]> pere.pagekite.me Git - text-free-culture-lessig.git/blob - freeculture.xml
Add links to French edition.
[text-free-culture-lessig.git] / freeculture.xml
1 <?xml version='1.0' encoding='UTF-8' ?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href="docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type="text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012-2015 with input from Martin Borg. -->
5 <!--
6 TODO
7 * Add missing indexterm entries by comparing with the 2004 edition.
8 -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC "-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
11 [
12 <!ENTITY copy "©">
13 <!ENTITY ndash "–">
14 <!ENTITY mdash "—">
15 <!ENTITY hellip "…">
16 <!ENTITY iuml "ï">
17 ]>
18
19 <book id="index" lang="en">
20 <bookinfo>
21 <title>Free Culture</title>
22
23 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
24
25 <subtitle>How big media uses technology and the law to lock down
26 culture and control creativity</subtitle>
27
28 <pubdate>2015-10-17</pubdate>
29
30 <edition>1</edition>
31
32 <releaseinfo>Version 2004-02-10</releaseinfo>
33
34 <authorgroup>
35 <author>
36 <firstname>Lawrence</firstname>
37 <surname>Lessig</surname>
38 </author>
39 <!--
40 Keep these out to avoid showing up as author in the PDF.
41
42 <editor>
43 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
44 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
45 </editor>
46
47 <othercredit role='converter'>
48 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
49 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
50 <contrib>Created this Docbook version from an earlier version</contrib>
51 </othercredit>
52 -->
53 </authorgroup>
54
55 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
56 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
57 -->
58 <subjectset scheme="libraryofcongress">
59 <subject>
60 <subjectterm>Intellectual property&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
61 </subject>
62 <subject>
63 <subjectterm>Mass media&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
64 </subject>
65 <subject>
66 <subjectterm>Technological innovations&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
67 </subject>
68 <subject>
69 <subjectterm>Art&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
70 </subject>
71 </subjectset>
72
73
74 <publisher>
75 <publishername>Petter Reinholdtsen</publishername>
76 <address><city>Oslo</city></address>
77 </publisher>
78
79 <copyright>
80 <year>2004</year>
81 <holder>Lawrence Lessig</holder>
82 </copyright>
83 <legalnotice>
84 <para>
85 <inlinemediaobject>
86 <imageobject>
87 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.png" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
88 </imageobject>
89 <imageobject>
90 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.svg" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
91 </imageobject>
92 <textobject>
93 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved</phrase>
94 </textobject>
95 </inlinemediaobject>
96 </para>
97
98 <para>
99 This book is licensed under a Creative Commons license. This license
100 permits non-commercial use of this work, so long as attribution is
101 given. For more information about the license visit
102 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/"/>.
103 </para>
104 </legalnotice>
105
106 <abstract>
107 <title>About the author</title>
108 <para>
109 Lawrence Lessig
110 (<ulink url="http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org</ulink>),
111 professor of law and a Roy L. Furman Professor of Law and Leadership
112 at Harvard Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
113 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
114 (<ulink url="http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org</ulink>).
115 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) and Code: And
116 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), Lessig is a member of
117 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
118 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
119 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
120 twice listed in BusinessWeek's <quote>e.biz 25,</quote> and named one
121 of Scientific American's <quote>50 visionaries.</quote> A graduate of
122 the University of Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law
123 School, Lessig clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh
124 Circuit Court of Appeals.
125 </para>
126 </abstract>
127
128 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
129 <mediaobject role="cover">
130 <imageobject remap="lrg" role="front-large">
131 <imagedata fileref="images/cover-front-72dpi.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
132 </imageobject>
133 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
134 <imagedata fileref="images/cover-front-10dpi.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
135 </imageobject>
136 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
137 <imagedata fileref="images/cover-front-10dpi.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
138 </imageobject>
139 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
140 <imagedata fileref="images/cover-front-10dpi.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
141 </imageobject>
142 </mediaobject>
143
144 <biblioid class="isbn">978-82-690182-0-2</biblioid>
145
146 <!-- LCCN from
147 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
148 -->
149 <biblioid class="libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
150
151 <biblioid class="uri">http://free-culture.cc/</biblioid>
152
153 </bookinfo>
154 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
155 <dedication id="alsobylessig">
156 <title>
157 Also by Lawrence Lessig
158 </title>
159
160 <itemizedlist>
161
162 <listitem><para>
163 The USA is lesterland: The nature of congressional corruption (2014)
164 </para></listitem>
165 <listitem><para>
166 Republic, lost: How money corrupts Congress - and a plan to stop it (2011)
167 </para></listitem>
168 <listitem><para>
169 Remix: Making art and commerce thrive in the hybrid economy (2008)
170 </para></listitem>
171 <listitem><para>
172 Code: Version 2.0 (2006)
173 </para></listitem>
174 <listitem><para>
175 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World (2001)
176 </para></listitem>
177 <listitem><para>
178 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace (1999)
179 </para></listitem>
180 </itemizedlist>
181 </dedication>
182 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
183 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
184 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
185 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
186 <dedication id='dedication'><title></title>
187 <!-- FIXME figure out how to do this better in dblatex and docbook-xsl -->
188 <?latex {\huge \centering
189 ?>
190 <para>
191 To Eric Eldred &mdash; whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
192 it continues still.
193 </para>
194 <?latex } % \huge \centering
195 ?>
196 </dedication>
197
198 <toc id="toc"></toc>
199
200 <lot>
201 <title>List of figures</title>
202 </lot>
203
204 <!--
205 c PREFACE xiii
206 c INTRODUCTION
207 c "PIRACY"
208 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
209 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
210 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
211 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
212 2 Film
213 2 Recorded Music
214 2 Radio
215 2 Cable TV
216 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
217 2 Piracy I
218 2 Piracy II
219 c "PROPERTY"
220 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
221 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
222 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
223 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
224 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
225 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
226 2 Beginnings
227 2 Law: Duration
228 2 Law: Scope
229 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
230 2 Architecture and Law: Force
231 2 Market: Concentration
232 2 Together
233 c PUZZLES
234 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
235 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
236 2 Constraining Creators
237 2 Constraining Innovators
238 2 Corrupting Citizens
239 c BALANCES
240 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
241 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
242 c CONCLUSION
243 c AFTERWORD
244 1 Us, Now
245 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
246 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
247 1 Them, Soon
248 2 1. More Formalities
249 3 Registration and Renewal
250 3 Marking
251 2 2. Shorter Terms
252 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
253 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
254 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
255 c NOTES
256 c ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
257 c INDEX
258 -->
259
260 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
261
262 <preface id="preface">
263 <title>Preface</title>
264 <indexterm id='idxpoguedavid' class='startofrange'><primary>Pogue, David</primary></indexterm>
265 <indexterm><primary>Code (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
266 <para>
267 <emphasis role="bold">At the end</emphasis> of his review of my first
268 book, <citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle>, David
269 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
270 computer-related texts, wrote this:
271 </para>
272 <blockquote>
273 <para>
274 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
275 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
276 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
277 system, you can always flip off the modem.<footnote id="preface01"><para>
278 David Pogue, <quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 30 January 2000.
279 </para></footnote>
280 </para>
281 </blockquote>
282 <para>
283 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book&mdash;that
284 software, or <quote>code,</quote> functioned as a kind of law&mdash;and his review
285 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
286 could always <quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome</quote>-like simply flip a
287 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
288 any troubles that exist in <emphasis>that</emphasis> space wouldn't
289 <quote>affect</quote> us anymore.
290 </para>
291 <para>
292 Pogue might have been right in 1999&mdash;I'm skeptical, but maybe.
293 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
294 <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
295 causes even after the modem is turned
296 <!--PAGE BREAK 12-->
297 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
298 on-line have fundamentally affected <quote>people who aren't online.</quote> There
299 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
300 </para>
301 <indexterm startref='idxpoguedavid' class='endofrange'/>
302 <para>
303 But unlike <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
304 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
305 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
306 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
307 important.
308 </para>
309 <para>
310 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
311 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of <quote>free culture</quote>&mdash;not
312 <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free beer</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
313 free software movement<footnote>
314 <para>
315 Richard M. Stallman, <citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed. 2002).
316 </para></footnote>), but <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free speech,</quote> <quote>free markets,</quote>
317 <quote>free trade,</quote> <quote>free enterprise,</quote> <quote>free will,</quote> and <quote>free elections.</quote> A
318 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
319 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
320 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
321 follow-on creators and innovators remain <emphasis>as free as
322 possible</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
323 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
324 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
325 <quote>permission culture</quote>&mdash;a culture in which creators get to create
326 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
327 past.
328 </para>
329 <para>
330 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not <quote>we</quote>
331 on the Left or <quote>you</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
332 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
333 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
334 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
335 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
336 culture deem fundamental.
337 </para>
338 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
339 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
340 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
341 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted</primary></indexterm>
342 <para>
343 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
344 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
345 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
346 generated more than 700,000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
347 As William Safire described marching <quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
348 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
349 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,</quote> he formulated perhaps
350 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
351 he asked,
352 </para>
353 <blockquote>
354 <para>
355 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
356 power&mdash;political, corporate, media, cultural&mdash;should be anathema to
357 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
358 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
359 the greatest expression of democracy.<footnote><para> William Safire,
360 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 May 2003.
361 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
362 </para></footnote>
363 </para>
364 </blockquote>
365 <para>
366 This idea is an element of the argument of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle>, though my
367 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
368 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
369 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
370 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
371 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
372 you&mdash;whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
373 Safire's left or on his right.
374 </para>
375 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'/>
376 <para>
377 <emphasis role="strong">The inspiration</emphasis> for the title and for
378 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
379 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
380 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in <citetitle>Free Software, Free
381 Society</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
382 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
383 that this work is <quote>merely</quote> derivative.
384 </para>
385 <para>
386 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
387 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
388 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
389 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
390 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
391 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
392 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
393 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
394
395 <!--PAGE BREAK 14-->
396 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
397 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
398 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
399 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
400 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
401 what I advance here.
402 </para>
403 <para>
404 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
405 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
406 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
407 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
408 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
409 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
410 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
411 book is written.
412 </para>
413
414 </preface>
415 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
416
417 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
418 <chapter label="" id="c-introduction">
419 <title>Introduction</title>
420 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
421 <para>
422 <emphasis role="strong">On December 17</emphasis>, 1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
423 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
424 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
425 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
426 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
427 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
428 </para>
429 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.</primary></indexterm>
430 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
431 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
432 <para>
433 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
434 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
435 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
436 and all the space above, to <quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.</quote><footnote><para>
437 St. George Tucker, <citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
438 Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18.
439 </para></footnote>
440 For many
441 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
442 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
443 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
444 </para>
445 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
446 <para>
447 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
448 law&mdash;deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
449 by the most important legal thinkers of our past&mdash;mattered. If
450 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
451 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
452 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
453 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
454 </para>
455 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
456 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
457 <para>
458 In 1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
459 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
460 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
461 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
462 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
463 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
464 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to <quote>an indefinite
465 extent, upwards,</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
466 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
467 </para>
468 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
469 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
470 <indexterm id='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='startofrange'><primary>Douglas, William O.</primary></indexterm>
471 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on airspace vs. land rights</secondary></indexterm>
472 <para>
473 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
474 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
475 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
476 <quote>taking</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
477 that <quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
478 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.</quote> But Justice Douglas
479 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
480 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
481 </para>
482 <blockquote>
483 <para>
484 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
485 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
486 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
487 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
488 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
489 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
490 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
491 the public has a just claim.<footnote>
492 <para>
493 United States v. Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. The Court did find
494 that there could be a <quote>taking</quote> if the government's use of its land
495 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
496 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, <quote>(Intellectual)
497 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
498 Authorship,</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review</citetitle> 48 (1996): 1293, 1333. See also Paul
499 Goldstein, <citetitle>Real Property</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press, 1984),
500 1112&ndash;13.
501 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
502 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
503 </para></footnote>
504 </para>
505 </blockquote>
506 <para>
507 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.</quote>
508 </para>
509 <indexterm startref='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='endofrange'/>
510 <para>
511 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
512 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
513 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
514 <!--PAGE BREAK 18-->
515 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: <quote>Common sense revolts
516 at the idea.</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
517 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
518 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
519 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
520 </para>
521 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
522 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
523 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
524 <para>
525 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
526 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
527 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
528 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
529 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
530 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
531 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
532 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
533 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by <quote>what
534 seemed reasonable</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
535 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
536 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
537 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
538 end, the force of what seems <quote>obvious</quote> to everyone else&mdash;the power of
539 <quote>common sense</quote>&mdash;would prevail. Their <quote>private interest</quote> would not be
540 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
541 </para>
542 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'/>
543 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'/>
544 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'/>
545 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='endofrange'/>
546 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
547 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham</primary></indexterm>
548 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
549 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael</primary></indexterm>
550 <indexterm id='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
551 <para>
552 <emphasis role='strong'>Edwin Howard Armstrong</emphasis> is one of
553 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
554 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
555 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
556 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
557 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
558 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in 1831. But
559 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
560 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
561 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
562 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
563 </para>
564 <para>
565 On the day after Christmas, 1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
566 for his most significant invention&mdash;FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
567 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
568 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
569 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
570 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
571 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
572 much less transmitter power and static.
573 </para>
574 <para>
575 On November 5, 1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
576 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
577 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
578 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
579 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
580 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
581 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
582 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
583 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.</quote>
584 </para>
585 <para>
586 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
587 </para>
588 <blockquote>
589 <para>
590 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
591 sounded like a glass of water being poured. &hellip; A paper was crumpled
592 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
593 fire. &hellip; Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
594 and guitar number were performed. &hellip; The music was projected with a
595 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio <quote>music
596 box.</quote><footnote><para>
597 Lawrence Lessing, <citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong</citetitle>
598 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209.
599 </para></footnote>
600 </para>
601 </blockquote>
602 <indexterm id='idxrca' class='startofrange'><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
603 <indexterm id='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
604 <para>
605 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
606 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
607 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
608 AM radio market. By 1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
609 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
610 a handful of networks.
611 <!--PAGE BREAK 20-->
612 </para>
613 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
614 <para>
615 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
616 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
617 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
618 that removed static from <quote>radio.</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
619 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
620 </para>
621 <blockquote>
622 <para>
623 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
624 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
625 revolution&mdash; start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
626 RCA.<footnote><para> See <quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
627 Electronic Era,</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
628 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
629
630 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #1</ulink>.
631 </para></footnote>
632 </para>
633 </blockquote>
634 <indexterm id='idxfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
635 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
636 <para>
637 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
638 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
639 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
640 described,
641 </para>
642 <indexterm id='idxlessinglawrence' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessing, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
643 <blockquote>
644 <para>
645 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
646 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
647 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
648 unrestrained, posed &hellip; a complete reordering of radio power
649 &hellip; and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
650 on which RCA had grown to power.<footnote><para>Lessing, 226.
651 </para></footnote>
652 </para>
653 </blockquote>
654 <indexterm id='idxfcconfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FCC</primary><secondary>on FM radio</secondary></indexterm>
655 <para>
656 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
657 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
658 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
659 FM radio's deployment generally. In 1936, RCA hired the former head
660 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
661 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM&mdash;principally by moving FM
662 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
663 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
664 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
665 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
666 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
667 </para>
668 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
669 <blockquote>
670 <para>
671 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
672 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
673 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
674 deviousness.<footnote><para>
675 Lessing, 256.
676 </para></footnote>
677 </para>
678 </blockquote>
679 <indexterm startref='idxlessinglawrence' class='endofrange'/>
680 <indexterm><primary>AT&amp;T</primary></indexterm>
681 <para>
682 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
683 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
684 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
685 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
686 (This change was strongly supported by AT&amp;T, because the loss of
687 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
688 wired links from AT&amp;T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
689 least temporarily.
690 </para>
691 <indexterm startref='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='endofrange'/>
692 <indexterm startref='idxfcconfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
693 <para>
694 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
695 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
696 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
697 invalid&mdash;baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
698 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
699 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
700 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
701 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
702 now broke, in 1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
703 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
704 </para>
705 <indexterm startref='idxfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
706 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'/>
707 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
708 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
709 <para>
710 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
711 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
712 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
713 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
714 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
715 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
716 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
717 course always public spirited; the reality is something
718 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
719 to themselves, would crumble in
720 <!--PAGE BREAK 22-->
721 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
722 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
723 effect of technological change.
724 </para>
725 <indexterm startref='idxrca' class='endofrange'/>
726 <indexterm startref='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='endofrange'/>
727 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
728 <para>
729 <emphasis role="strong">There's no</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
730 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
731 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
732 Internet and American Life Project, 58 percent of Americans had access
733 to the Internet in 2002, up from 49 percent two years
734 before.<footnote><para>
735 Amanda Lenhart, <quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
736 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,</quote> Pew Internet and American
737 Life Project, 15 April 2003: 6, available at
738 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #2</ulink>.
739 </para></footnote>
740 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
741 of 2004.
742 </para>
743 <para>
744 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
745 changed things. Some of these changes are technical&mdash;the Internet has
746 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
747 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
748 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
749 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
750 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
751 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
752 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
753 </para>
754 <para>
755 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
756 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
757 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
758 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
759 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
760 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
761 has introduced.
762 </para>
763 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
764 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel</primary></indexterm>
765 <indexterm><primary>culture</primary><seealso>free culture</seealso></indexterm>
766 <indexterm id='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='startofrange'><primary>culture</primary><secondary>commercial vs. noncommercial</secondary></indexterm>
767 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah</primary></indexterm>
768 <para>
769 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
770 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
771 regulation of each. By <quote>commercial culture</quote> I mean that part of our
772 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
773 <quote>noncommercial culture</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
774 parks or on
775 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
776 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
777 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his <quote>Reader,</quote> or
778 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
779 </para>
780 <para>
781 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
782 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
783 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
784 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
785 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
786 left this culture <quote>free.</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
787 individuals shared and transformed their culture&mdash;telling
788 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
789 clubs, sharing music, making tapes&mdash;were left alone by the law.
790 </para>
791 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>commercial creativity as primary purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
792 <para>
793 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
794 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
795 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
796 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
797 marketplace.<footnote>
798 <para>
799 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
800 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
801 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
802 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
803 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
804 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
805 D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote> <citetitle>Harvard
806 Law Review</citetitle> 4 (1890): 193, 198&ndash;200.
807 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
808 </para></footnote>
809 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
810 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
811 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
812 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
813 </para>
814 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
815 <indexterm><primary>permission culture</primary><secondary> free culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
816 <para>
817 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
818 been erased.<footnote><para>
819 See Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
820 2001), ch. 13.
821 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
822 </para></footnote>
823 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
824 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
825 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
826 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
827 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
828 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
829 the balance of our history&mdash;between uses of our culture that were
830 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission&mdash;has
831 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
832 culture, more and more a permission culture.
833 </para>
834 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
835 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
836 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
837 <indexterm><primary>protection of artists vs. business interests</primary></indexterm>
838 <para>
839 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
840 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
841 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
842 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
843 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
844 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
845 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
846 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
847 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
848 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
849 Causbys.
850 </para>
851 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='endofrange'/>
852 <para>
853 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
854 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
855 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
856 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
857 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
858 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
859 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
860 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
861 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
862 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
863 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
864 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
865 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
866 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
867 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
868 than creators do today&mdash;all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
869 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
870 </para>
871 <para>
872 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
873 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
874 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
875 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
876 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
877 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
878 remakes them.
879 </para>
880 <indexterm startref='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='endofrange'/>
881 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary> on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
882 <para>
883 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
884 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
885 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
886 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions&mdash;whether <quote>piracy</quote> will
887 be permitted, and whether <quote>property</quote> will be protected. The <quote>war</quote> that
888 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet&mdash;what
889 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
890 calls his <quote>own terrorist war</quote><footnote><para>
891 Amy Harmon, <quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
892 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,</quote> <citetitle>New York
893 Times</citetitle>, 17 January 2002.
894 </para></footnote>&mdash;has been framed as a battle about the
895 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
896 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
897 against it.
898 </para>
899 <para>
900 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
901 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
902 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
903 <quote>creative property.</quote> I believe that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that the
904 law, properly tuned, should punish <quote>piracy,</quote> whether on or off the
905 Internet.
906 </para>
907 <para>
908 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
909 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
910 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet <quote>pirates</quote> will also rid our
911 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
912 </para>
913 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
914 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
915 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
916 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
917 <para>
918 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first 180 years of
919 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
920 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
921 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
922 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,<footnote>
923 <para>
924 Neil W. Netanel, <quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
925 Journal</citetitle> 106 (1996): 283.
926 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
927 </para></footnote>
928 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
929 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
930 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
931 could cultivate and extend our culture.
932 </para>
933 <para>
934 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
935 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
936 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
937 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist&ndash;like,
938 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
939 granted&mdash;but it is not often granted to the critical or the
940 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
941 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
942 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
943 </para>
944 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. -->
945 <para>
946 The story that follows is about this war. It is not about the
947 <quote>centrality of technology</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
948 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
949 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
950 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
951 against an industry.
952 </para>
953 <para>
954 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
955 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
956 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
957 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
958 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
959 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
960 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
961 </para>
962 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
963 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
964 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary></indexterm>
965 <para>
966 <emphasis role="strong">Like the Causbys'</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about <quote>property.</quote> The
967 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
968 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
969 this <quote>property</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
970 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
971 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
972 of <quote>intellectual property</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
973 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
974 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
975 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
976 <quote>trespassing</quote> upon legitimate claims of <quote>property.</quote> It is as plain to
977 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
978 trespass.
979 </para>
980 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
981 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
982 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
983 <para>
984 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
985 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
986 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
987 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
988 war. Unlike
989 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
990 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
991 on its side.
992 </para>
993 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
994 <para>
995 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
996 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
997 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
998 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
999 our <quote>culture</quote> was as <quote>owned</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
1000 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
1001 <emphasis>uses</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
1002 accepted as it is now.
1003 </para>
1004 <para>
1005 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
1006 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
1007 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
1008 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1009 </para>
1010 <para>
1011 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1012 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1013 </para>
1014 <para>
1015 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1016 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1017 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1018 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1019 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1020 </para>
1021 <para>
1022 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1023 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1024 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1025 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1026 view?
1027 </para>
1028 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1029 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1030 <para>
1031 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1032 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1033 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1034 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of <quote>intellectual
1035 property.</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1036 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1037 this silliness will be much more profound.
1038 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1039 </para>
1040 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='endofrange'/>
1041 <para>
1042 <emphasis role="strong">The struggle</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas: <quote>piracy</quote> and
1043 <quote>property.</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1044 ideas.
1045 </para>
1046 <para>
1047 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1048 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1049 obscure French theorists&mdash;however natural that is for the weird
1050 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1051 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1052 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1053 </para>
1054 <para>
1055 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1056 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1057 government, pushed by big media to respond to this <quote>something new,</quote> is
1058 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1059 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let <quote>common
1060 sense</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1061 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1062 law&mdash;and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1063 fundamental about who we have always been.
1064 </para>
1065 <para>
1066 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1067 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1068 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1069 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1070 of one more consequence of this form of corruption&mdash;a consequence
1071 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1072 </para>
1073 </chapter>
1074 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1075 <part id="c-piracy">
1076 <title><quote>Piracy</quote></title>
1077 <partintro>
1078 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1079 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
1080 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
1081 <indexterm><primary>music publishing</primary></indexterm>
1082 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
1083 <para>
1084 <emphasis role="strong">Since the inception</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1085 been a war against <quote>piracy.</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1086 <quote>piracy,</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1087 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1088 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1089 </para>
1090 <blockquote>
1091 <para>
1092 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1093 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1094 of them for his own use.<footnote><para>
1095 <!-- f1 -->
1096 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield).
1097 </para></footnote>
1098 </para>
1099 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='endofrange'/>
1100 </blockquote>
1101 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary> efficient content distribution on</secondary></indexterm>
1102 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='startofrange'><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>efficiency of</secondary></indexterm>
1103 <para>
1104 Today we are in the middle of another <quote>war</quote> against <quote>piracy.</quote> The
1105 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1106 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1107 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1108 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1109 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1110 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1111 </para>
1112 <para>
1113 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1114 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1115 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1116 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1117 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will <quote>rob the author of the
1118 profit.</quote>
1119 </para>
1120 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='endofrange'/>
1121 <para>
1122 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1123 increasingly to technology to defend their <quote>property</quote> against this
1124 <quote>piracy.</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1125 raised to believe that <quote>property</quote> should be <quote>free.</quote> Forget tattoos,
1126 never mind body piercing&mdash;our kids are becoming
1127 <emphasis>thieves</emphasis>!
1128 </para>
1129 <para>
1130 There's no doubt that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1131 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1132 notion of <quote>piracy</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1133 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1134 </para>
1135 <para>
1136 The idea goes something like this:
1137 </para>
1138 <blockquote>
1139 <para>
1140 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1141 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1142 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1143 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1144 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1145 piracy.
1146 </para>
1147 </blockquote>
1148 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP</primary></indexterm>
1149 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle</primary></indexterm>
1150 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts</primary></indexterm>
1151 <indexterm><primary>creative property</primary><seealso>intellectual property rights</seealso></indexterm>
1152 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory of</secondary></indexterm>
1153 <indexterm id='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
1154 <para>
1155 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1156 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1157 theory of creative property<footnote><para>
1158 <!-- f2 -->
1159 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, <quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1160 in the Pepsi Generation,</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review</citetitle> 65 (1990): 397.
1161 </para></footnote>
1162 &mdash;if there is value, then someone must have a
1163 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1164 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1165 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.<footnote><para>
1166 <!-- f3 -->
1167 Lisa Bannon, <quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1168 Up,</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 21 August 1996, available at
1169 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #3</ulink>; Jonathan
1170 Zittrain, <quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1171 Speech, No One Wins,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 24 November 2002.
1172 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
1173 </para></footnote>
1174 There was <quote>value</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1175 <quote>right</quote>&mdash;even against the Girl Scouts.
1176 </para>
1177 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='endofrange'/>
1178 <para>
1179 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1180 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1182 of law protecting creative property. But the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1183 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1184 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1185 </para>
1186 <indexterm startref='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='endofrange'/>
1187 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
1188 <indexterm><primary>creativity</primary><seealso>innovation</seealso></indexterm>
1189 <indexterm id='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>legal restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
1190 <para>
1191 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1192 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1193 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1194 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1195 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1196 </para>
1197 <para>
1198 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1199 takes care to draw&mdash;the distinction between republishing someone's
1200 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1201 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1202 copyright law today regulates both.
1203 </para>
1204 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='endofrange'/>
1205 <para>
1206 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1207 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1208 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1209 entities could bear the burden of the law&mdash;even the burden of the
1210 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1211 more expense of doing business.
1212 </para>
1213 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>creativity impeded by</secondary></indexterm>
1214 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1215 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1216 <para>
1217 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1218 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1219 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1220 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1221 <quote>copying,</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1222 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1223 outweighs any original benefit&mdash;certainly as it affects
1224 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1225 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1226 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1227 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1228 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1229 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1230 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1231 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1232 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1233 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the <quote>Rise of the Creative
1234 Class.</quote><footnote>
1235 <para>
1236 <!-- f4 -->
1237 In <citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class</citetitle> (New York:
1238 Basic Books, 2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1239 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1240 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1241 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1242 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1243 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1244
1245 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1246 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1247 </para></footnote>
1248 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1249 this creative class.
1250 </para>
1251 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='endofrange'/>
1252 <para>
1253 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1254 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1255 context the current battles about behavior labeled <quote>piracy.</quote>
1256 </para>
1257 </partintro>
1258
1259 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1260 <chapter label="1" id="creators">
1261 <title>Chapter One: Creators</title>
1262 <indexterm id='idxanimatedcartoons' class='startofrange'><primary>animated cartoons</primary></indexterm>
1263 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'><primary>cartoon films</primary></indexterm>
1264 <indexterm id='idxfilmsanimated' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>animated</secondary></indexterm>
1265 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatwillie' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Willie</primary></indexterm>
1266 <indexterm id='idxmickeymouse' class='startofrange'><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
1267 <para>
1268 <emphasis role="strong">In 1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1269 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called <citetitle>Plane Crazy</citetitle>.
1270 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1271 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle> brought
1272 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1273 </para>
1274 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1275 <para>
1276 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1277 movie <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1278 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1279 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1280 Disney ran a test in the summer of 1928, the results were unambiguous.
1281 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1282 </para>
1283 <blockquote>
1284 <para>
1285 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1286 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1287 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1288 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1289 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1290 </para>
1291 <para>
1292 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1293 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1294 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1295 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1296 synchronization was pretty close.
1297 </para>
1298 <para>
1299 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1300 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1301 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1302 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1303 it was something new!<footnote><para>
1304 <!-- f1 -->
1305 Leonard Maltin, <citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1306 Cartoons</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34&ndash;35.
1307 </para></footnote>
1308 </para>
1309 </blockquote>
1310 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub</primary></indexterm>
1311 <para>
1312 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1313 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: <quote>I have never been so thrilled
1314 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.</quote>
1315 </para>
1316 <para>
1317 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1318 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1319 rarely&mdash;except in Disney's hands&mdash;been anything more than
1320 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1321 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1322 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1323 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1324 </para>
1325 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt' class='endofrange'/>
1326 <indexterm id='idxkeatonbuster' class='startofrange'><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1327 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1328 <para>
1329 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that 1928 also marks
1330 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1331 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1332 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>.
1333 </para>
1334 <para>
1335 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in 1895. In the era of silent
1336 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1337 uncontrollable laughter from his audience. <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1338 Jr</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1339 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton&mdash;wildly popular
1340 and among the best of its genre.
