for your land
5875 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
5876 requires that you lose your "creative property" right without any
5877 compensation at all.
5878 </para>
5879 <para>
5880 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
5881 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
5882 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
5883 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
5884 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
5885 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
5886 itself.
5887 </para>
5888 <para>
5889 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
5890 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
5891 The Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
5892 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
5893 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
5894 president (as it did in 1800). The framers were no doubt
5895 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
5896 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
5897 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
5898 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
5899 </para>
5900 <para>
5901 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
5902 least try to understand why. Why did the framers, fanatical property
5903 types that they were, reject the claim that creative property be given
5904 the same rights as all other property? Why did they require that for
5905 creative property there must be a public domain?
5906 </para>
5907 <para>
5908 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
5909 history of these "creative property" rights, and the control that they
5910 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
5911 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
5912 should be at the core of this war: Not whether creative property
5913 should be protected, but how. Not whether we will enforce the rights
5914 the law gives to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix
5915 of rights ought to be. Not whether artists should be paid, but whether
5916 institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need also
5917 control how culture develops.
5918 </para>
5919 <para>
5920
5921 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
5922 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
5923 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
5924 than the narrow language of the law allows. In Code and Other Laws of
5925 Cyberspace, I used a simple model to capture this more general
5926 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
5927 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
5928 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
5929 </para>
5930 <figure id="fig-1331">
5931 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.</title>
5932 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
5933 </figure>
5934 <para>
5935 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
5936 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
5937 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
5938 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
5939 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
5940 be regulated&mdash; either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
5941 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
5942 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
5943 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
5944 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
5945 Web, you can be punished
5946 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
5947 with a $150,000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
5948 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
5949 </para>
5950 <para>
5951 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
5952 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
5953 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
5954 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
5955 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
5956 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
5957 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
5958 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
5959 the source of the enforcement.
5960 </para>
5961 <para>
5962 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
5963 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
5964 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
5965 norms&mdash;it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
5966 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
5967 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
5968 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
5969 individual or group might behave.
5970 </para>
5971 <para>
5972 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
5973 "architecture"&mdash;the physical world as one finds it&mdash;is a
5974 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
5975 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
5976 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
5977 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
5978 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
5979 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
5980 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
5981 theft, but by nature, by "architecture." If a 500-pound boulder
5982 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
5983 constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
5984 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
5985 </para>
5986 <para>
5987
5988 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
5989 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
5990 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
5991 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
5992 undermined by another.
5993 </para>
5994 <para>
5995 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
5996 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
5997 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
5998 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
5999 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6000 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6001 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6002 </para>
6003 <indexterm id="idxdrivespeed" class='startofrange'>
6004 <primary>driving speed, constraints on</primary>
6005 </indexterm>
6006 <para>
6007 So, for example, consider the "freedom" to drive a car at a high
6008 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6009 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6010 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6011 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6012 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6013 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6014 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6015 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6016 the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own
6017 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6018 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6019 </para>
6020 <para>
6021 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6022 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6023 special role in affecting the three.<footnote><para>
6024 <!-- f3 -->
6025 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6026 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6027 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6028 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6029 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, Code: And
6030 Other Laws of Cyberspace (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90&ndash;95;
6031 Lawrence Lessig, "The New Chicago School," Journal of Legal Studies,
6032 June 1998.
6033 </para></footnote>
6034 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6035 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6036 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6037 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6038 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6039 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6040 used to require that other laws be more
6041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6042 strict&mdash;a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6043 limit, for example&mdash;so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6044 driving.
6045 </para>
6046 <indexterm startref="idxdrivespeed" class='endofrange'/>
6047
6048 <figure id="fig-1361">
6049 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.</title>
6050 <graphic fileref="images/1361.png"></graphic>
6051 </figure>
6052 <para>
6053 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6054 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6055 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6056 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6057 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6058 another.<footnote>
6059 <para>
6060 <!-- f4 -->
6061 Some people object to this way of talking about "liberty." They object
6062 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6063 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6064 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6065 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6066 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6067 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6068 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6069 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6070 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6071 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6072 of liberty. As I argued in Code, we come from a long tradition of
6073 political thought with a broader focus than the narrow question of
6074 what the government did when. John Stuart Mill defended freedom of
6075 speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow minds, not from the
6076 fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (Indiana:
6077 Hackett Publishing Co., 1978), 19. John R. Commons famously defended
6078 the economic freedom of labor from constraints imposed by the market;
6079 John R. Commons, "The Right to Work," in Malcom Rutherford and Warren
6080 J. Samuels, eds., John R. Commons: Selected Essays (London:
6081 Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6082 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6083 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6084 places easier; 42 United States Code, section 12101 (2000). Each of
6085 these interventions to change existing conditions changes the liberty
6086 of a particular group. The effect of those interventions should be
6087 accounted for in order to understand the effective liberty that each
6088 of these groups might face.
6089 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.</primary></indexterm>
6090 </para></footnote>
6091 </para>
6092 <sect2 id="hollywood">
6093 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right</title>
6094 <para>
6095 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6096 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6097 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6098 rallying makes sense.
6099 </para>
6100 <para>
6101 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6102 Internet:
6103 </para>
6104 <figure id="fig-1371">
6105 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6106 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6107 </figure>
6108 <para>
6109 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6110 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6111 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6112 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6113 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6114 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6115 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6116 recognize&mdash;kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6117 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6118 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6119 this form of infringement.
6120 </para>
6121 <para>
6122 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6123 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6124 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6125 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6126 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6127 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6128 </para>
6129 <para>
6130 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6131 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6132 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6133 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6134 Iraq
6135 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6136 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6137 looting that results.
6138 </para>
6139 <figure id="fig-1381">
6140 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.</title>
6141 <graphic fileref="images/1381.png"></graphic>
6142 </figure>
6143 <para>
6144 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6145 warriors. Indeed, in a "White Paper" prepared by the Commerce
6146 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995,
6147 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6148 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6149 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should
6150 strengthen intellectual property law, (2) businesses should adopt
6151 innovative marketing techniques, (3) technologists should push to
6152 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (4) educators should
6153 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6154 </para>
6155 <para>
6156 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed&mdash;if it was to
6157 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6158 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6159 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6160 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6161 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6162 life. Homeowners living in a
6163
6164 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6165 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6166 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6167 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6168 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6169 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6170 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6171 </para>
6172 <para>
6173 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6174 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6175 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6176 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6177 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6178 Brown describes it, its "architecture of revenue."
6179 </para>
6180 <para>
6181 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6182 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6183 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6184 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6185 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20
6186 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6187 of digital cameras.<footnote><para>
6188 <!-- f5 -->
6189 See Geoffrey Smith, "Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?"
6190 BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at
6191 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #23</ulink>. For a more
6192 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6193 R. Schoenberger, "Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?" Forbes.com, 6
6194 October 2003, available at
6195 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #24</ulink>.
6196 </para></footnote>
6197
6198 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6199 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6200 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads for the
6201 purpose of protecting the railroads? Closer to the subject of this
6202 book, remote channel changers have weakened the "stickiness" of
6203 television advertising (if a boring commercial comes on the TV, the
6204 remote makes it easy to surf ), and it may well be that this change
6205 has weakened the television advertising market. But does anyone
6206 believe we should regulate remotes to reinforce commercial television?
6207 (Maybe by limiting them to function only once a second, or to switch
6208 to only ten channels within an hour?)
6209 </para>
6210 <para>
6211 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6212 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6213 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6214 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6215 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6216 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6217 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6218 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, "established companies
6219 have an interest in excluding future competitors."<footnote><para>
6220 <!-- f6 -->
6221 Fred Warshofsky, The Patent Wars (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170&ndash;71.
6222 </para></footnote>
6223 And relative to a
6224 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6225 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6226 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6227 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6228 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6229 Brezhnev.
6230 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
6231 </para>
6232 <para>
6233 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6234 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6235 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6236 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6237 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6238 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6239 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6240 opportunities for innovation and change.
6241 </para>
6242 <para>
6243 In the context of laws regulating speech&mdash;which include,
6244 obviously, copyright law&mdash;that duty is even stronger. When the
6245 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6246 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6247 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6248 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6249 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6250 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: "Congress
6251 shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech." So when
6252 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would "abridge" the freedom
6253 of speech, it should ask&mdash; carefully&mdash;whether such
6254 regulation is justified.
6255 </para>
6256 <para>
6257 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6258 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6259 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6260 "justified." My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6261 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6262 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6263 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6264 </para>
6265 <para>
6266 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6267 </para>
6268 <para>
6269 In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss
6270 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6271 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the
6272 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6273 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6274 </para>
6275 <para>
6276 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6277 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6278 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6279 </para>
6280 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6281 <para>
6282 But in 1962, Rachel Carson published Silent Spring, which argued that
6283 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6284 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6285 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6286 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6287 <indexterm><primary>Silent Sprint (Carson)</primary></indexterm>
6288 </para>
6289 <para>
6290 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6291 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6292 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6293 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6294 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6295 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6296 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6297 </para>
6298 <para>
6299 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6300 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an "environmentalism" for
6301 culture.<footnote><para>
6302 <!-- f7 -->
6303 See, for example, James Boyle, "A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6304 Environmentalism for the Net?" Duke Law Journal 47 (1997): 87.
6305 </para></footnote>
6306 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6307 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6308 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6309 "for free." The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6310 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6311 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6312 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6313 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6314 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6315 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6316 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6317 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6318 </para>
6319 <para>
6320 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6321 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6322 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6323 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6324 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6325 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6326 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6327 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6328 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6329 </para>
6330 <para>
6331 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6332 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6333 be lost.
6334 </para>
6335 </sect2>
6336 <sect2 id="beginnings">
6337 <title>Beginnings</title>
6338 <para>
6339 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6340 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of "creative
6341 property" rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6342 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6343 </para>
6344 <para>
6345 The power to establish "creative property" rights is granted to
6346 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6347 odd. Article I, section 8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that:
6348 </para>
6349 <para>
6350 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6351 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6352 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
6353
6354 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
6355 We can call this the "Progress Clause," for notice what this clause
6356 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
6357 "creative property rights." It says that Congress has the power to
6358 promote progress. The grant of power is its purpose, and its purpose
6359 is a public one, not the purpose of enriching publishers, nor even
6360 primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
6361 </para>
6362 <para>
6363 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
6364 in chapter 6, the English limited the term of copyright so as to
6365 assure that a few would not exercise disproportionate control over
6366 culture by exercising disproportionate control over publishing. We can
6367 assume the framers followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed,
6368 unlike the English, the framers reinforced that objective, by
6369 requiring that copyrights extend "to Authors" only.
6370 </para>
6371 <para>
6372 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
6373 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
6374 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
6375 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
6376 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
6377 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
6378 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
6379 to reinforce the power of the states&mdash;including the Senate, whose
6380 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
6381 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
6382 case, a structure built checks and balances into the constitutional
6383 frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable concentrations of
6384 power.
6385 </para>
6386 <para>
6387 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call "copyright"
6388 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
6389 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
6390 "copyright" in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210
6391 years since they first struck its design.
6392 </para>
6393 <para>
6394 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
6395 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
6396 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
6397 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
6398 started here:
6399 </para>
6400 <figure id="fig-1441">
6401 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6402 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6403 </figure>
6404 <para>
6405 We will end here:
6406 </para>
6407 <figure id="fig-1442">
6408 <title>&quot;Copyright&quot; today.</title>
6409 <graphic fileref="images/1442.png"></graphic>
6410 </figure>
6411 <para>
6412 Let me explain how.
6413 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
6414 </para>
6415 </sect2>
6416 <sect2 id="lawduration">
6417 <title>Law: Duration</title>
6418 <para>
6419 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
6420 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
6421 the English had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws
6422 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
6423 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
6424 authorship.<footnote>
6425 <para>
6426 <!-- f8 -->
6427 William W. Crosskey, Politics and the Constitution in the History of
6428 the United States (London: Cambridge University Press, 1953), vol. 1,
6429 485&ndash;86: "extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
6430 Law of the Land,' the perpetual rights which authors had, or were
6431 supposed by some to have, under the Common Law" (emphasis added).
6432 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.</primary></indexterm>
6433 </para></footnote>
6434 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
6435 States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
6436 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
6437 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
6438 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
6439 domain to reprint and distribute works.
6440 </para>
6441 <para>
6442 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
6443 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
6444 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
6445 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
6446 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
6447 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
6448 </para>
6449 <para>
6450 In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
6451 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
6452 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
6453 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
6454 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
6455 </para>
6456 <para>
6457 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
6458 ten years of the Republic, only 5 percent of the works were actually
6459 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
6460 in the United States both before 1790 and from 1790 through 1800, 95
6461 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
6462 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
6463 likely within fourteen years.<footnote><para>
6464 <!-- f9 -->
6465 Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790
6466 to 1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, A
6467 History of Book Publishing in the United States, vol. 1, The Creation
6468 of an Industry, 1630&ndash;1865 (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000
6469 imprints recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
6470 1790 act; William J. Maher, Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
6471 and the Copyright Law of 1790 in Historical Context, 7&ndash;10 (2002),
6472 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
6473 #25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
6474 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
6475 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
6476 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
6477 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
6478 Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124. </para></footnote>
6479 </para>
6480 <para>
6481 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
6482 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
6483 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
6484 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
6485 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
6486 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
6487 copyright, either.
6488 </para>
6489 <para>
6490 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
6491 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
6492 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
6493 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
6494 domain.<footnote><para>
6495 <!-- f10 -->
6496 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
6497 instance, of the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were
6498 renewed in 1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
6499 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, "Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright,"
6500 Studies on Copyright, vol. 1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
6501 1963), 618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
6502 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, "Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,"
6503 University of Chicago Law Review 70 (2003): 471, 498&ndash;501, and
6504 accompanying figures. </para></footnote>
6505 </para>
6506 <para>
6507 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
6508 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
6509 out of print after one year.<footnote><para>
6510 <!-- f11 -->
6511 See Ringer, ch. 9, n. 2. </para></footnote> When that happens, the
6512 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
6513 no longer effectively controlled by copyright. The only practical
6514 commercial use of the books at that time is to sell the books as used
6515 books; that use&mdash;because it does not involve publication&mdash;is
6516 effectively free.
6517 </para>
6518 <para>
6519 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
6520 changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28
6521 years to a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
6522 from 14 years to 28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
6523 the term increased once again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal
6524 term of 14 years to 28 years, setting a maximum term of 56 years.
6525 </para>
6526 <para>
6527 Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
6528 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
6529 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
6530 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
6531 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
6532 In 1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
6533 And in 1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
6534 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
6535 </para>
6536 <para>
6537 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
6538 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
6539 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
6540 years, or 70 percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years
6541
6542 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
6543 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
6544 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
6545 of the expiration of a copyright term.
6546 </para>
6547 <para>
6548 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
6549 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
6550 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
6551 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
6552 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
6553 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
6554 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
6555 value.
6556 </para>
6557 <para>
6558 The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For
6559 all works created after 1978, there was only one copyright term&mdash;the
6560 maximum term. For "natural" authors, that term was life plus fifty
6561 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992,
6562 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
6563 before 1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
6564 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
6565 was ninety-five years.
6566 </para>
6567 <para>
6568 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
6569 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
6570 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
6571 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
6572 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
6573 that terms be "limited," we have no evidence that anything will limit
6574 them.
6575 </para>
6576 <para>
6577 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
6578 dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to
6579 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
6580 in 1973 was just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
6581 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
6582 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95
6583 years.<footnote><para>
6584 <!-- f12 -->
6585 These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the
6586 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
6587 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
6588 Posner, "Indefinitely Renewable Copyright," loc. cit.
6589 </para></footnote>
6590 </para>
6591 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
6592 </sect2>
6593 <sect2 id="lawscope">
6594 <title>Law: Scope</title>
6595 <para>
6596 The "scope" of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
6597 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
6598 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
6599 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
6600 </para>
6601 <para>
6602 In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only "maps,
6603 charts, and books." That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
6604 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
6605 the author the exclusive right to "publish" copyrighted works. That
6606 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
6607 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
6608 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
6609 did not extend to what lawyers call "derivative works." It would not,
6610 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
6611 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
6612 (such as a drama based on a published book).
6613 </para>
6614 <para>
6615 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
6616 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
6617 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
6618 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
6619 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
6620 work not only the exclusive right to "publish" the work, but also the
6621 exclusive right of control over any "copies" of that work. And most
6622 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
6623 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
6624 "derivative work" that might grow out of the original work. In this
6625 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
6626 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
6627 on the initial creative work.
6628 </para>
6629 <para>
6630 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
6631 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
6632 complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition
6633 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
6634 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
6635 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
6636 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
6637 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
6638 famous &copy; or the word copyright. And for most of the history of
6639 American copyright law, there was a requirement that works be
6640 deposited with the government before a copyright could be secured.
6641 </para>
6642 <para>
6643 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
6644 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
6645 in the first ten years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible
6646 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
6647 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
6648 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
6649 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
6650 copyrighted&mdash;that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
6651 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
6652 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
6653 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
6654 original author.
6655 </para>
6656 <para>
6657 All of these "formalities" were abolished in the American system when
6658 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
6659 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
6660 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
6661 a &copy;; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
6662 copy available for others to copy.
6663 </para>
6664 <para>
6665 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
6666 differences.
6667 </para>
6668 <para>
6669 If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who
6670 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
6671 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
6672 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
6673 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were
6674 174 publishers in the United States.<footnote><para>
6675 <!-- f13 -->
6676 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, "Poets, Pirates, and the
6677 Creation
6678 of American Literature," 29 New York University Journal of
6679 International
6680 Law and Politics 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed., Federal
6681 Copyright Records, 1790&ndash;1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987).
6682 </para></footnote>
6683 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
6684 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
6685 the United States&mdash;publishers.
6686 </para>
6687 <para>
6688 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
6689 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your
6690 poem by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my
6691 act was totally unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and
6692 made a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
6693 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
6694 creative
6695 activities remained free, while the activities of publishers were
6696 restrained.
6697 </para>
6698 <para>
6699 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
6700 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
6701 every note to your spouse, every doodle, every creative act that's
6702 reduced
6703 to a tangible form&mdash;all of this is automatically copyrighted.
6704 There is no need to register or mark your work. The protection follows
6705 the creation, not the steps you take to protect it.
6706 </para>
6707 <para>
6708 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
6709 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
6710 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
6711 </para>
6712 <para>
6713 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
6714 control
6715 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
6716 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of "derivative
6717 rights." If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
6718 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
6719 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
6720 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
6721 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
6722 exclusive
6723 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
6724 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
6725 </para>
6726 <para>
6727 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
6728 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
6729 expansion
6730 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
6731 copyright.
6732 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
6733 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
6734 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
6735 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
6736 </para>
6737 <para>
6738
6739 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
6740 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power within
6741 a free culture&mdash;at least, it's astonishing when you understand that the
6742 law applies not just to the commercial publisher but to anyone with a
6743 computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating and selling someone
6744 else's work. But whatever that wrong is, transforming someone else's
6745 work is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
6746 all&mdash;they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should not
6747 protect
6748 derivative rights at all.<footnote><para>
6749 <!-- f14 -->
6750 Jonathan Zittrain, "The Copyright Cage," Legal Affairs, July/August
6751 2003, available at
6752 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #26</ulink>.
6753 </para></footnote>
6754 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
6755 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
6756 the wrong of direct piracy.
6757 </para>
6758 <para>
6759 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same
6760 way. I can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my
6761 book. I can go to court and get an injunction against your
6762 transformative
6763 use of my book.<footnote><para>
6764 <!-- f15 -->
6765 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
6766 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the perspective
6767 of the First Amendment) between mere "copies" and derivative works. See
6768 Jed Rubenfeld, "The Freedom of Imagination: Copyright's
6769 Constitutionality,"
6770 Yale Law Journal 112 (2002): 1&ndash;60 (see especially pp. 53&ndash;59).
6771 </para></footnote>
6772 These two different uses of my creative work are
6773 treated the same.
6774 </para>
6775 <para>
6776 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why
6777 should you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes
6778 money from it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney
6779 creates
6780 a creature called "Mickey Mouse," why should you be able to make
6781 Mickey Mouse toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney
6782 originally created?
6783 </para>
6784 <para>
6785 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
6786 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
6787 simply
6788 to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from the
6789 rights originally granted.
6790 </para>
6791 </sect2>
6792 <sect2 id="lawreach">
6793 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach</title>
6794 <para>
6795 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
6796 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
6797 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
6798 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.<footnote><para>
6799 <!-- f16 -->
6800 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law certainly
6801 regulates more than "copies"&mdash;a public performance of a copyrighted
6802 song, for example, is regulated even though performance per se doesn't
6803 make a copy; 17 United States Code, section 106(4). And it certainly
6804 sometimes
6805 doesn't regulate a "copy"; 17 United States Code, section 112(a). But
6806 the presumption under the existing law (which regulates "copies;" 17
6807 United States Code, section 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
6808 </para></footnote>
6809 </para>
6810 <para>
6811 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
6812 "Copies." That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for copyright
6813 law to regulate. But as with Jack Valenti's argument at the start of this
6814 chapter, that "creative property" deserves the "same rights" as all other
6815 property, it is the obvious that we need to be most careful about. For
6816 while it may be obvious that in the world before the Internet, copies
6817 were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon reflection, it should be
6818 obvious that in the world with the Internet, copies should not be the
6819 trigger for copyright law. More precisely, they should not always be the
6820 trigger for copyright law.
6821 </para>
6822 <para>
6823 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
6824 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
6825 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
6826 the law of copyright automatically applies,<footnote><para>
6827 <!-- f17 -->
6828 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law extends,
6829 we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good argument for
6830 its extending where it does, and should not determine its reach on the
6831 basis
6832 of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by technology.
6833 </para></footnote>
6834 because it is clear that the
6835 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
6836 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
6837 </para>
6838 <para>
6839 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
6840 empty circle.
6841 </para>
6842 <figure id="fig-1521">
6843 <title>All potential uses of a book.</title>
6844 <graphic fileref="images/1521.png"></graphic>
6845 </figure>
6846 <para>
6847 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
6848 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
6849 all its potential uses. Most of these uses are unregulated by
6850 copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If you read a
6851 book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you give someone
6852 the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you resell a
6853 book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly states that
6854 after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can impose no
6855 further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you sleep on
6856 the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew it up,
6857 those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those acts do
6858 not make a copy.
6859 </para>
6860 <figure id="fig-1531">
6861 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.</title>
6862 <graphic fileref="images/1531.png"></graphic>
6863 </figure>
6864 <para>
6865 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
6866 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
6867 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
6868 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
6869 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see first
6870 diagram on next page).
6871 </para>
6872 <para>
6873 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
6874 that remain unregulated because the law considers these "fair uses."
6875 </para>
6876 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
6877 <figure id="fig-1541">
6878 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.</title>
6879 <graphic fileref="images/1541.png"></graphic>
6880 </figure>
6881 <para>
6882 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law treats
6883 as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
6884 unregulated.
6885 You are free to quote from this book, even in a review that
6886 is quite negative, without my permission, even though that quoting
6887 makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright owner the
6888 exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not, but the law
6889 denies the owner any exclusive right over such "fair uses" for public
6890 policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
6891 </para>
6892 <figure id="fig-1542">
6893 <title>Unregulated copying considered &quot;fair uses.&quot;</title>
6894 <graphic fileref="images/1542.png"></graphic>
6895 </figure>
6896 <para> </para>
6897 <figure id="fig-1551">
6898 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.</title>
6899 <graphic fileref="images/1551.png"></graphic>
6900 </figure>
6901 <para>
6902 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
6903 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
6904 sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that
6905 are nonetheless deemed "fair" regardless of the copyright owner's views.
6906 </para>
6907 <para>
6908 Enter the Internet&mdash;a distributed, digital network where every use
6909 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.<footnote><para>
6910 <!-- f18 -->
6911 I don't mean "nature" in the sense that it couldn't be different, but rather that
6912 its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks need not make
6913 copies of content they transmit, and a digital network could be designed to
6914 delete anything it copies so that the same number of copies remain.