1341 </para>
1342 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1343 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1344 <para>
1345 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1346 Willie.
1347 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1348 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1349 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,<footnote><para>
1350 <!-- f2 -->
1351 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1352 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #4</ulink>.
1353 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1354 use the music for five songs in <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>: <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote> <quote>The
1355 Simpleton</quote> (Delille), <quote>Mischief Makers</quote> (Carbonara), <quote>Joyful Hurry No. 1</quote>
1356 (Baron), and <quote>Gawky Rube</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song, <quote>The Turkey in the
1357 Straw,</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1358 Harry Surden, 10 July 2003, on file with author.
1359 </para></footnote>
1360 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1361 the invention of synchronized sound in <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle> that we
1362 get <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1363 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote>
1364 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1365 Mouse.
1366 </para>
1367 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatwillie' class='endofrange'/>
1368 <indexterm startref='idxmickeymouse' class='endofrange'/>
1369 <indexterm startref='idxkeatonbuster' class='endofrange'/>
1370 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='endofrange'/>
1371 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1372 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
1373 <para>
1374 This <quote>borrowing</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1375 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1376 films of his day.<footnote><para>
1377 <!-- f3 -->
1378 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, <quote>The Mouse
1379 that Ate the Public Domain,</quote> Findlaw, 5 March 2002, at
1380 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #5</ulink>.
1381 </para></footnote>
1382 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1383 knockoffs&mdash;slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1384 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1385 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1386 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1387 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1388 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1389 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1390 old.
1391 </para>
1392 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1393 <para>
1394 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1395 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1396 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1397 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1398 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1399 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1400 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1401 </para>
1402 <para>
1403 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1404 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1405 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1406 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1407 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1408 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1409 work of others is astonishing when set together: <citetitle>Snow White</citetitle>
1410 (1937), <citetitle>Fantasia</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Pinocchio</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Dumbo</citetitle>
1411 (1941), <citetitle>Bambi</citetitle> (1942), <citetitle>Song of the South</citetitle> (1946),
1412 <citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle> (1950), <citetitle>Alice in Wonderland</citetitle> (1951), <citetitle>Robin
1413 Hood</citetitle> (1952), <citetitle>Peter Pan</citetitle> (1953), <citetitle>Lady and the Tramp</citetitle>
1414 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1415 (1955), <citetitle>Mulan</citetitle> (1998), <citetitle>Sleeping Beauty</citetitle> (1959), <citetitle>101
1416 Dalmatians</citetitle> (1961), <citetitle>The Sword in the Stone</citetitle> (1963), and
1417 <citetitle>The Jungle Book</citetitle> (1967)&mdash;not to mention a recent example
1418 that we should perhaps quickly forget, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>
1419 (2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1420 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1421 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1422 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1423 </para>
1424 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales' class='endofrange'/>
1425 <para>
1426 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1427 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1428 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1429 its importance. We could call this <quote>Disney creativity,</quote> though that
1430 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, <quote>Walt Disney
1431 creativity</quote>&mdash;a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1432 culture around us and makes it something different.
1433 </para>
1434 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='endofrange'/>
1435 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='endofrange'/>
1436 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='endofrange'/>
1437 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><seealso>copyright law</seealso></indexterm>
1438 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
1439 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>defined</secondary></indexterm>
1440 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>traditional term for conversion to</secondary></indexterm>
1441 <para> In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1442 relatively fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was
1443 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1444 thirty years&mdash;for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1445 copyrighted.<footnote><para>
1446 <!-- f4 -->
1447 Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1448 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the <quote>average</quote> term by
1449 determining
1450 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1451 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in year
1452 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the
1453 average
1454 term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1455 Web site associated with this book, available at
1456 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #6</ulink>.
1457 </para></footnote>
1458 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1459 copyright holders of a creative work had an <quote>exclusive right</quote> to control
1460 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1461 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1462 </para>
1463 <para>
1464 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1465 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1466 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a <quote>lawyer-free
1467 zone.</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1468 for Disney to use and build upon in 1928. It was free for
1469 anyone&mdash; whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1470 approved or not&mdash;to use and build upon.
1471 </para>
1472 <indexterm startref='idxanimatedcartoons' class='endofrange'/>
1473 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsanimated' class='endofrange'/>
1474 <para>
1475 This is the ways things always were&mdash;until quite recently. For most
1476 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1477 until 1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1478 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1479
1480 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1481 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1482 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s
1483 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1484 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1485 content from before the Great Depression.
1486 </para>
1487 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'/>
1488 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc' class='endofrange'/>
1489 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='endofrange'/>
1490 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='endofrange'/>
1491 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='endofrange'/>
1492 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1493 <para>
1494 <emphasis role="strong">Of course</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on <quote>Walt Disney creativity.</quote>
1495 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1496 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1497 universal.
1498 </para>
1499 <indexterm id='idxcomicsjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1500 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1501 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1502 <indexterm id='idxmanga' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1503 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1504 <para>
1505 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1506 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: <citetitle>manga</citetitle>, or
1507 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of
1508 publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives
1509 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1510 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1511 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1512 </para>
1513 <para>
1514 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1515 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1516 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1517 the stories that these <quote>graphic novels</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1518 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are <quote>men in tights.</quote>
1519 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1520 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1521 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1522 interestingly different way.
1523 </para>
1524 <para>
1525 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1526 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1527 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1528 </para>
1529 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1530 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1531 <para>
1532 This is the phenomenon of <citetitle>doujinshi</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1533 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1534 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is <emphasis>just</emphasis> a
1535 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1536 transforming it either subtly or
1537 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1538 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1539 develop it differently&mdash;with a different story line. Or the comic can
1540 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1541 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently <quote>different.</quote> But they
1542 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1543 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1544 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1545 </para>
1546 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1547 <para>
1548 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1549 huge. More than 33,000 <quote>circles</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1550 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come
1551 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1552 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1553 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1554 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1555 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1556 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1557 </para>
1558 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1559 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1560 <para>
1561 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1562 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1563 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1564 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1565 one. Doujinshi are plainly <quote>derivative works.</quote> There is no general
1566 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1567 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1568 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1569 Jr</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that <quote>taking</quote> without
1570 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1571 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1572 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1573 </para>
1574 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt2' class='endofrange'/>
1575 <indexterm id='idxwinickjudd' class='startofrange'><primary>Winick, Judd</primary></indexterm>
1576 <para>
1577 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1578 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1579 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, <quote>The
1580 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1581 in Japan now. &hellip; American comics were born out of copying each
1582 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1583 other. &hellip; That's how [the artists] learn to draw &mdash; by going into comic
1584 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them</quote>
1585 and building from them.<footnote><para>
1586 <!-- f5 -->
1587 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, <citetitle>Reinventing Comics</citetitle> (New
1588 York: Perennial, 2000).
1589 </para></footnote>
1590 </para>
1591 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1592 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics</primary></indexterm>
1593 <para>
1594 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1595 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1596 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, <quote>there are these rules
1597 and you have to stick to them.</quote> There are things Superman <quote>cannot</quote>
1598 do. <quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1599 which are fifty years old.</quote>
1600 </para>
1601 <indexterm startref='idxwinickjudd' class='endofrange'/>
1602 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1603 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1604 <indexterm id='idxmehrasalil' class='startofrange'><primary>Mehra, Salil</primary></indexterm>
1605 <para>
1606 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1607 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1608 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1609 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1610 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1611 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1612 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.<footnote><para>
1613 <!-- f6 -->
1614 See Salil K. Mehra, <quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1615 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1616 Review</citetitle> 55 (2002): 155, 182. <quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1617 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1618 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1619 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1620 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1621 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.</quote>
1622 </para></footnote>
1623 </para>
1624 <indexterm startref='idxcomicsjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1625 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics' class='endofrange'/>
1626 <indexterm startref='idxmanga' class='endofrange'/>
1627 <para>
1628 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1629 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1630 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1631 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1632 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1633 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1634 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1635 a more general pattern of blocking this <quote>free taking</quote> by the doujinshi
1636 culture?
1637 </para>
1638 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='endofrange'/>
1639 <indexterm startref='idxmehrasalil' class='endofrange'/>
1640 <para>
1641 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1642 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1643 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. <quote>We don't have enough
1644 lawyers,</quote> he told me one afternoon. There <quote>just aren't enough resources
1645 to prosecute cases like this.</quote>
1646 </para>
1647 <para>
1648 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1649 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1650 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1651 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1652 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1653 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1654 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1655 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1656 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1657 their clients or hurt them?
1658 </para>
1659 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics' class='endofrange'/>
1660 <para>
1661 <emphasis role='strong'>Let's pause</emphasis> for a moment.
1662 </para>
1663 <para>
1664 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1665 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1666 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1667 </para>
1668 <para>
1669 We live in a world that celebrates <quote>property.</quote> I am one of those
1670 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1671 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1672 <quote>intellectual property.</quote><footnote><para>
1673 <!-- f7 -->
1674 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
1675 The term <citetitle>intellectual property</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1676 Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 11 (New York: New York
1677 University Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
1678 (New York: Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately
1679 describes a set of <quote>property</quote> rights &mdash; copyright, patents,
1680 trademark, and trade-secret &mdash; but the nature of those rights is
1681 very different.
1682 </para></footnote>
1683 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1684 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1685 property.
1686 </para>
1687 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt3' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1688 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1689 <indexterm><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1690 <para>
1691 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1692 plenty of value out there that <quote>property</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1693 mean <quote>money can't buy you love,</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1694 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1695 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1696 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1697 condemning that taking as wrong&mdash; even though trivial, even if
1698 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1699 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1700 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1701 Disney's use would have been considered <quote>fair.</quote> There was nothing
1702 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1703 the public domain.
1704 </para>
1705 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>derivative works based on</secondary></indexterm>
1706 <para>
1707 Thus, even though the things that Disney took&mdash;or more generally,
1708 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity&mdash;are
1709 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1710
1711 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1712 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1713 freedom is good.
1714 </para>
1715 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='endofrange'/>
1716 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1717 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1718 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1719 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1720 <indexterm id='idxmanga2' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1721 <para>
1722 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1723 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1724 work&mdash;or even one copy&mdash;without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1725 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1726 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1727 form, whether large or small.
1728 </para>
1729 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='endofrange'/>
1730 <para>
1731 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1732 say that the copycat comic artists are <quote>stealing.</quote> This form of Walt
1733 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1734 particular find it hard to say why.
1735 </para>
1736 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1737 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1738 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='endofrange'/>
1739 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1740 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1741 <indexterm startref='idxmanga2' class='endofrange'/>
1742 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
1743 <para>
1744 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1745 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1746 without asking or paying for the privilege. (<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1747 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1748 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?</quote>) Acting companies
1749 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1750 permission from anyone. (Does <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> believe
1751 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1752 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1753 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1754 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s;
1755 two volcano disaster films in 1997.
1756 </para>
1757 <para>
1758 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1759 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1760 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1761 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1762 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1763 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1764 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking&mdash;free
1765 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1766 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1767 </para>
1768 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt3' class='endofrange'/>
1769 <para>
1770 The hard question is therefore not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> a
1771 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1772 question instead is <quote><emphasis>How</emphasis> free is this culture?</quote>
1773 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1774 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1775 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1776 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1777 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1778 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1779 a studio or not?
1780 </para>
1781 <para>
1782 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1783 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1784 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1785 </para>
1786 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='endofrange'/>
1787
1788 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1789 </chapter>
1790 <chapter label="2" id="mere-copyists">
1791 <title>Chapter Two: <quote>Mere Copyists</quote></title>
1792 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis</primary></indexterm>
1793 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1794 <indexterm id='idxphotography' class='startofrange'><primary>photography</primary></indexterm>
1795 <para>
1796 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1797 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1798 <quote>photographs.</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1799 <quote>daguerreotypes.</quote> The process was complicated and
1800 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1801 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1802 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1803 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1804 </para>
1805 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William</primary></indexterm>
1806 <para>
1807 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1808 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1809 <quote>automatic pictures.</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1810 making <quote>negatives.</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1811 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1812 the 1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1813 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1814 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1815 amateurs.
1816 </para>
1817 <indexterm id='idxeastmangeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Eastman, George</primary></indexterm>
1818 <para>
1819 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1820 didn't happen until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1821 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1822 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1823 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1824 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1825 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1826 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1827 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1828 population of photographers.
1829 </para>
1830 <indexterm id='idxkodakcameras' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1831 <indexterm id='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)</primary></indexterm>
1832 <para>
1833 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1834 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1835 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. <quote>You press the button and we
1836 do the rest.</quote><footnote><para>
1837 <!-- f1 -->
1838 Reese V. Jenkins, <citetitle>Images and Enterprise</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975), 112.
1839 </para></footnote> As he described in <citetitle>The Kodak Primer</citetitle>:
1840 </para>
1841 <blockquote>
1842 <para>
1843 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1844 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1845 that only an expert can do. &hellip; We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1846 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1847 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1848 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1849 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1850 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1851 chemicals.<footnote>
1852 <para>
1853 <!-- f2 -->
1854 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1855 Brian Coe, <citetitle>The Birth of Photography</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1856 1977), 53.
1857 </para></footnote>
1858 </para>
1859 </blockquote>
1860 <indexterm startref='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='endofrange'/>
1861 <para>
1862 For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1863 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1864 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1865 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1866 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1867 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in 1888; one
1868 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1869 From 1888 through 1909, while industrial production was rising by 4.7
1870 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by 11
1871 percent.<footnote><para>
1872 <!-- f3 -->
1873 Jenkins, 177.
1874 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1875 an average annual increase of over 17 percent.<footnote><para>
1876 <!-- f4 -->
1877 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p. 178.
1878 </para></footnote>
1879 </para>
1880 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1881 <para>
1882
1883 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1884 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1885 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1886 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1887 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1888 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, <quote>For the
1889 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1890 permanent record of his family and its activities. &hellip; For the first
1891 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1892 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1893 interpretation or bias.</quote><footnote><para>
1894 <!-- f5 -->
1895 Coe, 58.
1896 </para></footnote>
1897 </para>
1898 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
1899 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
1900 <para>
1901 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1902 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1903 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1904 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1905 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1906 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its <quote>quality</quote>;
1907 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1908 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1909 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1910 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1911 have before.
1912 </para>
1913 <indexterm startref='idxkodakcameras' class='endofrange'/>
1914 <indexterm id='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>permissions</primary><secondary>photography exempted from</secondary></indexterm>
1915 <para>
1916 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1917 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1918 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1919 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1920 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1921 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1922 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1923 he wanted. Their answer was no.<footnote><para>
1924 <!-- f6 -->
1925 For illustrative cases, see, for example, <citetitle>Pavesich</citetitle>
1926 v. <citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co</citetitle>., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905);
1927 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Chinn</citetitle>, 123090 S.W. 364, 366
1928 (Ky. 1909); <citetitle>Corliss</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Walker</citetitle>, 64 F. 280 (Mass.
1929 Dist. Ct. 1894).
1930 </para></footnote>
1931 </para>
1932 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology' class='endofrange'/>
1933 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt4' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1934 <indexterm id='idximagesownershipof' class='startofrange'><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
1935 <para>
1936 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1937 familiar. The photographer was <quote>taking</quote> something from the person or
1938 building whose photograph he shot&mdash;pirating something of
1939 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1940 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1941 draw
1942 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1943 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1944 that they thought valuable.
1945 </para>
1946 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1947 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1948 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology2' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1949 <para>
1950 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1951 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1952 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1953 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1954 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.<footnote>
1955 <para>
1956 <!-- f7 -->
1957 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote>
1958 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review</citetitle> 4 (1890): 193.
1959 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1960 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.</primary></indexterm>
1961 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1962 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1963 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1964 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1965 </para>
1966 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt4' class='endofrange'/>
1967 <para>
1968 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1969 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1970 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1971 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1972 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1973 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1974 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1975 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1976 clearing the rights to do the capturing.<footnote><para>
1977 <!-- f8 -->
1978 See Melville B. Nimmer, <quote>The Right of Publicity,</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
1979 Problems</citetitle> 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, <quote>Privacy,</quote> <citetitle>California Law
1980 Review</citetitle> 48 (1960) 398&ndash;407; <citetitle>White</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
1981 Inc</citetitle>., 971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951
1982 (1993).
1983 </para></footnote>)
1984 </para>
1985 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1986 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
1987 <para>
1988 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1989 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1990 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1991 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1992 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1993 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1994 Kodak would be benefiting from the <quote>theft</quote> committed by the
1995 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1996 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1997 from the <quote>image-right</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
1998 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1999 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
2000 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
2001 </para>
2002 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology2' class='endofrange'/>
2003 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology3' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
2004 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
2005 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
2006 <para>
2007
2008 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
2009 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
2010 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
2011 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
2012 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
2013 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
2014 technology as they did&mdash;since professionals could have more
2015 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
2016 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
2017 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
2018 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
2019 realized.
2020 </para>
2021 <indexterm startref='idxphotography' class='endofrange'/>
2022 <indexterm startref='idxeastmangeorge' class='endofrange'/>
2023 <indexterm startref='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
2024 <indexterm startref='idximagesownershipof' class='endofrange'/>
2025 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
2026 <indexterm id='idxjustthink' class='startofrange'><primary>Just Think!</primary></indexterm>
2027 <para>
2028 <emphasis role='strong'>If you drive</emphasis> through San
2029 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
2030 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
2031 <quote>Just Think!</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
2032 there's little that's <quote>just</quote> cerebral in the projects
2033 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
2034 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
2035 the film of your VCR. Rather the <quote>film</quote> of digital
2036 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
2037 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
2038 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
2039 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
2040 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
2041 think. By tinkering, they learn.
2042 </para>
2043 <indexterm id='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>education</primary><secondary>in media literacy</secondary></indexterm>
2044 <indexterm id='idxmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>media literacy</primary></indexterm>
2045 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>media literacy and</secondary></indexterm>
2046 <para>
2047 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
2048 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
2049 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, <quote>Five years ago, a good
2050 real-time digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get
2051 professional quality for $595.</quote><footnote><para>
2052 <!-- f9 -->
2053 H. Edward Goldberg, <quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
2054 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,</quote>
2055 cadalyst, February 2002, available at
2056 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #7</ulink>.
2057 </para></footnote>
2058 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
2059 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
2060 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
2061 learning more and more of something teachers call <quote>media literacy.</quote>
2062 </para>
2063 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2064 <para>
2065 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
2066 <quote>Media literacy,</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
2067 Think!, puts it, <quote>is the ability &hellip; to understand, analyze, and
2068 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2069 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2070 the way people access it.</quote>
2071 </para>
2072 <indexterm startref='idxjustthink' class='endofrange'/>
2073 <para>
2074 This may seem like an odd way to think about <quote>literacy.</quote> For most
2075 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2076 and noticing split infinitives are the things that <quote>literate</quote> people know
2077 about.
2078 </para>
2079 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2080 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
2081 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
2082 <para>
2083 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of
2084 television commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000
2085 commercials generally,<footnote><para>
2086 <!-- f10 -->
2087 Judith Van Evra, <citetitle>Television and Child Development</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2088 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990); <quote>Findings on Family and TV
2089 Study,</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post</citetitle>, 25 May 1997, B6.
2090 </para></footnote>
2091 it is increasingly important to understand the <quote>grammar</quote> of media. For
2092 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2093 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2094 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2095 (at least at first) terrible media.
2096 </para>
2097 <para>
2098 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2099 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2100 has written understands how difficult writing is&mdash;how difficult
2101 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2102 language to be understandable&mdash;few of us have any real sense of
2103 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2104 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2105 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2106 </para>
2107 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology3' class='endofrange'/>
2108 <para>
2109 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2110 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2111 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2112 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2113 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2114 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2115 </para>
2116 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2117 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael</primary></indexterm>
2118 <para>
2119 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2120 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2121 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2122
2123 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2124 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2125 about <quote>the placement of objects, color, &hellip; rhythm, pacing, and
2126 texture.</quote><footnote>
2127 <para>
2128 <!-- f11 -->
2129 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish, 13 December
2130 2002.
2131 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2132 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2133 </para></footnote>
2134 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2135 <quote>played</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2136 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2137 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2138 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2139 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2140 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2141 to a wildly successful author.<footnote><para>
2142 <!-- f12 -->
2143 See Scott Steinberg, <quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,</quote> E!online, 4
2144 November 2000, available at
2145 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #8</ulink>; <quote>Timeline,</quote> 22 November 2000,
2146 available at
2147 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #9</ulink>.
2148 </para></footnote>
2149 </para>
2150 <indexterm><primary>computer games</primary></indexterm>
2151 <para>
2152 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2153 describes, <quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2154 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2155 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2156 led.</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2157 </para>
2158 <para>
2159 Yet the push for an expanded literacy&mdash;one that goes beyond text
2160 to include audio and visual elements&mdash;is not about making better
2161 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2162 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2163 </para>
2164 <blockquote>
2165 <para>
2166 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2167 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2168 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2169 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2170 being read-only.
2171 </para>
2172 </blockquote>
2173 <para>
2174 <quote>Read-only.</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2175 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2176 twentieth century.
2177 </para>
2178 <para>
2179 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2180 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2181 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2182 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2183 literacy,
2184 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2185 and this literacy in particular, is to <quote>empower people to choose the
2186 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2187 express.</quote><footnote>
2188 <para>
2189 <!-- f13 -->
2190 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2191 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2192 </para></footnote> It is to enable students <quote>to communicate in the
2193 language of the twenty-first century.</quote><footnote><para>
2194 <!-- f14 -->
2195 Ibid.
2196 </para></footnote>
2197 </para>
2198 <indexterm id='idxbarishstephanie' class='startofrange'><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2199 <para>
2200 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2201 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2202 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2203 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2204 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2205 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2206 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2207 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2208 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2209 students know something about&mdash;gun violence.
2210 </para>
2211 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='endofrange'/>
2212 <para>
2213 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2214 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2215 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2216 away. The <quote>kids were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night,</quote>
2217 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2218 what education should be about&mdash;learning how to express themselves.
2219 </para>
2220 <para>
2221 Using whatever <quote>free web stuff they could find,</quote> and relatively simple
2222 tools to enable the kids to mix <quote>image, sound, and text,</quote> Barish said
2223 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2224 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2225 close to the lives of these students. The project <quote>gave them a tool
2226 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2227 it,</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2228 expression&mdash;far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2229 been created using only text. <quote>If you had said to these students, <quote>you
2230 have to do it in text,</quote> they would've just thrown their hands up and
2231 gone and done something else,</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2232 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2233 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2234 <emphasis>these</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2235 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2236 </para>
2237 <indexterm startref='idxbarishstephanie' class='endofrange'/>
2238 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2239 <para>
2240
2241 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2242 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?</quote> I asked. In part,
2243 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2244 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of <quote>constructing
2245 meaning.</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2246 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2247 part&mdash;and increasingly, not the most powerful part&mdash;of
2248 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2249 our interview,
2250 </para>
2251 <blockquote>
2252 <para>
2253 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2254 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2255 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2256 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2257 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2258 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2259 you say, <quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.</quote>
2260 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2261 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2262 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, <quote>Well, with all these things that you
2263 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2264 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2265 for me something that reflects that.</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2266 camera and &hellip; saying, <quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2267 make a little movie.</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2268 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2269 about the topic.&hellip;
2270 </para>
2271 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2272 <para>
2273 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2274 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2275 bump up against the fact, <quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2276 to write something.</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2277 they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 times, till they got it right.
2278 </para>
2279 <para>
2280 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2281 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2282 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2283 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2284 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2285 had a lot of power with this language.
2286 </para>
2287 </blockquote>
2288 <indexterm startref='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2289 <indexterm startref='idxmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2290 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='endofrange'/>
2291 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='endofrange'/>
2292 <indexterm id='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='startofrange'><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2293 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center</primary></indexterm>
2294 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
2295 <para>
2296 <emphasis role='strong'>When two planes</emphasis> crashed into the
2297 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2298 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2299 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2300 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2301 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2302 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2303 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2304 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2305 watching.
2306 </para>
2307 <para>
2308 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2309 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2310 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was <quote>balance,</quote>
2311 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2312 increasingly come to expect it, <quote>news as entertainment,</quote> even if the
2313 entertainment is tragedy.
2314 </para>
2315 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
2316 <indexterm><primary>CBS</primary></indexterm>
2317 <indexterm><primary>Cyber Rights (Godwin)</primary></indexterm>
2318 <indexterm><primary>Godwin, Mike</primary></indexterm>
2319 <indexterm id='idxinternetnewseventson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>news events on</secondary></indexterm>
2320 <para>
2321 But in addition to this produced news about the <quote>tragedy of September
2322 11,</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2323 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2324 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2325 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2326 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2327 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2328 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2329 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2330 the term in his book <citetitle>Cyber Rights</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2331 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2332 was also the Internet.
2333 </para>
2334 <indexterm startref='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='endofrange'/>
2335 <para>
2336 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet&mdash;though I do think the
2337 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2338 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2339 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2340 movie
2341 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2342 by a student on the <quote>Just Think!</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2343 with sound or text.
2344 </para>
2345 <para>
2346 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2347 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2348 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2349 tradition&mdash;not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2350 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2351 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2352 spread practically instantaneously.
2353 </para>
2354 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2355 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2356 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2357 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2358 <para>
2359 September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2360 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2361 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2362 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2363 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2364 cultures, it records private facts in a public way&mdash;it's a kind
2365 of electronic <citetitle>Jerry Springer</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2366 </para>
2367 <indexterm startref='idxinternetnewseventson' class='endofrange'/>
2368 <indexterm><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2369 <indexterm id='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>public discourse conducted on</secondary></indexterm>
2370 <para>
2371 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2372 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2373 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2374 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2375 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2376 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2377 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2378 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2379 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2380 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2381 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2382 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2383 </para>
2384 <indexterm id='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
2385 <indexterm id='idxelections' class='startofrange'><primary>elections</primary></indexterm>
2386 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
2387 <para>
2388 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2389 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2390 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2391 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2392 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2393 people vote
2394 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2395 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2396 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2397 </para>
2398 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2399 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson' class='endofrange'/>
2400 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2401 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de</primary></indexterm>
2402 <indexterm id='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>public discourse in</secondary></indexterm>
2403 <indexterm><primary>jury system</primary></indexterm>
2404 <para>
2405 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2406 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2407 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2408 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2409 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2410 most important account of early <quote>Democracy in America.</quote> It wasn't
2411 popular elections that fascinated him&mdash;it was the jury, an
2412 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2413 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2414 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2415 deliberated. Members argued about the <quote>right</quote> result; they tried to
2416 persuade each other of the <quote>right</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2417 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2418 come to an end.<footnote><para>
2419 <!-- f15 -->
2420 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, <citetitle>Democracy in America</citetitle>,
2421 bk. 1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16.
2422 </para></footnote>
2423 </para>
2424 <indexterm startref='idxelections' class='endofrange'/>
2425 <para>
2426 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2427 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2428 are pushing to create just such an institution.<footnote><para>
2429 <!-- f16 -->
2430 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, <quote>Deliberation Day,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2431 Political Philosophy</citetitle> 10 (2) (2002): 129.
2432 </para></footnote>
2433 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2434 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2435 place for <quote>democratic deliberation</quote> to occur.
2436 </para>
2437 <indexterm id='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='startofrange'><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2438 <para>
2439 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2440 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2441 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2442 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2443 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2444 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.<footnote><para>
2445 <!-- f17 -->
2446 Cass Sunstein, <citetitle>Republic.com</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001),
2447 65&ndash;80, 175, 182, 183, 192.
2448 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2449 little beyond what our friends say.
2450 </para>
2451 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2452 <indexterm><primary>e-mail</primary></indexterm>
2453 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2454 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2455 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='endofrange'/>
2456 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='endofrange'/>
2457 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='endofrange'/>
2458 <para>
2459 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2460 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2461 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2462 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2463 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2464
2465 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2466 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2467 place.
2468 </para>
2469 <para>
2470 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2471 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2472 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2473 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2474 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2475 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2476 </para>
2477 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard</primary></indexterm>
2478 <para>
2479 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2480 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race
2481 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2482 is having an effect.
2483 </para>
2484 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent</primary></indexterm>
2485 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom</primary></indexterm>
2486 <indexterm id='idxmediablogpressureon' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>blog pressure on</secondary></indexterm>
2487 <indexterm id='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>news events on</secondary></indexterm>
2488 <para>
2489 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2490 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2491 <quote>misspoke</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2492 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2493 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2494 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2495 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2496 more instances of the same <quote>misspeaking</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2497 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2498 resign as senate majority leader.<footnote><para>
2499 <!-- f18 -->
2500 Noah Shachtman, <quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the
2501 Pot,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 16 January 2003, G5.
2502 </para></footnote>
2503 </para>
2504 <indexterm id='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2505 <para>
2506 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2507 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2508 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2509 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2510 on.
2511 </para>
2512 <indexterm startref='idxmediablogpressureon' class='endofrange'/>
2513 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>peer-generated rankings on</secondary></indexterm>
2514 <para>
2515 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2516 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2517 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2518 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2519 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2520 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2521 peer-generated rankings.
2522 </para>
2523 <indexterm startref='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='endofrange'/>
2524 <indexterm id='idxjournalism' class='startofrange'><primary>journalism</primary></indexterm>
2525 <indexterm id='idxwinerdave' class='startofrange'><primary>Winer, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2526 <para>
2527 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2528 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2529 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2530 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2531 difference is the absence of a financial <quote>conflict of interest.</quote> <quote>I think you
2532 have to take the conflict of interest</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2533 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2534 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2535 get it out of the way.</quote>
2536 </para>
2537 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2538 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2539 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2540 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
2541 <para>
2542 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2543 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2544 from the public than an unconcentrated media can&mdash;as CNN admitted
2545 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2546 its own employees.<footnote><para>
2547 <!-- f19 -->
2548 Telephone interview with David Winer, 16 April 2003.
2549 </para></footnote>
2550 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2551 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2552 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2553 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2554 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2555 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2556 told her that <emphasis>they</emphasis> were writing <quote>the story.</quote>)
2557 </para>
2558 <indexterm startref='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='endofrange'/>
2559 <para>
2560 Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2561 debate&mdash;<quote>amateur</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced,
2562 but in the sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to
2563 give their reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a
2564 story, as reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds
2565 from across the southwest United States turned to the Internet to
2566 retell what they had seen.<footnote><para>
2567 <!-- f20 -->
2568 John Schwartz, <quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2569 Information Online,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci
2570 D. Kramer, <quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,</quote>
2571 Online Journalism Review, 2 February 2003, available at
2572 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #10</ulink>.
2573 </para></footnote>
2574 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2575 <quote>triangulate,</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2576 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2577 out of it</quote>&mdash;with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2578 </para>
2579 <para>
2580 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2581 with blogs. <quote>It's going to become an essential skill,</quote> Winer predicts,
2582 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2583 not clear that <quote>journalism</quote> is happy about this&mdash;some journalists
2584 have been told to curtail their blogging.<footnote>
2585 <para>
2586 <!-- f21 -->
2587 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2588 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2589 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve</primary></indexterm>
2590 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2591 See Michael Falcone, <quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?</quote> <citetitle>New
2592 York Times</citetitle>, 29 September 2003, C4. (<quote>Not all news organizations have
2593 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2594 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2595 war on March 9, stopped posting 12 days later at his bosses'
2596 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a <citetitle>Houston Chronicle</citetitle> reporter, was
2597 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2598 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.</quote>)
2599 </para></footnote>
2600 But it is clear that we are still in transition. <quote>A
2601
2602 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2603 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,</quote> Winer told me.
2604 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2605 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2606 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, <quote>we will
2607 be the last thing that gets shut down.</quote>
2608 </para>
2609 <indexterm startref='idxjournalism' class='endofrange'/>
2610 <para>
2611 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because <quote>you
2612 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.</quote>
2613 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2614 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2615 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2616 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2617 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2618 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2619 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2620 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2621 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2622 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2623 extraordinary to report.
2624 </para>
2625 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage' class='endofrange'/>
2626 <indexterm startref='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='endofrange'/>
2627 <indexterm startref='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='endofrange'/>
2628 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2629 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson2' class='endofrange'/>
2630 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2631 <indexterm startref='idxwinerdave' class='endofrange'/>
2632 <indexterm id='idxbrownjohnseely' class='startofrange'><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
2633 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2634 <para>
2635 <emphasis role='strong'>John Seely Brown</emphasis> is the chief
2636 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2637 describes it, is <quote>human learning and &hellip; the creation of
2638 knowledge ecologies for creating &hellip; innovation.</quote>
2639 </para>
2640 <para>
2641 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2642 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2643 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2644 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2645 affect learning.
2646 </para>
2647 <para>
2648 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When <quote>a lot of us grew up,</quote>
2649 he explains, that tinkering was done <quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2650 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.</quote> But digital technologies
2651 enable a different kind of tinkering&mdash;with abstract ideas though
2652 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2653 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2654 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2655 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2656 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2657 or <quote>free collage,</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2658 the tinkering of many others.
2659 </para>
2660 <para>
2661 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2662 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2663 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2664 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2665 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2666 </para>
2667 <para>
2668 This opportunity creates a <quote>completely new kind of learning platform,</quote>
2669 as Brown describes. <quote>As soon as you start doing that, you &hellip;
2670 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2671 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2672 if they can improve it.</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2673 apprenticeship. <quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.</quote>
2674 </para>
2675 <para>
2676 In this process, <quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2677 They are code.</quote> Kids are <quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2678 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2679 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2680 platform. &hellip; You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2681 you tinker the more you improve.</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2682 learn.
2683 </para>
2684 <para>
2685 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2686 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2687 it, <quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2688 intelligence.</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2689 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2690 text. <quote>The Web &hellip; says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2691 you are visual, if you are interested in film &hellip; [then] there is a
2692 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2693 these multiple forms of intelligence.</quote>
2694 </para>
2695 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'/>
2696 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2697 <para>
2698 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2699 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2700
2701 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2702 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2703 kind of recognition.
2704 </para>
2705 <para>
2706 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2707 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2708 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2709 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2710 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2711 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2712 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2713 </para>
2714 <para>
2715 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2716 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2717 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>)
2718 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the <quote>right to
2719 tinker</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2720 general.<footnote><para>
2721 <!-- f22 -->
2722 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, <quote>Technological Access
2723 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2724 of the Association for Computer Machinery</citetitle> 43 (2000): 9.
2725 </para></footnote>
2726 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2727 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2728 </para>
2729 <para>
2730 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,</quote> Brown
2731 explains. We need to <quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2732 and want to learn.</quote>
2733 </para>
2734 <para>
2735 <quote>Yet,</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2736 evince, <quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2737 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. &hellip; We're building an
2738 architecture that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2739 system that closes down that part of the brain.</quote>
2740 </para>
2741 <para>
2742 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2743 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2744 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2745 the law to close down that technology.
2746 </para>
2747 <indexterm><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
2748 <indexterm startref='idxbrownjohnseely' class='endofrange'/>
2749 <para>
2750 <quote>No way to run a culture,</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2751 chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="collectors"/>,
2752 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2753 </para>
2754 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2755 </chapter>
2756 <chapter label="3" id="catalogs">
2757 <title>Chapter Three: Catalogs</title>
2758 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2759 <indexterm><primary>RPI</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</see></indexterm>
2760 <indexterm id='idxrensselaer' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary></indexterm>
2761 <indexterm id='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary><secondary>computer network search engine of</secondary></indexterm>
2762 <indexterm id='idxsearchengines' class='startofrange'><primary>search engines</primary></indexterm>
2763 <indexterm id='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='startofrange'><primary>university computer networks, p2p sharing on</primary></indexterm>
2764 <indexterm id='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>search engines used on</secondary></indexterm>
2765 <para>
2766 <emphasis role='strong'>In the fall</emphasis> of 2002, Jesse Jordan
2767 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2768 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2769 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2770 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2771 was available on the RPI network.
2772 </para>
2773 <para>
2774 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2775 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2776 to information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand
2777 undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school
2778 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2779 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2780 </para>
2781 <para>
2782 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2783 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2784 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2785 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2786 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2787 </para>
2788 <indexterm id='idxgoogle' class='startofrange'><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2789 <para>
2790 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2791 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2792 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2793 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2794 engines can do this even better. The idea of <quote>intranet</quote> search
2795 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2796 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2797 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2798 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2799 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2800 </para>
2801 <indexterm id='idxjordanjesse' class='startofrange'><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2802 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>network file system of</secondary></indexterm>
2803 <para>
2804 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2805 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2806 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2807 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2808 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2809 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2810 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2811 </para>
2812 <indexterm startref='idxgoogle' class='endofrange'/>
2813 <para>
2814 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2815 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2816 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2817 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2818 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2819 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2820 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2821 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2822 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2823 on-line.
2824 </para>
2825 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='endofrange'/>
2826 <para>
2827 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2828 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2829 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2830 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2831 be on users' computers.
2832 </para>
2833 <indexterm startref='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='endofrange'/>
2834 <para>
2835 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2836 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2837 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2838 might have created; university brochures&mdash;basically anything that
2839 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2840 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2841 computer.
2842 </para>
2843 <indexterm><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2844 <indexterm><primary>education</primary><secondary>tinkering as means of</secondary></indexterm>
2845 <para>
2846 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2847 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2848 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and&mdash;so that this
2849 point is absolutely clear&mdash;Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2850 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2851 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2852 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2853 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2854 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2855 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2856 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2857 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2858 supposed to do.
2859 </para>
2860 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
2861 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>against student file sharing</secondary></indexterm>
2862 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
2863 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
2864 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='endofrange'/>
2865 <para>
2866 On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2867 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2868 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2869 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2870 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2871 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2872 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2873 </para>
2874 <para>
2875 <quote>It was absurd,</quote> he told me. <quote>I don't think I did anything
2876 wrong. &hellip; I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2877 engine that I ran or &hellip; what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2878 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2879 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2880 easier to use</quote>&mdash;again, a <emphasis>search engine</emphasis>,
2881 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2882 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2883 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2884 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2885 with music.
2886 </para>
2887 <indexterm startref='idxsearchengines' class='endofrange'/>
2888 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
2889 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>statutory damages of</secondary></indexterm>
2890 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>individual defendants intimidated by</secondary></indexterm>
2891 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages</primary></indexterm>
2892 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>intimidation tactics of</secondary></indexterm>
2893 <para>
2894 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2895 network and had therefore <quote>willfully</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2896 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2897 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2898 <quote>willful infringement,</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2899 call <quote>statutory damages.</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2900 claim $150,000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2901 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2902 Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000.
2903 </para>
2904 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University</primary></indexterm>
2905 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University</primary></indexterm>
2906 <para>
2907 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2908 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2909 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2910 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2911 huge demands for <quote>damages</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2912 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2913 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $100
2914 <emphasis>billion</emphasis>&mdash;six times the
2915 <emphasis>total</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2916 2001.<footnote><para>
2917
2918 <!-- f1 -->
2919 Tim Goral, <quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks:
2920 Suit Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages,</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC</citetitle> 6
2921 (2003): 5, available at 2003 WL 55179443.
2922 </para></footnote>
2923 </para>
2924 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaer' class='endofrange'/>
2925 <para>
2926 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2927 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2928 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2929 $12,000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2930 $12,000 to dismiss the case.
2931 </para>
2932 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt</primary></indexterm>
2933 <para>
2934 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2935 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2936 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2937 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2938 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2939 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2940 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, <quote>You don't want to pay another
2941 visit to a dentist like me.</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2942 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2943 </para>
2944 <indexterm><primary>legal system, attorney costs in</primary></indexterm>
2945 <para>
2946 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2947 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2948 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2949 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2950 at least $250,000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2951 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2952 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2953 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2954 </para>
2955 <para>
2956 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $250,000 and a chance at winning,
2957 or $12,000 and a settlement.
2958 </para>
2959 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
2960 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
2961 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
2962 <para>
2963 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2964 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2965 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2966 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2967 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $1 million a year.
2968 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2969 artist makes $45,900.<footnote><para>
2970 <!-- f2 -->
2971 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001)
2972 (27&ndash;2042&mdash;Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2973 the Arts, <citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon</citetitle> (2000).
2974 </para></footnote>
2975 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2976 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2977 student for running a search engine?<footnote><para>
2978 <!-- f3 -->
2979 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in <quote>KaZaA and Punishment,</quote>
2980 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, A24.
2981 </para></footnote>
2982 </para>
2983 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='endofrange'/>
2984 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='endofrange'/>
2985 <para>
2986 On June 23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2987 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2988 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $15 million lawsuit became an
2989 activist:
2990 </para>
2991 <blockquote>
2992 <para>
2993 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2994 an activist. &hellip; [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2995 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2996 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2997 </para>
2998 </blockquote>
2999 <para>
3000 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
3001 his father told me, Jesse <quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
3002 I. &hellip; He's not a tree hugger. &hellip; I think it's bizarre that they would
3003 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
3004 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.</quote>
3005 </para>
3006 <indexterm startref='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='endofrange'/>
3007 <indexterm startref='idxjordanjesse' class='endofrange'/>
3008 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3009 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='endofrange'/>
3010 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='endofrange'/>
3011 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='endofrange'/>
3012 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
3013 </chapter>
3014 <chapter label="4" id="pirates">
3015 <title>Chapter Four: <quote>Pirates</quote></title>
3016 <indexterm id='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in development of content industry</secondary></indexterm>
3017 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
3018 <para>
3019 <emphasis role='strong'>If <quote>piracy</quote> means</emphasis>
3020 using the creative property of others without their
3021 permission&mdash;if <quote>if value, then right</quote> is
3022 true&mdash;then the history of the content industry is a history of
3023 piracy. Every important sector of <quote>big media</quote>
3024 today&mdash;film, records, radio, and cable TV&mdash;was born of a
3025 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
3026 generation's pirates join this generation's country club&mdash;until
3027 now.
3028 </para>
3029 <section id="film">
3030 <title>Film</title>
3031 <indexterm><primary>Hollywood film industry</primary><seealso>film industry</seealso></indexterm>
3032 <indexterm id='idxhollywoodfilmindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>Hollywood film industry</primary></indexterm>
3033 <indexterm id='idxpatentsonfilmtechnology' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on film technology</secondary></indexterm>
3034 <para>
3035 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.<footnote><para>
3036 <!-- f1 -->
3037 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
3038 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
3039 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 87&ndash;93,
3040 which details Edison's <quote>adventures</quote> with copyright and patent.
3041 </para></footnote>
3042 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
3043 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
3044 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
3045 exercised through a monopoly <quote>trust,</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
3046 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
3047 property&mdash;patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
3048 this creative property
3049 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
3050 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
3051 </para>
3052 <para>
3053 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
3054 </para>
3055 <blockquote>
3056 <para>
3057 A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
3058 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
3059 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
3060 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
3061 summer of 1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
3062 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
3063 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
3064 </para>
3065 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William</primary></indexterm>
3066 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company</primary></indexterm>
3067 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3068 <para>
3069 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
3070 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
3071 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
3072 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
3073 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
3074 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
3075 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
3076 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
3077 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
3078 license was revoked.<footnote><para>
3079 <!-- f2 -->
3080 J. A. Aberdeen, <citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
3081 Picture Producers</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts
3082 posted at <quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
3083 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,</quote> available at
3084 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #11</ulink>. For a
3085 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
3086 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, <quote>From
3087 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
3088 the Propertization of Copyright</quote> (September 2002), University of
3089 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
3090 Working Paper No. 159.
3091 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
3092 </para></footnote>
3093 </para>
3094 </blockquote>
3095 <para>
3096 The Napsters of those days, the <quote>independents,</quote> were
3097 companies like Fox. And no less than today, these independents were
3098 vigorously resisted. <quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery
3099 stolen, and <quote>accidents</quote> resulting in loss of negatives,
3100 equipment, buildings and sometimes life and limb frequently
3101 occurred.</quote><footnote><para>
3102 <!-- f3 -->
3103 Marc Wanamaker, <quote>The First Studios,</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority</citetitle>, archived at
3104 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #12</ulink>.
3105 </para></footnote>
3106 That led the independents to flee the East
3107 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
3108 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
3109 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
3110 did just that.
3111 </para>
3112 <indexterm startref='idxhollywoodfilmindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3113 <para>
3114 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
3115 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
3116 patent holder a truly <quote>limited</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
3117
3118 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
3119 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
3120 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
3121 Edison's creative property.
3122 </para>
3123 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsonfilmtechnology' class='endofrange'/>
3124 </section>
3125 <section id="recordedmusic">
3126 <title>Recorded Music</title>
3127 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
3128 <para>
3129 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
3130 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
3131 </para>
3132 <indexterm id='idxfourneauxhenri' class='startofrange'><primary>Fourneaux, Henri</primary></indexterm>
3133 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil</primary></indexterm>
3134 <para>
3135 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
3136 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
3137 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
3138 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
3139 their music. In other words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
3140 1899 hit <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
3141 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
3142 right to perform it publicly.
3143 </para>
3144 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3145 <para>
3146 But what if I wanted to record <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> using Edison's phonograph
3147 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
3148 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
3149 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
3150 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
3151 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
3152 <quote>public performance</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
3153 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
3154 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
3155 brain are not&mdash;yet&mdash; regulated by copyright law). So if I
3156 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
3157 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
3158 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
3159 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
3160 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
3161 its composer anything.
3162 </para>
3163 <indexterm startref='idxfourneauxhenri' class='endofrange'/>
3164 <indexterm id='idxkittredgealfred' class='startofrange'><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3165 <indexterm id='idxmusicpublishing' class='startofrange'><primary>music publishing</primary></indexterm>
3166 <para>
3167 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
3168 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
3169 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
3170 put it,
3171 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3172 </para>
3173 <blockquote>
3174 <para>
3175 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3176 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3177 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3178 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3179 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3180 rights.<footnote><para>
3181 <!-- f4 -->
3182 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3183 S. 6330 and H.R. 19853 Before the (Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th
3184 Cong. 59, 1st sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3185 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in <citetitle>Legislative History of the
3186 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3187 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3188 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3189 </para></footnote>
3190 </para>
3191 </blockquote>
3192 <indexterm startref='idxkittredgealfred' class='endofrange'/>
3193 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip</primary></indexterm>
3194 <para>
3195 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3196 people's works were <quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3197 genius of American composers,</quote><footnote><para>
3198 <!-- f5 -->
3199 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223
3200 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3201 </para></footnote>
3202 and the <quote>music publishing industry</quote>
3203 was thereby <quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.</quote><footnote><para>
3204 <!-- f6 -->
3205 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226
3206 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3207 </para></footnote>
3208 As John Philip
3209 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, <quote>When they make money
3210 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.</quote><footnote><para>
3211 <!-- f7 -->
3212 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23
3213 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3214 </para></footnote>
3215 </para>
3216 <indexterm startref='idxmusicpublishing' class='endofrange'/>
3217 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company</primary></indexterm>
3218 <indexterm><primary>player pianos</primary></indexterm>
3219 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
3220 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
3221 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
3222 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
3223 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>statutory license system in</secondary></indexterm>
3224 <para>
3225 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3226 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3227 player piano argued that <quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3228 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3229 of anything he had before their introduction.</quote> Rather, the machines
3230 increased the sales of sheet music.<footnote><para>
3231 <!-- f8 -->
3232
3233 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283&ndash;84
3234 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3235 Perforating Company of New York).
3236 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3237 Congress was <quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3238 they represent, and whose servants they are.</quote> <quote>All talk about
3239 <quote>theft,</quote></quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3240 wrote, <quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3241 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3242 statute.</quote><footnote><para>
3243 <!-- f9 -->
3244 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared
3245 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3246 Graphophone Company Association).
3247 </para></footnote>
3248 </para>
3249 <indexterm><primary>cover songs</primary></indexterm>
3250 <para>
3251 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3252 <emphasis>and</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3253 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the <quote>mechanical
3254 reproductions</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3255 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3256 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3257 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3258 recorded once. This is the part of
3259
3260 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3261 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3262 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3263 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3264 </para>
3265 <indexterm id='idxcompulsorylicense' class='startofrange'><primary>compulsory license</primary></indexterm>
3266 <indexterm id='idxstatutorylicenses' class='startofrange'><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
3267 <para>
3268 American law ordinarily calls this a <quote>compulsory license,</quote> but I will
3269 refer to it as a <quote>statutory license.</quote> A statutory license is a license
3270 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3271 Copyright Act in 1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3272 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3273 the fee set by the statute.
3274 </para>
3275 <indexterm id='idxgrishamjohn' class='startofrange'><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
3276 <para>
3277 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3278 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3279 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3280 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3281 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3282 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3283 Grisham.
3284 </para>
3285 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='endofrange'/>
3286 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3287 <para>
3288 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3289 thus, in effect, the law <emphasis>subsidizes</emphasis> the recording
3290 industry through a kind of piracy&mdash;by giving recording artists a
3291 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3292 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3293 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3294 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3295 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3296 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3297 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3298 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3299 creativity.<footnote><para>
3300
3301 <!-- f10 -->
3302 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and
3303 H.R. 11794 Before the (Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st
3304 sess., 217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3305 in <citetitle>Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3306 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3307 </para></footnote>
3308 </para>
3309 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='endofrange'/>
3310 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3311 <indexterm startref='idxgrishamjohn' class='endofrange'/>
3312 <para>
3313 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3314 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3315 records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3316 relates,
3317 </para>
3318 <blockquote>
3319 <para>
3320 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3321 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3322 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3323 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3324 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3325 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3326 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3327 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3328 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before 1909 and
3329 the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3330 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3331 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3332 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3333 choice.<footnote><para>
3334 <!-- f11 -->
3335 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee
3336 on the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8
3337 March 1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3338 this report.</para></footnote>
3339 </para>
3340 </blockquote>
3341 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='endofrange'/>
3342 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='endofrange'/>
3343 <indexterm startref='idxcompulsorylicense' class='endofrange'/>
3344 <indexterm startref='idxstatutorylicenses' class='endofrange'/>
3345 <para>
3346 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3347 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3348 </para>
3349 </section>
3350 <section id="radio">
3351 <title>Radio</title>
3352 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
3353 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
3354 <para>
3355 Radio was also born of piracy.
3356 </para>
3357 <para>
3358 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3359 <quote>public performance</quote> of the composer's work.<footnote><para>
3360 <!-- f12 -->
3361 See 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning,
3362 record companies printed <quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast</quote> and other
3363 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3364 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3365 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3366 station. See <citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Whiteman</citetitle>, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd
3367 Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3368 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3369 Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 281.
3370 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned</primary></indexterm>
3371 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3372 </para></footnote>
3373 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3374 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3375 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3376 </para>
3377 <indexterm id='idxradiomusicrecordingsplayedon' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>music recordings played on</secondary></indexterm>
3378 <para>
3379 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3380 copy of the <emphasis>composer's</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3381 also performing a copy of the <emphasis>recording artist's</emphasis>
3382 work. It's one thing to have <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> sung on the radio by the
3383 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3384 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3385 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3386 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3387 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3388 music for his work.
3389 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
3390
3391 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3392 </para>
3393 <para>
3394 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3395 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3396 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3397 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3398 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3399 of playing the song.
3400 </para>
3401 <indexterm id='idxmadonna' class='startofrange'><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3402 <para>
3403 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3404 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3405 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3406 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3407 </para>
3408 <para>
3409 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3410 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3411 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3412 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3413 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3414 <quote>protected</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3415 <emphasis>pirate</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3416 her anything.
3417 </para>
3418 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='endofrange'/>
3419 <indexterm startref='idxradiomusicrecordingsplayedon' class='endofrange'/>
3420 <indexterm startref='idxmadonna' class='endofrange'/>
3421 <para>
3422 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3423 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3424 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3425 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3426 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3427 to take something for nothing.
3428 </para>
3429 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='endofrange'/>
3430 </section>
3431 <section id="cabletv">
3432 <title>Cable TV</title>
3433 <indexterm id='idxcabletelevision' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
3434 <para>
3435 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3436 </para>
3437 <para>
3438 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3439 television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3440 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3441 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3442 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3443 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3444 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3445 did&mdash; Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3446 give away.
3447 </para>
3448 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas</primary></indexterm>
3449 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin</primary></indexterm>
3450 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3451 <para>
3452 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3453 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3454 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.</quote><footnote><para>
3455 <!-- f13 -->
3456 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the
3457 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3458 Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966)
3459 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3460 Commission).
3461 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3462 </para></footnote>
3463 There may have been a <quote>public interest</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3464 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3465 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, <quote>Does public
3466 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?</quote><footnote><para>
3467 <!-- f14 -->
3468 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3469 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3470 </para></footnote>
3471 As another broadcaster put it,
3472 </para>
3473 <blockquote>
3474 <para>
3475 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3476 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3477 paid for.<footnote><para>
3478 <!-- f15 -->
3479 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3480 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3481 </para></footnote>
3482 </para>
3483 </blockquote>
3484 <para>
3485 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3486 </para>
3487 <blockquote>
3488 <para>
3489 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3490 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3491 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3492 think there are harsher words which would fit it.<footnote><para>
3493 <!-- f16 -->
3494 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3495 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3496 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3497 </para></footnote>
3498 </para>
3499 </blockquote>
3500 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3501 <para>
3502 These were <quote>free-ride[rs],</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3503 Heston said, who were <quote>depriving actors of
3504 compensation.</quote><footnote><para>
3505 <!-- f17 -->
3506 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3507 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3508 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3509 </para>
3510 </footnote>
3511 </para>
3512 <para>
3513 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3514 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3515 </para>
3516 <blockquote>
3517 <para>
3518 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3519 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3520 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3521 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. &hellip; The
3522
3523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3524 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3525 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.<footnote><para>
3526 <!-- f18 -->
3527 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M.
3528 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3529 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3530 </para></footnote>
3531 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3532 </para>
3533 </blockquote>
3534 <para>
3535 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3536 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3537 </para>
3538 <para>
3539 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3540 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they <quote>pirated.</quote>
3541 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3542 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3543 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3544 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3545 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3546 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3547 companies thus built their empire in part upon a <quote>piracy</quote> of the value
3548 created by broadcasters' content.
3549 </para>
3550 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3551 <indexterm startref='idxcabletelevision' class='endofrange'/>
3552 <para>
3553 <emphasis role='strong'>These separate stories</emphasis> sing a
3554 common theme. If <quote>piracy</quote> means using value from someone
3555 else's creative property without permission from that creator&mdash;as
3556 it is increasingly described today<footnote><para>
3557 <!-- f19 -->
3558 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, <citetitle>The Engine
3559 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet&mdash;The Myth of Free
3560 Information</citetitle>, available at
3561 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #13</ulink>. <quote>The
3562 threat of piracy&mdash;the use of someone else's creative work without
3563 permission or compensation&mdash;has grown with the Internet.</quote>
3564 </para></footnote>
3565 &mdash; then <emphasis>every</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3566 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3567 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV. &hellip; The list is long and
3568 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3569 last. Every generation&mdash;until now.
3570 </para>
3571 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3572 </section>
3573 </chapter>
3574 <chapter label="5" id="piracy">
3575 <title>Chapter Five: <quote>Piracy</quote></title>
3576 <para>
3577 <emphasis role='strong'>There is piracy</emphasis> of copyrighted
3578 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3579 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3580 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3581 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3582 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3583 </para>
3584 <para>
3585 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of <quote>taking</quote>
3586 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3587 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3588 taking <quote>piracy,</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3589 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3590 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3591 has so often done in the past.
3592 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3593 </para>
3594 <section id="piracy-i">
3595 <title>Piracy I</title>
3596 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3597 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3598 <para>
3599 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3600 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3601 content, copy it, and sell it&mdash;all without the permission of a copyright
3602 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion
3603 every year to physical piracy<footnote><para>
3604 <!-- f1 -->
3605 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), <citetitle>The
3606 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003</citetitle>, July 2003, available
3607 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #14</ulink>. See
3608 also Ben Hunt, <quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3609 Times</citetitle>, 14 February 2003, 11.
3610 </para></footnote>
3611 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3612 estimates that it loses $3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3613 </para>
3614 <para>
3615 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3616 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3617 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3618 This piracy is wrong.
3619 </para>
3620 <para>
3621 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3622 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3623 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3624 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3625 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3626 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3627 of our existence, treated as right.
3628 </para>
3629 <para>
3630 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3631 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3632 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3633 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3634 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3635 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3636 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3637 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3638 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3639 </para>
3640 <para>
3641 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3642 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3643 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3644 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3645 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3646 similar childhood.
3647 </para>
3648 <para>
3649 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3650 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3651 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3652 of intellectual property law.<footnote><para>
3653 <!-- f2 -->
3654 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3655 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The
3656 New Press, 2003), 10&ndash;13, 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3657 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3658 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3659 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3660 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3661 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3662 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3663 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3664 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3665 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3666 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3667 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3668 TRIPS framework.
3669 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents</primary></indexterm>
3670 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
3671 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3672 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3673 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3674 is wrong.
3675 </para>
3676 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3677 <para>
3678 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3679 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3680 to American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3681 bought those American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any
3682 less money than they otherwise would have had.<footnote><para>
3683 <!-- f3 -->
3684 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3685 Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002),
3686 144&ndash;90. <quote>In some instances &hellip; the impact of piracy on the
3687 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3688 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3689 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3690 pirating were not an option.</quote> Ibid., 149.
3691 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3692 </para></footnote>
3693 </para>
3694 <para>
3695 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3696 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3697 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3698 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3699 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes &amp; Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3700 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?</quote>
3701 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes &amp;
3702 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3703 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3704 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3705 piracy of the tangible.
3706 </para>
3707 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'/>
3708 <para>
3709 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3710 property right of a very special sort, it <emphasis>is</emphasis> a
3711 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3712 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3713 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3714 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3715 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3716 give people the right to <quote>take</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3717 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3718
3719 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3720 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3721 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3722 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3723 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3724 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what <quote>property</quote> means.
3725 </para>
3726 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3727 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
3728 <indexterm><primary>open-source software</primary><see>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</see></indexterm>
3729 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
3730 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3731 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3732 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of</secondary></indexterm>
3733 <indexterm><primary>Windows</primary></indexterm>
3734 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>international software piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3735 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of</secondary></indexterm>
3736 <para>
3737 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3738 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese <quote>steal</quote>
3739 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3740 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3741 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3742 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3743 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3744 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3745 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3746 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3747 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3748 </para>
3749 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
3750 <para>
3751 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3752 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3753 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3754 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3755 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3756 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3757 </para>
3758 <indexterm><primary>Netscape</primary></indexterm>
3759 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer</primary></indexterm>
3760 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3761 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3762 <para>
3763 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3764 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3765 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3766 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3767 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3768 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3769 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3770 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3771 what&mdash;at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3772 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3773 violating the law is still wrong.
3774 </para>
3775 <para>
3776 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3777 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3778 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3779 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3780 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3781 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3782 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3783 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3784 is flat out wrong.
3785 </para>
3786 <para>
3787 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3788 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is. Or
3789 at least, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3790 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of <quote>piracy</quote> are useful
3791 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3792 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3793 <quote>piracy</quote> in that sense of the term.
3794 </para>
3795 <para>
3796 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3797 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3798 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3799 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3800 </para>
3801 <para>
3802 For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3803 controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it
3804 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable
3805 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3806 </para>
3807 <para>
3808 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3809 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3810 sharing to survive.