6915 </para></footnote>
6916 And because of this single,
6917 arbitrary feature of the design of a digital network, the scope of
6918 category
6919 1 changes dramatically. Uses that before were presumptively
6920 unregulated
6921 are now presumptively regulated. No longer is there a set of
6922 presumptively unregulated uses that define a freedom associated with a
6923 copyrighted work. Instead, each use is now subject to the copyright,
6924 because each use also makes a copy&mdash;category 1 gets sucked into
6925 category
6926 2. And those who would defend the unregulated uses of
6927 copyrighted
6928 work must look exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the
6929 burden of this shift.
6930 </para>
6931 <para>
6932 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
6933 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would be
6934 no plausible copyright-related argument that the copyright owner could
6935 make to control that use of her book. Copyright law would have
6936 nothing
6937 to say about whether you read the book once, ten times, or every
6938 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
6939 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of use&mdash;reading&mdash;
6940 could be regulated by copyright law because none of those uses
6941 produced
6942 a copy.
6943 </para>
6944 <para>
6945 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a
6946 different
6947 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
6948 only once or only once a month, then copyright law would aid the
6949 copyright
6950 owner in exercising this degree of control, because of the
6951 accidental
6952 feature of copyright law that triggers its application upon there
6953 being a copy. Now if you read the book ten times and the license says
6954 you may read it only five times, then whenever you read the book (or
6955 any portion of it) beyond the fifth time, you are making a copy of the
6956 book contrary to the copyright owner's wish.
6957 </para>
6958 <para>
6959 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
6960 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
6961 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
6962 points also become clear:
6963 </para>
6964 <para>
6965 First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
6966 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
6967 presumptively
6968 unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
6969 evidence
6970 at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they allowed
6971 our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important part of
6972 free culture before the Internet.
6973 </para>
6974 <para>
6975 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
6976 transformative
6977 uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand the wrong
6978 in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate any
6979 transformation
6980 you make of creative work using a machine. "Copy and paste"
6981 and "cut and paste" become crimes. Tinkering with a story and
6982 releasing
6983 it to others exposes the tinkerer to at least a requirement of
6984 justification.
6985 However troubling the expansion with respect to copying a
6986 particular work, it is extraordinarily troubling with respect to
6987 transformative
6988 uses of creative work.
6989 </para>
6990 <para>
6991 Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary
6992
6993 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
6994 burden on category 3 ("fair use") that fair use never before had to bear.
6995 If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I could read
6996 a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that this is a
6997 violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been any litigation
6998 about whether I have a fair use right to read, because before the
6999 Internet,
7000 reading did not trigger the application of copyright law and hence
7001 the need for a fair use defense. The right to read was effectively
7002 protected
7003 before because reading was not regulated.
7004 </para>
7005 <para>
7006 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7007 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7008 depend
7009 upon fair use&mdash;never even addressing the earlier question about
7010 the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection grounded in
7011 fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are unregulated. But
7012 when everything becomes presumptively regulated, then the
7013 protections
7014 of fair use are not enough.
7015 </para>
7016 <para>
7017 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7018 in the business of making "trailer" advertisements for movies available
7019 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7020 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7021 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7022 </para>
7023 <para>
7024 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it
7025 began
7026 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7027 previews.
7028 The idea was to expand their "selling by sampling" technique by
7029 giving on-line stores the same ability to enable "browsing." Just as in a
7030 bookstore you can read a few pages of a book before you buy the book,
7031 so, too, you would be able to sample a bit from the movie on-line
7032 before
7033 you bought it.
7034 </para>
7035 <para>
7036 In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film
7037 distributors
7038 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7039 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7040 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7042 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter&mdash;he had built a
7043 business
7044 on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney films; he
7045 had customers who depended upon his delivering this content. Disney
7046 would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the distribution
7047 immediately.
7048 Video Pipeline thought it was within their "fair use" rights
7049 to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a lawsuit to ask the
7050 court to declare that these rights were in fact their rights.
7051 </para>
7052 <para>
7053 Disney countersued&mdash;for $100 million in damages. Those damages
7054 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had "willfully
7055 infringed"
7056 on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7057 willful
7058 infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the actual
7059 harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set in the
7060 statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred clips of
7061 Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those movies,
7062 Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $100 million.
7063 </para>
7064 <para>
7065 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7066 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7067 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7068 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7069 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7070 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7071 Disney's permission.
7072 </para>
7073 <para>
7074 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts would
7075 consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change that gives
7076 Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't really control
7077 how people got access to their content. Once a video was in the
7078 marketplace,
7079 the "first-sale doctrine" would free the seller to use the video as he
7080 wished, including showing portions of it in order to engender sales of the
7081 entire movie video. But with the Internet, it becomes possible for Disney
7082 to centralize control over access to this content. Because each use of the
7083 Internet produces a copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the
7084 copyright owner's control. The technology expands the scope of effective
7085 control, because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7086 </para>
7087 <para>
7088 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7089 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7090 control
7091 is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes &amp; Noble has the right to say
7092 you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives them that right.
7093 But the market effectively protects against that abuse. If Barnes &amp;
7094 Noble
7095 banned browsing, then consumers would choose other bookstores.
7096 Competition protects against the extremes. And it may well be (my
7097 argument
7098 so far does not even question this) that competition would prevent
7099 any similar danger when it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers
7100 exercising
7101 the rights that authors have assigned to them might try to regulate
7102 how many times you read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book
7103 with anyone. But in a competitive market such as the book market, the
7104 dangers of this happening are quite slight.
7105 </para>
7106 <para>
7107 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7108 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7109 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7110 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7111 owners
7112 choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But in some
7113 contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7114 </para>
7115 </sect2>
7116 <sect2 id="lawforce">
7117 <title>Architecture and Law: Force</title>
7118 <para>
7119 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7120 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7121 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7122 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7123 </para>
7124 <para>
7125 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7126 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7127 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7128 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7129 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7130 your freedom.
7131 </para>
7132 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca</primary></indexterm>
7133 <para>
7134 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7135 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7136 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7137 Casablanca. Warner Brothers objected. They wrote a nasty letter to the
7138 Marxes, warning them that there would be serious legal consequences
7139 if they went forward with their plan.<footnote><para>
7140 <!-- f19 -->
7141 See David Lange, "Recognizing the Public Domain," Law and
7142 Contemporary
7143 Problems 44 (1981): 172&ndash;73.
7144 </para></footnote>
7145 </para>
7146 <para>
7147 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7148 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers "were brothers long before
7149 you were."<footnote><para>
7150 <!-- f20 -->
7151 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs, 1&ndash;3.
7152 </para></footnote>
7153 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word brothers,
7154 and if Warner Brothers insisted on trying to control Casablanca, then
7155 the Marx Brothers would insist on control over brothers.
7156 </para>
7157 <para>
7158 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7159 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7160 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7161 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7162 </para>
7163 <para>
7164 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because
7165 on the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by
7166 a machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7167 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7168 copyrighted
7169 content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the problem
7170 with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no shame. Code
7171 would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The consequence of
7172 that is not at all funny.
7173 </para>
7174 <para>
7175 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7176 </para>
7177 <para>
7178 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook
7179 is not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7180 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7181 technology,
7182 and the publisher delivers the content by using the technology.
7183 </para>
7184 <para>
7185 On the next page is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook
7186 Reader.
7187 </para>
7188 <para>
7189 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7190 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7191 public domain: Middlemarch, for example, is in the public domain.
7192 Some of them reproduce content that is not in the public domain: My
7193 own book The Future of Ideas is not yet within the public domain.
7194 Consider Middlemarch first. If you click on my e-book copy of
7195 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7196 Middlemarch, you'll see a fancy cover, and then a button at the bottom
7197 called Permissions.
7198 </para>
7199 <figure id="fig-1611">
7200 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader</title>
7201 <graphic fileref="images/1611.png"></graphic>
7202 </figure>
7203 <para>
7204 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7205 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7206 </para>
7207 <figure id="fig-1612">
7208 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.</title>
7209 <graphic fileref="images/1612.png"></graphic>
7210 </figure>
7211 <para>
7212 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7213 According to my eBook
7214 Reader, I have the permission
7215 to copy to the clipboard of the
7216 computer ten text selections
7217 every ten days. (So far, I've
7218 copied no text to the clipboard.)
7219 I also have the permission to
7220 print ten pages from the book
7221 every ten days. Lastly, I have
7222 the permission to use the Read
7223 Aloud button to hear
7224 Middlemarch
7225 read aloud through the
7226 computer.
7227 </para>
7228 <para>
7229 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7230 translation): Aristotle's Politics.
7231 </para>
7232 <figure id="fig-1621">
7233 <title>E-book of Aristotle;s &quot;Politics&quot;</title>
7234 <graphic fileref="images/1621.png"></graphic>
7235 </figure>
7236 <para>
7237 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7238 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
7239 the book.
7240 </para>
7241 <figure id="fig-1622">
7242 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle;s &quot;Politics&quot;.</title>
7243 <graphic fileref="images/1622.png"></graphic>
7244 </figure>
7245 <para>
7246 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
7247 original e-book version of my last book, The Future of Ideas:
7248 </para>
7249 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
7250 <figure id="fig-1631">
7251 <title>List of the permissions for &quot;The Future of Ideas&quot;.</title>
7252 <graphic fileref="images/1631.png"></graphic>
7253 </figure>
7254 <para>
7255 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
7256 </para>
7257 <para>
7258 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls "permissions"&mdash;
7259 as if the publisher has the power to control how you use these works.
7260 For works under copyright, the copyright owner certainly does have
7261 the power&mdash;up to the limits of the copyright law. But for work not
7262 under
7263 copyright, there is no such copyright power.<footnote><para>
7264 <!-- f21 -->
7265 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might, for
7266 example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I will read
7267 it only three times, or that I promise to read it three times. But that
7268 obligation
7269 (and the limits for creating that obligation) would come from the
7270 contract, not from copyright law, and the obligations of contract would
7271 not necessarily pass to anyone who subsequently acquired the book.
7272 </para></footnote>
7273 When my e-book of
7274 Middlemarch says I have the permission to copy only ten text selections
7275 into the memory every ten days, what that really means is that the
7276 eBook Reader has enabled the publisher to control how I use the book
7277 on my computer, far beyond the control that the law would enable.
7278 </para>
7279 <para>
7280 The control comes instead from the code&mdash;from the technology
7281 within which the e-book "lives." Though the e-book says that these are
7282 permissions, they are not the sort of "permissions" that most of us deal
7283 with. When a teenager gets "permission" to stay out till midnight, she
7284 knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out till 2 A.M., but
7285 will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when the Adobe eBook
7286 Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies of the text into
7287 the computer's memory, that means that after I've made ten copies, the
7288 computer will not make any more. The same with the printing
7289 restrictions:
7290 After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not print any more pages.
7291 It's the same with the silly restriction that says that you can't use the
7292 Read Aloud button to read my book aloud&mdash;it's not that the company
7293 will sue you if you do; instead, if you push the Read Aloud button with
7294 my book, the machine simply won't read aloud.
7295 </para>
7296 <para>
7297 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
7298 These are controls, not permissions. Imagine a world where the
7299 Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when you tried to
7300 type "Warner Brothers," erased "Brothers" from the sentence.
7301 </para>
7302 <para>
7303 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright law as
7304 copyright code. The controls over access to content will not be controls
7305 that are ratified by courts; the controls over access to content will be
7306 controls that are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that
7307 are built into the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls
7308 that are built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
7309 </para>
7310 <para>
7311 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
7312 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
7313 technologies
7314 that limited the ability of users to copy the software, but those
7315 were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial to defeat these
7316 protections as well?
7317 </para>
7318 <para>
7319 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
7320 eBook Reader.
7321 </para>
7322 <para>
7323 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a
7324 public
7325 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for
7326 free on the Adobe site was a copy of Alice's Adventures in Wonderland.
7327 This wonderful book is in the public domain. Yet when you clicked on
7328 Permissions for that book, you got the following report:
7329 </para>
7330 <figure id="fig-1641">
7331 <title>List of the permissions for &quot;Alice's Adventures in
7332 Wonderland&quot;.</title>
7333 <graphic fileref="images/1641.png"></graphic>
7334 </figure>
7335 <para>
7336 <!-- PAGE BREAK 164 -->
7337 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not
7338 allowed
7339 to copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
7340 "permissions"
7341 indicated, not allowed to "read aloud"!
7342 </para>
7343 <para>
7344 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
7345 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
7346 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
7347 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
7348 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
7349 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
7350 </para>
7351 <para>
7352 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
7353 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
7354 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
7355 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
7356 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
7357 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
7358 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
7359 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
7360 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
7361 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
7362 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
7363 </para>
7364 <para>
7365 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
7366 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
7367 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
7368 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
7369 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
7370 often crazy.
7371 </para>
7372 <para>
7373 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
7374 story of mine that makes the same point.
7375 </para>
7376 <indexterm id="idxaibo" class='startofrange'>
7377 <primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary>
7378 </indexterm>
7379 <para>
7380 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named "Aibo." The Aibo
7381 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
7382 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
7383 </para>
7384 <para>
7385 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
7386 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
7387 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
7388 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165 -->
7389 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
7390 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
7391 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
7392 </para>
7393 <para>
7394 "Teach" here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
7395 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
7396 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
7397 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
7398 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
7399 their computer "dog" to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
7400 </para>
7401 <para>
7402 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the
7403 word hack has a particularly unfriendly connotation. Nonprogrammers
7404 hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in horror movies do even
7405 worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call them, hack is a much
7406 more positive term. Hack just means code that enables the program to
7407 do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to do. If you buy
7408 a new printer for an old computer, you might find the old computer
7409 doesn't run, or "drive," the printer. If you discovered that, you'd later be
7410 happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone who has written a
7411 driver to enable the computer to drive the printer you just bought.
7412 </para>
7413 <para>
7414 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
7415 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
7416 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
7417 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
7418 ethically.
7419 </para>
7420 <para>
7421 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
7422 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
7423 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
7424 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
7425 than Sony had built.
7426 </para>
7427 <indexterm startref="idxaibo" class='endofrange'/>
7428 <para>
7429 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
7430 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
7431 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
7432 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
7433 the
7434
7435 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
7436 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
7437 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
7438 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
7439 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
7440 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
7441 thought, What possible problem could there be with teaching a robot
7442 dog to dance?
7443 </para>
7444 <para>
7445 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show&mdash;
7446 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
7447 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
7448 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
7449 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
7450 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
7451 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
7452 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
7453 into being silent about something he knew very well.
7454 </para>
7455 <para>
7456 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.<footnote><para>
7457 <!-- f22 -->
7458 See Pamela Samuelson, "Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,"
7459 Science 293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, "Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
7460 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks," American Prospect,
7461 January 2002; "Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
7462 DMCA," Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter, 11 December 2001; Bill
7463 Holland, "Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns," Billboard,
7464 May 2001; Janelle Brown, "Is the RIAA Running Scared?" Salon.com,
7465 April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, "Frequently Asked
7466 Questions about Felten and USENIX v. RIAA Legal Case," available at
7467 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #27</ulink>.
7468 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
7469 </para></footnote>
7470 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
7471 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
7472 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
7473 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
7474 </para>
7475 <para>
7476 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
7477 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
7478 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
7479 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
7480 "this music cannot be copied," and have a computer respect that
7481 command. The technology was to be part of a "trusted system" of
7482 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
7483 Internet much more.
7484 </para>
7485 <para>
7486 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
7487 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
7488 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
7489 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
7490 </para>
7491 <para>
7492 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
7493 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
7494 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
7495 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
7496 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
7497 </para>
7498 <para>
7499 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
7500 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
7501 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
7502 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
7503 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
7504 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
7505 </para>
7506 <para>
7507 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
7508 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
7509 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
7510 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
7511 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
7512 constituted, succeed.
7513 </para>
7514 <para>
7515 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
7516 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
7517 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
7518 wrote:
7519 </para>
7520 <blockquote>
7521 <para>
7522 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
7523 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
7524 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
7525 </para>
7526 </blockquote>
7527 <para>
7528 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
7529 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
7530 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
7531 </para>
7532 <blockquote>
7533 <para>
7534 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
7535 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
7536 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
7537 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
7538 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act ("DMCA").
7539 </para>
7540 </blockquote>
7541 <para>
7542 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
7543 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
7544 spreading such information an offense.
7545 </para>
7546 <para>
7547 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
7548 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
7549 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
7550 These new technologies would be copyright protection technologies&mdash;
7551 technologies to control the replication and distribution of copyrighted
7552 material. They were designed as code to modify the original code of the
7553 Internet, to reestablish some protection for copyright owners.
7554 </para>
7555 <para>
7556 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
7557 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
7558 legal code intended to buttress software code which itself was
7559 intended to support the legal code of copyright.
7560 </para>
7561 <para>
7562 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
7563 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
7564 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
7565 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
7566 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
7567 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
7568 have been a copyright violation.
7569 </para>
7570 <para>
7571 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
7572 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
7573 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
7574 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
7575 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
7576 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
7577 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
7578 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
7579 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
7580 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
7581 </para>
7582 <para>
7583 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
7584 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
7585 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
7586 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
7587 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
7588 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
7589 </para>
7590 <para>
7591 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
7592 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
7593 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
7594 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
7595 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
7596 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka "Mr. Rogers," for example, had
7597 testified in that case that he wanted people to feel free to tape
7598 Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
7599 </para>
7600 <blockquote>
7601 <para>
7602 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
7603 "Neighborhood" at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
7604 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
7605 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
7606 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
7607 "Neighborhood" off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the "Neighborhood"
7608 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
7609 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
7610 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
7611 broadcasting has always been "You are an important person just the way
7612 you are. You can make healthy decisions." Maybe I'm going on too long,
7613 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
7614 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
7615 important.<footnote><para>
7616 <!-- f23 -->
7617 Sony Corporation of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417,
7618 455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
7619 James Lardner, Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
7620 the VCR (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270&ndash;71.
7621 </para></footnote>
7622 </para>
7623 </blockquote>
7624 <para>
7625 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
7626 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
7627 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
7628 the VCR responsible.
7629 </para>
7630 <para>
7631 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
7632 the DMCA.
7633 </para>
7634 <para>
7635 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
7636 </para>
7637 <para>
7638 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
7639 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
7640 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
7641 pirating of copyrighted material&mdash;a bad end. Or they can be used
7642 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
7643 would be considered fair use&mdash;a good end.
7644 </para>
7645 <para>
7646 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
7647 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
7648 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
7649 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
7650 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
7651 and bad uses.
7652 </para>
7653 <figure id="fig-1711">
7654 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.</title>
7655 <graphic fileref="images/1711.png"></graphic>
7656 </figure>
7657 <para>
7658 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
7659 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
7660 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: No one ever died from
7661 copyright circumvention. Yet the law bans circumvention technologies
7662 absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some good, but
7663 permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
7664 </para>
7665 <para>
7666 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
7667 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
7668 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
7669 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
7670 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
7671 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
7672 </para>
7673 <para>
7674 This is how code becomes law. The controls built into the technology
7675 of copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
7676 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the law&mdash;increasing its
7677 regulation, even if the subject it regulates (activities that would otherwise
7678 plainly constitute fair use) is beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes
7679 law; code extends the law; code thus extends the control that copyright
7680 owners effect&mdash;at least for those copyright holders with the lawyers
7681 who can write the nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
7682 </para>
7683 <para>
7684 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
7685 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
7686 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
7687 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
7688 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
7689 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
7690 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
7691 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
7692 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
7693 </para>
7694 <para>
7695
7696 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
7697 For example, imagine you were part of a Star Trek fan club. You
7698 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
7699 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
7700 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
7701 simply continue it.<footnote><para>
7702 <!-- f24 -->
7703 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, "Legal Fictions,
7704 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law," Loyola of Los Angeles
7705 Entertainment Law Journal 17 (1997): 651.
7706 </para></footnote>
7707 </para>
7708 <para>
7709 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
7710 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
7711 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
7712 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
7713 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
7714 </para>
7715 <para>
7716 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
7717 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
7718 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
7719 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
7720 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
7721 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
7722 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
7723 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
7724 </para>
7725 <para>
7726 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
7727 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
7728 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
7729 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
7730 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
7731 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
7732 </para>
7733 </sect2>
7734 <sect2 id="marketconcentration">
7735 <title>Market: Concentration</title>
7736 <para>
7737 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically&mdash;tripled in
7738 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
7739 well&mdash;from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
7740 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
7741 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
7742 find better ways
7743 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
7744 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
7745 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
7746 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
7747 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
7748 market for creative work, has become the single most important
7749 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
7750 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
7751 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
7752 control.
7753 </para>
7754 <para>
7755 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
7756 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
7757 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
7758 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
7759 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
7760 </para>
7761 <para>
7762 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
7763 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
7764 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
7765 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
7766 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
7767 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
7768 announced in June 2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
7769 live in a world where just three companies control more than percent
7770 of the media.
7771 </para>
7772 <para>
7773 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
7774 nature.
7775 </para>
7776 <indexterm><primary>BMG</primary></indexterm>
7777 <para>
7778 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
7779 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
7780 ownership, "five companies control 85 percent of our media sources."<footnote><para>
7781 <!-- f25 -->
7782 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
7783 Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003)
7784 (statement of Senator John McCain). </para></footnote>
7785 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
7786 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 percent of the
7787 U.S. music market.<footnote><para>
7788 <!-- f26 -->
7789 Lynette Holloway, "Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
7790 Slide," New York Times, 23 December 2002.
7791 </para></footnote>
7792 The "five largest cable companies pipe
7793 programming to 74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide."<footnote><para>
7794 <!-- f27 -->
7795 Molly Ivins, "Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped," Charleston Gazette,
7796 31 May 2003.
7797 </para></footnote>
7798 </para>
7799 <para>
7800 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
7801 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
7802 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
7803 seventy-five stations. Today one company owns more than 1,200
7804 stations. During that period of consolidation, the total number of
7805 radio owners dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most markets, the two
7806 largest broadcasters control 74 percent of that market's
7807 revenues. Overall, just four companies control 90 percent of the
7808 nation's radio advertising revenues.
7809 </para>
7810 <para>
7811 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
7812 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
7813 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
7814 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
7815 the United States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all
7816 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent
7817 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
7818 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
7819 protected&mdash; by the market.
7820 </para>
7821 <para>
7822 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
7823 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
7824 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
7825 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
7826 </para>
7827 <blockquote>
7828 <para>
7829 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
7830 unmatched in its integration. They supply content&mdash;Fox movies
7831 . . . Fox TV shows . . . Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
7832 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
7833 advertisers&mdash;in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
7834 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
7835 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
7836 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
7837 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
7838 the same function in the United States.<footnote><para>
7839 <!-- f28 -->
7840 James Fallows, "The Age of Murdoch," Atlantic Monthly (September
7841 2003): 89.
7842 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
7843 </para></footnote>
7844 </para>
7845 </blockquote>
7846 <para>
7847 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
7848 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
7849 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
7850 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
7851 </para>
7852 <figure id="fig-1761">
7853 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.</title>
7854 <graphic fileref="images/1761.png"></graphic>
7855 </figure>
7856 <para>
7857 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
7858 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
7859 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
7860 distribute content?
7861 </para>
7862 <para>
7863 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
7864 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
7865 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
7866 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
7867 </para>
7868 <para>
7869 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
7870 integration may matter.
7871 </para>
7872 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman</primary></indexterm>
7873 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
7874 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
7875 <para>
7876 In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for All in the Family. He took
7877 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
7878 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
7879 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
7880 We wanted less edgy, not more.
7881 </para>
7882 <para>
7883 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
7884 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
7885 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
7886 control.<footnote><para>
7887 <!-- f29 -->
7888 Leonard Hill, "The Axis of Access," remarks before Weidenbaum Center
7889 Forum, "Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry," St. Louis,
7890 Missouri,
7891 3 April 2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
7892 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #28</ulink>;
7893 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
7894 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #29</ulink>).
7895 </para></footnote>
7896 </para>
7897 <para>
7898
7899 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
7900 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
7901 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
7902 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
7903 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992,
7904 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
7905 television&mdash;75 percent of it&mdash;was "independent" of the
7906 networks.
7907 </para>
7908 <para>
7909 In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
7910 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985,
7911 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
7912 2002, only five independent television studios remained. "In 1992,
7913 only 15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
7914 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
7915 controlled companies more than quintupled to 77 percent." "In 1992, 16
7916 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
7917 year there was one."<footnote><para>
7918 <!-- f30 -->
7919 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
7920 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st
7921 sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
7922 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
7923 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #30</ulink>. Kimmelman
7924 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
7925 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February
7926 2003.