3811 </para>
3812 </section>
3813 <section id="piracy-ii">
3814 <title>Piracy II</title>
3815 <para>
3816 The key to the <quote>piracy</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that <quote>rob[s]
3817 the author of [his] profit.</quote><footnote><para>
3818 <!-- f4 -->
3819 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777).
3820 </para></footnote>
3821 This means we must determine whether
3822 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3823 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3824 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3825 author of his profit.
3826 </para>
3827 <para>
3828 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn</primary></indexterm>
3829 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary><seealso>creativity</seealso></indexterm>
3830 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3831 <indexterm id='idxnapster' class='startofrange'><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
3832 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3833 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3834 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3835 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well<footnote><para>
3836 <!-- f5 -->
3837 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3838 See Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3839 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle> (New York:
3840 HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3841 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3842 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3843 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3844 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3845 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 89&ndash;92, 139.
3846
3847 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
3848 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3849 put together components that had been developed independently.
3850 </para>
3851 <para>
3852 <indexterm><primary>Kazaa</primary></indexterm>
3853 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>number of registrations on</secondary></indexterm>
3854 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>replacement of</secondary></indexterm>
3855 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999,
3856 Napster amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After
3857 eighteen months, there were close to 80 million registered users of the
3858 system.<footnote><para>
3859 <!-- f6 -->
3860 See Carolyn Lochhead, <quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,</quote> <citetitle>San
3861 Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24 September 2002, A1; <quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,</quote>
3862 <citetitle>New Scientist</citetitle>, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Napster Names CEO,
3863 Secures New Financing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 23 May 2003, C1;
3864 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton,
3865 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet</quote> (London) <citetitle>Times</citetitle>, 26 July 2002, 18.
3866 </para></footnote>
3867 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3868 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3869 boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3870 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3871 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3872 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend&mdash;
3873 or your 20,000 best friends.
3874 </para>
3875 <indexterm startref='idxnapster' class='endofrange'/>
3876 <para>
3877 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3878 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3879 September 2002 estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded
3880 music&mdash;28 percent of Americans older than 12.<footnote><para>
3881
3882 <!-- f7 -->
3883 See Ipsos-Insight, <citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution</citetitle>
3884 (September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3885 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have
3886 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3887 </para></footnote>
3888 A survey by the NPD group quoted in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>
3889 estimated that 43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3890 exchange content in May 2003.<footnote><para>
3891 <!-- f8 -->
3892 Amy Harmon, <quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,</quote> <citetitle>New
3893 York Times</citetitle>, 6 June 2003, A1.
3894 </para></footnote>
3895 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3896 massive quantity of content is being <quote>taken</quote> on these networks. The
3897 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3898 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3899 </para>
3900 <para>
3901 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3902 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3903 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3904 complicated than one might think. So consider&mdash;a bit more
3905 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3906 do&mdash;the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3907 of harm it entails.
3908 </para>
3909 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingfourtypesof' class='startofrange'><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>four types of</secondary></indexterm>
3910 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>range of content on</secondary></indexterm>
3911 <para>
3912 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3913 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3914 different kinds into four types.
3915 </para>
3916 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
3917 <listitem>
3918 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3919 <para>
3920 <!-- A. -->
3921 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3922 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3923 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3924 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3925 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3926 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3927 users who download instead of purchasing.
3928 </para></listitem>
3929 <listitem><para>
3930 <!-- B. -->
3931 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3932 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3933 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3934 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3935 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3936 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3937 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3938 music purchased.
3939 </para></listitem>
3940 <listitem><para>
3941 <!-- C. -->
3942 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3943 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3944 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3945 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3946 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3947 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3948 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend <quote>recalling</quote> old
3949 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3950 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3951 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3952 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero&mdash;the same
3953 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to
3954 a local collector.
3955 </para></listitem>
3956 <listitem><para>
3957 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3958 <!-- D. -->
3959 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3960 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3961 wants to give away.
3962 </para></listitem>
3963 </orderedlist>
3964 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingfourtypesof' class='endofrange'/>
3965 <para>
3966 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3967 </para>
3968 <para>
3969 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3970 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3971 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3972 harmful.<footnote><para>
3973 <!-- f9 -->
3974 See Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle>, 148&ndash;49.
3975 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3976 </para></footnote>
3977 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3978 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3979 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3980 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3981 answer&mdash;and certainly much more difficult than the current
3982 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3983 </para>
3984 <para>
3985 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3986 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3987 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3988 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3989 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of <quote>theft</quote> that is
3990 <quote>devastating</quote> the industry.
3991 </para>
3992 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
3993 <para>
3994 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3995 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3996 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3997 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3998 &amp; Young put it, <quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3999 technology, the labels fought it.</quote><footnote><para>
4000 <!-- f10 -->
4001 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary></indexterm>
4002 <indexterm><primary>DAT (digital audio tape)</primary></indexterm>
4003 See Cap Gemini Ernst &amp; Young, <citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
4004 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis</citetitle> (2003), 3. This report
4005 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
4006 practice of cassette taping in the 1970s, including an advertising
4007 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption <quote>Home taping
4008 is killing music.</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
4009 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
4010 behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
4011 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
4012 Assessment, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law</citetitle>,
4013 OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
4014 October 1989), 145&ndash;56. </para></footnote>
4015 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
4016 when record sales fell by 11.4 percent in 1981, the industry claimed
4017 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
4018 regulating technology was the answer.
4019 </para>
4020 <indexterm><primary>MTV</primary></indexterm>
4021 <para>
4022 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity to
4023 enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
4024 turnaround. <quote>In the end,</quote> Cap Gemini concludes,
4025 <quote>the <quote>crisis</quote> &hellip; was not the fault of the
4026 tapers&mdash;who did not [stop after MTV came into
4027 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
4028 being]&mdash;but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
4029 innovation at the major labels.</quote><footnote><para>
4030 <!-- f11 -->
4031 U.S. Congress, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying</citetitle>, 4.
4032 </para></footnote>
4033 </para>
4034 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'/>
4035 <para>
4036 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
4037 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
4038 the industry in particular, and society in general&mdash;or at least
4039 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
4040 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
4041 VCR&mdash;the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
4042 harmful. The question is also <emphasis>how</emphasis> harmful type A
4043 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
4044 </para>
4045 <para>
4046 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
4047 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
4048 The <quote>net harm</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
4049 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
4050 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
4051 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
4052 therefore have little <emphasis>static</emphasis> reason to resist
4053 them.
4054
4055 </para>
4056 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>sales levels of</secondary></indexterm>
4057 <para>
4058 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
4059 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
4060 actually suggest it might be close.
4061 </para>
4062 <para>
4063 In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9 percent,
4064 from 882 million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7
4065 percent.<footnote><para>
4066 <!-- f12 -->
4067 See Recording Industry Association of America, <citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics</citetitle>,
4068 available at
4069 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #15</ulink>. A later
4070 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
4071 Association of America, <citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy</citetitle>, 25 June 2003,
4072 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
4073 #16</ulink>: <quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
4074 have fallen by 26 percent from 1.16 billion units in to 860 million
4075 units in 2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
4076 of sales, revenues are down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in to $12.6
4077 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
4078 industry worldwide has gone from a $39 billion industry in 2000 down
4079 to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
4080 shipments).</quote>
4081 </para></footnote>
4082 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
4083 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
4084 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
4085 than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That no
4086 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
4087 account for at least some of the loss. <quote>From 1999 to 2001, the average
4088 price of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19.</quote><footnote>
4089 <!-- f13 -->
4090 <para>
4091 Jane Black, <quote>Big Music's Broken Record,</quote> BusinessWeek online, 13
4092 February 2003, available at
4093 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #17</ulink>.
4094 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane</primary></indexterm>
4095 </para>
4096 </footnote>
4097 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
4098 the decline. As Jane Black of <citetitle>BusinessWeek</citetitle> notes, <quote>The
4099 soundtrack to the film <citetitle>High Fidelity</citetitle> has a list price of
4100 $18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
4101 $19.99.</quote><footnote><para>
4102 <!-- f14 -->
4103 Ibid.
4104 </para></footnote>
4105 </para>
4106 <para>
4107
4108 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
4109 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
4110 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
4111 that the RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
4112 estimates that 2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
4113 although 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4114 free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 percent.
4115 </para>
4116 <para>
4117 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
4118 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
4119 The recording industry constantly asks, <quote>What's the difference between
4120 downloading a song and stealing a CD?</quote>&mdash;but their own numbers
4121 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
4122 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
4123 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
4124 downloads. If every download were a lost sale&mdash;if every use of
4125 Kazaa <quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit</quote>&mdash;then the industry
4126 would have suffered a 100 percent drop in sales last year, not a 7
4127 percent drop. If 2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4128 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, then there is
4129 a huge difference between <quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.</quote>
4130 </para>
4131 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'/>
4132 <para>
4133 These are the harms&mdash;alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
4134 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
4135 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
4136 these costs?
4137 </para>
4138 <para>
4139 One benefit is type C sharing&mdash;making available content that
4140 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
4141 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
4142 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
4143 available.<footnote><para>
4144 <!-- f15 -->
4145 By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels
4146 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
4147 Law&mdash;Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
4148 Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April
4149 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
4150 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #18</ulink>.
4151 </para></footnote>
4152 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
4153 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
4154 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
4155 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
4156 sense <emphasis>to the company</emphasis> to make it available.
4157 </para>
4158 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4159 <indexterm><primary>used record sales</primary></indexterm>
4160 <para>
4161 In real space&mdash;long before the Internet&mdash;the market had a simple
4162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
4163 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
4164 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
4165 today.<footnote><para>
4166 <!-- f16 -->
4167 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4168 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
4169 in existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the
4170 United States, an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter
4171 Press, <citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
4172 Market</citetitle> (2002), available at
4173 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #19</ulink>. Used
4174 records accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See National
4175 Association of Recording Merchandisers, <quote>2002 Annual Survey
4176 Results,</quote> available at
4177 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #20</ulink>.
4178 </para></footnote>
4179 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
4180 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
4181 content, <emphasis>even if the content is still under
4182 copyright</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
4183 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
4184 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
4185 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
4186 the content they sell.
4187 </para>
4188 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
4189 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard</primary></indexterm>
4190 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
4191 <para>
4192 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
4193 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
4194 the content available isn't making money from making the content
4195 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
4196 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
4197 when someone shares my 1949 recording of Bernstein's <quote>Two Love Songs,</quote>
4198 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
4199 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
4200 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
4201 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
4202 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
4203 </para>
4204 <para>
4205 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
4206 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
4207 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
4208 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
4209 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
4210 shut as well?
4211 </para>
4212 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
4213 <indexterm><primary>Doctorow, Cory</primary></indexterm>
4214 <indexterm><primary>Down and Out in the Magic Kingdom (Doctorow)</primary></indexterm>
4215 <para>
4216 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4217 type D sharing to occur&mdash;the sharing of content that copyright owners
4218 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4219 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4220 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
4221 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4222
4223 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4224 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4225 would be a great advertisement for the <quote>real</quote> book. People would read
4226 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4227 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4228 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4229 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4230 great book!)
4231 </para>
4232 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'/>
4233 <para>
4234 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4235 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4236 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4237 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4238 </para>
4239 <para>
4240 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4241 understandably says, <quote>This is how much we've lost,</quote> we must also ask,
4242 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4243 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4244 unavailable?</quote>
4245 </para>
4246 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson' class='endofrange'/>
4247 <para>
4248 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4249 chapter, much of the <quote>piracy</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4250 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4251 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="pirates"/>, much of
4252 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4253 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4254 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4255 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4256 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4257 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4258 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4259 found only with time.
4260 </para>
4261 <para>
4262 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4263 just what you call type A sharing?</quote>
4264 </para>
4265 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitszerotolerancein' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>zero tolerance in</secondary></indexterm>
4266 <indexterm id='idxnapsterinfringingmaterialblockedby' class='startofrange'><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>infringing material blocked by</secondary></indexterm>
4267 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharinginfringementprotectionsin' class='startofrange'><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>infringement protections in</secondary></indexterm>
4268 <para>
4269 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The effect
4270 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4271 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4272 Napster case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4273 developed a technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of
4274 identified
4275
4276 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4277 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4
4278 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4279 <quote>down to zero.</quote><footnote><para>
4280 <!-- f17 -->
4281 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34-
4282 35 (N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183
4283 MHP, available at
4284
4285 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #21</ulink>. For an
4286 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4287 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster</citetitle> (New
4288 York: Crown Business, 2003), 269&ndash;82.
4289 </para></footnote>
4290 </para>
4291 <indexterm startref='idxnapsterinfringingmaterialblockedby' class='endofrange'/>
4292 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharinginfringementprotectionsin' class='endofrange'/>
4293 <para>
4294 If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4295 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4296 assure that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance
4297 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of
4298 VCRs or 100 percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns
4299 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4300 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4301 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4302 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4303 </para>
4304 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitszerotolerancein' class='endofrange'/>
4305 <para>
4306 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4307 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4308 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4309 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4310 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4311 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4312 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4313 </para>
4314 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
4315 <indexterm><primary>composers, copyright protections of</primary></indexterm>
4316 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4317 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
4318 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
4319 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
4320 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>music recordings played on</secondary></indexterm>
4321 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
4322 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright protections in</secondary></indexterm>
4323 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
4324 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
4325 <indexterm><primary>composer's rights vs. producers' rights in</primary></indexterm>
4326 <para>
4327 So, as we've seen, when <quote>mechanical reproduction</quote> threatened the
4328 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4329 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4330 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4331 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4332 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4333 complained to Congress that their <quote>creative property</quote> was not being
4334 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4335 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4336 benefit was enough.
4337 </para>
4338 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
4339 <para>
4340 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4341 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4342 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4343 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4344 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4345 price.
4346 </para>
4347 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='endofrange'/>
4348 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>two central goals of</secondary></indexterm>
4349 <para>
4350
4351 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4352 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4353 pianos, served two important goals&mdash;indeed, the two central goals
4354 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4355 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4356 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4357 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4358 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4359 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4360 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4361 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4362 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4363 Congress chose a path that would assure
4364 <emphasis>compensation</emphasis> without giving the past
4365 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4366 </para>
4367 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='endofrange'/>
4368 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='endofrange'/>
4369 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'/>
4370 <indexterm id='idxbetamax' class='startofrange'><primary>Betamax</primary></indexterm>
4371 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
4372 <indexterm id='idxsonybetamaxtechnologydevelopedby' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Betamax technology developed by</secondary></indexterm>
4373 <para>
4374 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4375 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4376 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4377 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4378 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4379 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4380 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4381 <quote>record</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4382 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4383 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4384 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4385 </para>
4386 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='endofrange'/>
4387 <para>
4388 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4389 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4390 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4391 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4392 machine to copy only if there were a special <quote>copy me</quote> signal on the
4393 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4394 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4395 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4396 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4397 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4398 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4399 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4400 for the architecture it chose.
4401 </para>
4402 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4403 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on VCR technology</secondary></indexterm>
4404 <indexterm id='idxvalentijackonvcrtechnology' class='startofrange'><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>on VCR technology</secondary></indexterm>
4405 <para>
4406 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4407 champion. Valenti called VCRs <quote>tapeworms.</quote> He warned,
4408 <quote>When there are 20, 30, 40 million of these VCRs in the land, we
4409 will be invaded by millions of <quote>tapeworms,</quote> eating away
4410 at the very heart and essence of the most precious asset the copyright
4411 owner has, his copyright.</quote><footnote><para>
4412 <!-- f18 -->
4413 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4414 S. 1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st
4415 and 2nd sess., 459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4416 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4417 </para></footnote>
4418 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4419 creative judgment,</quote> he told Congress, <quote>to understand the devastation
4420 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4421 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4422 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4423 and plain common sense.</quote><footnote><para>
4424 <!-- f19 -->
4425 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475.
4426 </para></footnote>
4427 Indeed, as surveys would later show, 45
4428 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more<footnote><para>
4429 <!-- f20 -->
4430 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 480 F. Supp. 429,
4431 (C.D. Cal., 1979).
4432 </para></footnote>
4433 &mdash; a use the Court would later hold was not <quote>fair.</quote> By
4434 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4435 copyright infringement without creating a mechanism to compensate
4436 copyright owners,</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would <quote>take from the
4437 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4438 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4439 profit from its reproduction.</quote><footnote><para>
4440 <!-- f21 -->
4441 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony
4442 of Jack Valenti).
4443 </para></footnote>
4444 </para>
4445 <indexterm startref='idxbetamax' class='endofrange'/>
4446 <indexterm startref='idxsonybetamaxtechnologydevelopedby' class='endofrange'/>
4447 <para>
4448 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4449 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4450 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction&mdash;leading Judge Alex
4451 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the <quote>Hollywood
4452 Circuit</quote>&mdash;held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4453 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4454 rule, this totally familiar technology&mdash;which Jack Valenti had
4455 called <quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry</quote> (worse
4456 yet, it was a <emphasis>Japanese</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4457 American film industry)&mdash;was an illegal
4458 technology.<footnote><para>
4459 <!-- f22 -->
4460 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th Cir.
4461 1981).
4462 </para></footnote>
4463 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex</primary></indexterm>
4464 </para>
4465 <indexterm startref='idxvalentijackonvcrtechnology' class='endofrange'/>
4466 <para>
4467 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4468
4469 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4470 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4471 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4472 Court wrote,
4473 </para>
4474 <blockquote>
4475 <para>
4476 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4477 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4478 market
4479 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4480 authority
4481 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4482 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4483 implicated
4484 by such new technology.<footnote><para>
4485 <!-- f23 -->
4486 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417, 431 (1984).
4487 </para></footnote>
4488 </para>
4489 </blockquote>
4490 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='endofrange'/>
4491 <para>
4492 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4493 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4494 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4495 enough, this <quote>taking</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4496 together, a pattern is clear:
4497 </para>
4498
4499 <informaltable id="t1">
4500 <tgroup cols="4" align="left">
4501 <thead>
4502 <row>
4503 <entry>CASE</entry>
4504 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS <quote>PIRATED</quote></entry>
4505 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS</entry>
4506 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS</entry>
4507 </row>
4508 </thead>
4509 <tbody>
4510 <row>
4511 <entry>Recordings</entry>
4512 <entry>Composers</entry>
4513 <entry>No protection</entry>
4514 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4515 </row>
4516 <row>
4517 <entry>Radio</entry>
4518 <entry>Recording artists</entry>
4519 <entry>N/A</entry>
4520 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4521 </row>
4522 <row>
4523 <entry>Cable TV</entry>
4524 <entry>Broadcasters</entry>
4525 <entry>No protection</entry>
4526 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4527 </row>
4528 <row>
4529 <entry>VCR</entry>
4530 <entry>Film creators</entry>
4531 <entry>No protection</entry>
4532 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4533 </row>
4534 </tbody>
4535 </tgroup>
4536 </informaltable>
4537 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'/>
4538 <para>
4539 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4540 way content was distributed.<footnote><para>
4541 <indexterm><primary>DAT (digital audio tape)</primary></indexterm>
4542 <!-- f24 -->
4543 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4544 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4545 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4546 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4547 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4548 1992 (Title 17 of the <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat.
4549 4237, codified at 17 U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4550 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4551 Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 71. See also Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,</quote>
4552 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 293&ndash;96.
4553 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
4554 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
4555 </para></footnote>
4556 In each case, throughout our history,
4557 that change meant that someone got a <quote>free ride</quote> on someone else's
4558 work.
4559 </para>
4560 <para>
4561 In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4562 Congress eliminate all free riding. In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of
4563 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4564 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4565 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of <quote>piracy.</quote>
4566 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4567 the behavior of the <quote>pirates.</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4568 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4569 interests at stake.
4570 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4571 </para>
4572 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
4573 <para>
4574 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4575 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4576 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4577 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4578 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4579 regulated?
4580 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4581 to $15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4582 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4583 permission to record a song?
4584 </para>
4585 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on balance of interests in copyright law</secondary></indexterm>
4586 <para>
4587 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4588 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4589 copyright <quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4590 over all possible uses of his work.</quote><footnote><para>
4591 <!-- f25 -->
4592 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
4593 (1984).
4594 </para></footnote>
4595 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4596 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4597 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4598 balancing has historically been done <emphasis>after</emphasis> a
4599 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4600 facilitate the distribution of content.
4601 </para>
4602 <para>
4603 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4604 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4605 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4606 should not become a tool for <quote>stealing</quote> from artists. But neither
4607 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4608 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4609 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4610 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4611 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4612 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4613 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4614 public interest that innovation continue.
4615 </para>
4616 <para>
4617
4618 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4619 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4620 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4621 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4622 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4623 efficient. Yet these <quote>potential public benefits,</quote> as John Schwartz
4624 writes in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, <quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4625 fight.</quote><footnote><para>
4626 <!-- f26 -->
4627 John Schwartz, <quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4628 Echoes Past Efforts,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 September 2003, C3.
4629 </para></footnote>
4630 </para>
4631 <para>
4632 <emphasis role='strong'>Yet when anyone</emphasis> begins to talk
4633 about <quote>balance,</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4634 argument. <quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4635 incentives,</quote> they say, <quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4636 content,</quote> the warriors insist, <quote>is our
4637 <emphasis>property</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4638 <quote>rebalance</quote> our property rights? Do you have to wait
4639 before calling the police when your car has been stolen? And why
4640 should Congress deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do
4641 we ask whether the car thief had a good use for the car before we
4642 arrest him?</quote>
4643 </para>
4644 <para>
4645 <quote>It is <emphasis>our property</emphasis>,</quote> the warriors
4646 insist. <quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4647 is protected.</quote>
4648 </para>
4649 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4650 </section>
4651 </chapter>
4652 </part>
4653 <part id="c-property">
4654 <title><quote>Property</quote></title>
4655 <partintro>
4656 <para>
4657
4658 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4659 <emphasis role='strong'>The copyright warriors</emphasis> are right: A
4660 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4661 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4662 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4663 that partially determine the price she can get.
4664 </para>
4665 <para>
4666 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a <quote>property</quote> right is a
4667 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4668 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4669 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4670 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4671 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4672 when I take the good <emphasis>idea</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4673 table in the backyard&mdash;by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4674 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4675 then?
4676 </para>
4677 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
4678 <para>
4679 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4680 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4681 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4682 in the ordinary case&mdash;indeed, in practically every case except for a
4683 narrow
4684 range of exceptions&mdash;ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4685 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress&mdash;though I
4686 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4687 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4688 when I copy the way someone else dresses), <quote>He who receives an idea
4689 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4690 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.</quote><footnote><para>
4691 <!-- f1 -->
4692 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in
4693 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson</citetitle>, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4694 Ellery Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333&ndash;34.
4695 </para></footnote>
4696 </para>
4697 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>intangibility of</secondary></indexterm>
4698 <para>
4699 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4700 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4701 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4702 expression
4703 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4704 property.
4705 </para>
4706 <para>
4707 But how, and to what extent, and in what form&mdash;the details,
4708 in other words&mdash;matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4709 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4710 <quote>property</quote> in its proper context.<footnote><para>
4711 <!-- f2 -->
4712 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4713 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4714 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4715 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4716 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4717 Adam Mossoff, <quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,</quote>
4718 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review</citetitle> 45 (2003): 373, 429 n. 241.
4719 </para></footnote>
4720 </para>
4721 <para>
4722 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4723 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4724 <quote>copyright material is property</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4725 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4726 these stories, the significance of this true
4727 statement&mdash;<quote>copyright material is property</quote>&mdash; will be a bit
4728 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4729 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4730 </para>
4731 </partintro>
4732
4733 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4734 <chapter label="6" id="founders">
4735 <title>Chapter Six: Founders</title>
4736 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for</secondary></indexterm>
4737 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
4738 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
4739 <indexterm id='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='startofrange'><primary>England, copyright laws developed in</primary></indexterm>
4740 <indexterm id='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='startofrange'><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>history of copyright law in</secondary></indexterm>
4741 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4742 <indexterm><primary>Henry V</primary></indexterm>
4743 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4744 <indexterm id='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='startofrange'><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4745 <para>
4746 <emphasis role='strong'>William Shakespeare</emphasis> wrote
4747 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> in 1595. The play was first
4748 published in 1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4749 written. He would continue to write plays through 1613, and the plays
4750 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4751 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4752 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4753 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4754 Henry V: <quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4755 clichés.</quote>
4756 </para>
4757 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4758 <indexterm id='idxtonsonjacob' class='startofrange'><primary>Tonson, Jacob</primary></indexterm>
4759 <para>
4760 In 1774, almost 180 years after <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> was written, the
4761 <quote>copy-right</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4762 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.<footnote><para>
4763 <!-- f1 -->
4764 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben</primary></indexterm>
4765 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John</primary></indexterm>
4766 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4767 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4768 handsome <quote>definitive editions</quote> of classic works. In addition to <citetitle>Romeo and
4769 Juliet</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4770 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4771 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, <quote>Jacob Tonson,
4772 Bookseller,</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar</citetitle> 61:3 (1992): 424&ndash;31.
4773 </para></footnote>
4774 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4775 the Conger<footnote><para>
4776 <!-- f2 -->
4777 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle> (Nashville:
4778 Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 151&ndash;52.
4779 </para></footnote>
4780 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4781 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the <quote>copy</quote> of
4782 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4783 that no
4784 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4785 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4786 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4787 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4788 </para>
4789 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4790 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4791 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
4792 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4793 <para>
4794 Now, there's something puzzling about the year 1774 to anyone who
4795 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4796 history of copyright is 1710, the year that the British Parliament
4797 adopted the first <quote>copyright</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4798 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4799 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4800 works already published by 1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4801 additional years.<footnote><para>
4802 <!-- f3 -->
4803 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4804 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4805 <quote>copyright law.</quote> See Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 40.
4806 </para></footnote> Under this law, <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> should have been
4807 free in 1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4808 Tonson's control in 1774?
4809 </para>
4810 <indexterm startref='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='endofrange'/>
4811 <indexterm startref='idxtonsonjacob' class='endofrange'/>
4812 <indexterm id='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
4813 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
4814 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (1662)</primary></indexterm>
4815 <para>
4816 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a <quote>copyright</quote>
4817 was&mdash;indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4818 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4819 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of 1662, had
4820 expired in 1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4821 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4822 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4823 that the publishers, or <quote>Stationers,</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4824 books.
4825 </para>
4826 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='endofrange'/>
4827 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
4828 <para>
4829 There was no <emphasis>positive</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4830 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4831 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4832 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4833 from legislatures <quote>positive law.</quote> We call the words from judges
4834 <quote>common law.</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4835 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4836 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4837 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4838 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4839 </para>
4840 <indexterm startref='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='endofrange'/>
4841 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4842 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4843 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
4844 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4845 <para>
4846 This question was important to the publishers, or <quote>booksellers,</quote> as
4847 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4848 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4849 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4850
4851 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4852 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4853 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4854 ultimately
4855 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4856 </para>
4857 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>as narrow monopoly right</secondary></indexterm>
4858 <para>
4859 The Statute of Anne granted the author or <quote>proprietor</quote> of a book an
4860 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4861 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4862 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4863 copyright <quote>expired,</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4864 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4865 believed.
4866 </para>
4867 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne' class='endofrange'/>
4868 <para>
4869 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4870 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4871 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4872 <emphasis>at all?</emphasis>
4873 </para>
4874 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'/>
4875 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4876 <indexterm><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4877 <para>
4878 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4879 strong claim. Take <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> as an example: That play
4880 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4881 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4882 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4883 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4884 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4885 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4886 reason is there to allow someone else to <quote>steal</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4887 </para>
4888 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4889 <para>
4890 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4891 about the notion of <quote>copyright</quote> that existed at the time of the
4892 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4893 <quote>booksellers.</quote>
4894 </para>
4895 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
4896 <para>
4897 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4898 to apply the concept of <quote>copyright</quote> ever more broadly. But in 1710, it
4899 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4900 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4901 others from reprinting a book. In 1710, the <quote>copy-right</quote> was a right
4902 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4903 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4904 generally how
4905 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4906 a work could be <emphasis>used</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4907 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4908 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4909 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4910 </para>
4911 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4912 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4913 <para>
4914 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4915 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4916 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4917 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4918 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4919 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4920 allowed to make his films. The <quote>copy-right</quote> was only an exclusive
4921 right to print&mdash;no less, of course, but also no more.
4922 </para>
4923 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England</primary></indexterm>
4924 <indexterm id='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='startofrange'><primary>monopoly, copyright as</primary></indexterm>
4925 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (1656)</primary></indexterm>
4926 <para>
4927 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4928 They had had a long and ugly experience with <quote>exclusive rights,</quote>
4929 especially <quote>exclusive rights</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4930 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4931 monopolies&mdash;especially monopolies for works that already
4932 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4933 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4934 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In 1656, it passed the
4935 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4936 inventions. And by 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4937 monopoly in publishing.
4938 </para>
4939 <para>
4940 Thus the <quote>copy-right,</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4941 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4942 claim that <quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,</quote> try
4943 sounding convincing when uttering, <quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4944 have it forever.</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4945 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4946 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4947 </para>
4948 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
4949 <indexterm id='idxbooksellersenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>booksellers, English</primary></indexterm>
4950 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4951 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4952 <para>
4953 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4954 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4955 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4956 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4957 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4958
4959 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4960 kind&mdash;tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4961 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4962 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as <quote>old patentees
4963 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling</quote>; they were <quote>men who do
4964 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4965 indetted.</quote><footnote><para>
4966
4967 <!-- f4 -->
4968 Philip Wittenberg, <citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4969 Property</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31.
4970 </para></footnote>
4971 </para>
4972 <indexterm><primary>Enlightenment</primary></indexterm>
4973 <indexterm><primary>knowledge, freedom of</primary></indexterm>
4974 <para>
4975 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4976 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4977 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4978 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4979 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4980 with that idea.
4981 </para>
4982 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament2' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4983 <para>
4984 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4985 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4986 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4987 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4988 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4989 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4990 compromise
4991 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4992 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4993 construction and spread of culture.
4994 </para>
4995 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne2' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)
4996 </primary></indexterm>
4997 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
4998 <para>
4999 When 1731 (1710 + 21) came along, however, the booksellers were
5000 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
5001 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
5002 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
5003 to control publication. But in 1735 and 1737, they tried to persuade
5004 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
5005 they said; they needed more time.
5006 </para>
5007 <para>
5008 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
5009 words that echo today,
5010 </para>
5011 <blockquote>
5012 <para>
5013 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
5014 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
5015 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
5016 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
5017 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
5018 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
5019 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
5020 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
5021 Booksellers.<footnote><para>
5022 <!-- f5 -->
5023 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
5024 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
5025 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
5026 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
5027 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
5028 mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
5029 al., 8, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618).
5030 </para></footnote>
5031 </para>
5032 </blockquote>
5033 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne2' class='endofrange'/>
5034 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='endofrange'/>
5035 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5036 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
5037 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
5038 <para>
5039 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
5040 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
5041 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
5042 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
5043 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
5044 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
5045 creative <quote>property</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
5046 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
5047 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
5048 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
5049 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
5050 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
5051 way to protect authors.
5052 </para>
5053 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament2' class='endofrange'/>
5054 <para>
5055 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
5056 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
5057 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
5058 <quote>The publishers &hellip; had as much concern for authors as a cattle
5059 rancher has for cattle.</quote><footnote><para>
5060 <!-- f6 -->
5061 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5062 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
5063 Lyman Ray Patterson, <quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
5064 Law Review</citetitle> 40 (1987): 28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
5065 Vaidhyanathan, 37&ndash;48.
5066 </para></footnote>
5067 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
5068 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
5069 </para>
5070 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5071 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5072 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5073 <para>
5074 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
5075 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
5076 Donaldson.<footnote><para>
5077 <!-- f7 -->
5078 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, <citetitle>Authorship and Copyright</citetitle>
5079 (London: Routledge, 1992), 62&ndash;69.
5080 </para></footnote>
5081 </para>
5082 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne3' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
5083 <indexterm id='idxconger' class='startofrange'><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
5084 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James</primary></indexterm>
5085 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew</primary></indexterm>
5086 <para>
5087 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
5088 career in Edinburgh in 1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
5089 reprints <quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,</quote> at least
5090 under the Statute of Anne.<footnote><para>
5091 <!-- f8 -->
5092 Mark Rose, <citetitle>Authors and Owners</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
5093 1993), 92.
5094 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
5095 </para></footnote>
5096 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
5097 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
5098 and became <quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.</quote> <quote>[A]mong
5099 them,</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was <quote>the young James Boswell
5100 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
5101 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.</quote><footnote><para>
5102 <!-- f9 -->
5103 Ibid., 93.
5104 </para></footnote>
5105 </para>
5106 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5107 <para>
5108 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
5109 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
5110 inexpensive editions <quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
5111 of the supposed common law right of Literary
5112 Property.</quote><footnote><para>
5113 <!-- f10 -->
5114 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5115 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle>, 167 (quoting
5116 Borwell).
5117 </para></footnote>
5118 His books undercut the Conger prices by 30 to 50 percent, and he
5119 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
5120 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
5121 </para>
5122 <indexterm startref='idxconger' class='endofrange'/>
5123 <indexterm id='idxmillarvtaylor' class='startofrange'><primary>Millar v. Taylor</primary></indexterm>
5124 <para>
5125 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block <quote>piracy</quote> like
5126 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the <quote>pirates,</quote>
5127 the most important early victory being <citetitle>Millar</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Taylor</citetitle>.
5128 </para>
5129 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='endofrange'/>
5130 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers' class='endofrange'/>
5131 <indexterm id='idxthomsonjames' class='startofrange'><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5132 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5133 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)</primary></indexterm>
5134 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert</primary></indexterm>
5135 <para>
5136 Millar was a bookseller who in 1729 had purchased the rights to James
5137 Thomson's poem <quote>The Seasons.</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
5138 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
5139 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
5140 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
5141 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.<footnote><para>
5142 <!-- f11 -->
5143 Howard B. Abrams, <quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
5144 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review</citetitle> 29
5145 (1983): 1152.
5146 </para></footnote>
5147 </para>
5148 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
5149 <para>
5150 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
5151 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
5152 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
5153 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
5154 law would protect the author against subsequent <quote>pirates.</quote>
5155 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
5156 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
5157 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
5158 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
5159 </para>
5160 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw' class='endofrange'/>
5161 <indexterm startref='idxthomsonjames' class='endofrange'/>
5162 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='endofrange'/>
5163 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament3' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5164 <para>
5165 Considered as a matter of abstract justice&mdash;reasoning as if
5166 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
5167 principles&mdash;Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
5168 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
5169 with in 1710: How best to limit
5170 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
5171 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
5172 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in 1710, but
5173 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
5174 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
5175 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
5176 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
5177 </para>
5178 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='endofrange'/>
5179 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5180 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers2' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5181 <para>
5182 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
5183 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
5184 </para>
5185 <indexterm><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5186 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
5187 <indexterm id='idxhouseoflords' class='startofrange'><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5188 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>House of Lords vs.</secondary></indexterm>
5189 <para>
5190 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
5191 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
5192 Thomas Beckett.<footnote><para>
5193 <!-- f12 -->
5194 Ibid., 1156.
5195 </para></footnote>
5196 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
5197 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in <citetitle>Millar</citetitle>,
5198 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
5199 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
5200 Court. In February of 1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
5201 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
5202 </para>
5203 <indexterm startref='idxmillarvtaylor' class='endofrange'/>
5204 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament3' class='endofrange'/>
5205 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson v. Beckett</primary></indexterm>
5206 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5207 <para>
5208 As few legal cases ever do, <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle> drew an
5209 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
5210 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
5211 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
5212 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
5213 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
5214 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
5215 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
5216 </para>
5217 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne3' class='endofrange'/>
5218 <para>
5219 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
5220 presented to the House and voted upon first by the <quote>law lords,</quote>
5221 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
5222 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
5223 House of Lords generally voted.
5224 </para>
5225 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='endofrange'/>
5226 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5227 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5228 <para>
5229 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
5230 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
5231 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
5232 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
5233 (22 to 11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
5234 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
5235 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
5236 passed into the public domain.
5237 </para>
5238 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis</primary></indexterm>
5239 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John</primary></indexterm>
5240 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel</primary></indexterm>
5241 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
5242 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
5243 <para>
5244 <quote>The public domain.</quote> Before the case of <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle>
5245 v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
5246 England. Before 1774, there was a strong argument that common law
5247 copyrights were perpetual. After 1774, the public domain was
5248 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
5249 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
5250 history&mdash;including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
5251 and Bunyan&mdash;were free of legal restraint.
5252 </para>
5253 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='endofrange'/>
5254 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers2' class='endofrange'/>
5255 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw2' class='endofrange'/>
5256 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='endofrange'/>
5257 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5258 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5259 <para>
5260 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
5261 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
5262 where most of the <quote>pirate publishers</quote> did their work, people
5263 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the <citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser</citetitle>
5264 reported, <quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
5265 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
5266 decision of which so many individuals were interested.</quote> <quote>Great
5267 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
5268 and illuminations.</quote><footnote><para>
5269 <!-- f13 -->
5270 Rose, 97.
5271 </para></footnote>
5272 </para>
5273 <indexterm startref='idxhouseoflords' class='endofrange'/>
5274 <para>
5275 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
5276 equally strong in the opposite direction. The <citetitle>Morning Chronicle</citetitle>
5277 reported:
5278 </para>
5279 <blockquote>
5280 <para>
5281 By the above decision &hellip; near 200,000 pounds worth of what was
5282 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
5283 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
5284 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
5285 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
5286 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
5287 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
5288 successors.<footnote><para>
5289 <!-- f14 -->
5290 Ibid.
5291 </para></footnote>
5292 </para>
5293 </blockquote>
5294 <indexterm><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5295 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5296 <para>
5297 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
5298 <quote>Ruined</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
5299 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
5300 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
5301 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
5302 <emphasis>free</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
5303 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
5304 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
5305 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
5306 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
5307 book from someone. But <emphasis>free</emphasis> in the sense that the
5308 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
5309 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
5310 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
5311 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
5312 develop&mdash; chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
5313 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a <emphasis>competitive
5314 context</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
5315 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
5316 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
5317 </para>
5318 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellersenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5319 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5320 <para>
5321 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
5322 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
5323 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
5324 protected.
5325 </para>
5326 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='endofrange'/>
5327 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5328 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5329 <indexterm startref='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='endofrange'/>
5330 <indexterm startref='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='endofrange'/>
5331 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='endofrange'/>
5332 <indexterm startref='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='endofrange'/>
5333 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='endofrange'/>
5334 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='endofrange'/>
5335 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
5336 </chapter>
5337 <chapter label="7" id="recorders">
5338 <title>Chapter Seven: Recorders</title>
5339 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
5340 <indexterm id='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>documentary film</primary></indexterm>
5341 <indexterm id='idxelsejon' class='startofrange'><primary>Else, Jon</primary></indexterm>
5342 <indexterm id='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>in documentary film</secondary></indexterm>
5343 <indexterm id='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>fair use of copyrighted material in</secondary></indexterm>
5344 <para>
5345 <emphasis role='strong'>Jon Else</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5346 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5347 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5348 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5349 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5350 </para>
5351 <para>
5352 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5353 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5354 today.
5355 </para>
5356 <indexterm id='idxwagnerrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5357 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5358 <para>
5359 In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5360 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5361 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5362 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5363 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5364 stage.
5365 </para>
5366 <indexterm id='idxsimpsonsthe' class='startofrange'><primary>Simpsons, The</primary></indexterm>
5367 <para>
5368 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5369 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5370 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5371 and the opera company played Wagner, was <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. As Else judged
5372 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5373 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5374 about the scene.
5375 </para>
5376 <indexterm startref='idxwagnerrichard' class='endofrange'/>
5377 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>multiple copyrights associated with</secondary></indexterm>
5378 <para>
5379 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5380 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>.
5381 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5382 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5383 unless <quote>fair use</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5384 </para>
5385 <indexterm id='idxgraciefilms' class='startofrange'><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5386 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt' class='startofrange'><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5387 <para>
5388 Else called <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5389 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5390 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5391 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5392 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5393 </para>
5394 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5395 <para>
5396 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5397 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5398 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5399 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5400 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5401 </para>
5402 <indexterm startref='idxgraciefilms' class='endofrange'/>
5403 <para>
5404 Then, as Else told me, <quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5405 &hellip; that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation&mdash;or at
5406 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.</quote>
5407 And second, Fox <quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5408 to use this four-point-five seconds of &hellip; entirely unsolicited
5409 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.</quote>
5410 </para>
5411 <indexterm id='idxherrerarebecca' class='startofrange'><primary>Herrera, Rebecca</primary></indexterm>
5412 <para>
5413 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5414 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5415 explained to her, <quote>There must be some mistake here. &hellip; We're
5416 asking for your educational rate on this.</quote> That was the educational
5417 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5418 confirm what he had been told.
5419 </para>
5420 <indexterm><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5421 <para>
5422 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,</quote> he told me. <quote>Yes, you
5423 have your facts straight,</quote> she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the
5424 clip of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5425 about
5426
5427 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5428 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, <quote>And
5429 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.</quote> As an assistant
5430 to Herrera told Else later on, <quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5431 the money.</quote>
5432 </para>
5433 <indexterm startref='idxherrerarebecca' class='endofrange'/>
5434 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5435 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The</primary></indexterm>
5436 <para>
5437 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5438 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5439 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5440 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5441 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5442 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5443 </para>
5444 <para>
5445 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5446 copyright to <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5447 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5448 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5449 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5450 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5451 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5452 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5453 says the owner gets to control.
5454 </para>
5455 <para>
5456 For example, <quote>public performance</quote> is a use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> that the
5457 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5458 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see <quote>My
5459 Favorite <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>,</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5460 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5461 whatever she wants&mdash;$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set
5462 by the law.
5463 </para>
5464 <para>
5465 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5466 thought is <quote>fair use.</quote><footnote><para>
5467 <!-- f1 -->
5468 For an excellent argument that such use is <quote>fair use,</quote> but that
5469 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is <quote>fair use,</quote> see Richard
5470 A. Posner with William F. Patry, <quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5471 Wake of <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5472 Law School, 5 August 2003.
5473 </para></footnote>
5474 Else's use of just 4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>
5475 episode is clearly a fair use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>&mdash;and fair use does
5476 not require the permission of anyone.
5477 </para>
5478 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='endofrange'/>
5479 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt' class='endofrange'/>
5480 <para>
5481 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5482 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon <quote>fair use.</quote> Here's his reply:
5483 </para>
5484 <blockquote>
5485 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
5486 <para>
5487 The <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5488 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5489 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5490 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was <quote>clearly
5491 fair use</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5492 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5493 </para>
5494 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
5495 <listitem>
5496 <indexterm><primary>Errors and Omissions insurance</primary></indexterm>
5497 <para>
5498 <!-- 1. -->
5499 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5500 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5501 <quote>visual cue sheet</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5502 shot in the film. They take a dim view of <quote>fair use,</quote> and a claim of
5503 <quote>fair use</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5504 </para></listitem>
5505 <listitem>
5506 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5507 <indexterm><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5508 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George</primary></indexterm>
5509 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5510 <para>
5511 <!-- 2. -->
5512 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5513 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5514 tracking down and stopping unlicensed <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> usage, just as George
5515 Lucas had a very high profile litigating <citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5516 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5517 license to four seconds of <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5518 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5519 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5520 principle.
5521 </para></listitem>
5522 <listitem><para>
5523 <!-- 3. -->
5524 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5525 School &hellip; who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5526 that Fox would <quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5527 life,</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5528 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5529 pockets, me or them.
5530 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5531 </para>
5532 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='endofrange'/>
5533 </listitem>
5534 <listitem><para>
5535 <!-- 4. -->
5536 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5537 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5538 money.
5539 </para></listitem>
5540 </orderedlist>
5541 </blockquote>
5542 <indexterm startref='idxsimpsonsthe' class='endofrange'/>
5543 <para>
5544 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5545 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5546 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5547 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5548 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5549 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5550 </para>
5551 <para>
5552 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5553 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5554 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5555 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5556 not.
5557 </para>
5558 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='endofrange'/>
5559 <indexterm startref='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5560 <indexterm startref='idxelsejon' class='endofrange'/>
5561 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5562 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='endofrange'/>
5563 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='endofrange'/>
5564 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5565 </chapter>
5566 <chapter label="8" id="transformers">
5567 <title>Chapter Eight: Transformers</title>
5568 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul</primary></indexterm>
5569 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5570 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary></indexterm>
5571 <para>
5572 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5573 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5574 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5575 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5576 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5577 anticipation of the power of networks.
5578 </para>
5579 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on</secondary></indexterm>
5580 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in</primary></indexterm>
5581 <para>
5582 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5583 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology&mdash;not to distribute
5584 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5585 difficult. In 1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5586 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5587 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5588 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5589 important to his career.
5590 </para>
5591 <para>
5592 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5593 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5594 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5595 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5596 </para>
5597 <para>
5598 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5599 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5600 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5601 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5602 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5603 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5604 </para>
5605 <para>
5606 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. <quote>Our
5607 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5608 Eastwood's films,</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5609 arose. <quote>No one had ever really done this before,</quote> Alben explained. <quote>No
5610 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5611 actor's career.</quote>
5612 </para>
5613 <para>
5614 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5615 Slade asked, <quote>Well, what will it take?</quote>
5616 </para>
5617 <para>
5618 Alben replied, <quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5619 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5620 else that we want to use in these film clips.</quote> Slade said, <quote>Great! Go
5621 for it.</quote><footnote>
5622 <para>
5623 <!-- f1 -->
5624 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5625 publicity&mdash;rights an artist has to control the commercial
5626 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden <quote>Rip, Mix,
5627 Burn</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5628 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of</secondary></indexterm>
5629 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5630 </para></footnote>
5631 </para>
5632 <para>
5633 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5634 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5635 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5636 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5637 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5638 </para>
5639 <para>
5640 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5641 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5642 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5643 </para>
5644 <blockquote>
5645 <para>
5646 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5647 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include&mdash;of
5648 course we were going to use the <quote>Make my day</quote> clip from <citetitle>Dirty
5649 Harry</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5650 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5651 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5652 </para>
5653 <para>
5654 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5655 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5656 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5657 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5658 rate at the time was about $600. So we had to identify the
5659 people&mdash;some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5660 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5661 glass&mdash;is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5662 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5663 started calling people.
5664 </para>
5665 </blockquote>
5666 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald</primary></indexterm>
5667 <para>
5668 Some actors were glad to help&mdash;Donald Sutherland, for example,
5669 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5670 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5671 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5672 know, $1,200?</quote> And they would say, <quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5673 to get $1,200.</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5674 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5675 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5676 career.
5677 </para>
5678 <para>
5679 It was one <emphasis>year</emphasis> later&mdash;<quote>and even then we
5680 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.</quote>
5681 </para>
5682 <para>
5683 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5684 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5685 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5686 </para>
5687 <blockquote>
5688 <para>
5689 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5690 hands and said, <quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5691 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5692 actors.</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5693 constituent parts and said, <quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5694 directors, &hellip; this many musicians,</quote> and we just went at it very
5695 systematically and cleared the rights.
5696 </para>
5697 </blockquote>
5698 <para>
5699
5700 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5701 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5702 loved it, and it sold very well.
5703 </para>
5704 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter</primary></indexterm>
5705 <para>
5706 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5707 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5708 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, <quote>There is
5709 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5710 at all.</quote><footnote><para>
5711 <!-- f2 -->
5712 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, <citetitle>Seven
5713 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition</citetitle>, available at
5714 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #22</ulink>.
5715 </para></footnote>
5716 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5717 has to be made?
5718 </para>
5719 <para>
5720 For, as he acknowledged, <quote>very few &hellip; have the time and resources,
5721 and the will to do this,</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5722 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5723 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5724 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5725 </para>
5726 <blockquote>
5727 <para>
5728 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5729 he or she gets paid very well. &hellip; And then when 30 seconds of
5730 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5731 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person &hellip; should be
5732 compensated for that.
5733 </para>
5734 </blockquote>
5735 <para>
5736 Or at least, is this <emphasis>how</emphasis> the artist should be
5737 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5738 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5739 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5740 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5741 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5742 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5743 made to be more clean?
5744 </para>
5745 <blockquote>
5746 <para>
5747 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5748 mechanism&mdash;where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5749 subject to estranged former spouses&mdash;you'd see a lot more of this
5750 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5751 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5752 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5753 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5754 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5755 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5756 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5757 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5758 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5759 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5760 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, <quote>Oh, I
5761 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5762 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5763 money,</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5764 </para>
5765 </blockquote>
5766 <para>
5767 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5768 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5769 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5770 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5771 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5772 </para>
5773 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'/>
5774 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'/>
5775 <para>
5776 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5777 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5778 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5779 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5780 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5781 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5782 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5783 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5784 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5785 <quote>Does this still make sense?</quote>
5786 </para>
5787 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'/>
5788 <para>
5789 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5790 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5791 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5792 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5793
5794 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5795 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5796 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5797 </para>
5798 <para>
5799 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5800 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode.
5801 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5802 judges loved every minute of it.
5803 </para>
5804 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David</primary></indexterm>
5805 <para>
5806 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5807 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5808 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5809 room of over 250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5810 began his talk with a question: <quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5811 were just violated in this room?</quote>
5812 </para>
5813 <para>
5814 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5815 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David</primary></indexterm>
5816 <indexterm><primary>Court of Appeals</primary><secondary>Ninth Circuit</secondary></indexterm>
5817 <indexterm><primary>Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals</primary></indexterm>
5818 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
5819 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5820 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5821 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5822 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5823 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle
5824 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5825 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5826 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5827 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5828 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5829 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5830 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5831 couldn't easily do them legally.
5832 </para>
5833 <para>
5834 We live in a <quote>cut and paste</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5835 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5836 and paste architecture of the Internet created&mdash;in a second you can
5837 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5838 planted in your presentation.
5839 </para>
5840 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos</primary></indexterm>
5841 <para>
5842 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5843 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5844 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5845 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5846 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5847 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5848 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5849 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5850 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5851 </para>
5852 <para>
5853 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5854 wanted to be <quote>legal,</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5855 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5856 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5857 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5858 </para>
5859 <para>
5860 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5861 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5862 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5863 necessarily requiring that the <quote>free</quote> use be free as in <quote>free beer.</quote>
5864 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5865 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5866 along: a rule, for example, that says <quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5867 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5868 will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5869 copyright owner.</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5870 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5871 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5872 registers the work.
5873 </para>
5874 <para>
5875 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5876 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5877 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5878 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5879 </para>
5880 <para>
5881 <emphasis role='strong'>In February 2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5882 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5883 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live</citetitle> and
5884 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5885 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5886 would work together to form a <quote>unique filmmaking pact.</quote> Under the
5887 agreement, DreamWorks <quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5888 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and&mdash;with the use
5889 of stateof-the-art digital technology&mdash;insert Myers and other
5890 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5891 entertainment.</quote>
5892 </para>
5893 <para>
5894 The announcement called this <quote>film sampling.</quote> As Myers explained,
5895 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5896 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5897 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5898 to take that same concept and apply it to film.</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5899 quoted as saying, <quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5900 new audiences, it is Mike.</quote>
5901 </para>
5902 <para>
5903 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5904 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5905 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5906 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5907 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5908 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5909 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5910 privilege reserved for the funny and famous&mdash;and presumably rich.
5911 </para>
5912 <para>
5913 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5914 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of <quote>fair use.</quote>
5915 Much of <quote>sampling</quote> should be considered <quote>fair use.</quote> But few would
5916 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5917 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5918 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5919 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5920 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5921 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5922 process is a process of paying lawyers&mdash;again a privilege, or perhaps a
5923 curse, reserved for the few.
5924 </para>
5925 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5926 </chapter>
5927 <chapter label="9" id="collectors">
5928 <title>Chapter Nine: Collectors</title>
5929 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
5930 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
5931 <para>
5932 <emphasis role='strong'>In April 1996</emphasis>, millions of
5933 <quote>bots</quote>&mdash;computer codes designed to
5934 <quote>spider,</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5935 content&mdash;began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5936 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5937 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5938 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5939 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5940 Internet and stored them.
5941 </para>
5942 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5943 <para>
5944 By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5945 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5946 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5947 the world. Using a technology called <quote>the Way Back Machine,</quote> you could
5948 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to 1996, as
5949 well as when those pages changed.
5950 </para>
5951 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Orwell, George</primary></indexterm>
5952 <para>
5953 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5954 appreciated. In the dystopia described in <citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5955 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5956 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5957 reports.
5958 </para>
5959 <para>
5960 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5961 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5962 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5963 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5964 </para>
5965 <para>
5966 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5967 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5968 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5969 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5970 library&mdash;constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5971 </para>
5972 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'/>
5973 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5974 <para>
5975 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5976 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5977 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5978 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5979 what others might prefer you forget.<footnote><para>
5980 <!-- f1 -->
5981 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
5982 <indexterm><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
5983 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases</primary></indexterm>
5984 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5985 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003,
5986 press release stated, <quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.</quote> That was
5987 later changed, without notice, to <quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5988 Have Ended.</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003.
5989 </para></footnote>
5990 </para>
5991 <indexterm><primary>history, records of</primary></indexterm>
5992 <para>
5993 <emphasis role='strong'>We take it</emphasis> for granted that we can
5994 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5995 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5996 race riots in Watts in 1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in 1963,
5997 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5998 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5999 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
6000 remember&mdash;not just what it is convenient to remember, but
6001 remember something close to the truth.
6002 </para>
6003 <para>
6004 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
6005 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We <emphasis>all</emphasis>
6006 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
6007 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
6008 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
6009 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
6010 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
6011 </para>
6012 <para>
6013 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
6014 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
6015 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
6016 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
6017 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
6018 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
6019 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
6020 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet&mdash;the
6021 one kept by the Internet Archive.
6022 </para>
6023 <indexterm id='idxkahlebrewster' class='startofrange'><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
6024 <para>
6025 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
6026 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
6027 researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
6028 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
6029 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
6030 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
6031 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10
6032 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
6033 </para>
6034 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
6035 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive</primary></indexterm>
6036 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University</primary></indexterm>
6037 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
6038 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>archival function of</secondary></indexterm>
6039 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage2' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
6040 <para>
6041 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
6042 human history. At the end of 2002, it held <quote>two hundred and thirty
6043 terabytes of material</quote>&mdash;and was <quote>ten times larger than the
6044 Library of Congress.</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
6045 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
6046 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
6047 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
6048 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
6049 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
6050 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University&mdash;thanks to a
6051 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
6052 is available to scholars for a very low fee. <quote>But other than that,
6053 [television] is almost unavailable,</quote> Kahle told me. <quote>If you were
6054 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
6055 just a graduate student?</quote> As Kahle put it,
6056 </para>
6057 <blockquote>
6058 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan</primary></indexterm>
6059 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes</primary></indexterm>
6060 <para>
6061 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
6062 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
6063 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
6064 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
6065 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
6066
6067 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
6068 <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode that came out after it &hellip; it would be almost
6069 impossible. &hellip; Those materials are almost unfindable. &hellip;
6070 </para>
6071 </blockquote>
6072 <indexterm><primary>newspapers</primary><secondary>archives of</secondary></indexterm>
6073 <para>
6074 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
6075 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
6076 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
6077 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
6078 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
6079 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
6080 </para>
6081 <para>
6082 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
6083 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
6084 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
6085 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
6086 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
6087 work.
6088 </para>
6089 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
6090 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6091 <para>
6092 These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library
6093 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
6094 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
6095 borrow back the deposits&mdash;for an unlimited time at no cost. In
6096 1915 alone, there were more than 5,475 films deposited and <quote>borrowed
6097 back.</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
6098 held by any library. The copy exists&mdash;if it exists at
6099 all&mdash;in the library archive of the film company.<footnote><para>
6100 <!-- f2 -->
6101 Doug Herrick, <quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
6102 the Library of Congress,</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly</citetitle> 13 nos. 2&ndash;3
6103 (1980): 5; Anthony Slide, <citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
6104 Preservation in the United States</citetitle> (Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland &amp;
6105 Co., 1992), 36.
6106 </para></footnote>
6107 </para>
6108 <para>
6109 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
6110 were originally not copyrighted&mdash;there was no way to capture the
6111 broadcasts, so there was no fear of <quote>theft.</quote> But as technology enabled
6112 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
6113 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
6114 <quote>copyrighted.</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
6115 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
6116 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
6117 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
6118 </para>
6119 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
6120 <para>
6121 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and
6122 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
6123 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
6124 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
6125 September 11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
6126 stations from around the world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made
6127 their coverage during the week of September 11 available free on-line.
6128 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
6129 events of that day.
6130 </para>
6131 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive</primary></indexterm>
6132 <indexterm><primary>archive.org</primary><seealso>Internet Archive</seealso></indexterm>
6133 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage2' class='endofrange'/>
6134 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6135 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive</primary></indexterm>
6136 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film</primary></indexterm>
6137 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films</primary></indexterm>
6138 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick</primary></indexterm>
6139 <para>
6140 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
6141 archive of film includes close to 45,000 <quote>ephemeral films</quote> (meaning
6142 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
6143 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
6144 1,300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
6145 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
6146 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
6147 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
6148 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
6149 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
6150 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
6151 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
6152 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the <quote>Duck and Cover</quote> film
6153 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
6154 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
6155 few minutes&mdash;for free.
6156 </para>
6157 <para>
6158 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
6159 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
6160 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
6161 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
6162 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
6163 to find them.
6164 </para>
6165 <para>
6166 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
6167 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
6168 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
6169 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
6170 property, but during a second life that all creative property
6171 has&mdash;a noncommercial life.
6172 </para>
6173 <para>
6174 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
6175 of creative property goes through different <quote>lives.</quote> In its first
6176 life, if the
6177
6178 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
6179 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
6180 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
6181 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
6182 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
6183 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
6184 </para>
6185 <para>
6186 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
6187 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
6188 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
6189 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
6190 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
6191 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
6192 longer sold.
6193 </para>
6194 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6195 <para>
6196 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
6197 very quickly (the average today is after about a year<footnote><para>
6198 <!-- f3 -->
6199 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6200 Dave Barns, <quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
6201 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>,
6202 5 September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927
6203 and 1946, only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese,
6204 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,</quote> <citetitle>Boston
6205 College Law Review</citetitle> 44 (2003): 593 n. 51.
6206 </para></footnote>). After
6207 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
6208 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
6209 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
6210 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
6211 important to the spread and stability of culture.
6212 </para>
6213 <para>
6214 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
6215 creative property does not hold true with the most important
6216 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
6217 centuries. For these&mdash;television, movies, music, radio, the
6218 Internet&mdash;there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
6219 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes &amp;
6220 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
6221 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
6222 disappears.
6223 </para>
6224 <para>
6225 <emphasis role='strong'>For most of</emphasis> the twentieth century,
6226 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
6227 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
6228 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
6229 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
6230 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
6231 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
6232 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
6233 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
6234 little practical effect.