7927 </para></footnote>
7928 In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
7929 that ran it. "In the ten-year period between 1992 and 2002, the number
7930 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
7931 increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
7932 per week produced by independent studios decreased
7933 63%."<footnote><para>
7934 <!-- f31 -->
7935 Ibid.
7936 </para></footnote>
7937 </para>
7938 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
7939 <para>
7940 Today, another Norman Lear with another All in the Family would
7941 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
7942 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
7943 owned by the network.
7944 </para>
7945 <para>
7946 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
7947 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
7948 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
7949 </para>
7950 <blockquote>
7951 <para>
7952 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
7953 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
7954 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
7955 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
7956 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
7957 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
7958 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
7959 handful.<footnote><para>
7960 <!-- f32 -->
7961 "Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation," Now with Bill Moyers, Bill
7962 Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at
7963 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #31</ulink>.
7964 </para></footnote>
7965 </para>
7966 </blockquote>
7967 <para>
7968 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
7969 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
7970 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
7971 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
7972 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
7973 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
7974 question without risk of consequence&mdash;not necessarily banishment
7975 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
7976 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
7977 democracy.
7978 </para>
7979 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.</primary></indexterm>
7980 <para>
7981 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
7982 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the "Innovator's
7983 Dilemma": the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
7984 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
7985 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
7986 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.<footnote><para>
7987 <!-- f33 -->
7988 Clayton M. Christensen, The Innovator's Dilemma: The
7989 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business
7990 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press, 1997). Christensen
7991 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
7992 Kim B. Clark, "The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
7993 Concepts in Technological Evolution," Research Policy 14 (1985):
7994 235&ndash;51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
7995 Kaplan, Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
7996 Underperform the Market&mdash;and How to Successfully Transform Them
7997 (New York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001). </para></footnote>
7998
7999 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8000 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8001 sprinting.
8002 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
8003 </para>
8004 <para>
8005 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8006 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8007 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8008 measure.
8009 </para>
8010 <para>
8011 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8012 suggest the concern.
8013 </para>
8014 <para>
8015 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8016 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8017 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8018 </para>
8019 <para>
8020 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8021 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8022 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8023
8024 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8025 wrecked by drugs&mdash;though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8026 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8027 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8028 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8029 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8030 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8031 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8032 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8033 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8034 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8035 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8036 outweigh these costs.
8037 </para>
8038 <para>
8039 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8040 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8041 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8042 these issues.
8043 </para>
8044 <para>
8045 Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8046 a media campaign as part of the "war on drugs." The campaign produced
8047 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8048 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8049 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8050 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8051 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8052 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8053 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8054 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8055 </para>
8056 <para>
8057 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8058 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8059 </para>
8060 <para>
8061 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8062 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8063 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8064 war. Can you do it?
8065 </para>
8066 <para>
8067 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8068 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8069 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8070 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8071 message will be heard then?
8072 </para>
8073 <para>
8074 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8075 "controversial" ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8076 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8077 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8078 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8079 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8080 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8081 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8082 rights of the stations to be this biased.<footnote><para>
8083 <!-- f34 -->
8084 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads
8085 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8086 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as "against
8087 [their] policy." The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8088 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8089 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8090 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8091 Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8092 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, "On the Issue of
8093 an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV Networks," New
8094 York Times, 13 March 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time
8095 there is very little that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to
8096 even the playing field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, "Ad
8097 Hoc Access: The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8098 Radio," Yale Law and Policy Review 6 (1988): 449&ndash;79, and for a
8099 more recent summary of the stance of the FCC and the courts, see
8100 Radio-Television News Directors Association v. FCC, 184 F. 3d 872
8101 (D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8102 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8103 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8104 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, "Antidiesel Group Fuming
8105 After Muni Rejects Ad," SFGate.com, 16 June 2003, available at
8106 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #32</ulink>. The ground
8107 was that the criticism was "too controversial."
8108 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project</primary></indexterm>
8109 </para></footnote>
8110 </para>
8111 <para>
8112 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well&mdash;if we lived
8113 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8114 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8115 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8116 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8117 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8118 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8119 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8120 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8121 </para>
8122 </sect2>
8123 <sect2 id="together">
8124 <title>Together</title>
8125 <para>
8126 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8127 copyright warriors that the government should "protect my property."
8128 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8129 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8130 </para>
8131 <para>
8132 But when we see how dramatically this "property" has changed&mdash;
8133 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8134 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8135 cultivate our culture is dramatically different&mdash;the claim begins
8136 to seem
8137
8138 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8139 less innocent and obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to
8140 supplement the law's control, and (2) the power of concentrated
8141 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8142 the massively expanded "property" rights granted by copyright
8143 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8144 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8145 be redefined.
8146 </para>
8147 <para>
8148 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8149 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8150 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8151 our culture today.
8152 </para>
8153 <para>
8154 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8155 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8156 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8157 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8158 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8159 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8160 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8161 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8162 traditionally defined copyright's regulation&mdash;a weakening of that
8163 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
8164 </para>
8165 <para>
8166 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
8167 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
8168 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
8169 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
8170 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
8171 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
8172 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
8173 future. And these changes have to be reductions in the scope of
8174 copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase in control that
8175 technology and the market enable.
8176 </para>
8177 <para>
8178 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
8179 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
8180 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
8181 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
8182 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
8183 Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control more of
8184 the development of our culture than now.
8185 </para>
8186 <para> Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
8187 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
8188 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
8189 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
8190 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
8191 were independent of the networks. Never has copyright protected such a
8192 wide range of rights, against as broad a range of actors, for a term
8193 that was remotely as long. This form of regulation&mdash;a tiny
8194 regulation of a tiny part of the creative energy of a nation at the
8195 founding&mdash;is now a massive regulation of the overall creative
8196 process. Law plus technology plus the market now interact to turn this
8197 historically benign regulation into the most significant regulation of
8198 culture that our free society has known.<footnote><para>
8199 <!-- f35 -->
8200 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his "four surrenders" of
8201 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan, 159&ndash;60.
8202 </para></footnote>
8203 </para>
8204 <para>
8205 This has been a long chapter. Its point can now be briefly stated.
8206 </para>
8207 <para>
8208 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
8209 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
8210 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
8211 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
8212 that copyright law has undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this:
8213 </para>
8214
8215 <table id="t2">
8216 <title></title>
8217 <tgroup cols="3" align="char">
8218 <thead>
8219 <row>
8220 <entry></entry>
8221 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
8222 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8223 </row>
8224 </thead>
8225 <tbody>
8226 <row>
8227 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8228 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8229 <entry>Free</entry>
8230 </row>
8231 <row>
8232 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8233 <entry>Free</entry>
8234 <entry>Free</entry>
8235 </row>
8236 </tbody>
8237 </tgroup>
8238 </table>
8239
8240 <para>
8241 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
8242 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
8243 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
8244
8245 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
8246 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
8247 noncommercial work was also free.
8248 </para>
8249 <para>
8250 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
8251 </para>
8252
8253 <table id="t3">
8254 <title></title>
8255 <tgroup cols="3" align="char">
8256 <thead>
8257 <row>
8258 <entry></entry>
8259 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
8260 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8261 </row>
8262 </thead>
8263 <tbody>
8264 <row>
8265 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8266 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8267 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8268 </row>
8269 <row>
8270 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8271 <entry>Free</entry>
8272 <entry>Free</entry>
8273 </row>
8274 </tbody>
8275 </tgroup>
8276 </table>
8277
8278 <para>
8279 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law&mdash;if
8280 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
8281 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
8282 transformation were still essentially free.
8283 </para>
8284 <para>
8285 In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
8286 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
8287 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
8288 expanded. Thus by 1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
8289 we could say the law began to look like this:
8290 </para>
8291
8292 <table id="t4">
8293 <title></title>
8294 <tgroup cols="3" align="char">
8295 <thead>
8296 <row>
8297 <entry></entry>
8298 <entry>COPY</entry>
8299 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8300 </row>
8301 </thead>
8302 <tbody>
8303 <row>
8304 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8305 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8306 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8307 </row>
8308 <row>
8309 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8310 <entry>&copy;/Free</entry>
8311 <entry>Free</entry>
8312 </row>
8313 </tbody>
8314 </tgroup>
8315 </table>
8316
8317 <para>
8318 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
8319 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
8320 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
8321 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
8322 that the law now looks like this:
8323 </para>
8324
8325 <table id="t5">
8326 <title></title>
8327 <tgroup cols="3" align="char">
8328 <thead>
8329 <row>
8330 <entry></entry>
8331 <entry>COPY</entry>
8332 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8333 </row>
8334 </thead>
8335 <tbody>
8336 <row>
8337 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8338 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8339 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8340 </row>
8341 <row>
8342 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8343 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8344 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8345 </row>
8346 </tbody>
8347 </tgroup>
8348 </table>
8349
8350 <para>
8351 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
8352 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
8353 creativity&mdash;
8354 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
8355 commercial or not, transformative or not&mdash;with the same rules
8356 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
8357 </para>
8358 <para>
8359 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
8360 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
8361 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
8362 these domains actually does any good.
8363 </para>
8364 <para>
8365 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
8366 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
8367 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
8368 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
8369 reasons sketched especially in chapters 7 and 8, one might well wonder
8370 whether it does more harm than good for commercial transformation.
8371 More commercial transformative work would be created if derivative
8372 rights were more sharply restricted.
8373 </para>
8374 <para>
8375 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
8376 course copyright is a kind of "property," and of course, as with any
8377 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
8378 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
8379 property rights<footnote><para>
8380 <!-- f36 -->
8381 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
8382 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
8383 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, "The
8384 Disintegration of Property," in Nomos XXII: Property, J. Roland
8385 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
8386 Press, 1980).
8387 </para></footnote>)
8388 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
8389 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
8390 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
8391 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the "copyright"
8392 did not control at all the freedom of others to build upon or
8393 transform a creative work. American culture was born free, and for
8394 almost 180 years our country consistently protected a vibrant and rich
8395 free culture.
8396 </para>
8397 <para>
8398 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
8399 limits on the scope of the interests protected by "property." The very
8400 birth of "copyright" as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
8401 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
8402 story of chapter 6). The tradition of "fair use" is animated by a
8403 similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the costs of
8404 exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the story of
8405 chapter 7). Adding
8406 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
8407 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
8408 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter
8409 8). And granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect,
8410 claims of property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing
8411 the soul of a culture (chapter 9). Free cultures, like free markets,
8412 are built with property. But the nature of the property that builds a
8413 free culture is very different from the extremist vision that
8414 dominates the debate today.
8415 </para>
8416 <para>
8417 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
8418 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
8419 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
8420 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
8421 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
8422 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
8423 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
8424 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
8425 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
8426 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
8427 lawyer.
8428 </para>
8429 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
8430 </sect2>
8431 </sect1>
8432 </chapter>
8433 <chapter id="c-puzzles">
8434 <title>PUZZLES</title>
8435 <para></para>
8436 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
8437 <sect1 id="chimera">
8438 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera</title>
8439 <indexterm id="idxchimera" class='startofrange'>
8440 <primary>chimeras</primary>
8441 </indexterm>
8442 <indexterm id="idxwells" class='startofrange'>
8443 <primary>Wells, H. G.</primary>
8444 </indexterm>
8445 <indexterm id="idxtcotb" class='startofrange'>
8446 <primary>&quot;Country of the Blind, The&quot; (Wells)</primary>
8447 </indexterm>
8448
8449 <para>
8450 In a well-known short story by H. G. Wells, a mountain climber
8451 named Nunez trips (literally, down an ice slope) into an unknown and
8452 isolated valley in the Peruvian Andes.<footnote><para>
8453 <!-- f1. -->
8454 H. G. Wells, "The Country of the Blind" (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells,
8455 The Country of the Blind and Other Stories, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
8456 York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
8457 </para></footnote>
8458 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with "sweet water, pasture,
8459 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
8460 that bore an excellent fruit." But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
8461 takes this as an opportunity. "In the Country of the Blind," he tells
8462 himself, "the One-Eyed Man is King." So he resolves to live with the
8463 villagers to explore life as a king.
8464 </para>
8465 <para>
8466 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
8467 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
8468 "blind." They don't have the word blind. They think he's just thick.
8469 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
8470 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
8471 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. "`You
8472 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
8473 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
8474 alone!'"
8475 </para>
8476 <para>
8477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
8478 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
8479 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
8480 affection, a young woman who to him seems "the most beautiful thing in
8481 the whole of creation," understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
8482 description of what he sees "seemed to her the most poetical of
8483 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
8484 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
8485 indulgence." "She did not believe," Wells tells us, and "she could
8486 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted."
8487 </para>
8488 <para>
8489 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his "mysteriously delighted"
8490 love, the father and the village object. "You see, my dear," her
8491 father instructs, "he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
8492 anything right." They take Nunez to the village doctor.
8493 </para>
8494 <para>
8495 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. "His brain
8496 is affected," he reports.
8497 </para>
8498 <para>
8499 "What affects it?" the father asks. "Those queer things that are
8500 called the eyes . . . are diseased . . . in such a way as to affect
8501 his brain."
8502 </para>
8503 <para>
8504 The doctor continues: "I think I may say with reasonable certainty
8505 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
8506 simple and easy surgical operation&mdash;namely, to remove these
8507 irritant bodies [the eyes]."
8508 </para>
8509 <para>
8510 "Thank Heaven for science!" says the father to the doctor. They inform
8511 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
8512 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
8513 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
8514 It sometimes happens that the eggs of twins fuse in the mother's
8515 womb. That fusion produces a "chimera." A chimera is a single creature
8516 with two sets of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be
8517 different from the DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
8518
8519 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
8520 plot for murder mysteries. "But the DNA shows with 100 percent
8521 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
8522 scene. . . ."
8523 </para>
8524 <indexterm startref="idxtcotb" class='endofrange'/>
8525 <indexterm startref="idxwells" class="endofrange"/>
8526 <para>
8527 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
8528 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
8529 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
8530 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
8531 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
8532 understanding of a "person" should reflect this reality.
8533 </para>
8534 <para>
8535 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
8536 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
8537 unfairly enough, "the copyright wars," the more I think we're dealing
8538 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question "What is
8539 p2p file sharing?" both sides have it right, and both sides have it
8540 wrong. One side says, "File sharing is just like two kids taping each
8541 others' records&mdash;the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
8542 thirty years without any question at all." That's true, at least in
8543 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
8544 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
8545 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
8546 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
8547 </para>
8548 <para>
8549 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
8550 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
8551 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
8552 "friends" beyond recognition to say "my ten thousand best friends" can
8553 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
8554 what "we have always been allowed to do," we have not always been
8555 allowed to share music with "our ten thousand best friends."
8556 </para>
8557 <para>
8558 Likewise, when the other side says, "File sharing is just like walking
8559 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
8560 with it," that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
8561 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
8562 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
8563 from Tower.
8564 </para>
8565 <para>
8566
8567 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
8568 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
8569 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
8570 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
8571 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
8572 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
8573 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
8574 $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
8575 CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.)
8576 </para>
8577 <para>
8578 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
8579 that it is both&mdash;both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
8580 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
8581 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
8582 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
8583 </para>
8584 <para>
8585 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
8586 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
8587 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
8588 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
8589 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
8590 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
8591 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
8592 implemented.<footnote><para>
8593 <!-- f2. -->
8594 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
8595 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
8596 "Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World," 27 June 2003,
8597 available at
8598 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
8599 #33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
8600 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
8601 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
8602 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, "House Bill Aims to Up
8603 Stakes on Piracy," Los Angeles Times, 17 July 2003, available at
8604 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #34</ulink>. Civil
8605 penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied song. For a recent
8606 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
8607 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 songs
8608 through a family computer, see RIAA v. Verizon Internet Services (In
8609 re. Verizon Internet Services), 240 F. Supp. 2d 24
8610 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $90
8611 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
8612 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
8613 $12,000 to $17,500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
8614 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $98
8615 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
8616 Elizabeth Young, "Downloading Could Lead to Fines," redandblack.com,
8617 August 2003, available at
8618 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #35</ulink>. For an
8619 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
8620 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
8621 identities, see James Collins, "RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
8622 Name Students," Boston Globe, 8 August 2003, D3, available at
8623 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #36</ulink>.
8624 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
8625 </para></footnote>
8626
8627 </para>
8628 <indexterm startref="idxchimera" class='endofrange'/>
8629 <para>
8630 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
8631 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
8632 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
8633 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
8634 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
8635 </para>
8636 <para>
8637 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
8638 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
8639 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
8640 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
8641 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
8642 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe either extreme would be worse than a
8643 reasonable alternative. But I believe the zero-tolerance solution
8644 would be the worse of the two extremes.
8645 </para>
8646 <para>
8647
8648 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
8649 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
8650 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
8651 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
8652 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
8653 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
8654 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
8655 </para>
8656 <para>
8657 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to "steal" music. My
8658 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
8659 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
8660 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
8661 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
8662 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
8663 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
8664 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
8665 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
8666 protection for copyrighted material,
8667 </para>
8668 <blockquote>
8669 <para>
8670 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
8671 material, and we want to protect those rights.
8672 </para>
8673 <para>
8674 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of
8675 the major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
8676 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
8677 answer
8678 that question. Market forces operating naturally may very
8679 well produce a totally different industry model.
8680 </para>
8681 <para>
8682 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
8683 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
8684 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
8685 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
8686 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
8687 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
8688 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
8689 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
8690 interests.<footnote><para>
8691 <!-- f3. --> WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to
8692 Digital Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before
8693 the Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer
8694 Protection,
8695 House Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement
8696 of Peter Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
8697 EMusic.com),
8698 available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
8699 Congressional
8700 Testimony File.
8701 </para></footnote>
8702 </para>
8703 </blockquote>
8704 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
8705 <para>
8706 In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
8707 one of "the major labels." Its position on these matters has now
8708 changed.
8709 </para>
8710 <para>
8711 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
8712 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture, and will
8713 kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
8714 </para>
8715
8716 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
8717 </sect1>
8718 <sect1 id="harms">
8719 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms</title>
8720 <para>
8721
8722 To fight "piracy," to protect "property," the content industry has
8723 launched a war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have
8724 now brought the government into this war. As with any war, this one
8725 will have both direct and collateral damage. As with any war of
8726 prohibition,
8727 these damages will be suffered most by our own people.
8728 </para>
8729 <para>
8730 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
8731 particular, the consequences for "free culture." But my aim now is to
8732 extend
8733 this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
8734 justified?
8735 </para>
8736 <para>
8737 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
8738 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
8739 power of the property called "intellectual property" is at its greatest in
8740 our history.
8741 </para>
8742 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
8743 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
8744 <para>
8745 Yet "common sense" does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
8746 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
8747 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
8748 rejection of "piracy" still has play.
8749 </para>
8750 <para>
8751 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
8752 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
8753 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
8754 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
8755 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
8756 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
8757 </para>
8758 <sect2 id="constrain">
8759 <title>Constraining Creators</title>
8760 <para>
8761 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
8762 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
8763 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
8764 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
8765 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
8766 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
8767 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
8768 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
8769 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
8770 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
8771 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
8772 weave together a string&mdash;a mash-up&mdash; of songs from your
8773 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
8774 </para>
8775 <para>
8776 This digital "capturing and sharing" is in part an extension of the
8777 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
8778 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
8779 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
8780 of digital "capturing and sharing" promises a world of extraordinarily
8781 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
8782 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
8783 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
8784 the culture all around.
8785 </para>
8786 <para>
8787 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
8788 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
8789
8790 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
8791
8792 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
8793 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
8794 storytelling extended across the globe.
8795 </para>
8796 <para>
8797 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
8798 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
8799 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
8800 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
8801 that catalog cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound
8802 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
8803 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
8804 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
8805 work is presumptively illegal.
8806 </para>
8807 <para>
8808 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
8809 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
8810 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
8811 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
8812 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
8813 by the RIAA ( Jesse Jordan of chapter 3 was just one) were threatened
8814 with a $98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted
8815 songs to be copied. Yet World-Com&mdash;which defrauded investors of
8816 $11 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization
8817 of over $200 billion&mdash;received a fine of a mere $750
8818 million.<footnote><para>
8819 <!-- f1. -->
8820 See Lynne W. Jeter, Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom
8821 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley &amp; Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of
8822 the settlement, see MCI press release, "MCI Wins U.S. District Court
8823 Approval for SEC Settlement" (7 July 2003), available at
8824 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #37</ulink>.
8825 </para></footnote>
8826 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
8827 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
8828 no more than $250,000 in damages for pain and
8829 suffering.<footnote>
8830 <para>
8831 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
8832 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For
8833 an overview, see Tanya Albert, "Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
8834 Say Tort Reformers," amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at
8835 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #38</ulink>,
8836 and "Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps," CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003,
8837 available at
8838 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
8839 recent months.
8840 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.</primary></indexterm>
8841 </para></footnote>
8842 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
8843 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
8844 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
8845 </para>
8846 <para>
8847 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
8848 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will either
8849 never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive this
8850 creative
8851 process underground by branding the modern-day Walt Disneys
8852 "pirates." We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a public
8853 domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are designed to
8854
8855 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
8856 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right to
8857 create,
8858 and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As was the
8859 case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons, we will
8860 begin
8861 to see a world of underground art&mdash;not because the message is
8862 necessarily
8863 political, or because the subject is controversial, but because the
8864 very act of creating the art is legally fraught. Already, exhibits of
8865 "illegal
8866 art" tour the United States.<footnote><para>
8867 <!-- f3. --> See Danit Lidor, "Artists Just Wanna Be Free," Wired, 7 July 2003,
8868 available
8869 at
8870 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
8871 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #41</ulink>.
8872 </para></footnote>
8873 In what does their "illegality" consist?
8874 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
8875 critical or reflective.
8876 </para>
8877 <para>
8878 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
8879 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter 10. But an
8880 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
8881 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
8882 discovered in 2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
8883 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
8884 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
8885 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
8886 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
8887 </para>
8888 <para>
8889 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
8890 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
8891 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
8892 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
8893 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
8894 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
8895 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
8896 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
8897 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
8898 </para>
8899 <para>
8900 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
8901 described in chapter 7, in response to the story about documentary
8902 filmmaker Jon Else, I have been lectured again and again by lawyers
8903 who insist Else's use was fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the
8904 law regulates such a use.
8905 </para>
8906 <para>
8907
8908 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
8909 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
8910 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
8911 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad&mdash;in
8912 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
8913 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
8914 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
8915 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
8916 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
8917 </para>
8918 <para>
8919 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
8920 "breathing room" between regulation by the law and the access the law
8921 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
8922 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
8923 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
8924 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
8925 journalists&mdash; these are the real laws governing creativity. And
8926 these rules have little relationship to the "law" with which judges
8927 comfort themselves.
8928 </para>
8929 <para>
8930 For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful
8931 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
8932 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
8933 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
8934 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak&mdash;in that
8935 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
8936 "copyright" silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
8937 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
8938 culture that is free.
8939 </para>
8940 <para>
8941 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
8942 </para>
8943 <blockquote>
8944 <para>
8945 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
8946 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
8947 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
8948 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made . . . you're not
8949 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
8950 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
8951 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, "This has been
8952 cleared." You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
8953 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
8954 </para>
8955 </blockquote>
8956 </sect2>
8957 <sect2 id="innovators">
8958 <title>Constraining Innovators</title>
8959 <para>
8960 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
8961 story&mdash;creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
8962 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
8963 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
8964 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
8965 think there's little in this story to worry you.
8966 </para>
8967 <para>
8968 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
8969 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
8970 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
8971 one at that, 188 pages into a book like this), then you can see this
8972 other aspect by substituting "free market" every place I've spoken of
8973 "free culture." The point is the same, even if the interests
8974 affecting culture are more fundamental.
8975 </para>
8976 <para>
8977 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
8978 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
8979 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary&mdash;at
8980 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
8981 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
8982 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
8983 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
8984 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
8985 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
8986 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
8987 against the competitors of tomorrow.
8988 </para>
8989 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
8990 <para>
8991 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
8992 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
8993 strategy that I described in chapter 10. The consequence of this
8994 massive threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright
8995 law is that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely
8996 innovate only if they have the sign-off from last generation's
8997 dominant industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of
8998 cases that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
8999 lesson. That lesson&mdash;what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9000 "nuclear pall" that has fallen over the Valley&mdash;has been learned.