6235 </para>
6236 <para>
6237 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
6238 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
6239 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
6240 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
6241 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
6242 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
6243 </para>
6244 <para>
6245 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
6246 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
6247 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
6248 Kahle describes,
6249 </para>
6250 <blockquote>
6251 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>total number of</secondary></indexterm>
6252 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>total number of</secondary></indexterm>
6253 <indexterm><primary>music recordings</primary><see>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</see></indexterm>
6254 <indexterm><primary>music recordings</primary><see>recording industry</see></indexterm>
6255 <indexterm><primary>music recordings</primary><secondary>total number of</secondary></indexterm>
6256 <para>
6257 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
6258 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
6259 movies, &hellip; and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
6260 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
6261 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
6262 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
6263 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
6264 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
6265 &hellip; thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
6266 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
6267 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
6268 </para>
6269 </blockquote>
6270 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
6271 <para>
6272 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
6273 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
6274 libraries or archives could be. <emphasis>When</emphasis> the
6275 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
6276 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
6277 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
6278 will draw upon it to understand it;
6279 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
6280 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
6281 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
6282 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past&mdash;a
6283 future <emphasis>for</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
6284 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
6285 </para>
6286 <para>
6287 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
6288 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
6289 call these <quote>archives,</quote> as warm as the idea of a <quote>library</quote> might seem,
6290 the <quote>content</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
6291 someone's <quote>property.</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
6292 that Kahle and others would exercise.
6293 </para>
6294 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'/>
6295 <indexterm startref='idxkahlebrewster' class='endofrange'/>
6296 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
6297 </chapter>
6298 <chapter label="10" id="property-i">
6299 <title>Chapter Ten: <quote>Property</quote></title>
6300 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon</primary></indexterm>
6301 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
6302 <indexterm id='idxvalentijackbackgroundof' class='startofrange'><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>background of</secondary></indexterm>
6303 <para>
6304 <emphasis role='strong'>Jack Valenti</emphasis> has been the president
6305 of the Motion Picture Association of America since 1966. He first came
6306 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
6307 administration&mdash;literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
6308 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
6309 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
6310 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
6311 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
6312 </para>
6313 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
6314 <indexterm><primary>MGM</primary></indexterm>
6315 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6316 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox</primary></indexterm>
6317 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment</primary></indexterm>
6318 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6319 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
6320 <para>
6321 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
6322 Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal
6323 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
6324 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
6325 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
6326 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
6327 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
6328 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
6329 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
6330 Warner Brothers.
6331 </para>
6332 <para>
6333 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
6334 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
6335 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
6336 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
6337 political skill of a Southerner&mdash;the ability to appear simple and
6338 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
6339 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
6340 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
6341 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
6342 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
6343 Washingtonian way.
6344 </para>
6345 <para>
6346 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
6347 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
6348 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
6349 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
6350 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
6351 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
6352 redefine the meaning of <quote>creative property.</quote>
6353 </para>
6354 <para>
6355 In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
6356 perfectly:
6357 </para>
6358 <blockquote>
6359 <para>
6360 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
6361 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
6362 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
6363 theme which animates this entire debate: <emphasis>Creative property
6364 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
6365 other property owners in the nation</emphasis>. That is the issue.
6366 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
6367 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.<footnote><para>
6368 <!-- f1 -->
6369 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R.
6370 4794, H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the
6371 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
6372 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
6373 Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack
6374 Valenti).
6375 </para></footnote>
6376 </para>
6377 </blockquote>
6378 <para>
6379 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
6380 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
6381 <quote>central theme</quote> to which <quote>reasonable men and women</quote> will return is
6382 this:
6383 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6384 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6385 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.</quote>
6386 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6387 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6388 </para>
6389 <para>
6390 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6391 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6392 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6393 extreme a claim made by <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> who is serious in
6394 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6395 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6396 it comes to the nature and scope of <quote>creative property.</quote> His views
6397 have <emphasis>no</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6398 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6399 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6400 </para>
6401 <indexterm startref='idxvalentijackbackgroundof' class='endofrange'/>
6402 <para>
6403 While <quote>creative property</quote> is certainly <quote>property</quote> in a nerdy and
6404 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,<footnote><para>
6405 <!-- f2 -->
6406 Lawyers speak of <quote>property</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6407 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6408 object. Thus, my <quote>property right</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6409 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For
6410 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of <quote>property</quote> to
6411 <quote>lawyer talk,</quote> see Bruce Ackerman, <citetitle>Private Property and the
6412 Constitution</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 26&ndash;27.
6413 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6414 <quote>creative property owners</quote> have been <quote>accorded the same rights and
6415 protection resident in all other property owners.</quote> Indeed, if creative
6416 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6417 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6418 in our tradition.
6419 </para>
6420 <para>
6421 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6422 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6423 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6424 overturned in 1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6425 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6426 culture would develop.
6427 </para>
6428 <para>
6429 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6430 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6431 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6432 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6433 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6434 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6435 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6436 the same would be to
6437
6438 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6439 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6440 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6441 perfect control.
6442 </para>
6443 <para>
6444 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6445 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6446 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6447 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6448 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6449 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6450 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6451 </para>
6452 <para>
6453 <emphasis role='strong'>To get</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6454 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6455 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6456 </para>
6457 <para>
6458 The framers of our Constitution loved <quote>property.</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6459 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6460 important requirement. If the government takes your property&mdash;if
6461 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6462 farm&mdash;it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's <quote>Takings
6463 Clause,</quote> to pay you <quote>just compensation</quote> for that taking. The
6464 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6465 sacred. It cannot <emphasis>ever</emphasis> be taken from the property
6466 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6467 </para>
6468 <para>
6469 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6470 Valenti calls <quote>creative property.</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6471 power to create <quote>creative property,</quote> the Constitution
6472 <emphasis>requires</emphasis> that after a <quote>limited time,</quote> Congress
6473 take back the rights that it has granted and set the <quote>creative
6474 property</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6475 the expiration of a copyright term <quote>takes</quote> your copyright and turns it
6476 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6477 pay <quote>just compensation</quote> for this <quote>taking.</quote> Instead, the same
6478 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6479 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6480 requires that you lose your <quote>creative property</quote> right without any
6481 compensation at all.
6482 </para>
6483 <para>
6484 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6485 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6486 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6487 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6488 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6489 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6490 itself.
6491 </para>
6492 <indexterm id='idxjeffersonthomas' class='startofrange'><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
6493 <para>
6494 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6495 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6496 The Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6497 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6498 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6499 president (as it did in 1800). The framers were no doubt
6500 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6501 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6502 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6503 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6504 </para>
6505 <para>
6506 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6507 least try to understand <emphasis>why</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6508 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6509 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6510 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6511 domain?
6512 </para>
6513 <indexterm startref='idxjeffersonthomas' class='endofrange'/>
6514
6515 <para>
6516 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6517 history of these <quote>creative property</quote> rights, and the control that they
6518 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6519 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6520 should be at the core of this war: Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis>
6521 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6522 <emphasis>whether</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6523 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6524 ought to be. Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6525 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6526 also control how culture develops.
6527 </para>
6528 <indexterm><primary>Code (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
6529 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
6530 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>four modalities of constraint on</secondary></indexterm>
6531 <indexterm id='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>four modalities of</secondary></indexterm>
6532 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as ex post regulation modality</secondary></indexterm>
6533 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6534 <para>
6535
6536 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6537 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6538 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6539 than the narrow language of the law allows. In <citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6540 Cyberspace</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6541 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6542 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6543 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6544 </para>
6545 <figure id="fig-1331">
6546 <title></title>
6547 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
6548 </figure>
6549 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6550 <para>
6551 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6552 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6553 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6554 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6555 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6556 be regulated&mdash; either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6557 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6558 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6559 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6560 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6561 Web, you can be punished
6562 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6563 with a $150,000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6564 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6565 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6566 </para>
6567 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6568 <para>
6569 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6570 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6571 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6572 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6573 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6574 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6575 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6576 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6577 the source of the enforcement.
6578 </para>
6579 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6580 <para>
6581 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6582 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6583 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6584 norms&mdash;it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6585 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6586 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6587 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6588 individual or group might behave.
6589 </para>
6590 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6591 <para>
6592 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6593 <quote>architecture</quote>&mdash;the physical world as one finds it&mdash;is a
6594 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6595 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6596 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6597 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6598 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6599 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6600 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6601 theft, but by nature, by <quote>architecture.</quote> If a 500-pound boulder
6602 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6603 constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6604 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6605 </para>
6606 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6607 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6608 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints' class='endofrange'/>
6609 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6610 <para>
6611
6612 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6613 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6614 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6615 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6616 undermined by another.
6617 </para>
6618 <para>
6619 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6620 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6621 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6622 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6623 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6624 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6625 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6626 </para>
6627 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6628 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6629 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6630 <indexterm id='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>driving speed, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6631 <indexterm id='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>speeding, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6632 <para>
6633 So, for example, consider the <quote>freedom</quote> to drive a car at a high
6634 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6635 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6636 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6637 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6638 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6639 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6640 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6641 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6642 the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own
6643 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6644 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6645 </para>
6646 <para>
6647 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6648 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6649 special role in affecting the three.<footnote><para>
6650 <!-- f3 -->
6651 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6652 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6653 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6654 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6655 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Code: And
6656 Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90&ndash;95;
6657 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>The New Chicago School,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies</citetitle>,
6658 June 1998.
6659 <indexterm><primary>Code (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
6660 </para></footnote>
6661 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6662 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6663 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6664 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6665 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6666 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6667 used to require that other laws be more
6668 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6669 strict&mdash;a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6670 limit, for example&mdash;so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6671 driving.
6672 </para>
6673 <indexterm startref='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6674 <indexterm startref='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6675 <figure id="fig-1361">
6676 <title></title>
6677 <graphic fileref="images/1361.svg" align="center" width="12em"></graphic>
6678
6679 </figure>
6680 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6681 <para>
6682 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6683 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6684 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6685 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6686 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6687 another.<footnote>
6688 <para>
6689 <!-- f4 -->
6690 Some people object to this way of talking about <quote>liberty.</quote> They object
6691 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6692 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6693 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6694 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6695 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6696 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6697 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6698 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6699 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6700 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6701 of liberty. As I argued in <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, we come from a
6702 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6703 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6704 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6705 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6706 <citetitle>On Liberty</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6707 1978), 19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6708 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons, <quote>The
6709 Right to Work,</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6710 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays</citetitle> (London:
6711 Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6712 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6713 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6714 places easier; 42 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
6715 12101 (2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6716 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6717 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6718 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6719 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (1990)</primary></indexterm>
6720 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.</primary></indexterm>
6721 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6722 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6723 <indexterm><primary>Code (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
6724 </para></footnote>
6725 </para>
6726 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='endofrange'/>
6727 <section id="hollywood">
6728 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right</title>
6729 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
6730 <para>
6731 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6732 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6733 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6734 rallying makes sense.
6735 </para>
6736 <para>
6737 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6738 Internet:
6739 </para>
6740 <figure id="fig-1371">
6741 <title></title>
6742 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
6743
6744 </figure>
6745 <indexterm id='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='startofrange'><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6746 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6747 <indexterm id='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='startofrange'><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6748 <para>
6749 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6750 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6751 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6752 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6753 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6754 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6755 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6756 recognize&mdash;kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6757 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6758 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6759 this form of infringement.
6760 </para>
6761 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright regulatory balance lost with</secondary></indexterm>
6762 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>regulatory balance lost in</secondary></indexterm>
6763 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6764 <indexterm><primary>MP3s</primary></indexterm>
6765 <para>
6766 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6767 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6768 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6769 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6770 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6771 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6772 </para>
6773 <indexterm startref='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='endofrange'/>
6774 <indexterm startref='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='endofrange'/>
6775 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>established industries threatened by changes in</secondary></indexterm>
6776 <para>
6777 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6778 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6779 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6780 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6781 Iraq
6782 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6783 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6784 looting that results.
6785 </para>
6786 <figure id="fig-1381">
6787 <title></title>
6788 <graphic fileref="images/1381.svg" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
6789
6790 </figure>
6791 <indexterm><primary>Commerce, U.S. Department of</primary></indexterm>
6792 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
6793 <para>
6794 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6795 warriors. Indeed, in a <quote>White Paper</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6796 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995,
6797 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6798 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6799 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should
6800 strengthen intellectual property law, (2) businesses should adopt
6801 innovative marketing techniques, (3) technologists should push to
6802 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (4) educators should
6803 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6804 </para>
6805 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='endofrange'/>
6806 <indexterm startref='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='endofrange'/>
6807 <indexterm><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6808 <indexterm><primary>steel industry</primary></indexterm>
6809 <para>
6810 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed&mdash;if it was to
6811 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6812 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6813 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6814 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6815 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6816 life. Homeowners living in a
6817
6818 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6819 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6820 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6821 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6822 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6823 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6824 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6825 </para>
6826 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='endofrange'/>
6827 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='endofrange'/>
6828 <indexterm><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
6829 <para>
6830 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6831 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6832 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6833 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6834 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6835 Brown describes it, its <quote>architecture of revenue.</quote>
6836 </para>
6837 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
6838 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
6839 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
6840 <indexterm><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
6841 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
6842 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
6843 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry</primary></indexterm>
6844 <indexterm><primary>remote channel changers</primary></indexterm>
6845 <para>
6846 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6847 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6848 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6849 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6850 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20
6851 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6852 of digital cameras.<footnote><para>
6853 <!-- f5 -->
6854 See Geoffrey Smith, <quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?</quote>
6855 BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at
6856 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #23</ulink>. For a more
6857 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6858 R. Schoenberger, <quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?</quote> Forbes.com, 6
6859 October 2003, available at
6860 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #24</ulink>.
6861 </para></footnote>
6862
6863 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6864 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6865 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6866 <emphasis>for the purpose of</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6867 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6868 weakened the <quote>stickiness</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6869 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf), and it
6870 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6871 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6872 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6873 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6874 </para>
6875 <indexterm id='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='startofrange'><primary>free market, technological changes in</primary></indexterm>
6876 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
6877 <indexterm><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
6878 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
6879 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
6880 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
6881 <indexterm><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
6882 <para>
6883 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6884 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6885 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6886 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6887 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6888 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6889 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6890 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, <quote>established companies
6891 have an interest in excluding future competitors.</quote><footnote><para>
6892 <!-- f6 -->
6893 Fred Warshofsky, <citetitle>The Patent Wars</citetitle> (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170&ndash;71.
6894 </para></footnote>
6895 And relative to a
6896 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6897 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6898 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6899 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6900 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6901 Brezhnev.
6902 </para>
6903 <para>
6904 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6905 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6906 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6907 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6908 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6909 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6910 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6911 opportunities for innovation and change.
6912 </para>
6913 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
6914 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
6915 <indexterm><primary>speech, freedom of</primary><secondary>constitutional guarantee of</secondary></indexterm>
6916 <para>
6917 In the context of laws regulating speech&mdash;which include,
6918 obviously, copyright law&mdash;that duty is even stronger. When the
6919 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6920 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6921 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6922 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6923 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6924 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: <quote>Congress
6925 shall make no law &hellip; abridging the freedom of speech.</quote> So when
6926 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would <quote>abridge</quote> the freedom
6927 of speech, it should ask&mdash; carefully&mdash;whether such
6928 regulation is justified.
6929 </para>
6930 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='endofrange'/>
6931 <indexterm startref='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='endofrange'/>
6932 <para>
6933 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6934 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6935 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6936 <quote>justified.</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6937 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6938 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6939 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6940 </para>
6941 <para>
6942 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6943 </para>
6944 <indexterm id='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='startofrange'><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann</primary></indexterm>
6945 <indexterm id='idxddt' class='startofrange'><primary>DDT</primary></indexterm>
6946 <indexterm id='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='startofrange'><primary>insecticide, environmental consequences of</primary></indexterm>
6947 <indexterm id='idxfarming' class='startofrange'><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6948 <para>
6949 In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss
6950 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6951 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the
6952 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6953 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6954 </para>
6955 <para>
6956 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6957 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6958 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6959 </para>
6960 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6961 <indexterm><primary>Silent Spring (Carson)</primary></indexterm>
6962 <indexterm id='idxenvironmentalism' class='startofrange'><primary>environmentalism</primary></indexterm>
6963 <para>
6964 But in 1962, Rachel Carson published <citetitle>Silent Spring</citetitle>, which argued that
6965 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6966 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6967 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6968 </para>
6969 <para>
6970 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6971 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6972 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6973 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6974 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6975 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6976 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6977 </para>
6978 <indexterm startref='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='endofrange'/>
6979 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James</primary></indexterm>
6980 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovative freedom balanced with fair compensation in</secondary></indexterm>
6981 <para>
6982 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6983 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an <quote>environmentalism</quote> for
6984 culture.<footnote><para>
6985 <!-- f7 -->
6986 See, for example, James Boyle, <quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6987 Environmentalism for the Net?</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal</citetitle> 47 (1997): 87.
6988 </para></footnote>
6989 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6990 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6991 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6992 <quote>for free.</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6993 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6994 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6995 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6996 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6997 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6998 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6999 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
7000 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
7001 </para>
7002 <indexterm startref='idxfarming' class='endofrange'/>
7003 <para>
7004 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
7005 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
7006 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
7007 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
7008 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
7009 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
7010 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
7011 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
7012 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
7013 </para>
7014 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='endofrange'/>
7015 <para>
7016 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
7017 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
7018 be lost.
7019 </para>
7020 <indexterm startref='idxddt' class='endofrange'/>
7021 <indexterm startref='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='endofrange'/>
7022 <indexterm startref='idxenvironmentalism' class='endofrange'/>
7023 </section>
7024 <section id="beginnings">
7025 <title>Beginnings</title>
7026 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>on creative property</secondary></indexterm>
7027 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
7028 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
7029 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
7030 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
7031 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>constitutional tradition on</secondary></indexterm>
7032 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
7033 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
7034 <para>
7035 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
7036 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of <quote>creative
7037 property</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
7038 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
7039 </para>
7040 <indexterm id='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>in constitutional Progress Clause</secondary></indexterm>
7041 <para>
7042 The power to establish <quote>creative property</quote> rights is granted to
7043 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
7044 odd. Article I, section 8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that:
7045 </para>
7046 <blockquote>
7047 <para>
7048 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
7049 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
7050 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
7051 </para>
7052 </blockquote>
7053
7054 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
7055 <para>
7056 We can call this the <quote>Progress Clause,</quote> for notice what this clause
7057 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
7058 <quote>creative property rights.</quote> It says that Congress has the power
7059 <emphasis>to promote progress</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
7060 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
7061 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
7062 </para>
7063 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
7064 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
7065 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>history of American</secondary></indexterm>
7066 <para>
7067 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
7068 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="founders"/>,
7069 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
7070 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
7071 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
7072 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
7073 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
7074 copyrights extend <quote>to Authors</quote> only.
7075 </para>
7076 <indexterm><primary>Senate, U.S.</primary></indexterm>
7077 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>structural checks and balances of</secondary></indexterm>
7078 <indexterm><primary>electoral college</primary></indexterm>
7079 <para>
7080 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
7081 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
7082 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
7083 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
7084 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
7085 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
7086 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
7087 to reinforce the power of the states&mdash;including the Senate, whose
7088 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
7089 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
7090 case, a <emphasis>structure</emphasis> built checks and balances into
7091 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
7092 concentrations of power.
7093 </para>
7094 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='endofrange'/>
7095 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
7096 <para>
7097 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call <quote>copyright</quote>
7098 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
7099 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
7100 <quote>copyright</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210
7101 years since they first struck its design.
7102 </para>
7103 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='endofrange'/>
7104 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='endofrange'/>
7105 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='endofrange'/>
7106 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
7107 <para>
7108 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
7109 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
7110 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
7111 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
7112 started here:
7113 </para>
7114 <figure id="fig-1441">
7115 <title></title>
7116 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
7117 </figure>
7118 <para>
7119 We will end here:
7120 </para>
7121 <figure id="fig-1442">
7122 <title></title>
7123 <graphic fileref="images/1442.svg" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
7124 </figure>
7125 <para>
7126 Let me explain how.
7127 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
7128 </para>
7129 </section>
7130 <section id="lawduration">
7131 <title>Law: Duration</title>
7132 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
7133 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7134 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7135 <indexterm><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>common law protections of</secondary></indexterm>
7136 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>balance of U.S. content in</secondary></indexterm>
7137 <para>
7138 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
7139 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
7140 the English had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws
7141 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
7142 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
7143 authorship.<footnote>
7144 <para>
7145 <!-- f8 -->
7146 William W. Crosskey, <citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the
7147 History of the United States</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University
7148 Press, 1953), vol. 1, 485&ndash;86: <quote>extinguish[ing], by plain
7149 implication of <quote>the supreme Law of the Land,</quote>
7150 <emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or were supposed by
7151 some to have, under the Common Law</emphasis></quote> (emphasis
7152 added).
7153 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.</primary></indexterm>
7154 </para></footnote>
7155 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
7156 States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
7157 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
7158 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
7159 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
7160 domain to reprint and distribute works.
7161 </para>
7162 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
7163 <indexterm id='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>federal vs. state</secondary></indexterm>
7164 <para>
7165 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
7166 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
7167 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
7168 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
7169 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
7170 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
7171 </para>
7172 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
7173 <para>
7174 In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
7175 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
7176 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
7177 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
7178 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
7179 </para>
7180 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='endofrange'/>
7181 <para>
7182 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
7183 ten years of the Republic, only 5 percent of the works were actually
7184 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
7185 in the United States both before 1790 and from 1790 through 1800, 95
7186 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
7187 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
7188 likely within fourteen years.<footnote><para>
7189 <!-- f9 -->
7190 Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790
7191 to 1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, <citetitle>A
7192 History of Book Publishing in the United States</citetitle>, vol. 1, <citetitle>The Creation
7193 of an Industry, 1630&ndash;1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000
7194 imprints recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
7195 1790 act; William J. Maher, <citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
7196 and the Copyright Law of 1790 in Historical Context</citetitle>, 7&ndash;10 (2002),
7197 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
7198 #25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
7199 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
7200 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
7201 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
7202 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
7203 Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124. </para></footnote>
7204 </para>
7205 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact' class='endofrange'/>
7206 <indexterm startref='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='endofrange'/>
7207 <para>
7208 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
7209 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
7210 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
7211 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
7212 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
7213 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
7214 copyright, either.
7215 </para>
7216 <para>
7217 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
7218 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
7219 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
7220 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
7221 domain.<footnote><para>
7222 <!-- f10 -->
7223 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
7224 instance, of the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were
7225 renewed in 1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
7226 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, <quote>Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright,</quote>
7227 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright</citetitle>, vol. 1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
7228 1963), 618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
7229 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote>
7230 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 471, 498&ndash;501, and
7231 accompanying figures. </para></footnote>
7232 </para>
7233 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='endofrange'/>
7234 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
7235 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
7236 <para>
7237 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
7238 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
7239 out of print after one year.<footnote><para>
7240 <!-- f11 -->
7241 See Ringer, ch. 9, n. 2. </para></footnote> When that happens, the
7242 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
7243 no longer <emphasis>effectively</emphasis> controlled by
7244 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
7245 is to sell the books as used books; that use&mdash;because it does not
7246 involve publication&mdash;is effectively free.
7247 </para>
7248 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7249 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
7250 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
7251 <para>
7252 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
7253 changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28
7254 years to a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
7255 from 14 years to 28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
7256 the term increased once again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal
7257 term of 14 years to 28 years, setting a maximum term of 56 years.
7258 </para>
7259 <indexterm><primary>CTEA</primary><seealso>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</seealso></indexterm>
7260 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7261 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
7262 <para>
7263 Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
7264 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
7265 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
7266 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
7267 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
7268 In 1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
7269 And in 1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
7270 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
7271 </para>
7272 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
7273 <para>
7274 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
7275 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
7276 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
7277 years, or 70 percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years
7278
7279 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
7280 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
7281 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
7282 of the expiration of a copyright term.
7283 </para>
7284 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='endofrange'/>
7285 <para>
7286 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
7287 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
7288 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
7289 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
7290 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
7291 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
7292 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
7293 value.
7294 </para>
7295 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7296 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>of natural authors vs. corporations</secondary></indexterm>
7297 <indexterm><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>copyright terms for</secondary></indexterm>
7298 <para>
7299 The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For
7300 all works created after 1978, there was only one copyright term&mdash;the
7301 maximum term. For <quote>natural</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
7302 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992,
7303 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
7304 before 1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
7305 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
7306 was ninety-five years.
7307 </para>
7308 <para>
7309 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
7310 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
7311 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
7312 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
7313 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
7314 that terms be <quote>limited,</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
7315 them.
7316 </para>
7317 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='endofrange'/>
7318 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
7319 <para>
7320 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
7321 dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to
7322 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
7323 in 1973 was just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
7324 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
7325 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95
7326 years.<footnote><para>
7327 <!-- f12 -->
7328 These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the
7329 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
7330 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
7331 Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote> loc. cit.
7332 </para></footnote>
7333 </para>
7334 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='endofrange'/>
7335 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='endofrange'/>
7336 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='endofrange'/>
7337 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='endofrange'/>
7338 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='endofrange'/>
7339 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
7340 </section>
7341 <section id="lawscope">
7342 <title>Law: Scope</title>
7343 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7344 <para>
7345 The <quote>scope</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
7346 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
7347 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
7348 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
7349 </para>
7350 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7351 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>historical shift in copyright coverage of</secondary></indexterm>
7352 <para>
7353 In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only <quote>maps,
7354 charts, and books.</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
7355 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
7356 the author the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> copyrighted works. That
7357 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
7358 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
7359 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
7360 did not extend to what lawyers call <quote>derivative works.</quote> It would not,
7361 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
7362 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
7363 (such as a drama based on a published book).
7364 </para>
7365 <para>
7366 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
7367 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
7368 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
7369 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
7370 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
7371 work not only the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> the work, but also the
7372 exclusive right of control over any <quote>copies</quote> of that work. And most
7373 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
7374 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
7375 <quote>derivative work</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
7376 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
7377 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
7378 on the initial creative work.
7379 </para>
7380 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>marking of</secondary></indexterm>
7381 <indexterm id='idxformalities' class='startofrange'><primary>formalities</primary></indexterm>
7382 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>registration requirement of</secondary></indexterm>
7383 <para>
7384 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
7385 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
7386 complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition
7387 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
7388 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
7389 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
7390 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
7391 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
7392 famous &copy; or the word <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>. And for most
7393 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
7394 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
7395 secured.
7396 </para>
7397 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='endofrange'/>
7398 <para>
7399 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
7400 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
7401 in the first ten years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible
7402 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
7403 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
7404 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
7405 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
7406 copyrighted&mdash;that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
7407 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
7408 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
7409 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
7410 original author.
7411 </para>
7412 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>European</secondary></indexterm>
7413 <para>
7414 All of these <quote>formalities</quote> were abolished in the American system when
7415 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
7416 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
7417 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
7418 a &copy;; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
7419 copy available for others to copy.
7420 </para>
7421 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='endofrange'/>
7422 <indexterm startref='idxformalities' class='endofrange'/>
7423 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='endofrange'/>
7424 <para>
7425 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
7426 differences.
7427 </para>
7428 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact2' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7429 <para>
7430 If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who
7431 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
7432 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
7433 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
7434 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were
7435 174 publishers in the United States.<footnote><para>
7436 <!-- f13 -->
7437 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, <quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
7438 Creation of American Literature,</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
7439 International Law and Politics</citetitle> 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
7440 Federal Copyright Records, 1790&ndash;1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987).
7441
7442 </para></footnote>
7443 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
7444 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
7445 the United States&mdash;publishers.
7446 </para>
7447 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7448 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7449 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7450 <para>
7451 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
7452 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
7453 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
7454 was totally unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and made
7455 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
7456 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
7457 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
7458 were restrained.
7459 </para>
7460 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact2' class='endofrange'/>
7461 <para>
7462 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
7463 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
7464 every note to your spouse, every doodle, <emphasis>every</emphasis>
7465 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form&mdash;all of this is
7466 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
7467 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
7468 protect it.
7469 </para>
7470 <para>
7471 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
7472 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
7473 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
7474 </para>
7475 <para>
7476 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
7477 control
7478 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
7479 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of <quote>derivative
7480 rights.</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
7481 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
7482 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
7483 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
7484 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
7485 exclusive
7486 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
7487 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
7488 </para>
7489 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7490 <para>
7491 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
7492 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
7493 expansion
7494 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
7495 copyright.
7496 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
7497 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
7498 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
7499 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
7500 </para>
7501 <para>
7502 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
7503 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
7504 within a free culture&mdash;at least, it's astonishing when you
7505 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
7506 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
7507 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
7508 <emphasis>that</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
7509 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
7510 all&mdash;they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
7511 not protect derivative rights at all.<footnote><para>
7512 <!-- f14 -->
7513 Jonathan Zittrain, <quote>The Copyright Cage,</quote> <citetitle>Legal
7514 Affairs</citetitle>, July/August 2003, available at
7515 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #26</ulink>.
7516 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
7517 </para></footnote>
7518 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
7519 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7520 the wrong of direct piracy.
7521 </para>
7522 <para>
7523 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7524 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7525 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7526 of my book.<footnote><para>
7527 <!-- f15 -->
7528 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7529 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7530 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere <quote>copies</quote> and
7531 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld, <quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7532 Copyright's Constitutionality,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7533 Journal</citetitle> 112 (2002): 1&ndash;60 (see especially
7534 pp. 53&ndash;59).
7535 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb</primary></indexterm>
7536 </para></footnote>
7537 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7538 </para>
7539 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7540 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
7541 <indexterm><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
7542 <para>
7543 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7544 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7545 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7546 called <quote>Mickey Mouse,</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7547 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7548 created?