9001 </para>
9002 <para>
9003 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9004 I told in The Future of Ideas and which has progressed in a way that
9005 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9006 </para>
9007 <para>
9008 In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9009 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9010 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9011 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9012 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9013 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9014 </para>
9015 <para>
9016 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9017 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9018 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9019 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9020 Raitt. And so on.
9021 </para>
9022 <para>
9023 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9024 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9025 preference data. In January 2000, the company launched a service
9026 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9027 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9028 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9029 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9030 wherever you were&mdash;at work or at home&mdash;you could get access
9031 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9032 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9033 </para>
9034 <para>
9035 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9036 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9037
9038 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9039 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9040 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9041 the kind of content the users liked.
9042 </para>
9043 <para>
9044 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000
9045 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9046 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9047 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9048 therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9049 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9050 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9051 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was 50,000
9052 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers something
9053 they had already bought.
9054 </para>
9055 <para>
9056 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9057 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9058 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9059 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9060 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9061 MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9062 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $54 million. Vivendi
9063 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9064 </para>
9065 <para>
9066 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9067 </para>
9068 <para>
9069 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9070 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9071 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9072 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9073 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9074 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9075 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9076 demanded.
9077 </para>
9078 <para>
9079 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9080 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9081 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9082 clients in this
9083 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9084 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9085 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9086 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9087 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9088 </para>
9089 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John</primary></indexterm>
9090 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9091 <para>
9092 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003,
9093 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9094 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9095 its development, its cofounder ( John Hummer), and general partner
9096 (Hank Barry).<footnote><para>
9097 <!-- f4. --> See Joseph Menn, "Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor," Los Angeles
9098 Times, 23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9099 innovation
9100 in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, "The Music
9101 Revolution
9102 Will Not Be Digitized," Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available at
9103 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #42</ulink>.
9104 See also Jon Healey, "Online Music Services Besieged," Los Angeles
9105 Times, 28 May 2001.
9106 </para></footnote>
9107 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have
9108 recognized the right of the content industry to control how the
9109 industry
9110 should develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a
9111 company whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again,
9112 the aim of the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if
9113 you fund a company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs,
9114 you are at risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well.
9115 Your investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
9116 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers
9117 are afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in Business
9118 2.0, Rafe Needleman describes a discussion with BMW:
9119 </para>
9120 <blockquote>
9121 <indexterm><primary>BMW</primary></indexterm>
9122 <para>
9123 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
9124 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
9125 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
9126 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
9127 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
9128 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
9129 United States with bona fide MP3 players. . . . <footnote>
9130 <para>
9131 <!-- f5. -->
9132 Rafe Needleman, "Driving in Cars with MP3s," Business 2.0, 16 June
9133 2003, available at
9134 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #43</ulink>. I am grateful
9135 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
9136 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
9137 </para></footnote>
9138 </para>
9139 </blockquote>
9140 <para>
9141 This is the world of the mafia&mdash;filled with "your money or your
9142 life" offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
9143 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
9144 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
9145 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
9146 constantly threatened by litigation.
9147 </para>
9148 <para>
9149
9150 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
9151 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
9152 enterprises. The point is the definition of "illegal." The law is a mess of
9153 uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply to new
9154 technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial deference, and
9155 by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that copyright law
9156 imposes,
9157 that uncertainty now yields a reality which is far more
9158 conservative
9159 than is right. If the law imposed the death penalty for parking
9160 tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets, we'd also have much
9161 less driving. The same principle applies to innovation. If innovation is
9162 constantly checked by this uncertain and unlimited liability, we will
9163 have much less vibrant innovation and much less creativity.
9164 </para>
9165 <para>
9166 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
9167 use. Whatever the "real" law is, realism about the effect of law in
9168 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
9169 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
9170 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
9171 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
9172 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
9173 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
9174 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
9175 produce an overregulatedregulated market.
9176 </para>
9177 <para>
9178 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
9179 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
9180 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
9181 culture&mdash;a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
9182 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
9183 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
9184 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
9185 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
9186 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
9187 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
9188 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
9189 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
9190 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
9191 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
9192 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
9193 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
9194 result. The uncertainty of the law is one burden on innovation. There
9195 is a second burden that operates more directly. This is the effort by
9196 many in the content industry to use the law to directly regulate the
9197 technology of the Internet so that it better protects their content.
9198 </para>
9199 <para>
9200 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
9201 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
9202 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
9203 this feature is a "bug." The efficient spread of content means that
9204 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
9205 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
9206 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables "piracy," then,
9207 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
9208 </para>
9209 <para>
9210 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
9211 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
9212 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
9213 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.<footnote><para>
9214 <!-- f6. --> "Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World," GartnerG2 and
9215 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
9216 (2003), 33&ndash;35, available at
9217 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
9218 </para></footnote>
9219
9220 Congress
9221 has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
9222 "broadcast
9223 flag" that would be required on any device capable of transmitting
9224 digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable the copying of
9225 any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other members of
9226 Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from liability
9227 for technology they might deploy that would hunt down copyright
9228 violators
9229 and disable their machines.<footnote><para>
9230 <!-- f7. --> GartnerG2, 26&ndash;27.
9231 </para></footnote>
9232
9233 </para>
9234 <para>
9235 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
9236 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
9237 regulation
9238 of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the particular
9239 technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens and costs on
9240
9241 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
9242 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
9243 those requirements.
9244 </para>
9245 <para>
9246 In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
9247 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation would
9248 impose.<footnote><para>
9249 <!-- f8. --> See David McGuire, "Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy," Newsbytes,
9250 February 2002 (Entertainment).
9251 </para></footnote>
9252 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not
9253 be protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
9254 harm than good.
9255 </para>
9256 <para>
9257 There is one more obvious way in which this war has harmed
9258 innovation&mdash;again,
9259 a story that will be quite familiar to the free market
9260 crowd.
9261 </para>
9262 <para>
9263 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
9264 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
9265 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
9266 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
9267 </para>
9268 <para>
9269 As I described in chapter 10, despite this feature of copyright as
9270 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by Jessica
9271 Litman in her book Digital Copyright,<footnote><para>
9272 <!-- f9. --> Jessica Litman, Digital Copyright (Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books,
9273 2001).
9274 </para></footnote>
9275 overall this history of copyright
9276 is not bad. As chapter 10 details, when new technologies have come
9277 along, Congress has struck a balance to assure that the new is protected
9278 from the old. Compulsory, or statutory, licenses have been one part of
9279 that strategy. Free use (as in the case of the VCR) has been another.
9280 </para>
9281 <para>
9282 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
9283 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
9284 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
9285 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
9286 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
9287 </para>
9288 <para>
9289 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.<footnote><para>
9290 <!-- f10. --> The only circuit court exception is found in Recording Industry Association
9291 of America (RIAA) v. Diamond Multimedia Systems, 180 F. 3d 1072 (9th
9292 Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit reasoned that
9293 makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for contributory
9294 copyright
9295 infringement for a device that is unable to record or redistribute
9296 music
9297 (a device whose only copying function is to render portable a music file
9298 already stored on a user's hard drive).
9299 At the district court level, the only exception is found in
9300 Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer
9301 Studios, Inc. v. Grokster, Ltd., 259 F. Supp. 2d 1029 (C.D.
9302 Cal., 2003), where the court found the link between the distributor and
9303 any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the distributor liable for
9304 contributory or vicarious infringement liability.
9305 </para></footnote>
9306 It has been
9307 mirrored in the responses threatened and actually implemented by
9308 Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses here.<footnote><para>
9309 <!-- f11. -->
9310 For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
9311 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize
9312 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
9313 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
9314 August 2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
9315 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
9316 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a "broadcast flag" that
9317 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
9318 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
9319 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
9320 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, "Copyright and
9321 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World," 27 June 2003, 33&ndash;34,
9322 available at
9323 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
9324 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
9325 </para></footnote>
9326 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
9327 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
9328 </para>
9329 <para>
9330
9331 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
9332 As I described in chapter 4, when a radio station plays a song, the
9333 recording artist doesn't get paid for that "radio performance" unless
9334 he or she is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had
9335 recorded a version of "Happy Birthday"&mdash;to memorialize her famous
9336 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden&mdash;
9337 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
9338 copyright owners of "Happy Birthday" would get some money, whereas
9339 Marilyn Monroe would not.
9340 </para>
9341 <para>
9342 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
9343 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
9344 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
9345 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
9346 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
9347 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
9348 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
9349 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
9350 recording artists.
9351 </para>
9352 <para>
9353 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
9354 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
9355 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
9356 spectrum. Thus, I can "tune in" to an Internet radio station in
9357 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
9358 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
9359 metropolitan area.
9360 </para>
9361 <para>
9362 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
9363 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
9364 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
9365 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
9366 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
9367 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
9368 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
9369 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
9370 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
9371 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
9372 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
9373 </para>
9374 <para>
9375
9376 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
9377 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
9378 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
9379 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
9380 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
9381 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
9382 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
9383 FM radio,
9384 </para>
9385 <blockquote>
9386 <para>
9387 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
9388 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
9389 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
9390 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
9391 than by technical restrictions. . . . Armstrong likened the situation
9392 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
9393 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
9394 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
9395 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
9396 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
9397 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
9398 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
9399 shackles.<footnote><para>
9400 <!-- f12. -->
9401 Lessing, 239.
9402 </para></footnote>
9403 </para>
9404 </blockquote>
9405 <para>
9406 This potential for FM radio was never realized&mdash;not
9407 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
9408 underestimated the power of "vested interests, habits, customs and
9409 legislation"<footnote><para>
9410 <!-- f13. -->
9411 Ibid., 229.
9412 </para></footnote>
9413 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
9414 </para>
9415 <para>
9416 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
9417 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
9418 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
9419 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
9420 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
9421 radio?
9422 </para>
9423 <para>
9424 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
9425 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
9426
9427 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
9428 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the
9429 phenomenon
9430 of Internet radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress
9431 to adopt a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
9432 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
9433 hypothetical
9434 Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording of
9435 "Happy Birthday" on the air, Internet radio does. Not only is the law not
9436 neutral toward Internet radio&mdash;the law actually burdens Internet radio
9437 more than it burdens terrestrial radio.
9438 </para>
9439 <para>
9440 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
9441 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
9442 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
9443 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
9444 over $1 million a year.<footnote>
9445 <para>
9446 <!-- f14. -->
9447 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
9448 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
9449 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
9450 iLaw (Stanford), 3 July 2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
9451 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
9452 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
9453 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP
9454 DTRA 1 and 2, available at
9455 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #45</ulink>.
9456 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
9457 C. Picker, "Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
9458 Distribution," Antitrust Bulletin (Summer/Fall 2002): 461: "This was
9459 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
9460 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
9461 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
9462 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
9463 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way."
9464 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)</primary></indexterm>
9465 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
9466 </para></footnote>
9467 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
9468 equivalent fee.
9469 </para>
9470 <para>
9471 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
9472 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio station)
9473 would have to collect the following data from every listening transaction:
9474 </para>
9475 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
9476 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
9477 <listitem><para>
9478 name of the service;
9479 </para></listitem>
9480 <listitem><para>
9481 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
9482 </para></listitem>
9483 <listitem><para>
9484 type of program (archived/looped/live);
9485 </para></listitem>
9486 <listitem><para>
9487 date of transmission;
9488 </para></listitem>
9489 <listitem><para>
9490 time of transmission;
9491 </para></listitem>
9492 <listitem><para>
9493 time zone of origination of transmission;
9494 </para></listitem>
9495 <listitem><para>
9496 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
9497 </para></listitem>
9498 <listitem><para>
9499 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
9500 </para></listitem>
9501 <listitem><para>
9502 sound recording title;
9503 </para></listitem>
9504 <listitem><para>
9505 ISRC code of the recording;
9506 </para></listitem>
9507 <listitem><para>
9508 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
9509 </para></listitem>
9510 <listitem><para>
9511 featured recording artist;
9512 </para></listitem>
9513 <listitem><para>
9514 retail album title;
9515 </para></listitem>
9516 <listitem><para>
9517 recording label;
9518 </para></listitem>
9519 <listitem><para>
9520 UPC code of the retail album;
9521 </para></listitem>
9522 <listitem><para>
9523 catalog number;
9524 </para></listitem>
9525 <listitem><para>
9526 copyright owner information;
9527 </para></listitem>
9528 <listitem><para>
9529 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
9530 </para></listitem>
9531 <listitem><para>
9532 name of the service or entity;
9533 </para></listitem>
9534 <listitem><para>
9535 channel or program;
9536 </para></listitem>
9537 <listitem><para>
9538 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
9539 </para></listitem>
9540 <listitem><para>
9541 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
9542 </para></listitem>
9543 <listitem><para>
9544 time zone where the signal was received (user);
9545 </para></listitem>
9546 <listitem><para>
9547 Unique User identifier;
9548 </para></listitem>
9549 <listitem><para>
9550 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
9551 </para></listitem>
9552 </orderedlist>
9553
9554 <para>
9555 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
9556 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
9557 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
9558 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
9559 Internet radio has to pay a type of copyright fee that terrestrial radio
9560 does not.
9561 </para>
9562 <para>
9563 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
9564 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
9565 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
9566 </para>
9567 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
9568 <para>
9569 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
9570 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
9571 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
9572 </para>
9573 <blockquote>
9574 <para>
9575 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
9576 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
9577 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
9578 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
9579 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
9580 webcasters asked the RIAA, . . . "How do you come up with a
9581
9582 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
9583 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio?
9584 Because
9585 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who
9586 want to pay, and that should establish the market rate, and if you
9587 set the rate so high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out
9588 of business. . . ."
9589 </para>
9590 <para>
9591 And the RIAA experts said, "Well, we don't really model this
9592 as an industry with thousands of webcasters, we think it should be
9593 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
9594 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market." (Emphasis added.)
9595 </para>
9596 </blockquote>
9597 <para>
9598 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
9599 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
9600 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
9601 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
9602 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
9603 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
9604 effective to prevent it.
9605 </para>
9606 </sect2>
9607 <sect2 id="corruptingcitizens">
9608 <title>Corrupting Citizens</title>
9609 <para>
9610 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
9611 dinosaurs
9612 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
9613 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
9614 </para>
9615 <para>
9616 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
9617 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
9618 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
9619 </para>
9620 <para>
9621 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
9622 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
9623 large number of citizens. According to The New York Times, 43 million
9624 Americans downloaded music in May 2002.<footnote><para>
9625 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, "The Music Downloading Deluge," Pew
9626 Internet and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at
9627 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #46</ulink>.
9628 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that 37 million
9629 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early 2001.
9630 </para></footnote>
9631 According to the RIAA,
9632 the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
9633 set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As the
9634
9635 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
9636 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
9637 the world, but against students building search engines, and
9638 increasingly
9639 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
9640 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
9641 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
9642 extreme
9643 response by the other.
9644 </para>
9645 <para>
9646 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
9647 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
9648 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
9649 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
9650 ($15,000,000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
9651 paying all the money in the world in damages ($250,000 in legal fees)
9652 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
9653 ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
9654 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September 2003, the RIAA
9655 sued 261 individuals&mdash;including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
9656 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
9657 was.<footnote><para>
9658 <!-- f16. -->
9659 Alex Pham, "The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case," Los
9660 Angeles Times, 10 September 2003, Business.
9661 </para></footnote>
9662 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
9663 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
9664 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000
9665 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
9666 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
9667 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
9668 they oppose.
9669 </para>
9670 <para>
9671 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
9672 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
9673 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
9674 consumption of alcohol was 1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
9675 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just 30 percent
9676 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
9677 consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition
9678 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
9679 number were criminals.<footnote><para>
9680 <!-- f17. -->
9681 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, "Alcohol Consumption During
9682 Prohibition," American Economic Review 81, no. 2 (1991): 242.
9683 </para></footnote>
9684 We have
9685 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
9686 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
9687 narcotics that 7 percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.<footnote><para>
9688 <!-- f18. -->
9689 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
9690 Reform Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of
9691 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
9692 </para></footnote>
9693 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of
9694 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
9695 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
9696 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
9697 cheat.<footnote><para>
9698 <!-- f19. -->
9699 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, "Tax
9700 Compliance," Journal of Economic Literature 36 (1998): 818 (survey of
9701 compliance literature).
9702 </para></footnote>
9703 We pride ourselves on our "free society," but an endless array of
9704 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
9705 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
9706 </para>
9707 <para>
9708 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
9709 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
9710 students about the importance of "ethics." As my colleague Charlie
9711 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
9712 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
9713 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
9714 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
9715 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
9716 teach them how to behave ethically&mdash;how to say no to bribes, or
9717 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
9718 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
9719 Americans&mdash;more significantly in some parts of America than in
9720 others, but still, everywhere in America today&mdash;can't live their
9721 lives both normally and legally, since "normally" entails a certain
9722 degree of illegality.
9723 </para>
9724 <para>
9725 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
9726 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
9727 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
9728 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
9729 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
9730 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
9731 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
9732 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
9733 to consider the alternative.
9734 </para>
9735 <para>
9736
9737 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
9738 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
9739 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
9740 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
9741 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
9742 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
9743 </para>
9744 <para>
9745 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
9746 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
9747 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
9748 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
9749 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
9750 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
9751 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
9752 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
9753 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
9754 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
9755 introduced this different idea of "sharing." We need to be able to
9756 call these twenty million Americans "citizens," not "felons."
9757 </para>
9758 <para>
9759 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
9760 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
9761 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
9762 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
9763 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
9764 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
9765 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
9766 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
9767 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
9768 a nation of felons?
9769 </para>
9770 <para>
9771 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
9772 </para>
9773 <para>
9774 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
9775 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
9776 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
9777 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
9778 used
9779
9780 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
9781 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That "use" of the
9782 recordings is free.
9783 </para>
9784 <para>
9785 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
9786 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
9787 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am "free" to copy,
9788 or "rip," music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
9789 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that "freedom" was a
9790 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the "Rip, Mix, Burn"
9791 capacities of digital technologies.
9792 </para>
9793 <indexterm><primary>Adromeda</primary></indexterm>
9794 <para>
9795 This "use" of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
9796 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
9797 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
9798 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
9799 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
9800 Others&mdash;the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
9801 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
9802 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
9803 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
9804 </para>
9805 <para>
9806 This use is enabled by unprotected media&mdash;either CDs or records.
9807 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
9808 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
9809 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
9810 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
9811 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
9812 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
9813 on people's machines.
9814 </para>
9815 <para>
9816 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
9817 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
9818 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
9819 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
9820 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
9821 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
9822
9823 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
9824 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
9825 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
9826 plastic or were part of a massively complex "digital rights
9827 management" system.
9828 </para>
9829 <para>
9830 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
9831 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
9832 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
9833 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
9834 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
9835 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
9836 freedom to move content easily?
9837 </para>
9838 <para>
9839 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
9840 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
9841 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
9842 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
9843 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
9844 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
9845 alternative&mdash;namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
9846 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
9847 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
9848 </para>
9849 <para>
9850 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
9851 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
9852 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
9853 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
9854 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
9855 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
9856 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
9857 </para>
9858 <para>
9859 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
9860 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
9861 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
9862 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
9863 </para>
9864 <para>
9865 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
9866 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
9867
9868 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
9869
9870 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
9871 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
9872 There's one more aspect to this corruption that is particularly
9873 important to civil liberties, and follows directly from any war of
9874 prohibition. As Electronic Frontier Foundation attorney Fred von
9875 Lohmann describes, this is the "collateral damage" that "arises
9876 whenever you turn a very large percentage of the population into
9877 criminals." This is the collateral damage to civil liberties
9878 generally.
9879 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
9880 </para>
9881 <para>
9882 "If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker," von Lohmann
9883 explains,
9884 </para>
9885 <blockquote>
9886 <para>
9887 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
9888 evaporate to one degree or another. . . . If you're a copyright
9889 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
9890 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
9891 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
9892 access? . . . Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, "Oh, well,
9893 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker." Well, what this campaign
9894 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
9895 American Internet-using population into "lawbreakers."
9896 </para>
9897 </blockquote>
9898 <para>
9899 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
9900 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
9901 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
9902 </para>
9903 <para>
9904 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA
9905 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
9906 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
9907 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
9908 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
9909 an Internet user is revealed.
9910 </para>
9911 <para>
9912 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
9913 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
9914 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
9915 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
9916 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
9917 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
9918 the family could be liable for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop
9919 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
9920 Jesse Jordan.<footnote><para>
9921 <!-- f20. -->
9922 See Frank Ahrens, "RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
9923 Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,"
9924 Washington Post, 10 September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, "Worried Parents
9925 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
9926 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
9927 Being Sued," Orlando Sentinel Tribune, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson
9928 Graham, "Recording Industry Sues Parents," USA Today, 15 September
9929 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, "She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
9930 Fan, Either," New York Times, 25 September 2003, C1; Margo Varadi, "Is
9931 Brianna a Criminal?" Toronto Star, 18 September 2003, P7.
9932 </para></footnote>
9933
9934 </para>
9935 <para>
9936 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
9937 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
9938 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.<footnote><para>
9939 <!-- f21. -->
9940 See "Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
9941 Some Methods Used," CNN.com, available at
9942 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #47</ulink>.
9943 </para></footnote>
9944 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
9945 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
9946 one of those MP3s will have the same "fingerprint."
9947 </para>
9948 <para>
9949 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
9950 friend gives a CD to your daughter&mdash;a collection of songs just
9951 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
9952 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
9953 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
9954 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
9955 network is "cooperating" with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
9956 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
9957 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
9958 as a "criminal." And under the rules that universities are beginning
9959 to deploy,<footnote><para>
9960 <!-- f22. -->
9961 See Jeff Adler, "Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,"
9962 Boston Globe, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, "Four
9963 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
9964 Colleges," Washington Post, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
9965 "Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk," Christian Science
9966 Monitor, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, "Music
9967 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
9968 Lawsuit Possible," Chicago Tribune, 16 July 2003, 1C; Beth Cox, "RIAA
9969 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities," Internet News, 30 January
9970 2003, available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9971 #48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, "Download Warning 101: Freshman
9972 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
9973 Sharing," San Francisco Chronicle, 11 August 2003, E11; "Raid, Letters
9974 Are Weapons at Universities," USA Today, 26 September 2000, 3D.
9975 </para></footnote>
9976 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
9977 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
9978 </para>
9979 <para>
9980 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
9981 a lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
9982 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
9983 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
9984 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
9985 this "contraband" as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
9986 college students
9987
9988 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
9989 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
9990 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
9991 Says von Lohmann,
9992 </para>
9993 <blockquote>
9994 <para>
9995 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
9996 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
9997 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
9998 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
9999 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10000 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10001 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10002 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10003 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10004 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10005 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10006 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10007 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10008 larger number of Americans than drug use. . . . If forty to sixty
10009 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10010 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10011 million of them.
10012 </para>
10013 </blockquote>
10014 <para>
10015 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered "criminals" under
10016 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective&mdash;
10017 securing rights to authors&mdash;without these millions being
10018 considered "criminals," who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10019 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10020 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10021 </para>
10022
10023 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10024 </sect2>
10025 </sect1>
10026 </chapter>
10027 <chapter id="c-balances">
10028 <title>BALANCES</title>
10029
10030 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10031 <para>
10032 So here's the picture: You're standing at the side of the road. Your
10033 car is on fire. You are angry and upset because in part you helped start
10034 the fire. Now you don't know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket,
10035 filled with gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10036 </para>
10037 <para>
10038 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10039 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10040 stop&mdash;or before she understands just why she should
10041 stop&mdash;the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10042 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10043 everything around.
10044 </para>
10045 <para>
10046 A war about copyright rages all around&mdash;and we're all focusing on
10047 the wrong thing. No doubt, current technologies threaten existing
10048 businesses. No doubt they may threaten artists. But technologies
10049 change. The industry and technologists have plenty of ways to use
10050 technology to protect themselves against the current threats of the
10051 Internet. This is a fire that if let alone would burn itself out.
10052 </para>
10053 <para>
10054 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
10055 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
10056 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
10057 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
10058 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
10059 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
10060 made that is happening all around.
10061 </para>
10062 <para>
10063 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
10064 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
10065 gasoline onto this fire.
10066 </para>
10067 <para>
10068 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
10069 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
10070 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
10071 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
10072 </para>
10073 <para>
10074 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
10075 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
10076 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
10077 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
10078 success will require.
10079 </para>
10080
10081 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
10082 <sect1 id="eldred">
10083 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred</title>
10084 <para>
10085 In 1995, a father was frustrated that his daughters didn't seem to
10086 like Hawthorne. No doubt there was more than one such father, but at
10087 least one did something about it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer
10088 programmer living in New Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the
10089 Web. An electronic version, Eldred thought, with links to pictures and
10090 explanatory text, would make this nineteenth-century author's work
10091 come alive.
10092 </para>
10093 <para>
10094 It didn't work&mdash;at least for his daughters. They didn't find
10095 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
10096 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
10097 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
10098 them available for free.
10099 </para>
10100 <para>
10101 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
10102 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
10103 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
10104 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
10105 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
10106 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
10107 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
10108 many others, into a form more accessible&mdash;technically
10109 accessible&mdash;today.
10110 </para>
10111 <para>
10112 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
10113 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's Scarlet Letter had passed into the
10114 public domain in 1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
10115 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
10116 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
10117 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
10118 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
10119 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (Cinderella), sometimes not
10120 (The Hunchback of Notre Dame, Treasure Planet). These are all
10121 commercial publications of public domain works.
10122 </para>
10123 <para>
10124 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
10125 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
10126 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
10127 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
10128 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
10129 call the "noncommercial publishing industry," which before the
10130 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
10131 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
10132 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
10133 generally.<footnote><para>
10134 <!-- f1. -->
10135 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
10136 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
10137 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers&mdash;people who
10138 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
10139 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
10140 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
10141 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
10142 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
10143 Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on
10144 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
10145 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
10146 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
10147 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
10148 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
10149 protect noncommercial pornographers.</para></footnote>
10150 </para>
10151 <para>
10152 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's
10153 collection of poems New Hampshire was slated to pass into the public
10154 domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in his free public
10155 library. But Congress got in the way. As I described in chapter 10,
10156 in 1998, for the eleventh time in forty years, Congress extended the
10157 terms of existing copyrights&mdash;this time by twenty years. Eldred
10158 would not be free to add any works more recent than 1923 to his
10159 collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work would pass into
10160 the public domain until that year (and not even then, if Congress
10161 extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period, more than 1
10162 million patents will pass into the public domain.
10163 </para>
10164 <para>
10165
10166 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
10167 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
10168 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
10169 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
10170 "copyrights should be forever."<footnote><para>
10171 <!-- f2. -->
10172 The full text is: "Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
10173 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
10174 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
10175 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
10176 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
10177 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
10178 Congress," 144 Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998).
10179 </para></footnote>
10180
10181 </para>
10182 <para>
10183 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
10184 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
10185 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
10186 second law passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
10187 of publishing would make Eldred a felon&mdash;whether or not anyone
10188 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
10189 to undertake.
10190 </para>
10191 <para>
10192 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
10193 constitutional
10194 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
10195 interpretation.
10196 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
10197 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
10198 importantly
10199 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
10200 </para>
10201 <blockquote>
10202 <para>
10203 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science . . .
10204 by securing for limited Times to Authors . . . exclusive Right to
10205 their . . . Writings. . . .
10206 </para>
10207 </blockquote>
10208 <para>
10209 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
10210 clause of Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
10211 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
10212 something&mdash;for example, to regulate "commerce among the several
10213 states" or "declare War." But here, the "something" is something quite
10214 specific&mdash;to "promote . . . Progress"&mdash;through means that
10215 are also specific&mdash; by "securing" "exclusive Rights" (i.e.,
10216 copyrights) "for limited Times."
10217 </para>
10218 <para>
10219 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
10220 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
10221 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
10222 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be "limited" will have
10223 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
10224 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
10225 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
10226 what the Constitution plainly forbids&mdash;perpetual terms "on the
10227 installment plan," as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
10228 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
10229 </para>
10230 <para>
10231 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
10232 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
10233 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
10234 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
10235 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
10236 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
10237 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
10238 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
10239 this gravy train going.
10240 </para>
10241 <para>
10242 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
10243 government. "Corruption" not in the sense that representatives are
10244 bribed. Rather, "corruption" in the sense that the system induces the
10245 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
10246 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
10247 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
10248 do&mdash;and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
10249 </para>
10250 <para>
10251 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
10252 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
10253 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
10254 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry
10255 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
10256 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
10257 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
10258 published by anyone for free.
10259 </para>
10260 <para>
10261 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from
10262 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
10263 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
10264 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
10265 report:
10266 </para>
10267 <para>
10268 "Next year," the adviser announces, "our copyrights in works A, B,
10269
10270 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
10271 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
10272 receiving the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of
10273 those works.
10274 </para>
10275 <para>
10276 "There's a proposal in Congress, however," she continues, "that
10277 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
10278 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
10279 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes."
10280 </para>
10281 <para>
10282 "Hope?" a fellow board member says. "Can't we be doing something
10283 about it?"
10284 </para>
10285 <para>
10286 "Well, obviously, yes," the adviser responds. "We could contribute
10287 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
10288 they support the bill."
10289 </para>
10290 <para>
10291 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
10292 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. "How much
10293 would we get if this extension were passed?" you ask the adviser. "How
10294 much is it worth?"
10295 </para>
10296 <para>
10297 "Well," the adviser says, "if you're confident that you will continue
10298 to get at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
10299 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent),
10300 then this law would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate."
10301 </para>
10302 <para>
10303 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
10304 correct conclusion:
10305 </para>
10306 <para>
10307 "So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
10308 $1,000,000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
10309 contributions
10310 would assure that the bill was passed?"
10311 </para>
10312 <para>
10313 "Absolutely," the adviser responds. "It is worth it to you to
10314 contribute
10315 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
10316 copyrights. Which for us means over $1,000,000."
10317 </para>
10318 <para>
10319 You quickly get the point&mdash;you as the member of the board and, I
10320 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
10321 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
10322 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
10323 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
10324 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
10325 copyrights
10326 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
10327 the copyright term extended.
10328 </para>
10329 <para>
10330 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as
10331 legislation
10332 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
10333 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
10334 </para>
10335 <para>
10336 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
10337 Copyright
10338 Term Extension Act, this "theory" about incentives was proved
10339 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
10340 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
10341 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
10342 contributions.<footnote><para>
10343 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, "Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
10344 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years,"
10345 Chicago Tribune, 17 October 1998, 22.
10346 </para></footnote>
10347 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
10348 $1.5 million lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more
10349 than $200,000 in campaign contributions.<footnote><para>
10350 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, "Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
10351 Age," available at
10352 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #49</ulink>.
10353 </para></footnote>
10354 Disney is estimated to have
10355 contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in the
10356 cycle.<footnote><para>
10357 <!-- f5. --> Alan K. Ota, "Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,"
10358 Congressional
10359 Quarterly This Week, 8 August 1990, available at
10360 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #50</ulink>.
10361 </para></footnote>
10362
10363 </para>
10364 <para>
10365 Constitutional law is not oblivious to the obvious. Or at least,
10366 it need not be. So when I was considering Eldred's complaint, this
10367 reality
10368 about the never-ending incentives to increase the copyright term
10369 was central to my thinking. In my view, a pragmatic court committed
10370 to interpreting and applying the Constitution of our framers would see
10371 that if Congress has the power to extend existing terms, then there
10372 would be no effective constitutional requirement that terms be
10373 "limited."
10374 If they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again
10375 and again.
10376 </para>
10377 <para>
10378 It was also my judgment that this Supreme Court would not allow
10379 Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to the Supreme
10380 Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted the power
10381 of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as exceeding the
10382 power granted to it by the Constitution. Among constitutional
10383 scholars,
10384 the most famous example of this trend was the Supreme Court's
10385
10386 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
10387 decision in 1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
10388 guns near schools.
10389 </para>
10390 <para>
10391 Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
10392 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
10393 power to regulate only "commerce among the several states" (aka
10394 "interstate
10395 commerce"), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
10396 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
10397 interstate
10398 commerce.
10399 </para>
10400 <para>
10401 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there
10402 was no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
10403 activity,
10404 when considered on a national scale, affects interstate commerce.
10405 A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was instead
10406 interpreted
10407 to impose no limit.
10408 </para>
10409 <para>
10410 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command,
10411 changed that in United States v. Lopez. The government had argued
10412 that possessing guns near schools affected interstate commerce. Guns
10413 near schools increase crime, crime lowers property values, and so on. In
10414 the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the government whether
10415 there was any activity that would not affect interstate commerce under
10416 the reasoning the government advanced. The government said there
10417 was not; if Congress says an activity affects interstate commerce, then
10418 that activity affects interstate commerce. The Supreme Court, the
10419 government
10420 said, was not in the position to second-guess Congress.
10421 </para>
10422 <para>
10423 "We pause to consider the implications of the government's
10424 arguments,"
10425 the Chief Justice wrote.<footnote><para>
10426 <!-- f6. --> United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995).
10427 </para></footnote>
10428 If anything Congress says is interstate
10429 commerce must therefore be considered interstate commerce, then
10430 there would be no limit to Congress's power. The decision in Lopez was
10431 reaffirmed five years later in United States v. Morrison.<footnote><para>
10432 <!-- f7. --> United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598 (2000).
10433 </para></footnote>
10434
10435 </para>
10436 <para>
10437 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
10438 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.<footnote><para>
10439 <!-- f8. --> If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle carries
10440 from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in the
10441 context
10442 of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered by the
10443 government would allow the government unending power to regulate
10444 commerce&mdash;the limitation to interstate commerce notwithstanding. The
10445 same point is true in the context of the Copyright Clause. Here, too, the
10446 government's interpretation would allow the government unending power
10447 to regulate copyrights&mdash;the limitation to "limited times" notwithstanding.
10448 </para></footnote>
10449 And if it is applied to the
10450 Progress Clause, the principle should yield the conclusion that
10451 Congress
10452 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
10453 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an
10454 existing
10455 term, then there would be no "stopping point" to Congress's power
10456 over terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such
10457 a limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
10458 copyrights
10459 should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the term of
10460 existing copyrights.
10461 </para>
10462 <para>
10463 If, that is, the principle announced in Lopez stood for a principle.
10464 Many believed the decision in Lopez stood for politics&mdash;a conservative
10465 Supreme Court, which believed in states' rights, using its power over
10466 Congress to advance its own personal political preferences. But I
10467 rejected
10468 that view of the Supreme Court's decision. Indeed, shortly after
10469 the decision, I wrote an article demonstrating the "fidelity" in such an
10470 interpretation of the Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court
10471 decides cases based upon its politics struck me as extraordinarily
10472 boring.
10473 I was not going to devote my life to teaching constitutional law if
10474 these nine Justices were going to be petty politicians.
10475 </para>
10476 <para>
10477 Now let's pause for a moment to make sure we understand what
10478 the argument in Eldred was not about. By insisting on the
10479 Constitution's
10480 limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing piracy.
10481 Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of piracy&mdash;piracy of
10482 the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his work and when Walt
10483 Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright term was just
10484 fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and Disney had
10485 already
10486 enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their work. They had
10487 gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution envisions: In
10488 exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years, they created new
10489 work. But now these entities were using their power&mdash;expressed
10490 through the power of lobbyists' money&mdash;to get another twenty-year
10491 dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop would be taken from the
10492 public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a piracy that affects us all.
10493 </para>
10494 <para>
10495 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
10496
10497 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
10498 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
10499 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than "legal piracy."<footnote><para>
10500 <!-- f9. --> Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S.
10501 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available at
10502 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #51</ulink>.
10503 </para></footnote>
10504 But
10505 it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional system,
10506 our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's requirements,
10507 but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's charter.
10508 </para>
10509 <para>
10510 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
10511 copyright
10512 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
10513 influence
10514 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
10515 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
10516 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
10517 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
10518 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
10519 bought to extend them again.
10520 </para>
10521 <para>
10522 It is valuable copyrights that are responsible for terms being
10523 extended.
10524 Mickey Mouse and "Rhapsody in Blue." These works are too
10525 valuable for copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our
10526 society
10527 from copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains
10528 Disney's.
10529 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works
10530 from the 1920s and 1930s that have continuing commercial value. The
10531 real harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The
10532 real harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially
10533 exploited,
10534 and no longer available as a result.
10535 </para>
10536 <para>
10537 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to
10538 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
10539 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
10540 copyright holders for that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
10541 But the law and its effect were not limited to that 2 percent. The law
10542 extended the terms of copyright generally.<footnote><para>
10543 <!-- f10. --> The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
10544 Congressional
10545 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
10546 of Petitioners, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 7, available at
10547 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #52</ulink>.
10548 </para></footnote>
10549
10550 </para>
10551 <para>
10552 Think practically about the consequence of this
10553 extension&mdash;practically,
10554 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
10555
10556 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
10557 work. In 1930, 10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those
10558 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
10559 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
10560 remaining
10561 9,873. What would you have to do?
10562 </para>
10563 <para>
10564 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were
10565 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
10566 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
10567 titles and authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration
10568 and renewal records for works published in 1930. That will produce a
10569 list of books still under copyright.
10570 </para>
10571 <para>
10572 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
10573 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
10574 </para>
10575 <para>
10576 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
10577 owners
10578 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
10579 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
10580 being at least a list?
10581 </para>
10582 <para>
10583 But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in
10584 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
10585 practically
10586 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
10587 thousands
10588 of such records&mdash;especially since the person who registered is
10589 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930!
10590 </para>
10591 <para>
10592 "But there isn't a list of who owns property generally," the
10593 apologists
10594 for the system respond. "Why should there be a list of copyright
10595 owners?"
10596 </para>
10597 <para>
10598 Well, actually, if you think about it, there are plenty of lists of who
10599 owns what property. Think about deeds on houses, or titles to cars.
10600 And where there isn't a list, the code of real space is pretty good at
10601 suggesting
10602 who the owner of a bit of property is. (A swing set in your
10603 backyard is probably yours.) So formally or informally, we have a pretty
10604 good way to know who owns what tangible property.
10605 </para>
10606 <para>
10607 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
10608 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
10609 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
10610
10611 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
10612 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
10613 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
10614 happen
10615 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
10616 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
10617 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
10618 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
10619 know quite well who owns what property.
10620 </para>
10621 <para>
10622 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
10623 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
10624 already
10625 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
10626 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
10627 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
10628 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
10629 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
10630 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
10631 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
10632 </para>
10633 <para>
10634 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
10635 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
10636 consequence
10637 for other creative works is much more dire.
10638 </para>
10639 <indexterm><primary>Agee, Michael</primary></indexterm>
10640 <para>
10641 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
10642 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
10643 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
10644 made between 1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, The Lucky Dog, is
10645 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923
10646 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
10647 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
10648 money. According to one estimate, "Roach has sold about 60,000
10649 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's silent
10650 films."<footnote><para>
10651 <!-- f11. -->
10652 See David G. Savage, "High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,"
10653 Los Angeles Times, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, "Classic Movies,
10654 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
10655 Down Copyright Extension," Orlando Sentinel Tribune, 9 October 2002.
10656 </para></footnote>
10657
10658 </para>
10659 <para>
10660 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
10661 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
10662 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
10663 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
10664 </para>
10665 <para>
10666 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
10667
10668 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
10669 any continuing commercial value. The rest&mdash;to the extent it
10670 survives at all&mdash;sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
10671 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
10672 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
10673 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
10674 work available for distribution.
10675 </para>
10676 <para>
10677 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
10678 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
10679 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
10680 it cost more than $10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
10681 film in 1993, it can now cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of
10682 mm film.<footnote><para>
10683 <!-- f12. --> Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
10684 Supporting
10685 the Petitoners, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-
10686 618), 12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae filed on behalf of Petitioners by
10687 the Internet Archive, Eldred v. Ashcroft, available at
10688 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #53</ulink>.
10689 </para></footnote>
10690
10691 </para>
10692 <para>
10693 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
10694 important.
10695 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
10696 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
10697 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
10698 locate the copyright owner.
10699 </para>
10700 <para>
10701 Or more accurately, owners. As we've seen, there isn't only a single
10702 copyright associated with a film; there are many. There isn't a single
10703 person whom you can contact about those copyrights; there are as
10704 many as can hold the rights, which turns out to be an extremely large
10705 number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights to these films is
10706 exceptionally
10707 high.
10708 </para>
10709 <para>
10710 "But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
10711 copyright owner when she shows up?" Sure, if you want to commit a
10712 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
10713 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
10714 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
10715 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
10716 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
10717 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
10718 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
10719 </para>
10720 <para>
10721 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
10722
10723 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
10724 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
10725 benefit
10726 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
10727 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
10728 the copyright expires.
10729 </para>
10730 <para>
10731 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
10732 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
10733 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
10734 canisters
10735 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
10736 than dust.
10737 </para>
10738 <para>
10739 Of all the creative work produced by humans anywhere, a tiny
10740 fraction has continuing commercial value. For that tiny fraction, the
10741 copyright is a crucially important legal device. For that tiny fraction,
10742 the copyright creates incentives to produce and distribute the
10743 creative
10744 work. For that tiny fraction, the copyright acts as an "engine of
10745 free expression."
10746 </para>
10747 <para>
10748 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
10749 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
10750 indicated,
10751 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
10752 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
10753 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
10754 distributors,
10755 the commercial life ends.
10756 </para>
10757 <para>
10758 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
10759 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes &amp; Noble, and
10760 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
10761 between
10762 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
10763 Friday
10764 night watching a 1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
10765 of culture is important and valuable&mdash;for entertainment but also, and
10766 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
10767 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
10768 have, we need to have access to this history.
10769 </para>
10770 <para>
10771 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
10772
10773 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
10774 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
10775 this context do no good.
10776 </para>
10777 <para>
10778 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
10779 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
10780 copyright-related use that would be inhibited by an exclusive right.
10781 When a book went out of print, you could not buy it from a publisher.
10782 But you could still buy it from a used book store, and when a used
10783 book store sells it, in America, at least, there is no need to pay the
10784 copyright owner anything. Thus, the ordinary use of a book after its
10785 commercial life ended was a use that was independent of copyright law.
10786 </para>
10787 <para>
10788 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
10789 a film&mdash;the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs&mdash;were
10790 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
10791 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
10792 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
10793 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
10794 market didn't have more to offer.
10795 </para>
10796 <para>
10797 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
10798 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
10799 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
10800 would not have interfered with anything.
10801 </para>
10802 <para>
10803 But this situation has now changed.
10804 </para>
10805 <para>
10806 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
10807 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
10808 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
10809 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
10810 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
10811 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
10812 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
10813 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
10814 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
10815 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
10816 </para>
10817 <para>
10818 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
10819 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
10820 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
10821 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
10822 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
10823 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
10824 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
10825 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
10826 written for a radically different context.
10827 </para>
10828 <para>
10829 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
10830 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
10831 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
10832 copyright purpose, for the purpose of copyright is to enable the
10833 commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are talking about
10834 culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this context,
10835 copyright is serving no purpose at all related to the spread of
10836 knowledge. In this context, copyright is not an engine of free
10837 expression. Copyright is a brake.
10838 </para>
10839 <para>
10840 You may well ask, "But if digital technologies lower the costs for
10841 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
10842 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
10843 culture widely?"
10844 </para>
10845 <para>
10846 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
10847 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes &amp; Noble
10848 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
10849 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
10850 of a library is to serve what "the market" would demand. But if you
10851 think the role of a library is bigger than this&mdash;if you think its
10852 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
10853 particular bit of that culture or not&mdash;then we can't count on the
10854 commercial market to do our library work for us.
10855 </para>
10856 <para>
10857 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
10858 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
10859 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
10860 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
10861
10862 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
10863 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
10864 culture, 94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
10865 and 1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
10866 commercial market, if access is a value, then 6 percent is a failure
10867 to provide that value.<footnote><para>
10868 <!-- f13. -->
10869 Jason Schultz, "The Myth of the 1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory," 20
10870 December 2002, available at
10871 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #54</ulink>.
10872 </para></footnote>
10873
10874 </para>
10875 <para>
10876 In January 1999, we filed a lawsuit on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal
10877 district court in Washington, D.C., asking the court to declare the
10878 Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act unconstitutional. The two
10879 central claims that we made were (1) that extending existing terms
10880 violated the Constitution's "limited Times" requirement, and (2) that
10881 extending terms by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
10882 </para>
10883 <para>
10884 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
10885 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
10886 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
10887 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
10888 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
10889 </para>
10890 <para>
10891 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
10892 copyrights be for "limited Times" only. His argument was as elegant as
10893 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
10894 "stopping point" to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
10895 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
10896 terms that are "limited." Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
10897 to interpret the term "limited Times" to give it meaning. And the best
10898 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
10899 power to extend existing terms.
10900 </para>
10901 <para>
10902 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
10903 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
10904 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
10905 whole, where the court will sit "en banc" to hear the case.
10906 </para>
10907 <para>
10908 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
10909 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
10910
10911 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
10912 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
10913 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
10914 overstepped its bounds.
10915 </para>
10916 <para>
10917 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
10918 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
10919 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
10920 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
10921 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
10922 </para>
10923 <para>
10924 But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
10925 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
10926 was set for October of 2002. The summer would be spent writing
10927 briefs and preparing for argument.
10928 </para>
10929 <para>
10930 It is over a year later as I write these words. It is still
10931 astonishingly hard. If you know anything at all about this story, you
10932 know that we lost the appeal. And if you know something more than just
10933 the minimum, you probably think there was no way this case could have
10934 been won. After our defeat, I received literally thousands of missives
10935 by well-wishers and supporters, thanking me for my work on behalf of
10936 this noble but doomed cause. And none from this pile was more
10937 significant to me than the e-mail from my client, Eric Eldred.
10938 </para>
10939 <para>
10940 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
10941 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
10942 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
10943 mistake lost it.
10944 </para>
10945 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
10946 <para>
10947 The mistake was made early, though it became obvious only at the very
10948 end. Our case had been supported from the very beginning by an
10949 extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart, and by the law firm he had
10950 moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of
10951 heat
10952 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
10953 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
10954 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
10955 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
10956 </para>
10957 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
10958 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan</primary></indexterm>
10959 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
10960 <para>
10961 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
10962 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
10963 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
10964 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
10965 told me, if we could make the issue seem "important" to the Supreme
10966 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
10967 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against "the
10968 most powerful media companies in the world."
10969 </para>
10970 <para>
10971 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
10972 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
10973 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
10974 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
10975 "right" as in "true," I thought, but it is "wrong" as in "it just shouldn't be
10976 that way." As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
10977 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
10978 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
10979 interpretation
10980 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
10981 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
10982 unconstitutional,
10983 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
10984 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
10985 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
10986 Constitution,
10987 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
10988 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
10989 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
10990 </para>
10991 <para>
10992 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
10993 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
10994 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
10995 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
10996 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
10997 why it was unconstitutional.
10998 </para>
10999 <para>
11000 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
11001
11002 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
11003 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
11004 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
11005 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
11006 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed that
11007 this field of review was simply the preference of a small political
11008 minority.
11009 Although my focus in the case was not to demonstrate how bad the
11010 Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it was unconstitutional,
11011 my hope was to make this argument against a background of briefs that
11012 covered the full range of political views. To show that this claim against
11013 the CTEA was grounded in law and not politics, then, we tried to
11014 gather the widest range of credible critics&mdash;credible not because they
11015 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
11016 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
11017 </para>
11018 <para>
11019 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
11020 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
11021 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
11022 Congress. In November 1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
11023 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
11024 "Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
11025 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
11026 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
11027 to get bogged down?" The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
11028 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
11029 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
11030 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
11031 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11032 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis</primary></indexterm>
11033 </para>
11034 <para>
11035 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
11036 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
11037 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
11038 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
11039 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
11040 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
11041 </para>
11042 <para>
11043 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
11044 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
11045
11046 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
11047 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/ Linux
11048 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
11049 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
11050 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
11051 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
11052 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
11053 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
11054 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11055 </para>
11056 <para>
11057 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
11058 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
11059 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
11060 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
11061 </para>
11062 <para>
11063 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
11064 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
11065 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
11066 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
11067 clear.