7549 </para>
7550 <para>
7551 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7552 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7553 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7554 the rights originally granted.
7555 </para>
7556 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7557 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='endofrange'/>
7558 </section>
7559 <section id="lawreach">
7560 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach</title>
7561 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7562 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7563 <para>
7564 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7565 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7566 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7567 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.<footnote><para>
7568 <!-- f16 -->
7569 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7570 certainly regulates more than <quote>copies</quote>&mdash;a public performance of a
7571 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7572 per se doesn't make a copy; 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7573 106(4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a <quote>copy</quote>; 17
7574 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section 112(a). But the presumption under the
7575 existing law (which regulates <quote>copies;</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7576 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7577 </para></footnote>
7578 </para>
7579 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
7580 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>other property rights vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7581 <para>
7582 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7583 <quote>Copies.</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7584 <emphasis>copy</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7585 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that <quote>creative
7586 property</quote> deserves the <quote>same rights</quote> as all other property, it is the
7587 <emphasis>obvious</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7588 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7589 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7590 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7591 copies should <emphasis>not</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7592 law. More precisely, they should not <emphasis>always</emphasis> be
7593 the trigger for copyright law.
7594 </para>
7595 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='endofrange'/>
7596 <para>
7597 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7598 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7599 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7600 the law of copyright automatically applies,<footnote><para>
7601 <!-- f17 -->
7602 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7603 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7604 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7605 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7606 technology.
7607 </para></footnote>
7608 because it is clear that the
7609 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7610 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7611 </para>
7612 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7613 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='endofrange'/>
7614 <para>
7615 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7616 empty circle.
7617 </para>
7618 <figure id="fig-1521">
7619 <title></title>
7620 <graphic fileref="images/1521.svg" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
7621 </figure>
7622 <indexterm id='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>three types of uses of</secondary></indexterm>
7623 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7624 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright applicability altered by technology of</secondary></indexterm>
7625 <indexterm id='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='startofrange'><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright intent altered by</secondary></indexterm>
7626 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7627 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7628 <para>
7629 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7630 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7631 all its potential <emphasis>uses</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7632 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7633 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7634 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7635 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7636 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7637 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7638 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7639 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7640 acts do not make a copy.
7641 </para>
7642 <figure id="fig-1531">
7643 <title></title>
7644 <graphic fileref="images/1531.png" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
7645 </figure>
7646 <para>
7647 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7648 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7649 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7650 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7651 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see
7652 diagram in figure <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-1541"/>).
7653 </para>
7654 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7655 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7656 <figure id="fig-1541">
7657 <title></title>
7658 <graphic fileref="images/1541.svg" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
7659 </figure>
7660 <indexterm id='idxfairuse' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary></indexterm>
7661 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7662 <para>
7663 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7664 that remain unregulated because the law considers these <quote>fair uses.</quote>
7665 </para>
7666 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7667 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
7668 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
7669 <para>
7670 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7671 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7672 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7673 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7674 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7675 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7676 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such <quote>fair uses</quote>
7677 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7678 </para>
7679 <figure id="fig-1542">
7680 <title></title>
7681 <graphic fileref="images/1542.svg" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
7682 </figure>
7683 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7684 <para>
7685 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7686 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7687 sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that
7688 are nonetheless deemed <quote>fair</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7689 </para>
7690 <indexterm startref='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='endofrange'/>
7691 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7692 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
7693 <indexterm><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7694 <para>
7695 Enter the Internet&mdash;a distributed, digital network where every use
7696 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.<footnote><para>
7697 <!-- f18 -->
7698 I don't mean <quote>nature</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7699 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7700 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7701 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7702 of copies remain.
7703 </para></footnote>
7704 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7705 digital network, the scope of category 1 changes dramatically. Uses
7706 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7707 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7708 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7709 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7710 a copy&mdash;category 1 gets sucked into category 2. And those who
7711 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7712 exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7713 shift.
7714 </para>
7715 <indexterm startref='idxfairuse' class='endofrange'/>
7716 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='endofrange'/>
7717 <para>
7718 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7719 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7720 be no plausible <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>-related argument that
7721 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7722 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7723 the book once, ten times, or every
7724 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7725 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7726 use&mdash;reading&mdash; could be regulated by copyright law because
7727 none of those uses produced a copy.
7728 </para>
7729 <indexterm id='idxebooks' class='startofrange'><primary>e-books</primary></indexterm>
7730 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>technological developments and</secondary></indexterm>
7731 <para>
7732 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7733 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7734 only once or only once a month, then <emphasis>copyright
7735 law</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7736 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7737 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7738 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7739 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7740 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7741 copyright owner's wish.
7742 </para>
7743 <figure id="fig-1551">
7744 <title></title>
7745 <graphic fileref="images/1551.svg" align="center" width="10em"></graphic>
7746 </figure>
7747 <para>
7748 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7749 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7750 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7751 points also become clear:
7752 </para>
7753 <para>
7754 First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7755 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7756 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7757 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7758 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7759 part of free culture before the Internet.
7760 </para>
7761 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7762 <para>
7763 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7764 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7765 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7766 <emphasis>any</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7767 using a machine. <quote>Copy and paste</quote> and <quote>cut and paste</quote> become
7768 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7769 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7770 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7771 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7772 creative work.
7773 </para>
7774 <indexterm id='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7775 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7776 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>fair use vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7777 <para>
7778 Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary
7779
7780 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7781 burden on category 3 (<quote>fair use</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7782 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7783 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7784 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7785 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7786 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7787 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7788 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7789 regulated.
7790 </para>
7791 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='endofrange'/>
7792 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='endofrange'/>
7793 <indexterm startref='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='endofrange'/>
7794 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='endofrange'/>
7795 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='endofrange'/>
7796 <para>
7797 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7798 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7799 depend upon fair use&mdash;never even addressing the earlier question
7800 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7801 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7802 <emphasis>unregulated</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7803 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7804 enough.
7805 </para>
7806 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='endofrange'/>
7807 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'/>
7808 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson2' class='endofrange'/>
7809 <indexterm startref='idxebooks' class='endofrange'/>
7810 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='endofrange'/>
7811 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='endofrange'/>
7812 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='endofrange'/>
7813 <indexterm id='idxvideopipeline' class='startofrange'><primary>Video Pipeline</primary></indexterm>
7814 <indexterm id='idxadvertising' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
7815 <indexterm id='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='startofrange'><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>trailer advertisements of</secondary></indexterm>
7816 <para>
7817 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7818 in the business of making <quote>trailer</quote> advertisements for movies available
7819 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7820 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7821 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7822 </para>
7823 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7824 <para>
7825 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it began
7826 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7827 previews. The idea was to expand their <quote>selling by sampling</quote>
7828 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7829 <quote>browsing.</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7830 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7831 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7832 </para>
7833 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
7834 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7835 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7836 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
7837 <para>
7838 In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7839 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7840 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7841 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7842 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7843 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter&mdash;he had built a
7844 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7845 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7846 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7847 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7848 <quote>fair use</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7849 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7850 their rights.
7851 </para>
7852 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising' class='endofrange'/>
7853 <indexterm startref='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='endofrange'/>
7854 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7855 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>willful infringement findings in</secondary></indexterm>
7856 <indexterm><primary>willful infringement</primary></indexterm>
7857 <para>
7858 Disney countersued&mdash;for $100 million in damages. Those damages
7859 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had <quote>willfully
7860 infringed</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7861 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7862 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7863 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7864 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7865 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $100 million.
7866 </para>
7867 <para>
7868 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7869 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7870 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7871 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7872 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7873 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7874 Disney's permission.
7875 </para>
7876 <indexterm><primary>first-sale doctrine</primary></indexterm>
7877 <para>
7878 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7879 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7880 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7881 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7882 was in the marketplace, the <quote>first-sale doctrine</quote> would free the
7883 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7884 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7885 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7886 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7887 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7888 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7889 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7890 </para>
7891 <indexterm startref='idxvideopipeline' class='endofrange'/>
7892 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc2' class='endofrange'/>
7893 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='endofrange'/>
7894 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='endofrange'/>
7895 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='endofrange'/>
7896 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='endofrange'/>
7897 <indexterm><primary>Barnes &amp; Noble</primary></indexterm>
7898 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7899 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
7900 <para>
7901 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7902 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7903 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes &amp; Noble has the
7904 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7905 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7906 abuse. If Barnes &amp; Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7907 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7908 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7909 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7910 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7911 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7912 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7913 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7914 happening are quite slight.
7915 </para>
7916 <para>
7917 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7918 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7919 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7920 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7921 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7922 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7923 </para>
7924 </section>
7925 <section id="lawforce">
7926 <title>Architecture and Law: Force</title>
7927 <para>
7928 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7929 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7930 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7931 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7932 </para>
7933 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>technology as automatic enforcer of</secondary></indexterm>
7934 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright enforcement controlled by</secondary></indexterm>
7935 <para>
7936 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7937 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7938 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7939 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7940 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7941 your freedom.
7942 </para>
7943 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca</primary></indexterm>
7944 <indexterm id='idxmarxbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7945 <indexterm id='idxwarnerbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7946 <para>
7947 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7948 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7949 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7950 <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7951 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7952 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7953 plan.<footnote><para>
7954 <!-- f19 -->
7955 See David Lange, <quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7956 Contemporary Problems</citetitle> 44 (1981): 172&ndash;73.
7957 </para></footnote>
7958 </para>
7959 <para>
7960 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7961 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers <quote>were brothers long before
7962 you were.</quote><footnote><para>
7963 <!-- f20 -->
7964 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
7965 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and
7966 Copywrongs</citetitle>, 1&ndash;3.
7967 </para></footnote>
7968 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7969 <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7970 trying to control <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>, then the Marx
7971 Brothers would insist on control over <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>.
7972 </para>
7973 <para>
7974 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7975 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7976 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7977 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7978 </para>
7979 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7980 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson3' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
7981 <para>
7982 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7983 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7984 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7985 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7986 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7987 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7988 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7989 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7990 </para>
7991 <indexterm startref='idxwarnerbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7992 <indexterm startref='idxmarxbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7993
7994 <indexterm id='idxadobeebookreader' class='startofrange'><primary>Adobe eBook Reader</primary></indexterm>
7995 <para>
7996 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7997 </para>
7998 <para>
7999 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
8000 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
8001 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
8002 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
8003 technology.
8004 </para>
8005 <figure id="fig-example-adobe-ebook-reader" float="1">
8006 <title></title>
8007 <graphic fileref="images/example-adobe-ebook-reader.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8008 </figure>
8009 <para>
8010 In figure
8011 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-example-adobe-ebook-reader"/>
8012 is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook Reader.
8013 </para>
8014 <para>
8015 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
8016 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
8017 public domain: <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, for example, is in
8018 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
8019 public domain: My own book <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
8020 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
8021 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
8022 copy of
8023 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
8024 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
8025 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
8026 </para>
8027 <para>
8028 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
8029 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
8030 </para>
8031 <figure id="fig-1612">
8032 <title></title>
8033 <graphic fileref="images/1612.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8034 </figure>
8035 <para>
8036 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
8037 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
8038 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
8039 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
8040 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
8041 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>
8042 read aloud through the computer.
8043 </para>
8044 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle</primary></indexterm>
8045 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics</citetitle>, (Aristotle)</primary></indexterm>
8046 <para>
8047 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
8048 translation): Aristotle's <citetitle>Politics</citetitle>.
8049 </para>
8050 <figure id="fig-1621">
8051 <title></title>
8052 <graphic fileref="images/aristotele-ebook.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8053 </figure>
8054 <para>
8055 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
8056 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
8057 the book.
8058 </para>
8059 <figure id="fig-1622">
8060 <title></title>
8061 <graphic fileref="images/1622.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8062 </figure>
8063 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
8064 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
8065 <para>
8066 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
8067 original e-book version of my last book, <citetitle>The Future of
8068 Ideas</citetitle>:
8069 </para>
8070 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
8071 <figure id="fig-1631">
8072 <title></title>
8073 <graphic fileref="images/1631.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8074 </figure>
8075 <para>
8076 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
8077 </para>
8078 <para>
8079 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
8080 <quote>permissions</quote>&mdash; as if the publisher has the power to control how
8081 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
8082 certainly does have the power&mdash;up to the limits of the copyright
8083 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
8084 power.<footnote><para>
8085 <!-- f21 -->
8086 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
8087 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
8088 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
8089 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
8090 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
8091 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
8092 subsequently acquired the book.
8093 <indexterm><primary>contracts</primary></indexterm>
8094 </para></footnote>
8095 When my e-book of <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> says I have the
8096 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
8097 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
8098 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
8099 control that the law would enable.
8100 </para>
8101 <para>
8102 The control comes instead from the code&mdash;from the technology
8103 within which the e-book <quote>lives.</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
8104 permissions, they are not the sort of <quote>permissions</quote> that most of us
8105 deal with. When a teenager gets <quote>permission</quote> to stay out till
8106 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
8107 till 2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
8108 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
8109 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
8110 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
8111 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
8112 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
8113 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
8114 aloud&mdash;it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
8115 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
8116 won't read aloud.
8117 </para>
8118 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8119 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8120 <para>
8121 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
8122 These are <emphasis>controls</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
8123 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
8124 you tried to type <quote>Warner Brothers,</quote> erased <quote>Brothers</quote> from the
8125 sentence.
8126 </para>
8127 <para>
8128 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
8129 <emphasis>law</emphasis> as copyright <emphasis>code</emphasis>. The
8130 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
8131 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
8132 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
8133 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
8134 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
8135 </para>
8136 <para>
8137 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
8138 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
8139 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
8140 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
8141 to defeat these protections as well?
8142 </para>
8143 <para>
8144 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
8145 eBook Reader.
8146 </para>
8147 <indexterm id='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='startofrange'><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)</primary></indexterm>
8148 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>e-book restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
8149 <para>
8150 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
8151 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
8152 on the Adobe site was a copy of <citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
8153 Wonderland</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
8154 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
8155 following report:
8156 </para>
8157 <figure id="fig-1641">
8158 <title></title>
8159 <graphic fileref="images/1641.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8160 </figure>
8161 <!-- PAGE BREAK 164-->
8162 <para>
8163 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
8164 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
8165 <quote>permissions</quote> indicated, not allowed to <quote>read aloud</quote>!
8166 </para>
8167 <para>
8168 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
8169 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
8170 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
8171 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
8172 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
8173 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
8174 </para>
8175 <para>
8176 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
8177 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
8178 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
8179 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
8180 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
8181 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
8182 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
8183 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
8184 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
8185 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
8186 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
8187 </para>
8188 <indexterm startref='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='endofrange'/>
8189 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='endofrange'/>
8190 <para>
8191 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
8192 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
8193 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
8194 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
8195 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
8196 often crazy.
8197 </para>
8198 <indexterm startref='idxadobeebookreader' class='endofrange'/>
8199 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson3' class='endofrange'/>
8200 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet2' class='endofrange'/>
8201 <para>
8202 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
8203 story of mine that makes the same point.
8204 </para>
8205 <indexterm id='idxaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8206 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog1' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8207 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8208 <para>
8209 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named <quote>Aibo.</quote> The Aibo
8210 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
8211 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
8212 </para>
8213 <para>
8214 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
8215 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
8216 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
8217 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
8218 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
8219 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
8220 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
8221 </para>
8222 <para>
8223 <quote>Teach</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
8224 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
8225 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
8226 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
8227 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
8228 their computer <quote>dog</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
8229 </para>
8230 <indexterm><primary>hacks</primary></indexterm>
8231 <para>
8232 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
8233 <citetitle>hack</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
8234 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
8235 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
8236 them, <citetitle>hack</citetitle> is a much more positive
8237 term. <citetitle>Hack</citetitle> just means code that enables the
8238 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
8239 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
8240 old computer doesn't run, or <quote>drive,</quote> the printer. If you discovered
8241 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
8242 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
8243 you just bought.
8244 </para>
8245 <para>
8246 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
8247 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
8248 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
8249 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
8250 ethically.
8251 </para>
8252 <para>
8253 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
8254 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
8255 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
8256 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
8257 than Sony had built.
8258 </para>
8259 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8260 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog1' class='endofrange'/>
8261 <indexterm startref='idxaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8262 <para>
8263 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
8264 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
8265 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
8266 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
8267 the
8268
8269 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
8270 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
8271 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
8272 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
8273 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
8274 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
8275 thought, <emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
8276 a robot dog to dance?</emphasis>
8277 </para>
8278 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>government case against</secondary></indexterm>
8279 <para>
8280 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show&mdash;
8281 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
8282 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
8283 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
8284 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
8285 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
8286 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
8287 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
8288 into being silent about something he knew very well.
8289 </para>
8290 <para>
8291 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.<footnote><para>
8292 <!-- f22 -->
8293 See Pamela Samuelson, <quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,</quote>
8294 <citetitle>Science</citetitle> 293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, <quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
8295 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect</citetitle>,
8296 January 2002; <quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
8297 DMCA,</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter</citetitle>, 11 December 2001; Bill
8298 Holland, <quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,</quote> <citetitle>Billboard</citetitle>,
8299 May 2001; Janelle Brown, <quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?</quote> Salon.com,
8300 April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, <quote>Frequently Asked
8301 Questions about <citetitle>Felten and USENIX</citetitle> v. <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> Legal Case,</quote> available at
8302 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #27</ulink>.
8303 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
8304 </para></footnote>
8305 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
8306 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
8307 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
8308 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
8309 </para>
8310 <para>
8311 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
8312 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
8313 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
8314 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
8315 <quote>this music cannot be copied,</quote> and have a computer respect that
8316 command. The technology was to be part of a <quote>trusted system</quote> of
8317 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
8318 Internet much more.
8319 </para>
8320 <para>
8321 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
8322 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
8323 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
8324 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
8325 </para>
8326 <para>
8327 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
8328 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
8329 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
8330 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
8331 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
8332 </para>
8333 <para>
8334 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
8335 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
8336 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
8337 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
8338 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
8339 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
8340 </para>
8341 <para>
8342 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
8343 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
8344 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
8345 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
8346 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
8347 constituted, succeed.
8348 </para>
8349 <indexterm id='idxaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8350 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog2' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8351 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8352 <para>
8353 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
8354 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
8355 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
8356 wrote:
8357 </para>
8358 <blockquote>
8359 <para>
8360 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
8361 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
8362 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
8363 </para>
8364 </blockquote>
8365 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8366 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog2' class='endofrange'/>
8367 <indexterm startref='idxaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8368 <para>
8369 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
8370 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
8371 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
8372 </para>
8373 <blockquote>
8374 <para>
8375 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
8376 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
8377 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
8378 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
8379 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (<quote>DMCA</quote>).
8380 </para>
8381 </blockquote>
8382 <para>
8383 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
8384 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
8385 spreading such information an offense.
8386 </para>
8387 <para>
8388 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
8389 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
8390 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
8391 These new technologies would be copyright protection
8392 technologies&mdash; technologies to control the replication and
8393 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
8394 <emphasis>code</emphasis> to modify the original
8395 <emphasis>code</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
8396 protection for copyright owners.
8397 </para>
8398 <para>
8399 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
8400 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
8401 <emphasis>legal code</emphasis> intended to buttress
8402 <emphasis>software code</emphasis> which itself was intended to
8403 support the <emphasis>legal code of copyright</emphasis>.
8404 </para>
8405 <para>
8406 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
8407 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
8408 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
8409 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
8410 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
8411 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
8412 have been a copyright violation.
8413 </para>
8414 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8415 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8416 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8417 <para>
8418 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
8419 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
8420 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
8421 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
8422 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
8423 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
8424 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
8425 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
8426 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
8427 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
8428 </para>
8429 <para>
8430 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
8431 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
8432 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
8433 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
8434 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
8435 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
8436 </para>
8437 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8438 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8439 <para>
8440 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
8441 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
8442 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
8443 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
8444 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
8445 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka <quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers</citetitle>,</quote>
8446 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
8447 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
8448 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8449 </para>
8450 <blockquote>
8451 <para>
8452 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
8453 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
8454 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
8455 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
8456 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
8457 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the <quote>Neighborhood</quote>
8458 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
8459 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
8460 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
8461 broadcasting has always been <quote>You are an important person just the way
8462 you are. You can make healthy decisions.</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
8463 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
8464 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
8465 important.<footnote><para>
8466 <!-- f23 -->
8467 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8468 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
8469 455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
8470 James Lardner, <citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
8471 the VCR</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270&ndash;71.
8472 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8473 </para></footnote>
8474 </para>
8475 </blockquote>
8476 <para>
8477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
8478 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
8479 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
8480 the VCR responsible.
8481 </para>
8482 <para>
8483 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon in figure
8484 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n"
8485 linkend="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/>, which we can adopt to the
8486 DMCA.
8487 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8488 </para>
8489 <para>
8490 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
8491 </para>
8492 <figure id="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig" float="1">
8493 <title>&mdash; On which item have the courts ruled that manufacturers and
8494 retailers be held responsible for having supplied the
8495 equipment?</title>
8496 <graphic fileref="images/vcr-comic.png" align="center" width="55%"></graphic>
8497 </figure>
8498 <para>
8499 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
8500 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
8501 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
8502 pirating of copyrighted material&mdash;a bad end. Or they can be used
8503 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
8504 would be considered fair use&mdash;a good end.
8505 </para>
8506 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'><primary>handguns</primary></indexterm>
8507 <para>
8508 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
8509 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
8510 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
8511 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
8512 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
8513 and bad uses.
8514 </para>
8515 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8516 <para>
8517 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
8518 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
8519 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: <emphasis>No one ever
8520 died from copyright circumvention</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
8521 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
8522 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
8523 </para>
8524 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'/>
8525 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'/>
8526 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8527 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8528 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8529 <para>
8530 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
8531 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
8532 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
8533 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
8534 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
8535 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
8536 </para>
8537 <para>
8538 This is how <emphasis>code</emphasis> becomes
8539 <emphasis>law</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
8540 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
8541 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
8542 law&mdash;increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
8543 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
8544 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
8545 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect&mdash;at
8546 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
8547 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
8548 </para>
8549 <para>
8550 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
8551 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
8552 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
8553 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
8554 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
8555 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
8556 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
8557 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
8558 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
8559 </para>
8560 <para>
8561
8562 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
8563 For example, imagine you were part of a <citetitle>Star Trek</citetitle> fan club. You
8564 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
8565 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
8566 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
8567 simply continue it.<footnote><para>
8568 <!-- f24 -->
8569 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, <quote>Legal Fictions,
8570 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
8571 Entertainment Law Journal</citetitle> 17 (1997): 651.
8572 </para></footnote>
8573 </para>
8574 <para>
8575 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
8576 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
8577 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
8578 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
8579 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
8580 </para>
8581 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
8582 <para>
8583 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
8584 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
8585 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
8586 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
8587 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
8588 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
8589 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
8590 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
8591 </para>
8592 <para>
8593 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
8594 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
8595 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
8596 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8597 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8598 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8599 </para>
8600 </section>
8601 <section id="marketconcentration">
8602 <title>Market: Concentration</title>
8603 <para>
8604 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically&mdash;tripled in
8605 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8606 well&mdash;from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8607 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8608 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8609 find better ways
8610 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8611 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8612 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8613 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8614 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8615 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8616 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8617 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8618 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8619 control.
8620 </para>
8621 <para>
8622 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8623 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8624 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8625 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8626 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8627 </para>
8628 <para>
8629 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8630 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8631 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8632 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8633 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8634 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8635 announced in June 2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8636 live in a world where just three companies control more than 85 percent
8637 of the media.
8638 </para>
8639 <para>
8640 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8641 nature.
8642 </para>
8643 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8644 <indexterm><primary>BMG</primary></indexterm>
8645 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
8646 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John</primary></indexterm>
8647 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8648 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8649 <para>
8650 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8651 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8652 ownership, <quote>five companies control 85 percent of our media sources.</quote><footnote><para>
8653 <!-- f25 -->
8654 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8655 Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003)
8656 (statement of Senator John McCain). </para></footnote>
8657 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8658 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 percent of the
8659 U.S. music market.<footnote><para>
8660 <!-- f26 -->
8661 Lynette Holloway, <quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8662 Slide,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 23 December 2002.
8663 </para></footnote>
8664 The <quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8665 programming to 74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.</quote><footnote><para>
8666 <!-- f27 -->
8667 Molly Ivins, <quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette</citetitle>,
8668 31 May 2003.
8669 </para></footnote>
8670 </para>
8671 <indexterm id='idxradioownershipconsolidationin' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>ownership consolidation in</secondary></indexterm>
8672 <para>
8673 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8674 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8675 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8676 seventy-five stations. Today <emphasis>one</emphasis> company owns
8677 more than 1,200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8678 total number of radio owners dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most
8679 markets, the two largest broadcasters control 74 percent of that
8680 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control 90 percent of
8681 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8682 </para>
8683 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8684 <indexterm id='idxnewspapersownershipconsolidationof' class='startofrange'><primary>newspapers</primary><secondary>ownership consolidation of</secondary></indexterm>
8685 <para>
8686 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8687 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8688 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8689 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8690 the United States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all
8691 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent
8692 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8693 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8694 protected&mdash; by the market.
8695 </para>
8696 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8697 <para>
8698 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8699 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8700 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8701 </para>
8702 <blockquote>
8703 <para>
8704 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8705 unmatched in its integration. They supply content&mdash;Fox movies
8706 &hellip; Fox TV shows &hellip; Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8707 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8708 advertisers&mdash;in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8709 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8710 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8711 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8712 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8713 the same function in the United States.<footnote><para>
8714 <!-- f28 -->
8715 James Fallows, <quote>The Age of Murdoch,</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly</citetitle> (September
8716 2003): 89.
8717 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8718 </para></footnote>
8719 </para>
8720 </blockquote>
8721 <indexterm startref='idxnewspapersownershipconsolidationof' class='endofrange'/>
8722 <indexterm startref='idxradioownershipconsolidationin' class='endofrange'/>
8723 <para>
8724 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8725 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8726 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8727 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8728 </para>
8729 <figure id="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership">
8730 <title></title>
8731 <graphic fileref="images/pattern-modern-media-ownership.png" align="center" width="100%"></graphic>
8732 </figure>
8733 <para>
8734 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8735 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8736 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8737 distribute content?
8738 </para>
8739 <para>
8740 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8741 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8742 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8743 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8744 </para>
8745 <para>
8746 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8747 integration may matter.
8748 </para>
8749 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman</primary></indexterm>
8750 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8751 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8752 <para>
8753 In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle>. He took
8754 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8755 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8756 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8757 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8758 </para>
8759 <para>
8760 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8761 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8762 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8763 control.<footnote><para>
8764 <!-- f29 -->
8765 Leonard Hill, <quote>The Axis of Access,</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8766 Forum, <quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,</quote> St. Louis,
8767 Missouri, 3 April 2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8768 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #28</ulink>;
8769 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8770 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #29</ulink>).
8771 </para></footnote>
8772 </para>
8773 <para>
8774
8775 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8776 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8777 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8778 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8779 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992,
8780 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8781 television&mdash;75 percent of it&mdash;was <quote>independent</quote> of the
8782 networks.
8783 </para>
8784 <para>
8785 In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8786 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985,
8787 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8788 2002, only five independent television studios remained. <quote>In 1992,
8789 only 15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8790 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8791 controlled companies more than quintupled to 77 percent.</quote> <quote>In 1992, 16
8792 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8793 year there was one.</quote><footnote><para>
8794 <!-- f30 -->
8795 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8796 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st
8797 sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8798 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8799 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8800 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8801 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February
8802 2003.
8803 </para></footnote>
8804 In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8805 that ran it. <quote>In the ten-year period between 1992 and 2002, the number
8806 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8807 increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8808 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8809 63%.</quote><footnote><para>
8810 <!-- f31 -->
8811 Ibid.
8812 </para></footnote>
8813 </para>
8814 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8815 <para>
8816 Today, another Norman Lear with another <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle> would
8817 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8818 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8819 owned by the network.
8820 </para>
8821 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry</primary></indexterm>
8822 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill</primary></indexterm>
8823 <para>
8824 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8825 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8826 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8827 </para>
8828 <blockquote>
8829 <para>
8830 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8831 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8832 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8833 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8834 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8835 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8836 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8837 handful.<footnote><para>
8838 <!-- f32 -->
8839 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers</citetitle>, Bill
8840 Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at
8841 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #31</ulink>.
8842 </para></footnote>
8843 </para>
8844 </blockquote>
8845 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>media concentration and</secondary></indexterm>
8846 <para>
8847 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8848 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8849 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8850 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8851 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8852 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8853 question without risk of consequence&mdash;not necessarily banishment
8854 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8855 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8856 democracy.
8857 </para>
8858 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.</primary></indexterm>
8859 <para>
8860 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8861 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the <quote>Innovator's
8862 Dilemma</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8863 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8864 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8865 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.<footnote><para>
8866 <!-- f33 -->
8867 Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8868 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle>
8869 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press, 1997). Christensen
8870 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8871 Kim B. Clark, <quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8872 Concepts in Technological Evolution,</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy</citetitle> 14 (1985):
8873 235&ndash;51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8874 Kaplan, <citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8875 Underperform the Market&mdash;and How to Successfully Transform Them</citetitle>
8876 (New York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001). </para></footnote>
8877
8878 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8879 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8880 sprinting.
8881 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
8882 </para>
8883 <para>
8884 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8885 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8886 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8887 measure.
8888 </para>
8889 <para>
8890 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8891 suggest the concern.