11068 </para>
11069 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George</primary></indexterm>
11070 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
11071 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James</primary></indexterm>
11072 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11073 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton</primary></indexterm>
11074 <para>
11075 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
11076 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
11077 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
11078 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
11079 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
11080 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
11081 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
11082 nothing more than "rent-seeking"&mdash;the fancy term economists use
11083 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
11084 </para>
11085 <para>
11086 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
11087 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
11088 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
11089 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
11090 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
11091 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
11092 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
11093 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
11094
11095 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
11096 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
11097 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
11098 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11099 </para>
11100 <para>
11101 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
11102 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
11103 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
11104 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
11105 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
11106 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
11107 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
11108 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
11109 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
11110 confidence in our argument.
11111 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11112 </para>
11113 <para>
11114 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
11115 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these "friends" included
11116 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
11117 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
11118 copyright holders.
11119 </para>
11120 <para>
11121 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
11122 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either&mdash;they
11123 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
11124 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
11125 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
11126 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
11127 wanted to control.
11128 </para>
11129 <para>
11130 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
11131 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
11132 Dr. Seuss's work&mdash; better than allowing it to fall into the
11133 public domain&mdash;because if this creativity were in the public
11134 domain, then people could use it to "glorify drugs or to create
11135 pornography."<footnote><para>
11136 <!-- f14. -->
11137 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537
11138 U.S. (2003) (No. 01-618), 19.
11139 </para></footnote>
11140 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
11141 "protection" of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
11142 to license Porgy and Bess to anyone who refuses to use African
11143 Americans in the cast.<footnote><para>
11144 <!-- f15. -->
11145 Dinitia Smith, "Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
11146 Mouse Joins the Fray," New York Times, 28 March 1998, B7.
11147 </para></footnote>
11148 That's
11149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
11150 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
11151 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
11152 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George</primary></indexterm>
11153 </para>
11154 <para>
11155 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
11156 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
11157 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
11158 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
11159 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, "Give us twenty years
11160 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
11161 better with them than anyone else." Congress of course likes to reward
11162 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
11163 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
11164 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
11165 </para>
11166 <para>
11167 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
11168 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
11169 copyrights&mdash;extensions that would further concentrate the market;
11170 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
11171 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
11172 Between February and October, there was little I did beyond preparing
11173 for this case. Early on, as I said, I set the strategy.
11174 </para>
11175 <para>
11176 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One
11177 camp we called "the Conservatives." The other we called "the Rest."
11178 The Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
11179 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
11180 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
11181 five who had supported the Lopez/Morrison line of cases that said that
11182 an enumerated power had to be interpreted to assure that Congress's
11183 powers had limits.
11184 </para>
11185 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11186 <para>
11187 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
11188 Congress's power. These four&mdash;Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
11189 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer&mdash;had repeatedly argued that
11190 the Constitution
11191 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
11192 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
11193 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
11194 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
11195 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
11196 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
11197 </para>
11198 <para>
11199 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
11200 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
11201 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
11202 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
11203 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
11204 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
11205 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
11206 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
11207 sense.
11208 </para>
11209 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11210 <para>
11211 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
11212 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
11213 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
11214 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
11215 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
11216 these retrospective extensions.
11217 </para>
11218 <para>
11219 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
11220 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
11221 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
11222 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
11223 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
11224 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
11225 </para>
11226 <para>
11227 This analysis of "the Rest" showed most clearly where our focus
11228 had to be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open
11229 these five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
11230 overriding
11231 argument that animated our claim rested on the Conservatives'
11232 most important jurisprudential innovation&mdash;the argument that Judge
11233 Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals, that Congress's power
11234 must be interpreted so that its enumerated powers have limits.
11235 </para>
11236 <para>
11237 This then was the core of our strategy&mdash;a strategy for which I am
11238 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the Lopez
11239
11240 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
11241 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always
11242 have unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain
11243 about Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this
11244 power was supposed to be "limited." Our aim would be to get the
11245 Court to reconcile Eldred with Lopez: If Congress's power to regulate
11246 commerce was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate
11247 copyright be limited.
11248 </para>
11249 <para>
11250 The argument on the government's side came down to this:
11251 Congress
11252 has done it before. It should be allowed to do it again. The
11253 government
11254 claimed that from the very beginning, Congress has been
11255 extending the term of existing copyrights. So, the government argued,
11256 the Court should not now say that practice is unconstitutional.
11257 </para>
11258 <para>
11259 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
11260 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in
11261 and in 1909. And of course, in 1962, Congress began extending
11262 existing
11263 terms regularly&mdash;eleven times in forty years.
11264 </para>
11265 <para>
11266 But this "consistency" should be kept in perspective. Congress
11267 extended
11268 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
11269 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
11270 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
11271 existing
11272 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
11273 restraint
11274 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
11275 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
11276 hesitated
11277 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
11278 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
11279 Oral argument was scheduled for the first week in October. I
11280 arrived
11281 in D.C. two weeks before the argument. During those two
11282 weeks, I was repeatedly "mooted" by lawyers who had volunteered to
11283
11284 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
11285 help in the case. Such "moots" are basically practice rounds, where
11286 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
11287 </para>
11288 <para>
11289 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
11290 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
11291 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
11292 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
11293 Congress
11294 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
11295 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
11296 this central idea.
11297 </para>
11298 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11299 <para>
11300 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
11301 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
11302 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
11303 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
11304 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11305 </para>
11306 <para>
11307 "I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
11308 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
11309 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
11310 the harm&mdash;passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
11311 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning."
11312 </para>
11313 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11314 <para>
11315 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
11316 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
11317 right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
11318 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
11319 does the right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it is right. As
11320 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
11321 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
11322 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
11323 The night before the argument, a line of people began to form
11324 in front of the Supreme Court. The case had become a focus of the
11325 press and of the movement to free culture. Hundreds stood in line
11326
11327 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
11328 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
11329 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
11330 </para>
11331 <para>
11332 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
11333 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
11334 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
11335 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
11336 congressmen
11337 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
11338 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
11339 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
11340 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
11341 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
11342 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
11343 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
11344 family of the Justices.
11345 </para>
11346 <para>
11347 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
11348 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
11349 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
11350 those enumerated powers had any limit.
11351 </para>
11352 <para>
11353 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
11354 The history was bothering her.
11355 </para>
11356 <blockquote>
11357 <para>
11358 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
11359 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
11360 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
11361 practice that began with the very first act.
11362 </para>
11363 </blockquote>
11364 <para>
11365 She was quite willing to concede "that this flies directly in the face
11366 of what the framers had in mind." But my response again and again
11367 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
11368 </para>
11369 <blockquote>
11370 <para>
11371 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
11372 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
11373 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
11374 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
11375 is yes.
11376 </para>
11377 </blockquote>
11378 <para>
11379 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
11380 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
11381 Kennedy, who observed,
11382 </para>
11383 <blockquote>
11384 <para>
11385 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
11386 the '76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
11387 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
11388 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
11389 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
11390 </para>
11391 </blockquote>
11392 <para>
11393 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
11394 student,
11395 I answered,
11396 </para>
11397 <blockquote>
11398 <para>
11399 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
11400 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
11401 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
11402 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an
11403 effectively
11404 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
11405 </para>
11406 </blockquote>
11407 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11408 <para>
11409 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
11410 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
11411 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
11412 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
11413 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
11414 </para>
11415 <para>
11416 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had
11417 been crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the Lopez ruling, and we
11418 hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
11419 </para>
11420 <para>
11421 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
11422 sympathetic.
11423 To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
11424
11425 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
11426 </para>
11427 <blockquote>
11428 <para>
11429 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
11430 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
11431 </para>
11432 <para>
11433 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
11434 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
11435 domain
11436 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
11437 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
11438 into the Copyright Clause.
11439 </para>
11440 </blockquote>
11441 <para>
11442 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
11443 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
11444 asked Solicitor General Olson,
11445 </para>
11446 <blockquote>
11447 <para>
11448 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11449 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
11450 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
11451 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11452 time.
11453 </para>
11454 </blockquote>
11455 <para>
11456 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
11457 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
11458 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
11459 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
11460 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
11461 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
11462 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
11463 Patent Clause&mdash; indeed, the very first case striking a law of
11464 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
11465 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
11466 Court to my side.
11467 </para>
11468 <para>
11469 As I left the court that day, I knew there were a hundred points I
11470 wished I could remake. There were a hundred questions I wished I had
11471
11472 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
11473 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
11474 optimistic.
11475 </para>
11476 <para>
11477 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
11478 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
11479 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
11480 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
11481 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
11482 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
11483 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
11484 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
11485 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
11486 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
11487 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court&mdash;in particular,
11488 the Conservatives&mdash;would feel itself constrained by the rule of
11489 law that it had established elsewhere.
11490 </para>
11491 <para>
11492 The morning of January 15, 2003, I was five minutes late to the office
11493 and missed the 7:00 A.M. call from the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to
11494 the message, I could tell in an instant that she had bad news to report.The
11495 Supreme Court had affirmed the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven
11496 justices had voted in the majority. There were two dissents.
11497 </para>
11498 <para>
11499 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
11500 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
11501 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
11502 </para>
11503 <para>
11504 My reasoning. Here was a case that pitted all the money in the world
11505 against reasoning. And here was the last naïve law professor, scouring
11506 the pages, looking for reasoning.
11507 </para>
11508 <para>
11509 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
11510 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
11511 Lopez. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
11512 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
11513 even appear in the Court's opinion.
11514 </para>
11515 <para>
11516
11517 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
11518 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
11519 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
11520 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
11521 </para>
11522 <para>
11523 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable&mdash;for her, and for Justice
11524 Souter. Neither believes in Lopez. It would be too much to expect them
11525 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
11526 they had worked so hard to defeat.
11527 </para>
11528 <para>
11529 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
11530 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
11531 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
11532 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
11533 reconcile the two simply by not addressing the argument. There was no
11534 inconsistency because they would not talk about the two together.
11535 There was therefore no principle that followed from the Lopez case: In
11536 that context, Congress's power would be limited, but in this context
11537 it would not.
11538 </para>
11539 <para>
11540 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
11541 they would respect? By what right did they&mdash;the silent
11542 five&mdash;get to select the part of the Constitution they would
11543 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
11544 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
11545 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
11546 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
11547 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
11548 the system we have.
11549 </para>
11550 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11551 <para>
11552 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
11553 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
11554 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
11555 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
11556 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
11557 the Court discounted the parallel&mdash;without explaining how the
11558 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
11559 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
11560 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
11561 </para>
11562 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11563 <para>
11564 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
11565 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
11566 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
11567 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
11568 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8
11569 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
11570 that the actual number was 99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
11571 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
11572 "limited," and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
11573 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
11574 </para>
11575 <para>
11576 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
11577 because neither believed in the Lopez case, neither was willing to push
11578 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
11579 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
11580 Sentelle. It was Hamlet without the Prince.
11581 </para>
11582 <para>
11583 Defeat brings depression. They say it is a sign of health when
11584 depression gives way to anger. My anger came quickly, but it didn't cure
11585 the depression. This anger was of two sorts.
11586 </para>
11587 <para>
11588 It was first anger with the five "Conservatives." It would have been
11589 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of Lopez didn't
11590 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
11591 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
11592 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
11593 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
11594 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is "originalism"&mdash;to
11595 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
11596 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
11597 Lopez and many other "originalist" rulings. Where was their
11598 "originalism" now?
11599 </para>
11600 <para>
11601 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
11602 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
11603 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
11604 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
11605
11606 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
11607 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
11608 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
11609 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
11610 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
11611 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
11612 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
11613 own principles.
11614 </para>
11615 <para>
11616 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
11617 myself.
11618 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
11619 the law as it is.
11620 </para>
11621 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11622 <para>
11623 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
11624 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
11625 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
11626 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
11627 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
11628 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
11629 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
11630 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
11631 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
11632 </para>
11633 <para>
11634 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
11635 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
11636 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
11637 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
11638 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
11639 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
11640 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
11641 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
11642 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
11643 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
11644 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
11645 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
11646 effort to persuade; but I
11647 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
11648 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
11649 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
11650 should decide the issue.
11651 </para>
11652 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11653 <para>
11654 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
11655 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
11656 Kathleen Sullivan?
11657 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11658 </para>
11659 <para>
11660 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
11661 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
11662 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
11663 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
11664 </para>
11665 <para>
11666 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
11667 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
11668 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
11669 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
11670 have persuaded.
11671 </para>
11672 <para>
11673 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
11674 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
11675 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
11676 case was a mistake. "The Court is not ready," Peter Jaszi said; this
11677 issue should not be raised until it is.
11678 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
11679 </para>
11680 <para>
11681 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
11682 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
11683 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
11684 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
11685 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
11686 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
11687 this case&mdash;a decision I had made four years before&mdash;was wrong.
11688 While the reaction to the Sonny Bono Act itself was almost
11689 unanimously negative, the reaction to the Court's decision was mixed.
11690 No one, at least in the press, tried to say that extending the term of
11691 copyright was a good idea. We had won that battle over ideas. Where
11692
11693 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
11694 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
11695 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
11696 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
11697 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
11698 harmful law. The New York Times wrote in its editorial,
11699 </para>
11700 <blockquote>
11701 <para>
11702 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
11703 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
11704 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
11705 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
11706 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
11707 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
11708 </para>
11709 </blockquote>
11710 <para>
11711 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
11712 hilarious images&mdash;of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
11713 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced on the next
11714 page. The "powerful and wealthy" line is a bit unfair. But the punch
11715 in the face felt exactly like that.
11716 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
11717 </para>
11718 <para>
11719 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
11720 quote from The New York Times. That "grand experiment" we call the
11721 "public domain" is over? When I can make light of it, I think, "Honey,
11722 I shrunk the Constitution." But I can rarely make light of it. We had
11723 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
11724 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
11725 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
11726 </para>
11727 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
11728 </sect1>
11729 <sect1 id="eldred-ii">
11730 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II</title>
11731 <para>
11732 The day Eldred was decided, fate would have it that I was to travel to
11733 Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in Eldred was
11734 denied&mdash;meaning the case was really finally over&mdash;fate would
11735 have it that I was giving a speech to technologists at Disney World.)
11736 This was a particularly long flight to my least favorite city. The
11737 drive into the city from Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I
11738 opened up my computer and wrote an op-ed piece.
11739 </para>
11740 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11741 <para>
11742 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
11743 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
11744 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
11745 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
11746 Justice Kennedy: "For all these years the act has impeded progress in
11747 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
11748 that." And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
11749 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
11750 </para>
11751 <para>
11752 The New York Times published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
11753 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
11754 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
11755 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
11756 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
11757 the work passed into the public domain.
11758 </para>
11759 <para>
11760 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
11761 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
11762 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
11763 </para>
11764 <para>
11765 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
11766 is either the "Public Domain Enhancement Act" or the "Copyright
11767 Term Deregulation Act." Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
11768 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
11769 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
11770 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $1. But for
11771 everything else, let the content go.
11772 </para>
11773 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
11774 <para>
11775 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
11776 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
11777 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
11778 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
11779 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
11780 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
11781 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
11782 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
11783 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
11784 the stupid harm of the present system.
11785 </para>
11786 <para>
11787 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
11788 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
11789 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
11790 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
11791 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
11792 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
11793 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
11794 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
11795 where copyright owners could be identified.
11796 </para>
11797 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (1908)</primary></indexterm>
11798 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
11799 <para>
11800 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
11801 As I described in chapter 10, formalities in copyright law were
11802 removed in 1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
11803 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.<footnote><para>
11804 <!-- f1. -->
11805 Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
11806 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
11807 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
11808 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act,
11809 every text of the Convention has provided that "the enjoyment and the
11810 exercise" of rights guaranteed by the Convention "shall not be subject
11811 to any formality." The prohibition against formalities is presently
11812 embodied in Article 5(2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
11813 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
11814 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
11815 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
11816 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
11817 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
11818 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
11819 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
11820 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, International
11821 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials (New York: Foundation
11822 Press, 2001), 153&ndash;54. </para></footnote>
11823 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a "natural right." Natural
11824 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
11825 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
11826 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
11827 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
11828 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
11829 </para>
11830 <para>
11831 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
11832 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
11833 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
11834 "Walt Disney creativity" is destroyed when there is no simple way to
11835 know what's protected and what's not.
11836 </para>
11837 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
11838 <para>
11839 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
11840 Berlin in 1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
11841 Convention in 1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
11842 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
11843 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
11844 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
11845 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an i or cross a t resulted
11846 in the loss of widows' only income.
11847 </para>
11848 <para>
11849 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
11850 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
11851 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
11852 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
11853 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
11854 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
11855 </para>
11856 <para>
11857 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
11858 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
11859 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
11860 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
11861 burden
11862 imposed upon creators.
11863 </para>
11864 <para>
11865 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was
11866 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
11867
11868 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
11869 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
11870 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
11871 the government. He has a property right over the table "naturally,"
11872 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
11873 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
11874 table.
11875 </para>
11876 <para>
11877 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
11878 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
11879 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
11880 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
11881 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
11882 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
11883 spread.
11884 </para>
11885 <para>
11886 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
11887 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
11888 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
11889 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
11890 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
11891 important reason to secure registration&mdash;both because it makes
11892 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
11893 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
11894 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
11895 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
11896 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
11897 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
11898 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
11899 system of protection for property generally.
11900 </para>
11901 <para>
11902 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
11903 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
11904 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
11905 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
11906 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
11907 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
11908 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
11909 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
11910
11911 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
11912 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive, lawyer transactions
11913 take their place.
11914 </para>
11915 <para>
11916 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
11917 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
11918 didn't "get." Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
11919 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
11920 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, "short," then this
11921 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
11922 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
11923 be presumptively uncontrolled.
11924 </para>
11925 <para>
11926 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
11927 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
11928 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
11929 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
11930 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
11931 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
11932 seen before because there are no formalities.
11933 </para>
11934 <para>
11935 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
11936 it is worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
11937 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
11938 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
11939 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
11940 </para>
11941 <para>
11942 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
11943 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
11944 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
11945 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
11946 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you.
11947 </para>
11948 <para>
11949 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
11950 registering the work mean that the $1 is really misleading? Isn't the
11951 hassle worth more than $1? Isn't that the real problem with
11952 registration?
11953 </para>
11954 <para>
11955 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
11956 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
11957 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
11958
11959 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
11960 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
11961 address the real problem of governments standing at the core of any
11962 system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a solution. That
11963 solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For now, assume it
11964 was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it was one-click
11965 registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple, one-click
11966 registration fifty years after a work was published. Based upon
11967 historical data, that system would move up to 98 percent of commercial
11968 work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life, into the
11969 public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
11970 </para>
11971 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
11972 <para>
11973 When Steve Forbes endorsed the idea, some in Washington began to pay
11974 attention. Many people contacted me pointing to representatives who
11975 might be willing to introduce the Eldred Act. And I had a few who
11976 directly suggested that they might be willing to take the first step.
11977 </para>
11978 <para>
11979 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
11980 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
11981 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
11982 possible. In May 2003, it looked as if the bill would be
11983 introduced. On May 16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, "we are
11984 close." There was a general reaction in the blog community that
11985 something good might happen here.
11986 </para>
11987 <para>
11988 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
11989 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
11990 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
11991 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
11992 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
11993 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
11994 </para>
11995 <para>
11996 The MPAA argued first that Congress had "firmly rejected the central
11997 concept in the proposed bill"&mdash;that copyrights be renewed. That
11998 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's "firm rejection" had occurred
11999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
12000 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
12001 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
12002 owners&mdash;apparently those who could not afford the $1 fee. Third,
12003 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
12004 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
12005 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
12006 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
12007 off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
12008 argued that the bill would impose "enormous" costs, since a
12009 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
12010 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
12011 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
12012 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
12013 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
12014 film is a valid derivative use.
12015 </para>
12016 <para>
12017 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
12018 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
12019 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
12020 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
12021 or not&mdash;a controversial claim in any case&mdash;unless they know
12022 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
12023 </para>
12024 <para>
12025 At the beginning of this book, I told two stories about the law
12026 reacting to changes in technology. In the one, common sense prevailed.
12027 In the other, common sense was delayed. The difference between the two
12028 stories was the power of the opposition&mdash;the power of the side
12029 that fought to defend the status quo. In both cases, a new technology
12030 threatened old interests. But in only one case did those interest's
12031 have the power to protect themselves against this new competitive
12032 threat.
12033 </para>
12034 <para>
12035 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
12036 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
12037 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
12038 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
12039 sense?
12040 </para>
12041 <para>
12042
12043 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
12044 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
12045 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
12046 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
12047 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
12048 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
12049 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
12050 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
12051 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
12052 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
12053 </para>
12054 <para>
12055 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
12056 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
12057 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
12058 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
12059 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
12060 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the "Dark
12061 Content" that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
12062 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
12063 </para>
12064 <para>
12065 What does this industry really want?
12066 </para>
12067 <para>
12068 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
12069 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
12070 protecting their content. The effort to block the Eldred Act is an effort
12071 to assure that nothing more passes into the public domain. It is another
12072 step to assure that the public domain will never compete, that there
12073 will be no use of content that is not commercially controlled, and that
12074 there will be no commercial use of content that doesn't require their
12075 permission first.
12076 </para>
12077 <para>
12078 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
12079 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
12080 its aim not the protection of "property" but the rejection of a
12081 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is theirs. Their
12082 aim is to assure that all there is is what is theirs.
12083 </para>
12084 <para>
12085 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
12086 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
12087
12088 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
12089 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
12090 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
12091 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
12092 and to share its own creation.
12093 </para>
12094 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
12095 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
12096 <para>
12097 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
12098 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
12099 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
12100 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
12101 block the progress of others.
12102 </para>
12103 <para>
12104 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
12105 "property" in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
12106 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
12107 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing "permission
12108 society." The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
12109 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
12110 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
12111 </para>
12112 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
12113 </sect1>
12114 </chapter>
12115 <chapter id="c-conclusion">
12116 <title>CONCLUSION</title>
12117 <para>
12118 There are more than 35 million people with the AIDS virus
12119 worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live in sub-Saharan Africa.
12120 Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen million Africans
12121 is proportional percentage-wise to seven million Americans. More
12122 importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
12123 </para>
12124 <para>
12125 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
12126 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
12127 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
12128 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
12129 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
12130 the disease almost invisible.
12131 </para>
12132 <para>
12133 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
12134 United States, they cost between $10,000 and $15,000 per person per
12135 year. Today, some cost $25,000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
12136 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
12137 population:
12138 $15,000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
12139 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.<footnote><para>
12140 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, "Final Report: Integrating
12141 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy" (London, 2002),
12142 available at
12143 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
12144 release
12145 issued 9 July 2002, only 230,000 of the 6 million who need drugs in
12146 the developing world receive them&mdash;and half of them are in Brazil.
12147 </para></footnote>
12148 </para>
12149 <para>
12150 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
12151 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
12152 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
12153 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
12154 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
12155 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
12156 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
12157 </para>
12158 <para>
12159 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
12160 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
12161 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
12162 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
12163 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
12164 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
12165 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
12166 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
12167 changes.
12168 </para>
12169 <para>
12170 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
12171 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
12172 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
12173 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
12174 costs significantly below the market price.
12175 </para>
12176 <para>
12177 In 1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
12178 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
12179 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
12180 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
12181 Africa from India. This is called "parallel importation," and it is
12182 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
12183 permitted within the European Union.<footnote>
12184 <para>
12185 <!-- f2. -->
12186 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism: Who
12187 Owns the Knowledge Economy? (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37.
12188 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
12189 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12190 </para></footnote>
12191 </para>
12192 <para>
12193 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed,
12194 more than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property
12195 Association
12196 characterized it, "The U.S. government pressured South Africa . . .
12197 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel imports."<footnote><para>
12198 <!-- f3. --> International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), Patent Protection and
12199 Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan Africa, a Report
12200 Prepared
12201 for the World Intellectual Property Organization (Washington, D.C.,
12202 2000), 14, available at
12203 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #56</ulink>. For a firsthand account of the struggle over
12204 South Africa, see Hearing Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice,
12205 Drug Policy, and Human Resources, House Committee on Government
12206 Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess., Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150&ndash;57
12207 (statement of James Love).
12208 </para></footnote>
12209 Through the
12210 Office of the United States Trade Representative, the government
12211 asked South Africa to change the law&mdash;and to add pressure to that
12212 request,
12213 in 1998, the USTR listed South Africa for possible trade sanctions.
12214 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
12215 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies
12216 began
12217 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the
12218 government's
12219 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments
12220 from the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical
12221 companies,
12222 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
12223 international
12224 law by discriminating against a particular kind of patent&mdash;
12225 pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments, with the
12226 United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect these patents
12227 as it respects any other patent, regardless of any effect on the treatment
12228 of AIDS within South Africa.<footnote><para>
12229 <!-- f4. -->
12230 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), Patent
12231 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12232 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12233 Organization (Washington, D.C., 2000), 15. </para></footnote>
12234 </para>
12235 <para>
12236 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
12237 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
12238 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
12239 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
12240 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
12241 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
12242 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
12243 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
12244 </para>
12245 <para>
12246 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
12247 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
12248 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
12249 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
12250 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
12251 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save 15 to 30 million lives.
12252 </para>
12253 <para>
12254 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
12255 profits of United States drug companies&mdash;at least, not substantially. It
12256 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
12257 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
12258 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
12259 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
12260 by U.S. companies.
12261 </para>
12262 <para>
12263 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
12264 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
12265 argument
12266 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
12267 about the sanctity of property.<footnote><para>
12268 <!-- f5. -->
12269 See Sabin Russell, "New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
12270 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive," San Francisco Chronicle, 24
12271 May 1999, A1, available at
12272 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #57</ulink>
12273 ("compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
12274 system of intellectual property protection"); Robert Weissman, "AIDS
12275 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
12276 Medicines," Foreign Policy in Focus 4:23 (August 1999), available at
12277 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #58</ulink>
12278 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, "TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
12279 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
12280 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis," Widener Law
12281 Symposium Journal (Spring 2001): 175.
12282 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
12283 </para></footnote>
12284 It was because "intellectual property" would be violated that these
12285 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
12286 importance of "intellectual property" that led these government actors
12287 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
12288 </para>
12289 <para>
12290 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
12291 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
12292 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
12293 direct cost would be to speed the death of 15 to 30 million Africans,
12294 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the "sanctity" of an
12295 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
12296 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
12297 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
12298 </para>
12299 <para>
12300 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
12301 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
12302 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
12303 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
12304 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system&mdash;
12305 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
12306 </para>
12307 <para>
12308 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
12309 drug companies would love&mdash;they say, and I believe them&mdash;to
12310 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
12311 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
12312 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
12313 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
12314 </para>
12315 <para>
12316 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
12317 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
12318 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, "How
12319 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $1 a pill, but the same
12320 drug would cost an American $1,500?" Because there is no "sound
12321 bite" answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
12322 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
12323 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
12324 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
12325 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
12326 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
12327 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal&mdash;the sanctity of an
12328 idea called "intellectual property."
12329 </para>
12330 <para>
12331 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
12332 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
12333 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
12334 What is the argument?
12335 </para>
12336 <para>
12337 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
12338 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
12339 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
12340 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
12341 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
12342 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
12343 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
12344 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
12345 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
12346 were balanced in just this sense.
12347 </para>
12348 <para>
12349 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
12350 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
12351 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
12352 our tradition, now reigns in this culture&mdash;bizarrely, and with
12353 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
12354 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make. A
12355 simple idea blinds us, and under the cover of darkness, much happens
12356 that most of us would reject if any of us looked. So uncritically do
12357 we accept the idea of property in ideas that we don't even notice how
12358 monstrous it is to deny ideas to a people who are dying without
12359 them. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in culture
12360 that we don't even question when the control of that property removes
12361 our
12362 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
12363 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
12364 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
12365 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
12366 this common sense open its eyes.
12367 </para>
12368 <para>
12369 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
12370 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
12371 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
12372 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
12373 to fight "piracy," and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
12374 the idea of "creative property," while transforming real creators into
12375 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
12376 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
12377 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
12378 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
12379 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
12380 produce the "perfect storm" for free culture.
12381 </para>
12382 <para>
12383 In August 2003, a fight broke out in the United States about a
12384 decision by the World Intellectual Property Organization to cancel a
12385 meeting.<footnote><para>
12386 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, "The Quiet War over Open-Source," Washington Post,
12387 August 2003, E1, available at
12388 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #59</ulink>; William New, "Global Group's
12389 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir," National Journal's Technology
12390 Daily, 19 August 2003, available at
12391 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #60</ulink>; William New, "U.S. Official
12392 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO," National Journal's Technology
12393 Daily, 19 August 2003, available at
12394 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #61</ulink>.
12395 </para></footnote>
12396 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
12397 a meeting to discuss "open and collaborative projects to create public
12398 goods." These are projects that have been successful in producing
12399 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
12400 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
12401 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
12402 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
12403 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
12404 that I describe in the Afterword. It included a project to develop
12405 single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs), which are thought to have
12406 great significance in biomedical research. (That nonprofit project
12407 comprised a consortium of the Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and
12408 technological companies, including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
12409 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
12410 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
12411 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
12412 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
12413 in the early 1980s. And it included "open source and free software."
12414 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
12415 </para>
12416 <para>
12417 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
12418 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
12419 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
12420 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
12421 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
12422 </para>
12423 <para>
12424 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.<footnote><para>
12425 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
12426 meeting.
12427 </para></footnote>
12428 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
12429 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
12430 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
12431 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
12432 property issues.
12433 </para>
12434 <para>
12435 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
12436 about WIPO. In February 2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
12437 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
12438 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
12439 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
12440 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
12441 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
12442 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
12443 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
12444 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
12445 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
12446 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
12447 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
12448 talk about an "Information Society" unless one also talked about the
12449 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
12450 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
12451 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
12452 stuff of
12453 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
12454 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
12455 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
12456 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
12457 </para>
12458 <para>
12459 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
12460 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
12461 thus the meeting about "open and collaborative projects to create
12462 public goods" seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
12463 </para>
12464 <para>
12465 But there is one project within that list that is highly
12466 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is "open source
12467 and free software." Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
12468 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
12469 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
12470 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
12471 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
12472 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
12473 rather than "proprietary software," for their own internal uses.
12474 </para>
12475 <para>
12476 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
12477 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
12478 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
12479 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
12480 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
12481 operating system, the most famous bit of "free software"&mdash;and IBM
12482 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support "open source and
12483 free software" is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
12484 to support a mode of software development that is different from
12485 Microsoft's.<footnote><para>
12486 <!-- f8. -->
12487 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
12488 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
12489 "open source" software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
12490 principal opposition is to "free software" licensed under a "copyleft"
12491 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
12492 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, "The Future
12493 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide," Government Policy
12494 Toward Open Source Software (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
12495 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
12496 Public Policy Research, 2002), 69, available at
12497 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #62</ulink>. See also
12498 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, The Commercial Software
12499 Model, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (3
12500 May 2001), available at
12501 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #63</ulink>.
12502 </para></footnote>
12503 </para>
12504 <para>
12505 More important for our purposes, to support "open source and free
12506 software" is not to oppose copyright. "Open source and free software"
12507 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
12508 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
12509 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
12510 by
12511 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
12512 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
12513 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
12514 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
12515 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
12516 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
12517 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
12518 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
12519 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
12520 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
12521 </para>
12522 <para>
12523 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
12524 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
12525 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
12526 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
12527 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
12528 Washington Post, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
12529 States government to veto the meeting.<footnote><para>
12530 <!-- f9. -->
12531 Krim, "The Quiet War over Open-Source," available at <ulink
12532 url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #64</ulink>.
12533 </para></footnote>
12534 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
12535 </para>
12536 <para>
12537 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
12538 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
12539 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
12540 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
12541 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
12542 its lobbying efforts.
12543 </para>
12544 <para>
12545 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
12546 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
12547 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
12548 Office, explained that "open-source software runs counter to the
12549 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights."
12550 She is quoted as saying, "To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
12551 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
12552 goals of WIPO."
12553 </para>
12554 <para>
12555 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
12556 </para>
12557 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
12558 <para>
12559 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
12560 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
12561 right called "copyright". Without it, restrictions imposed by those
12562 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it "runs counter" to the mission
12563 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
12564 in understanding&mdash;the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
12565 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
12566 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
12567 </para>
12568 <para>
12569 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to "promote"
12570 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
12571 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
12572 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
12573 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
12574 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
12575 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
12576 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
12577 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
12578 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
12579 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
12580 </para>
12581 <para>
12582 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
12583 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
12584 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
12585 what to do with those rights because, again, they are their rights. If
12586 they want to "waive" or "disclaim" their rights, that is, within our
12587 tradition, totally appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than
12588 $20 billion to do good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the
12589 objectives of the property system. That is, on the contrary, just what
12590 a property system is supposed to be about: giving individuals the
12591 right to decide what to do with their property.
12592 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
12593 </para>
12594 <para>
12595 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
12596 "which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights," she's
12597 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
12598 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
12599 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
12600 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from "waiving" or
12601 "disclaiming" an intellectual property right. That the interest of
12602 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
12603 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
12604 way possible.
12605 </para>
12606 <para>
12607 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
12608 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called "feudalism." Under
12609 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
12610 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
12611 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
12612 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
12613 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
12614 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
12615 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
12616 that control.
12617 </para>
12618 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12619 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
12620 <para>
12621 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
12622 choice we are now making about intellectual property.<footnote><para>
12623 <!-- f10. -->
12624 See Drahos with Braithwaite, Information Feudalism, 210&ndash;20.
12625 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12626 </para></footnote>
12627 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
12628 choice now is whether that information society will be free or
12629 feudal. The trend is toward the feudal.
12630 </para>
12631 <para>
12632 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
12633 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
12634 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
12635 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
12636 </para>
12637 <blockquote>
12638 <para>
12639 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
12640 it should be ("the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
12641 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
12642 not simply to promote intellectual property rights"), not as it is. If
12643 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
12644 say anything wrong. But in the world
12645 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
12646 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
12647 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
12648 </para>
12649 </blockquote>
12650 <para>
12651 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
12652 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
12653 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
12654 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
12655 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
12656 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
12657 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
12658 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
12659 </para>
12660 <para>
12661 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
12662 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
12663 "goal" of a government should be "to promote the right balance" of
12664 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
12665 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. "Typical for
12666 an academic," the poster might well have continued.
12667 </para>
12668 <para>
12669 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
12670 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
12671 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
12672 our own country's history).
12673 </para>
12674 <para>
12675 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
12676 government should be to "seek balance," then count me with the silly,
12677 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
12678 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
12679 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
12680 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
12681 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
12682 not lies is just na&iuml;ve, then who have we, the most powerful
12683 democracy in the world, become?
12684 </para>
12685 <para>
12686 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
12687 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
12688 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
12689 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
12690 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
12691 been part of our tradition for most of our history&mdash;free culture.
12692 </para>
12693 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
12694 <para>
12695 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon. There are
12696 moments of hope in this struggle. And moments that surprise. When the
12697 FCC was considering relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby
12698 further increase the concentration in media ownership, an
12699 extraordinary bipartisan coalition formed to fight this change. For
12700 perhaps the first time in history, interests as diverse as the NRA,
12701 the ACLU, Moveon.org, William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women
12702 for Peace organized to oppose this change in FCC policy. An
12703 astonishing 700,000 letters were sent to the FCC, demanding more
12704 hearings and a different result.
12705 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted</primary></indexterm>
12706 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
12707 </para>
12708 <para>
12709 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
12710 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
12711 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
12712 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
12713 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
12714 concentration in the media.
12715 </para>
12716 <para>
12717 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
12718 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
12719 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
12720 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
12721 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
12722 </para>
12723 <para>
12724 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
12725 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
12726 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
12727 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
12728 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
12729 range of rights&mdash;property rights of a historically extreme
12730 form&mdash;that makes their bigness bad.
12731 </para>
12732 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
12733 <para>
12734 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
12735 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
12736 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
12737 Americans have a long history of fighting "big," wisely or not. That
12738 we could be motivated to fight "big" again is not something new.
12739 </para>
12740 <para>
12741 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
12742 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
12743 the idea of "intellectual property." Not because balance is alien to
12744 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
12745 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
12746 called "property" is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
12747 </para>
12748 <para>
12749 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
12750 of our tragedy.
12751 </para>
12752 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob</primary></indexterm>
12753 <para>
12754 As I write these final words, the news is filled with stories about
12755 the RIAA lawsuits against almost three hundred individuals.<footnote><para>
12756 <!-- f11. -->
12757 John Borland, "RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers," CNET News.com, September
12758 2003, available at
12759 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #65</ulink>; Paul
12760 R. La Monica, "Music Industry Sues Swappers," CNN/Money, 8 September
12761 2003, available at
12762 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #66</ulink>; Soni
12763 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, "Sued for a Song,
12764 N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among 261 Cited as Sharers," New York Daily News, 9
12765 September 2003, 3; Frank Ahrens, "RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
12766 Targets; Single Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
12767 Defendants," Washington Post, 10 September 2003, E1; Katie Dean,
12768 "Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA," Wired News, 10 September 2003,
12769 available at
12770 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #67</ulink>.
12771 </para></footnote>
12772 Eminem has just been sued for "sampling" someone else's
12773 music.<footnote><para>
12774 <!-- f12. -->
12775 Jon Wiederhorn, "Eminem Gets Sued . . . by a Little Old Lady,"
12776 mtv.com, 17 September 2003, available at
12777 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #68</ulink>.
12778 </para></footnote>
12779 The story about Bob Dylan "stealing" from a Japanese author has just
12780 finished making the rounds.<footnote><para>
12781 <!-- f13. -->
12782 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, "Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
12783 Dylan Songs," Kansascity.com, 9 July 2003, available at
12784 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #69</ulink>.
12785 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
12786 </para></footnote>
12787 An insider from Hollywood&mdash;who insists he must remain
12788 anonymous&mdash;reports "an amazing conversation with these studio
12789 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
12790 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
12791 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
12792 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first." Congressmen are
12793 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
12794 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
12795 kids who use a computer to share content.
12796 </para>
12797 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
12798 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
12799 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
12800 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto</primary></indexterm>
12801 <para>
12802 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
12803 that it will build a "Creative Archive," from which British citizens can
12804 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.<footnote><para>
12805 <!-- f14. --> "BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public," BBC press release,
12806 24 August 2003, available at
12807 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #70</ulink>.
12808 </para></footnote>
12809 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
12810 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
12811 content and free licenses in that Latin American
12812 country.<footnote><para>
12813 <!-- f15. -->
12814 "Creative Commons and Brazil," Creative Commons Weblog, 6 August 2003,
12815 available at
12816 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #71</ulink>.
12817 </para></footnote>
12818 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
12819 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
12820 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
12821 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
12822 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
12823 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
12824 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
12825 day into the Causbys.
12826 </para>
12827 <para>
12828 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
12829 potential is ever to be realized.
12830
12831 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
12832
12833 </para>
12834 </chapter>
12835 <chapter id="c-afterword">
12836 <title>AFTERWORD</title>
12837 <para>
12838
12839 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
12840 At least some who have read this far will agree with me that something
12841 must be done to change where we are heading. The balance of this book
12842 maps what might be done.
12843 </para>
12844 <para>
12845 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
12846 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
12847 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
12848 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
12849 </para>
12850 <para>
12851 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
12852 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
12853 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists&mdash;all to tell this
12854 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
12855 is so important.
12856 </para>
12857 <para>
12858 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
12859 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
12860 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
12861 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
12862 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
12863 </para>
12864 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
12865
12866 <sect1 id="usnow">
12867 <title>US, NOW</title>
12868 <para>
12869 Common sense is with the copyright warriors because the debate so far
12870 has been framed at the extremes&mdash;as a grand either/or: either
12871 property or anarchy, either total control or artists won't be paid. If
12872 that really is the choice, then the warriors should win.
12873 </para>
12874 <para>
12875 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
12876 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
12877 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright&mdash;"All Rights
12878 Reserved"&mdash; and those who reject copyright&mdash;"No Rights
12879 Reserved." The "All Rights Reserved" sorts believe that you should ask
12880 permission before you "use" a copyrighted work in any way. The "No
12881 Rights Reserved" sorts believe you should be able to do with content
12882 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
12883 </para>
12884 <para>
12885 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
12886 tilted in the "no rights reserved" direction. Content could be copied
12887 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
12888 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
12889 the
12890
12891 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
12892 original design of the Internet was "no rights reserved." Content was
12893 "taken" regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
12894 unprotected.
12895 </para>
12896 <para>
12897 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
12898 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
12899 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
12900 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
12901 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
12902 architecture made the effective default "no rights reserved," the
12903 future architecture will make the effective default "all rights
12904 reserved." The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
12905 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
12906 content requires permission. The "cut and paste" world that defines
12907 the Internet today will become a "get permission to cut and paste"
12908 world that is a creator's nightmare.
12909 </para>
12910 <para>
12911 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle&mdash;neither
12912 "all rights reserved" nor "no rights reserved" but "some rights
12913 reserved"&mdash; and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
12914 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
12915 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
12916 before.
12917 </para>
12918
12919 <sect2 id="examples">
12920 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples</title>
12921 <para>
12922 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
12923 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
12924 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
12925 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
12926 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
12927 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
12928 to your neighbors or boss. The "privacy" of your browsing habits was
12929 assured.
12930 </para>
12931 <para>
12932 What made it assured?
12933 </para>
12934 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
12935 <para>
12936 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
12937 10, your privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture
12938 for gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
12939 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
12940 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
12941 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
12942 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
12943 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
12944 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
12945 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
12946 (there is no law protecting "privacy" in public places), and in many
12947 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
12948 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
12949 </para>
12950 <indexterm><primary>Amazon</primary></indexterm>
12951 <para>
12952 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
12953 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
12954 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
12955 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
12956 "recently viewed" pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
12957 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
12958 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any "privacy"
12959 protected by the friction disappears, too.
12960 </para>
12961 <para>
12962 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
12963 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
12964 people should have the "right" to browse in a library without the
12965 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
12966 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
12967 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
12968 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
12969 disappears.
12970 </para>
12971 <para>
12972 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define "privacy"
12973 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
12974 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
12975 friction did.<footnote><para>
12976 <!-- f1. -->
12977
12978 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, "Fair Information Practices and the
12979 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get)," Stanford Technology
12980 Law Review 1 (2001): par. 6&ndash;18, available at
12981
12982 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>
12983 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
12984 also Jeffrey Rosen, The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
12985 in an Anxious Age (New York: Random House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs
12986 between technology and privacy).</para></footnote>
12987 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
12988 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
12989
12990 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
12991 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
12992 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
12993 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
12994 </para>
12995 <para>
12996 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
12997 movement. When computers with software were first made available
12998 commercially, the software&mdash;both the source code and the
12999 binaries&mdash; was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
13000 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
13001 care much about controlling their software.
13002 </para>
13003 <indexterm><primary>Stallman, Richard</primary></indexterm>
13004 <para>
13005 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
13006 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
13007 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
13008 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
13009 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
13010 people's work.
13011 </para>
13012 <para>
13013 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
13014 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
13015 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
13016 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
13017 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
13018 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
13019 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
13020 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
13021 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
13022 anything else?
13023 </para>
13024 <para>
13025 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
13026 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
13027 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
13028 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
13029 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
13030 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
13031 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
13032 </para>
13033 <para>
13034 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
13035 early 1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
13036 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
13037 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
13038 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
13039 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
13040 fundamentally weakened.
13041 </para>
13042 <para>
13043 Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
13044 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
13045 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's "Linux"
13046 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
13047 </para>
13048 <para>
13049 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
13050 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
13051 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
13052 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
13053 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
13054 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
13055 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
13056 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
13057 byproduct.
13058 </para>
13059 <para>
13060 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
13061 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
13062 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
13063 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
13064 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
13065 what before had been passively guaranteed.
13066 </para>
13067 <para>
13068 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
13069 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
13070 scientific journals are produced.
13071 </para>
13072 <para>
13073 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
13074 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
13075 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
13076 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
13077 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
13078 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
13079 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
13080 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
13081 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
13082 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
13083 and Westlaw are also free
13084 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
13085 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
13086 Court opinion through their respective services.
13087 </para>
13088 <para>
13089 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
13090 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
13091 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
13092 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
13093 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
13094 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
13095 access to material that is not in the public domain.
13096 </para>
13097 <para>
13098 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
13099 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
13100 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
13101 </para>
13102 <para>
13103 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
13104 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
13105 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
13106 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
13107 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
13108 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
13109 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
13110 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
13111 the technology of paper journals (architecture)&mdash;namely, that it
13112 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
13113 </para>
13114 <para>
13115 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
13116 that libraries not give the general public access to the
13117 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
13118 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
13119 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
13120 granted before.
13121 </para>
13122 <para>
13123 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
13124 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
13125 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
13126 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
13127 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
13128 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
13129 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
13130 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
13131 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
13132 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
13133 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
13134 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
13135 </para>
13136 <para>
13137 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
13138 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
13139 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
13140 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
13141 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
13142 presumptively a good&mdash;especially when it helps spread knowledge
13143 and science.
13144 </para>
13145
13146 </sect2>
13147 <sect2 id="oneidea">
13148 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea</title>
13149 <indexterm id="idxcc" class='startofrange'>
13150 <primary>Creative Commons</primary>
13151 </indexterm>
13152 <para>
13153 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
13154 increasing control effected through law and technology.
13155 </para>
13156 <para>
13157 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
13158 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
13159 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of reasonable
13160 copyright on top of the extremes that now reign. It does this by
13161 making it easy for people to build upon other people's work, by making
13162 it simple for creators to express the freedom for others to take and
13163 build upon their work. Simple tags, tied to human-readable
13164 descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses, make this possible.
13165 </para>
13166 <para>
13167 Simple&mdash;which means without a middleman, or without a lawyer. By
13168 developing a free set of licenses that people can attach to their
13169 content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of content that can
13170 easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are then linked to
13171 machine-readable versions of the license that enable computers
13172 automatically to identify content that can easily be shared. These
13173 three expressions together&mdash;a legal license, a human-readable
13174 description, and
13175 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
13176 machine-readable tags&mdash;constitute a Creative Commons license. A
13177 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
13178 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
13179 that the person associated with the license believes in something
13180 different than the "All" or "No" extremes. Content is marked with the
13181 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
13182 certain freedoms are given.
13183 </para>
13184 <para>
13185 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
13186 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
13187 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
13188 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
13189 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
13190 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses ("share and share
13191 alike"). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
13192 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
13193 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
13194 </para>
13195 <para>
13196 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
13197 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
13198 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
13199 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
13200 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
13201 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
13202 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
13203 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
13204 a public domain.
13205 </para>
13206 <para>
13207 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
13208 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
13209 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
13210 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
13211 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
13212 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
13213 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
13214 of content ("content conducers," as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
13215 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
13216 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
13217 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia</primary></indexterm>
13218 </para>
13219 <para>
13220 The aim is not to fight the "All Rights Reserved" sorts. The aim is to
13221 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
13222 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
13223 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
13224 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
13225 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
13226 the background of digital technologies. New rules&mdash;with different
13227 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
13228 them&mdash;are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
13229 to begin to build those rules.
13230 </para>
13231 <para>
13232 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
13233 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
13234 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, Down and Out in
13235 the Magic Kingdom, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
13236 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
13237 </para>
13238 <para>
13239 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
13240 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1)
13241 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
13242 and (2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
13243 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (1) will download
13244 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2)
13245 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
13246 them (2)-goods. If there are more (2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the
13247 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably increase
13248 sales of Cory's book.
13249 </para>
13250 <para>
13251 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
13252 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
13253 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
13254 was a total success.
13255 </para>
13256 <para>
13257 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
13258 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
13259 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
13260 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled Free for All,
13261 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
13262 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
13263 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
13264 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
13265 well.
13266 </para>
13267 <para>
13268 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread
13269 proprietary content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of
13270 the Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for
13271 other reasons. Many who use the "sampling license" do so because
13272 anything else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that
13273 others are free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample
13274 content from the licensed work; they are just not free to make full
13275 copies of the licensed work available to others. This is consistent
13276 with their own art&mdash;they, too, sample from others. Because the
13277 legal costs of sampling are so high (Walter Leaphart, manager of the
13278 rap group Public Enemy, which was born sampling the music of others,
13279 has stated that he does not "allow" Public Enemy to sample anymore,
13280 because the legal costs are so high<footnote><para>
13281 <!-- f2. -->
13282
13283 Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
13284 Culture Wars (2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
13285 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
13286 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>.
13287 </para></footnote>),
13288 these artists release into the creative environment content
13289 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
13290 </para>
13291 <para>
13292 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
13293 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
13294 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
13295 you are effectively saying you believe in the "All Rights Reserved"
13296 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
13297 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
13298 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
13299 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
13300 this notion of "Some Rights Reserved," and gives many the chance to
13301 say it to others.
13302 </para>
13303 <para>
13304 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
13305 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
13306 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
13307 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
13308
13309 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
13310 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
13311 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
13312 </para>
13313 <para>
13314 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
13315 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
13316 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
13317 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
13318 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
13319 steps are possible.
13320 </para>
13321 <para>
13322 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
13323 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
13324 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
13325 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
13326 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
13327 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
13328 creativity to spread more easily.
13329 </para>
13330 <indexterm startref="idxcc" class='endofrange'/>
13331
13332 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
13333 </sect2>
13334 </sect1>
13335 <sect1 id="themsoon">
13336 <title>THEM, SOON</title>
13337 <para>
13338 We will not reclaim a free culture by individual action alone. It will
13339 also take important reforms of laws. We have a long way to go before
13340 the politicians will listen to these ideas and implement these reforms.
13341 But that also means that we have time to build awareness around the
13342 changes that we need.
13343 </para>
13344 <para>
13345 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
13346 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
13347 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
13348 to our end.
13349 </para>
13350
13351 <sect2 id="formalities">
13352 <title>1. More Formalities</title>
13353 <para>
13354 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
13355 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
13356 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
13357 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
13358 </para>
13359 <para>
13360 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
13361 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
13362 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
13363 protected.
13364 </para>
13365 <para>
13366 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
13367 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
13368 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
13369 default is control, and "formalities" are banished.
13370 </para>
13371 <para>
13372 Why?
13373 </para>
13374 <para>
13375 As I suggested in chapter 10, the motivation to abolish formalities
13376 was a good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
13377 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
13378 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
13379 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
13380 formalities were getting in the way.
13381 </para>
13382 <para>
13383 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
13384 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
13385 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
13386 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
13387 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
13388 trace&mdash; there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
13389 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
13390 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
13391 past. And thus, the lack of formalities forces many into silence where
13392 they otherwise could speak.
13393 </para>
13394 <para>
13395 The law should therefore change this requirement<footnote><para>
13396 <!-- f1. -->
13397 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
13398 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
13399 adopted by other countries as well.</para></footnote>&mdash;but it
13400 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
13401 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
13402 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
13403 </para>
13404 <para>
13405 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
13406 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
13407 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
13408 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
13409 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
13410 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
13411 developed by others.
13412 </para>
13413
13414 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
13415
13416 <sect3 id="registration">
13417 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL</title>
13418 <para>
13419 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
13420 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
13421 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
13422 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
13423 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
13424 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
13425 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
13426 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
13427 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
13428 panic&mdash;nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
13429 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
13430 </para>
13431 <para>
13432 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
13433 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
13434 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
13435 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
13436 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
13437 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
13438 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
13439 </para>
13440 <para>
13441 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
13442 There are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world.
13443 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
13444 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
13445 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
13446 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
13447 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
13448 with which registration occurs up.
13449 </para>
13450 <para>
13451 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
13452 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
13453 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
13454 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
13455 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
13456 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
13457 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
13458 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
13459 formality&mdash;while producing a database
13460 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
13461 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
13462 </para>
13463
13464 </sect3>
13465 <sect3 id="marking">
13466 <title>MARKING</title>
13467 <para>
13468 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
13469 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
13470 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule&mdash;akin to
13471 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
13472 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
13473 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
13474 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
13475 uniformly across all media.
13476 </para>
13477 <para>
13478 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
13479 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
13480 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
13481 use the work.
13482 </para>
13483 <para>
13484 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
13485 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
13486 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
13487 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
13488 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
13489 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
13490 signal from the failure to mark&mdash;not the loss of the copyright, but the
13491 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
13492 </para>
13493 <para>
13494 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
13495 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
13496 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
13497 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
13498 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
13499 doesn't give permission.<footnote><para>
13500 <!-- f2. -->
13501 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
13502 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
13503 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
13504 </para></footnote>
13505 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be "use unless someone
13506 complains." If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
13507 stop using the work in any new
13508 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
13509 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
13510 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
13511 their work.
13512 </para>
13513 <para>
13514 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
13515 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
13516 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
13517 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
13518 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
13519 </para>
13520 <para>
13521 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
13522 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
13523 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
13524 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
13525 judged preferable, and it would base that choice solely upon the
13526 consideration of which method could best be integrated into the
13527 registration and renewal system. We would not count on the government
13528 to innovate; but we would count on the government to keep the product
13529 of innovation in line with its other important functions.
13530 </para>
13531 <para>
13532 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
13533 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
13534 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
13535 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
13536 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
13537 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
13538 </para>
13539 <para>
13540 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
13541 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
13542 make things unclear.
13543 </para>
13544 <para>
13545 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
13546 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
13547 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
13548 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
13549 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
13550 that assertion at the appropriate time.
13551 </para>
13552
13553 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
13554 </sect3>
13555 </sect2>
13556 <sect2 id="shortterms">
13557 <title>2. Shorter Terms</title>
13558 <para>
13559 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
13560 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
13561 natural authors.
13562 </para>
13563 <para>
13564 In The Future of Ideas, I proposed a seventy-five-year term, granted
13565 in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every five
13566 years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
13567 Eldred v. Ashcroft, the proposals became even more radical. The
13568 Economist endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year copyright
13569 term.<footnote><para>
13570 <!-- f3. -->
13571 "A Radical Rethink," Economist, 366:8308 (25 January 2003): 15,
13572 available at
13573 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #74</ulink>.
13574 </para></footnote>
13575 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
13576 </para>
13577 <para>
13578 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
13579 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
13580 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
13581 terms.
13582 </para>
13583 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
13584 <listitem><para>
13585 <!-- (1) -->
13586 Keep it short: The term should be as long as necessary to give
13587 incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied to very strong
13588 protections for authors (so authors were able to reclaim rights from
13589 publishers), rights to the same work (not derivative works) might be
13590 extended further. The key is not to tie the work up with legal
13591 regulations when it no longer benefits an author. </para></listitem>
13592 <listitem><para>
13593 <!-- (2) -->
13594 Keep it simple: The line between the public domain and protected
13595 content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the fuzziness of "fair use,"
13596 and the distinction between "ideas" and "expression." That kind of
13597 law gives them lots of work. But our framers had a simpler idea in
13598 mind: protected versus unprotected. The value of short terms is that
13599 there is little need to build exceptions into copyright when the term
13600 itself is kept short. A clear and active "lawyer-free zone" makes the
13601 complexities of "fair use" and "idea/expression" less necessary to
13602 navigate.
13603 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
13604 </para></listitem>
13605 <listitem><para>
13606 <!-- (3) -->
13607 Keep it alive: Copyright should have to be renewed. Especially if the
13608 maximum term is long, the copyright owner should be required to signal
13609 periodically that he wants the protection continued. This need not be
13610 an onerous burden, but there is no reason this monopoly protection has
13611 to be granted for free. On average, it takes ninety minutes for a
13612 veteran to apply for a pension.<footnote><para>
13613 <!-- f4. -->
13614 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
13615 and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001),
13616 available at
13617 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #75</ulink>.
13618 </para></footnote>
13619 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
13620 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
13621 single form.
13622 </para></listitem>
13623 <listitem><para>
13624 <!-- (4) -->
13625 Keep it prospective: Whatever the term of copyright should be, the
13626 clearest lesson that economists teach is that a term once given should
13627 not be extended. It might have been a mistake in 1923 for the law to
13628 offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I don't think so, but it's
13629 possible. If it was a mistake, then the consequence was that we got
13630 fewer authors to create in 1923 than we otherwise would have. But we
13631 can't correct that mistake today by increasing the term. No matter
13632 what we do today, we will not increase the number of authors who wrote
13633 in 1923. Of course, we can increase the reward that those who write
13634 now get (or alternatively, increase the copyright burden that smothers
13635 many works that are today invisible). But increasing their reward will
13636 not increase their creativity in 1923. What's not done is not done,
13637 and there's nothing we can do about that now. </para></listitem>
13638 </orderedlist>
13639 <para>
13640 These changes together should produce an average copyright term
13641 that is much shorter than the current term. Until 1976, the average
13642 term was just 32.2 years. We should be aiming for the same.
13643 </para>
13644 <para>
13645 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas "radical." (After all, I
13646 call them "extremists.") But again, the term I recommended was longer
13647 than the term under Richard Nixon. How "radical" can it be to ask for
13648 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
13649 </para>
13650
13651 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
13652
13653 </sect2>
13654 <sect2 id="freefairuse">
13655 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use</title>
13656 <para>
13657 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
13658 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
13659 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
13660 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
13661 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
13662 the emergence of that new technology.
13663 </para>
13664 <para>
13665 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors "exclusive
13666 right" to "their writings." Congress has given authors an exclusive
13667 right to "their writings" plus any derivative writings (made by
13668 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
13669 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
13670 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
13671 though that movie is not "my writing."
13672 </para>
13673 <para>
13674 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it
13675 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
13676 control translations and dramatizations of a work.<footnote><para>
13677 <!-- f5. -->
13678 Benjamin Kaplan, An Unhurried View of Copyright (New York: Columbia
13679 University Press, 1967), 32.
13680 </para></footnote>
13681 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
13682 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
13683 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
13684 </para>
13685 <blockquote>
13686 <para>
13687 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
13688 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
13689 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
13690 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.<footnote><para>
13691 <!-- f6. --> Ibid., 56.
13692 </para></footnote>
13693 </para>
13694 </blockquote>
13695 <para>
13696 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
13697 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
13698 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
13699 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
13700 Consider each limitation in turn.
13701 </para>
13702 <para>
13703 Term: If Congress wants to grant a derivative right, then that right
13704 should be for a much shorter term. It makes sense to protect John
13705
13706 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
13707 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
13708 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
13709 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
13710 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
13711 after the creative work is done.
13712 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
13713 </para>
13714 <para>
13715 Scope: Likewise should the scope of derivative rights be narrowed.
13716 Again, there are some cases in which derivative rights are important.
13717 Those should be specified. But the law should draw clear lines around
13718 regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted material. When all
13719 "reuse" of creative material was within the control of businesses,
13720 perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate the lines. It no
13721 longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the lines. Think about all
13722 the creative possibilities that digital technologies enable; now
13723 imagine pouring molasses into the machines. That's what this general
13724 requirement of permission does to the creative process. Smothers it.
13725 </para>
13726 <para>
13727 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
13728 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
13729 foreseeable derivative rights&mdash;turning a book into a movie, or a
13730 poem into a musical score&mdash;it doesn't make sense to require
13731 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
13732 much more sense.
13733 </para>
13734 <para>
13735 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
13736 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
13737 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
13738 Paul Goldstein.<footnote>
13739 <para>
13740 <!-- f7. -->
13741 Paul Goldstein, Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
13742 Jukebox (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187&ndash;216.
13743 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul</primary></indexterm>
13744 </para></footnote>
13745 His view is that the law should be written so that
13746 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
13747 </para>
13748 <para>
13749 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
13750 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
13751 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
13752 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
13753 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
13754 </para>
13755 <para>
13756 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
13757 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
13758 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
13759 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
13760 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
13761 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
13762 </para>
13763 </sect2>
13764
13765 <sect2 id="liberatemusic">
13766 <title>4. Liberate the Music&mdash;Again</title>
13767 <para>
13768 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
13769 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
13770 is, to most people, most pressing&mdash;music. There is no other
13771 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
13772 battles around the sharing of music.
13773 </para>
13774 <para>
13775 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
13776 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
13777 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
13778 killer app&mdash;possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
13779 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
13780 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
13781 innovation on the network.
13782 </para>
13783 <para>
13784 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
13785 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
13786 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
13787 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
13788 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
13789 </para>
13790 <para>
13791 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the
13792 spread of content for which the performer has not been paid. But of
13793 course, that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in
13794 chapter 5, they enable four different kinds of sharing:
13795 </para>
13796 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
13797 <listitem><para>
13798 <!-- A. -->
13799 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
13800 for purchasing CDs.
13801 </para></listitem>
13802 <listitem><para>
13803 <!-- B. -->
13804 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
13805 on the way to purchasing CDs.
13806 </para></listitem>
13807 <listitem><para>
13808 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
13809 <!-- C. -->
13810 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
13811 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
13812 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
13813 </para></listitem>
13814 <listitem><para>
13815 <!-- D. -->
13816 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
13817 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
13818 owner plainly endorses.
13819 </para></listitem>
13820 </orderedlist>
13821 <para>
13822 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
13823 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
13824 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
13825 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
13826 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
13827 significantly weakened.
13828 </para>
13829 <para>
13830 As I said in chapter 5, the actual harm caused by sharing is
13831 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
13832 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
13833 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
13834 networks.
13835 </para>
13836 <para>
13837 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
13838 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
13839 should respond.
13840 </para>
13841 <para>
13842 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
13843 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
13844 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
13845 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
13846 is cumbersome and slow&mdash;we in the United States are lucky to have
13847 broadband service at 1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
13848 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
13849 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
13850 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
13851 Internet is mainly just an idea.
13852 </para>
13853 <para>
13854 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
13855 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
13856 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
13857 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
13858 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
13859 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
13860 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
13861 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
13862 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
13863 where everywhere you are&mdash;except maybe the desert or the
13864 Rockies&mdash;you can instantaneously be connected to the
13865 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
13866 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
13867 </para>
13868 <para>
13869 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services
13870 that give you access to content on the fly&mdash;such as Internet
13871 radio, content that is streamed to the user when the user
13872 demands. Here, then, is the critical point: When it is extremely easy
13873 to connect to services that give access to content, it will be easier
13874 to connect to services that give you access to content than it will be
13875 to download and store content on the many devices you will have for
13876 playing content. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe than
13877 it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
13878 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
13879 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
13880 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
13881 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
13882 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
13883 paying for this content even though "free" content is available in the
13884 form of MP3s across the Web.<footnote><para>
13885 <!-- f8. -->
13886 See, for example, "Music Media Watch," The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3
13887 April 2002, available at
13888 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #76</ulink>.
13889 </para></footnote>
13890
13891 </para>
13892 <para>
13893 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
13894 present: It is emphatically temporary. The "problem" with file
13895 sharing&mdash;to the extent there is a real problem&mdash;is a problem
13896 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
13897 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
13898 makers today to be "solving" this problem in light of a technology
13899 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
13900 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
13901 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
13902 artists get paid, during
13903
13904 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
13905 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
13906 and twenty-first-century technologies.
13907 </para>
13908 <para>
13909 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different "problems"
13910 here to solve. Let's start with type D content&mdash;uncopyrighted
13911 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
13912 "problem" with this content is to make sure that the technology that
13913 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
13914 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
13915 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
13916 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
13917 order to eliminate kidnapping.
13918 </para>
13919 <para>
13920 Type C content raises a different "problem." This is content that was,
13921 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
13922 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
13923 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
13924 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
13925 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
13926 way that returns something to the artist.
13927 </para>
13928 <para>
13929 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
13930 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
13931 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
13932 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
13933 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
13934 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
13935 from the author's perspective, this "sharing" of his content without
13936 his being compensated is less than ideal.
13937 </para>
13938 <para>
13939 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
13940 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
13941 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
13942 providers would be free, under this rule, to "share" that content,
13943 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
13944 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
13945 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
13946 </para>
13947 <para>
13948
13949 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
13950 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
13951 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
13952 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
13953 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
13954 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
13955 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
13956 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
13957 trade.
13958 </para>
13959 <para>
13960 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
13961 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
13962 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
13963 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
13964 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
13965 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
13966 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
13967 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
13968 </para>
13969 <para>
13970 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
13971 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
13972 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
13973 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
13974 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
13975 delivering and accessing content.
13976 </para>
13977 <para>
13978 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
13979 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
13980 </para>
13981 <para>
13982 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
13983 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
13984 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
13985 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
13986 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
13987 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
13988 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
13989 harmed the interests of the content industry.
13990 </para>
13991 <para>
13992 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
13993 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
13994 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
13995 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
13996 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
13997 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
13998 way to compensate those who are harmed.
13999 </para>
14000 <para>
14001 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
14002 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.<footnote>
14003 <para>
14004 <!-- f9. --> William Fisher, Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities (last revised:
14005 10 October 2000), available at
14006 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #77</ulink>; William Fisher, Promises to Keep:
14007 Technology, Law, and the Future of Entertainment (forthcoming) (Stanford:
14008 Stanford University Press, 2004), ch. 6, available at
14009 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #78</ulink>. Professor
14010 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
14011 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
14012 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, "Impose a
14013 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing," available at
14014 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, "Who's Holding Back
14015 Broadband?" Washington Post, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
14016 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
14017 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, 26 February 2002,
14018 available at
14019 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
14020 Use Fee (IPUF), 3 March 2002, available at
14021 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
14022 "Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly," USA Today, 13 May
14023 2002, available at
14024 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, "Getting Copyright Right,"
14025 IEEE Spectrum Online, 1 July 2002, available at
14026 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #83</ulink>; Declan
14027 McCullagh, "Verizon's Copyright Campaign," CNET News.com, 27 August
14028 2002, available at
14029 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #84</ulink>.
14030 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
14031 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
14032 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
14033 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
14034 debate by about a decade. See
14035 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #85</ulink>.
14036 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
14037 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William</primary></indexterm>
14038 </para></footnote>
14039 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
14040 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
14041 would (1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
14042 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
14043 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
14044 develop (2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
14045 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (3) artists would be
14046 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (4) an appropriate
14047 tax.
14048 </para>
14049 <para>
14050 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
14051 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
14052 Promises to Keep. The modification that I would make is relatively
14053 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
14054 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
14055 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
14056 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
14057 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
14058 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
14059 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
14060 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
14061 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
14062 controlling access.
14063 </para>
14064 <para>
14065 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
14066 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
14067 the system supports the widest range of "semiotic democracy"
14068 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
14069 other changes I described were accomplished&mdash;in particular, the
14070 limits on derivative
14071
14072 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
14073 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
14074 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
14075 allowed to do with the content itself.
14076 </para>
14077 <para>
14078 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
14079 "harm" to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
14080 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
14081 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
14082 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
14083 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat "free" by being
14084 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
14085 of songs at even the very high price of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents,
14086 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
14087 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
14088 Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a song. And no doubt
14089 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
14090 on-line.
14091 </para>
14092 <para>
14093 This competition has already occurred against the background of "free"
14094 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
14095 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
14096 that, there is nothing impossible at all about "competing with free."
14097 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
14098 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
14099 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
14100 theaters are often luxurious&mdash;with "first class" seats, and meals
14101 served while you watch a movie&mdash;as they struggle and succeed in
14102 finding ways to compete with "free."
14103 </para>
14104 <para>
14105 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
14106 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
14107 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
14108 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
14109 innovators&mdash;ones who would have a right to the content, and would
14110 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
14111 the law.
14112 </para>
14113 <para>
14114 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
14115 </para>
14116 <para>
14117
14118 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
14119 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
14120 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
14121 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
14122 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
14123 create.
14124 </para>
14125 <para>
14126 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
14127 by
14128 </para>
14129 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14130 <listitem><para>
14131 <!-- 1. -->
14132 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
14133 </para></listitem>
14134 <listitem><para>
14135 <!-- 2. -->
14136 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
14137 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
14138 statute;
14139 </para></listitem>
14140 <listitem><para>
14141 <!-- 3. -->
14142 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
14143 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
14144 </para></listitem>
14145 </orderedlist>
14146 <para>
14147 But what if "piracy" doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
14148 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
14149 consumers continue to "take" content for nothing? Should the law do
14150 something then?
14151 </para>
14152 <para>
14153 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
14154 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
14155 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
14156 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
14157 technology that is 95 percent secure and produces a market of size x,
14158 or (b) to have a technology that is 50 percent secure but produces a
14159 market of five times x? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
14160 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
14161 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
14162 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
14163 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
14164 pirates.
14165 </para>
14166 <para>
14167 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
14168 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
14169 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
14170
14171 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
14172 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
14173 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
14174 </para>
14175 </sect2>
14176
14177 <sect2 id="firelawyers">
14178 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers</title>
14179 <para>
14180 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
14181 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
14182 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
14183 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
14184 </para>
14185 <para>
14186 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
14187 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
14188 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
14189 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
14190 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
14191 strong view queers the law.
14192 </para>
14193 <para>
14194 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
14195 "radical" by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
14196 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
14197 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
14198 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
14199 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
14200 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
14201 Nimmer, thought it obvious.<footnote><para>
14202 <!-- f10. -->
14203 Lawrence Lessig, "Copyright's First Amendment" (Melville B. Nimmer
14204 Memorial Lecture), UCLA Law Review 48 (2001): 1057, 1069&ndash;70.
14205 </para></footnote>
14206
14207 </para>
14208 <para>
14209 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
14210 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
14211 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
14212 </para>
14213 <para>
14214 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
14215 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
14216 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
14217 the legal system are slight.<footnote><para>
14218 <!-- f11. -->
14219 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
14220 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
14221 leading him to question his own publicly stated
14222 position&mdash;twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
14223 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
14224 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
14225 J. Liebowitz, Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
14226 Drive the Digital Marketplace (New York: Amacom, 2002), (reviewing his
14227 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
14228 "Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?" working paper, June 2003,
14229 available at
14230 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #86</ulink>.
14231 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
14232 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
14233 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
14234 Rethinking, 174&ndash;76.
14235 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
14236 </para></footnote>
14237 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
14238 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
14239 them it works.
14240 </para>
14241 <para>
14242 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
14243 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
14244 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
14245 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
14246 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
14247 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
14248 practically never be done.
14249 </para>
14250 <para>
14251 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
14252 billed at the largest firms at more than $400 per hour. How much time
14253 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
14254 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
14255 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
14256 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
14257 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
14258 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
14259 </para>
14260 <para>
14261 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
14262 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
14263 their duty to change the way the law works&mdash;or better, to change the
14264 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
14265 top 1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
14266 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
14267 </para>
14268 <para>
14269 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
14270 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
14271 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
14272 its review.
14273 </para>
14274 <para>
14275 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
14276 technology&mdash;the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
14277 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
14278 technology&mdash;a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
14279 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
14280 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
14281 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
14282 </para>
14283 <para>
14284 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture&mdash;but it should
14285 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
14286
14287 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311 -->
14288 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
14289 simple pragmatic question: "Will it do good?" When challenged about
14290 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, "Why not?"
14291 </para>
14292 <para>
14293 We should ask, "Why?" Show me why your regulation of culture is
14294 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
14295 keep your lawyers away.
14296 </para>
14297 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
14298 </sect2>
14299 </sect1>
14300 </chapter>
14301 <chapter id="c-notes">
14302 <title>NOTES</title>
14303 <para>
14304 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
14305 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
14306 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
14307 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
14308 this book. For each link below, you can go to
14309 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
14310 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
14311 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
14312 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
14313 the material.
14314 </para>
14315 <!-- PAGE BREAK 336 -->
14316
14317 </chapter>
14318 <chapter id="c-acknowledgments">
14319 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS</title>
14320 <para>
14321 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
14322 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
14323 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
14324 to him that this book is dedicated.
14325 </para>
14326 <para>
14327 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
14328 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
14329 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
14330 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
14331 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
14332 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
14333 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
14334 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
14335 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
14336 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
14337 critical eye on much of this.
14338 </para>
14339 <para>
14340 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
14341 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
14342 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
14343 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
14344 <!-- PAGE BREAK 337 -->
14345 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
14346 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
14347 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
14348 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
14349 </para>
14350 <para>
14351 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
14352 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
14353 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
14354 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
14355 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
14356 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
14357 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
14358 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
14359 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
14360 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
14361 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
14362 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
14363 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
14364 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
14365 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, "Wink," Roger Wood, "Ximmbo da Jazz,"
14366 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
14367 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
14368 a bunch of great replies.)
14369 </para>
14370 <para>
14371 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
14372 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
14373 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
14374 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
14375 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
14376 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
14377 throughout this book.
14378 </para>
14379 <para>
14380 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
14381 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
14382 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
14383 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
14384 </para>
14385 <!-- PAGE BREAK 338 -->
14386
14387 </chapter>
14388 </book>