8892 </para>
8893 <para>
8894 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8895 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8896 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8897 </para>
8898 <indexterm><primary>criminal justice system</primary></indexterm>
8899 <para>
8900 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8901 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8902 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8903
8904 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8905 wrecked by drugs&mdash;though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8906 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8907 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8908 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8909 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8910 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8911 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8912 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8913 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8914 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8915 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8916 outweigh these costs.
8917 </para>
8918 <para>
8919 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8920 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8921 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8922 these issues.
8923 </para>
8924 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8925 <indexterm id='idxcommercials' class='startofrange'><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
8926 <indexterm id='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='startofrange'><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
8927 <indexterm><primary>Nick and Norm anti-drug campaign</primary></indexterm>
8928 <para>
8929 Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8930 a media campaign as part of the <quote>war on drugs.</quote> The campaign produced
8931 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8932 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8933 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8934 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8935 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8936 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8937 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8938 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8939 </para>
8940 <para>
8941 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8942 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8943 </para>
8944 <para>
8945 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8946 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8947 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8948 war. Can you do it?
8949 </para>
8950 <para>
8951 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8952 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8953 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8954 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8955 message will be heard then?
8956 </para>
8957 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
8958 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
8959 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on television advertising bans</secondary></indexterm>
8960 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>controversy avoided by</secondary></indexterm>
8961 <para>
8962 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8963 <quote>controversial</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8964 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8965 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8966 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8967 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8968 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8969 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8970 rights of the stations to be this biased.<footnote><para>
8971 <!-- f34 -->
8972 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8973 <indexterm><primary>Comcast</primary></indexterm>
8974 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project</primary></indexterm>
8975 <indexterm><primary>NBC</primary></indexterm>
8976 <indexterm><primary>WJOA</primary></indexterm>
8977 <indexterm><primary>WRC</primary></indexterm>
8978 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8979 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads
8980 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8981 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as <quote>against
8982 [their] policy.</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8983 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8984 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8985 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8986 Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8987 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, <quote>On the
8988 Issue of an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV
8989 Networks,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 13 March
8990 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time there is very little
8991 that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to even the playing
8992 field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, <quote>Ad Hoc Access:
8993 The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8994 Radio,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review</citetitle> 6
8995 (1988): 449&ndash;79, and for a more recent summary of the stance of
8996 the FCC and the courts, see <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors
8997 Association</citetitle> v. <citetitle>FCC</citetitle>, 184 F. 3d 872
8998 (D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8999 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
9000 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
9001 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, <quote>Antidiesel Group
9002 Fuming After Muni Rejects Ad,</quote> SFGate.com, 16 June 2003,
9003 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9004 #32</ulink>. The ground was that the criticism was <quote>too
9005 controversial.</quote>
9006 </para></footnote>
9007 </para>
9008 <indexterm startref='idxcommercials' class='endofrange'/>
9009 <indexterm startref='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='endofrange'/>
9010 <para>
9011 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well&mdash;if we lived
9012 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
9013 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
9014 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
9015 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
9016 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
9017 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
9018 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
9019 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
9020 </para>
9021 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'/>
9022 </section>
9023 <section id="together">
9024 <title>Together</title>
9025 <para>
9026 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
9027 copyright warriors that the government should <quote>protect my property.</quote>
9028 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
9029 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
9030 </para>
9031 <para>
9032 But when we see how dramatically this <quote>property</quote> has changed&mdash;
9033 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
9034 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
9035 cultivate our culture is dramatically different&mdash;the claim begins
9036 to seem
9037
9038 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
9039 less innocent and obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to
9040 supplement the law's control, and (2) the power of concentrated
9041 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
9042 the massively expanded <quote>property</quote> rights granted by copyright
9043 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
9044 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
9045 be redefined.
9046 </para>
9047 <para>
9048 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
9049 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
9050 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
9051 our culture today.
9052 </para>
9053 <para>
9054 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
9055 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
9056 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
9057 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
9058 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
9059 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
9060 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
9061 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
9062 traditionally defined copyright's regulation&mdash;a weakening of that
9063 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
9064 </para>
9065 <para>
9066 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
9067 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
9068 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
9069 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
9070 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
9071 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
9072 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
9073 future. And these changes have to be <emphasis>reductions</emphasis>
9074 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
9075 in control that technology and the market enable.
9076 </para>
9077 <para>
9078 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
9079 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
9080 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
9081 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
9082 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
9083 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
9084 more of the development of our culture than now</emphasis>.
9085 </para>
9086 <para>
9087 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
9088 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
9089 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
9090 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
9091 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
9092 were independent of the networks. <emphasis>Never</emphasis> has
9093 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
9094 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
9095 regulation&mdash;a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
9096 energy of a nation at the founding&mdash;is now a massive regulation
9097 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
9098 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
9099 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
9100 known.<footnote><para>
9101 <!-- f35 -->
9102 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
9103 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his <quote>four surrenders</quote> of
9104 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan, 159&ndash;60.
9105 </para></footnote>
9106 </para>
9107 <para>
9108 <emphasis role='strong'>This has been</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
9109 point can now be briefly stated.
9110 </para>
9111 <para>
9112 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
9113 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
9114 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
9115 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
9116 that copyright law has undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this:
9117 </para>
9118
9119 <informaltable id="t2">
9120 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9121 <thead>
9122 <row>
9123 <entry></entry>
9124 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9125 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9126 </row>
9127 </thead>
9128 <tbody>
9129 <row>
9130 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9131 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9132 <entry>Free</entry>
9133 </row>
9134 <row>
9135 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9136 <entry>Free</entry>
9137 <entry>Free</entry>
9138 </row>
9139 </tbody>
9140 </tgroup>
9141 </informaltable>
9142
9143 <para>
9144 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
9145 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
9146 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
9147
9148 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
9149 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
9150 noncommercial work was also free.
9151 </para>
9152 <para>
9153 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
9154 </para>
9155
9156 <informaltable id="t3">
9157 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9158 <thead>
9159 <row>
9160 <entry></entry>
9161 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9162 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9163 </row>
9164 </thead>
9165 <tbody>
9166 <row>
9167 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9168 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9169 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9170 </row>
9171 <row>
9172 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9173 <entry>Free</entry>
9174 <entry>Free</entry>
9175 </row>
9176 </tbody>
9177 </tgroup>
9178 </informaltable>
9179
9180 <para>
9181 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law&mdash;if
9182 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
9183 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
9184 transformation were still essentially free.
9185 </para>
9186 <para>
9187 In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
9188 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
9189 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
9190 expanded. Thus by 1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
9191 we could say the law began to look like this:
9192 </para>
9193
9194 <informaltable id="t4">
9195 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9196 <thead>
9197 <row>
9198 <entry></entry>
9199 <entry>COPY</entry>
9200 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9201 </row>
9202 </thead>
9203 <tbody>
9204 <row>
9205 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9206 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9207 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9208 </row>
9209 <row>
9210 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9211 <entry>&copy; / Free</entry>
9212 <entry>Free</entry>
9213 </row>
9214 </tbody>
9215 </tgroup>
9216 </informaltable>
9217
9218 <para>
9219 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
9220 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
9221 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
9222 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
9223 that the law now looks like this:
9224 </para>
9225
9226 <informaltable id="t5">
9227 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9228 <thead>
9229 <row>
9230 <entry></entry>
9231 <entry>COPY</entry>
9232 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9233 </row>
9234 </thead>
9235 <tbody>
9236 <row>
9237 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9238 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9239 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9240 </row>
9241 <row>
9242 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9243 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9244 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9245 </row>
9246 </tbody>
9247 </tgroup>
9248 </informaltable>
9249
9250 <para>
9251 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
9252 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
9253 creativity&mdash;
9254 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
9255 commercial or not, transformative or not&mdash;with the same rules
9256 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
9257 </para>
9258 <para>
9259 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
9260 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
9261 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
9262 these domains actually does any good.
9263 </para>
9264 <para>
9265 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
9266 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
9267 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
9268 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
9269 reasons sketched especially in chapters
9270 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/> and
9271 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>, one
9272 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
9273 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
9274 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
9275 </para>
9276 <para>
9277 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
9278 course copyright is a kind of <quote>property,</quote> and of course, as with any
9279 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
9280 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
9281 property rights<footnote><para>
9282 <!-- f36 -->
9283 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement</primary></indexterm>
9284 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
9285 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
9286 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, <quote>The
9287 Disintegration of Property,</quote> in <citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property</citetitle>, J. Roland
9288 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
9289 Press, 1980).
9290 </para></footnote>)
9291 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
9292 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
9293 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
9294 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the <quote>copyright</quote>
9295 did not control <emphasis>at all</emphasis> the freedom of others to
9296 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
9297 free, and for almost 180 years our country consistently protected a
9298 vibrant and rich free culture.
9299 </para>
9300 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
9301 <para>
9302 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
9303 limits on the scope of the interests protected by <quote>property.</quote> The very
9304 birth of <quote>copyright</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
9305 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
9306 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9307 linkend="founders"/>). The tradition of <quote>fair use</quote> is
9308 animated by a similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the
9309 costs of exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the
9310 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9311 linkend="recorders"/>). Adding
9312 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
9313 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
9314 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter <xref
9315 xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>). And
9316 granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect, claims of
9317 property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing the soul
9318 of a culture (chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9319 linkend="collectors"/>). Free cultures, like free markets, are built
9320 with property. But the nature of the property that builds a free
9321 culture is very different from the extremist vision that dominates the
9322 debate today.
9323 </para>
9324 <para>
9325 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
9326 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
9327 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
9328 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
9329 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
9330 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
9331 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
9332 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
9333 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
9334 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
9335 lawyer.
9336 </para>
9337 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
9338 </section>
9339 </chapter>
9340 </part>
9341 <part id="c-puzzles">
9342 <title>Puzzles</title>
9343
9344 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
9345 <chapter label="11" id="chimera">
9346 <title>Chapter Eleven: Chimera</title>
9347 <indexterm id='idxchimera' class='startofrange'><primary>chimeras</primary></indexterm>
9348 <indexterm id='idxwells' class='startofrange'><primary>Wells, H. G.</primary></indexterm>
9349 <indexterm id='idxtcotb' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The</quote> (Wells)</primary></indexterm>
9350
9351 <para>
9352 <emphasis role='strong'>In a well-known</emphasis> short story by
9353 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
9354 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
9355 Andes.<footnote><para>
9356 <!-- f1. -->
9357 H. G. Wells, <quote>The Country of the Blind</quote> (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells,
9358 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
9359 York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
9360 </para></footnote>
9361 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with <quote>sweet water, pasture,
9362 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
9363 that bore an excellent fruit.</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
9364 takes this as an opportunity. <quote>In the Country of the Blind,</quote> he tells
9365 himself, <quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.</quote> So he resolves to live with the
9366 villagers to explore life as a king.
9367 </para>
9368 <para>
9369 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
9370 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
9371 <quote>blind.</quote> They don't have the word <citetitle>blind</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
9372 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
9373 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
9374 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. <quote><quote>You
9375 don't understand,</quote> he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
9376 resolute, and which broke. <quote>You are blind and I can see. Leave me
9377 alone!</quote></quote>
9378 </para>
9379 <para>
9380 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
9381 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
9382 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
9383 affection, a young woman who to him seems <quote>the most beautiful thing in
9384 the whole of creation,</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
9385 description of what he sees <quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
9386 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
9387 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
9388 indulgence.</quote> <quote>She did not believe,</quote> Wells tells us, and <quote>she could
9389 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.</quote>
9390 </para>
9391 <para>
9392 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his <quote>mysteriously delighted</quote>
9393 love, the father and the village object. <quote>You see, my dear,</quote> her
9394 father instructs, <quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
9395 anything right.</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
9396 </para>
9397 <para>
9398 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. <quote>His brain
9399 is affected,</quote> he reports.
9400 </para>
9401 <para>
9402 <quote>What affects it?</quote> the father asks. <quote>Those queer things that are
9403 called the eyes &hellip; are diseased &hellip; in such a way as to affect
9404 his brain.</quote>
9405 </para>
9406 <para>
9407 The doctor continues: <quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
9408 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
9409 simple and easy surgical operation&mdash;namely, to remove these
9410 irritant bodies [the eyes].</quote>
9411 </para>
9412 <para>
9413 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
9414 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
9415 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
9416 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
9417 </para>
9418 <para>
9419 <emphasis role='strong'>It sometimes</emphasis> happens that the eggs
9420 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
9421 <quote>chimera.</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
9422 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
9423 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
9424
9425 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
9426 plot for murder mysteries. <quote>But the DNA shows with 100 percent
9427 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
9428 scene. &hellip;</quote>
9429 </para>
9430 <indexterm startref='idxtcotb' class='endofrange'/>
9431 <indexterm startref='idxwells' class="endofrange"/>
9432 <para>
9433 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
9434 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
9435 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
9436 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
9437 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
9438 understanding of a <quote>person</quote> should reflect this reality.
9439 </para>
9440 <para>
9441 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
9442 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
9443 unfairly enough, <quote>the copyright wars,</quote> the more I think we're dealing
9444 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question <quote>What is
9445 p2p file sharing?</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
9446 wrong. One side says, <quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
9447 others' records&mdash;the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
9448 thirty years without any question at all.</quote> That's true, at least in
9449 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
9450 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
9451 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
9452 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
9453 </para>
9454 <para>
9455 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
9456 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
9457 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
9458 <quote>friends</quote> beyond recognition to say <quote>my ten thousand best friends</quote> can
9459 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
9460 what <quote>we have always been allowed to do,</quote> we have not always been
9461 allowed to share music with <quote>our ten thousand best friends.</quote>
9462 </para>
9463 <para>
9464 Likewise, when the other side says, <quote>File sharing is just like walking
9465 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
9466 with it,</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
9467 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
9468 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
9469 from Tower.
9470 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9471 </para>
9472 <para>
9473
9474 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
9475 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
9476 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
9477 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
9478 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
9479 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
9480 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
9481 $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
9482 CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.)
9483 </para>
9484 <para>
9485 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
9486 that it is both&mdash;both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
9487 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
9488 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
9489 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
9490 </para>
9491 <para>
9492 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
9493 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
9494 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
9495 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
9496 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
9497 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
9498 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
9499 implemented.<footnote><para>
9500 <!-- f2. -->
9501 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9502 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
9503 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
9504 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003,
9505 available at
9506 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9507 #33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
9508 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
9509 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
9510 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, <quote>House Bill Aims to Up
9511 Stakes on Piracy,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 17 July 2003, available at
9512 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #34</ulink>. Civil
9513 penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied song. For a recent
9514 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
9515 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 songs
9516 through a family computer, see <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
9517 re. Verizon Internet Services)</citetitle>, 240 F. Supp. 2d 24
9518 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $90
9519 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
9520 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
9521 $12,000 to $17,500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
9522 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $98
9523 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
9524 Elizabeth Young, <quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,</quote> redandblack.com,
9525 August 2003, available at
9526 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #35</ulink>. For an
9527 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
9528 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
9529 identities, see James Collins, <quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
9530 Name Students,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 8 August 2003, D3, available at
9531 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #36</ulink>.
9532 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
9533 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
9534 </para></footnote>
9535
9536 </para>
9537 <indexterm startref='idxchimera' class='endofrange'/>
9538 <para>
9539 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
9540 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
9541 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
9542 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
9543 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
9544 </para>
9545 <para>
9546 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
9547 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
9548 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
9549 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
9550 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
9551 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe <emphasis>either</emphasis> extreme
9552 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
9553 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
9554 </para>
9555 <para>
9556
9557 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
9558 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
9559 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
9560 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
9561 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
9562 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
9563 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
9564 </para>
9565 <para>
9566 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to <quote>steal</quote> music. My
9567 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
9568 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
9569 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
9570 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
9571 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
9572 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
9573 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
9574 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
9575 protection for copyrighted material,
9576 </para>
9577 <blockquote>
9578 <para>
9579 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
9580 material, and we want to protect those rights.
9581 </para>
9582 <para>
9583 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
9584 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
9585 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
9586 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
9587 produce a totally different industry model.
9588 </para>
9589 <para>
9590 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
9591 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
9592 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
9593 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
9594 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
9595 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
9596 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
9597 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
9598 interests.<footnote><para>
9599 <!-- f3. -->
9600 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
9601 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
9602 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
9603 House Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement of Peter
9604 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
9605 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
9606 Congressional Testimony File. </para></footnote>
9607 </para>
9608 </blockquote>
9609 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
9610 <para>
9611 In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
9612 one of <quote>the major labels.</quote> Its position on these matters has now
9613 changed.
9614 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9615 </para>
9616 <para>
9617 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
9618 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9619 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9620 </para>
9621
9622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9623 </chapter>
9624 <chapter label="12" id="harms">
9625 <title>Chapter Twelve: Harms</title>
9626 <para>
9627 <emphasis role='strong'>To fight</emphasis> <quote>piracy,</quote> to
9628 protect <quote>property,</quote> the content industry has launched a
9629 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9630 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9631 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9632 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9633 </para>
9634 <para>
9635 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9636 particular, the consequences for <quote>free culture.</quote> But my aim now is to
9637 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9638 justified?
9639 </para>
9640 <para>
9641 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9642 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9643 power of the property called <quote>intellectual property</quote> is at its greatest in
9644 our history.
9645 </para>
9646 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
9647 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
9648 <para>
9649 Yet <quote>common sense</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9650 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9651 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9652 rejection of <quote>piracy</quote> still has play.
9653 </para>
9654 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9655 <para>
9656 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9657 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9658 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9659 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9660 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9661 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9662 </para>
9663 <section id="constrain">
9664 <title>Constraining Creators</title>
9665 <para>
9666 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9667 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9668 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9669 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9670 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9671 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9672 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9673 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9674 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9675 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9676 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9677 weave together a string&mdash;a mash-up&mdash; of songs from your
9678 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9679 </para>
9680 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>digital sharing within</secondary></indexterm>
9681 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
9682 <para>
9683 This digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> is in part an extension of the
9684 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9685 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9686 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9687 of digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9688 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9689 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9690 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9691 the culture all around.
9692 </para>
9693 <para>
9694 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9695 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9696
9697 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9698
9699 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9700 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9701 storytelling extended across the globe.
9702 </para>
9703 <para>
9704 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9705 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9706 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9707 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9708 that catalog cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9709 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9710 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9711 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9712 work is presumptively illegal.
9713 </para>
9714 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom</primary></indexterm>
9715 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9716 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9717 <indexterm><primary>doctors malpractice claims against</primary></indexterm>
9718 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
9719 <para>
9720 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9721 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9722 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9723 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9724 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9725 by the RIAA (Jesse Jordan of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9726 labelnumber" linkend="catalogs"/> was just one) were threatened with a
9727 $98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted songs
9728 to be copied. Yet World-Com&mdash;which defrauded investors of $11
9729 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization of
9730 over $200 billion&mdash;received a fine of a mere $750
9731 million.<footnote><para>
9732 <!-- f1. -->
9733 See Lynne W. Jeter, <citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom</citetitle>
9734 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley &amp; Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of
9735 the settlement, see MCI press release, <quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9736 Approval for SEC Settlement</quote> (7 July 2003), available at
9737 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #37</ulink>.
9738 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom</primary></indexterm>
9739 </para></footnote>
9740 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9741 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9742 no more than $250,000 in damages for pain and
9743 suffering.<footnote>
9744 <para>
9745 <!-- f2. -->
9746 The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9747 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For
9748 an overview, see Tanya Albert, <quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: <quote>We'll Be Back,</quote>
9749 Say Tort Reformers,</quote> amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at
9750 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #38</ulink>,
9751 and <quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,</quote> CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003,
9752 available at
9753 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9754 recent months.
9755 <indexterm><primary>tort reform</primary></indexterm>
9756 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.</primary></indexterm>
9757 </para></footnote>
9758 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9759 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9760 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9761 </para>
9762 <indexterm><primary>art, underground</primary></indexterm>
9763 <para>
9764 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9765 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9766 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9767 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9768 Disneys <quote>pirates.</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9769 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9770 designed to
9771
9772 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9773 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9774 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9775 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9776 we will begin to see a world of underground art&mdash;not because the
9777 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9778 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9779 fraught. Already, exhibits of <quote>illegal art</quote> tour the United
9780 States.<footnote><para>
9781 <!-- f3. -->
9782
9783 See Danit Lidor, <quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,</quote> <citetitle>Wired</citetitle>, 7 July
9784 2003, available at
9785 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9786 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #41</ulink>.
9787 </para></footnote>
9788 In what does their <quote>illegality</quote> consist?
9789 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9790 critical or reflective.
9791 </para>
9792 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9793 <para>
9794 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9795 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9796 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. But an
9797 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9798 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9799 discovered in 2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9800 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9801 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9802 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9803 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9804 </para>
9805 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
9806 <para>
9807 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9808 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9809 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9810 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9811 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9812 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9813 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9814 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9815 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9816 </para>
9817 <para>
9818 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9819 described in chapter
9820 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/>, in
9821 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9822 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9823 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9824 use.
9825 </para>
9826 <para>
9827
9828 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9829 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9830 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9831 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad&mdash;in
9832 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9833 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9834 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9835 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9836 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9837 </para>
9838 <para>
9839 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9840 <quote>breathing room</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9841 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9842 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9843 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9844 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9845 journalists&mdash; these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9846 these rules have little relationship to the <quote>law</quote> with which judges
9847 comfort themselves.
9848 </para>
9849 <para>
9850 For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful
9851 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9852 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9853 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9854 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak&mdash;in that
9855 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9856 <quote>copyright</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9857 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9858 culture that is free.
9859 </para>
9860 <para>
9861 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9862 </para>
9863 <blockquote>
9864 <para>
9865 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9866 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9867 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9868 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made &hellip; you're not
9869 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9870 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9871 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, <quote>This has been
9872 cleared.</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9873 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9874 </para>
9875 </blockquote>
9876 </section>
9877 <section id="innovators">
9878 <title>Constraining Innovators</title>
9879 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovation hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
9880 <indexterm id='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>innovation</primary><secondary>industry establishment opposed to</secondary></indexterm>
9881 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
9882 <para>
9883 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9884 story&mdash;creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9885 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9886 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9887 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9888 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9889 </para>
9890 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints2' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9891 <para>
9892 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9893 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9894 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9895 one at that, <xref xrefstyle="select: pagenumber"
9896 linkend="innovators"/> pages into a book like this), then you
9897 can see this other aspect by substituting <quote>free market</quote>
9898 every place I've spoken of <quote>free culture.</quote> The point is
9899 the same, even if the interests affecting culture are more
9900 fundamental.
9901 </para>
9902 <para>
9903 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9904 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9905 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary&mdash;at
9906 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9907 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9908 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9909 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9910 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9911 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9912 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9913 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9914 </para>
9915 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints2' class='endofrange'/>
9916 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9917 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
9918 <para>
9919 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9920 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9921 strategy that I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9922 labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9923 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9924 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9925 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9926 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9927 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9928 lesson. That lesson&mdash;what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9929 <quote>nuclear pall</quote> that has fallen over the Valley&mdash;has been learned.
9930 </para>
9931 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
9932 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
9933 <para>
9934 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9935 I told in <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9936 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9937 </para>
9938 <indexterm id='idxmpcom' class='startofrange'><primary>MP3.com</primary></indexterm>
9939 <indexterm id='idxmympcom' class='startofrange'><primary>my.mp3.com</primary></indexterm>
9940 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael</primary></indexterm>
9941 <para>
9942 In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9943 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9944 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9945 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9946 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9947 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9948 </para>
9949 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9950 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>preference data on</secondary></indexterm>
9951 <para>
9952 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9953 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9954 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9955 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9956 Raitt. And so on.
9957 </para>
9958 <para>
9959 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9960 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9961 preference data. In January 2000, the company launched a service
9962 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9963 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9964 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9965 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9966 wherever you were&mdash;at work or at home&mdash;you could get access
9967 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9968 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9969 </para>
9970 <para>
9971 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9972 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9973
9974 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9975 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9976 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9977 the kind of content the users liked.
9978 </para>
9979 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'/>
9980 <para>
9981 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000
9982 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9983 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9984 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9985 therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9986 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9987 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9988 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was 50,000
9989 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers something
9990 they had already bought.
9991 </para>
9992 <indexterm id='idxvivendiuniversal' class='startofrange'><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9993 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
9994 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9995 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9996 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
9997 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
9998 <indexterm><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>outsize penalties of</secondary></indexterm>
9999 <para>
10000 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
10001 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
10002 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
10003 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
10004 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
10005 MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
10006 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $54 million. Vivendi
10007 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
10008 </para>
10009 <para>
10010 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
10011 </para>
10012 <para>
10013 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
10014 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
10015 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
10016 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
10017 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
10018 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
10019 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
10020 demanded.
10021 </para>
10022 <indexterm startref='idxvivendiuniversal' class='endofrange'/>
10023 <para>
10024 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
10025 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
10026 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
10027 clients in this
10028 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
10029 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
10030 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
10031 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
10032 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
10033 </para>
10034 <indexterm startref='idxmpcom' class='endofrange'/>
10035 <indexterm startref='idxmympcom' class='endofrange'/>
10036 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='endofrange'/>
10037 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
10038 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
10039 <indexterm id='idxbmw' class='startofrange'><primary>BMW</primary></indexterm>
10040 <indexterm id='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='startofrange'><primary>cars, MP3 sound systems in</primary></indexterm>
10041 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
10042 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John</primary></indexterm>
10043 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
10044 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad</primary></indexterm>
10045 <indexterm><primary>MP3 players</primary></indexterm>
10046 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>venture capital for</secondary></indexterm>
10047 <indexterm id='idxneedlemanrafe' class='startofrange'><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
10048 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
10049 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
10050 <para>
10051 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003,
10052 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
10053 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
10054 its development, its cofounder (John Hummer), and general partner
10055 (Hank Barry).<footnote><para>
10056 <!-- f4. -->
10057 See Joseph Menn, <quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
10058 Times</citetitle>, 23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
10059 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, <quote>The Music
10060 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,</quote> Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available
10061 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #42</ulink>.
10062 See also Jon Healey, <quote>Online Music Services Besieged,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
10063 Times</citetitle>, 28 May 2001.
10064 </para></footnote>
10065 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
10066 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
10067 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
10068 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
10069 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
10070 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
10071 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
10072 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
10073 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
10074 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
10075 <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
10076 discussion with BMW:
10077 </para>
10078 <blockquote>
10079 <para>
10080 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
10081 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
10082 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
10083 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
10084 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
10085 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
10086 United States with bona fide MP3 players. &hellip; <footnote>
10087 <para>
10088 <!-- f5. -->
10089 Rafe Needleman, <quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,</quote> <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, 16 June
10090 2003, available at
10091 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #43</ulink>. I am grateful
10092 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
10093 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
10094 </para></footnote>
10095 </para>
10096 </blockquote>
10097 <indexterm startref='idxbmw' class='endofrange'/>
10098 <indexterm startref='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='endofrange'/>
10099 <indexterm startref='idxneedlemanrafe' class='endofrange'/>
10100 <para>
10101 This is the world of the mafia&mdash;filled with <quote>your money or your
10102 life</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
10103 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
10104 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
10105 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
10106 constantly threatened by litigation.
10107 </para>
10108 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints3' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
10109 <indexterm id='idxpermissionculturetransactioncostof' class='startofrange'><primary>permission culture</primary><secondary>transaction cost of</secondary></indexterm>
10110 <indexterm><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>outsize penalties of</secondary></indexterm>
10111 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>legal murkiness on</secondary></indexterm>
10112 <para>
10113
10114 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
10115 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
10116 enterprises. The point is the definition of <quote>illegal.</quote> The law is a
10117 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
10118 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
10119 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
10120 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
10121 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
10122 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
10123 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
10124 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
10125 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
10126 much less creativity.
10127 </para>
10128 <para>
10129 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
10130 use. Whatever the <quote>real</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
10131 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
10132 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
10133 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
10134 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
10135 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
10136 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
10137 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
10138 produce an overregulated-regulated market.
10139 </para>
10140 <para>
10141 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
10142 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
10143 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
10144 culture&mdash;a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
10145 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
10146 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
10147 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
10148 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
10149 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
10150 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
10151 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
10152 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
10153 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
10154 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
10155 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
10156 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
10157 result.
10158 </para>
10159 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints3' class='endofrange'/>
10160 <indexterm startref='idxpermissionculturetransactioncostof' class='endofrange'/>
10161 <para>
10162 <emphasis role='strong'>The uncertainty</emphasis> of the law is one
10163 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
10164 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
10165 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
10166 better protects their content.
10167 </para>
10168 <para>
10169 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
10170 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
10171 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
10172 this feature is a <quote>bug.</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
10173 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
10174 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
10175 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables <quote>piracy,</quote> then,
10176 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
10177 </para>
10178 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10179 <para>
10180 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
10181 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
10182 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
10183 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.<footnote><para>
10184 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> GartnerG2 and
10185 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
10186 (2003), 33&ndash;35, available at
10187 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10188 </para></footnote>
10189 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
10190 <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
10191 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
10192 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
10193 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
10194 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
10195 copyright violators and disable their machines.<footnote><para>
10196 <!-- f7. -->
10197 GartnerG2, 26&ndash;27.
10198 </para></footnote>
10199 </para>
10200 <para>
10201 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
10202 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
10203 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
10204 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
10205 and costs on
10206 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
10207 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
10208 those requirements.
10209 </para>
10210 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
10211 <para>
10212 In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
10213 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
10214 would impose.<footnote><para>
10215 <!-- f8. -->
10216 See David McGuire, <quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,</quote> Newsbytes,
10217 February 2002 (Entertainment).
10218 </para></footnote>
10219 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
10220 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
10221 harm than good.
10222 </para>
10223 <para>
10224 <emphasis role='strong'>There is one</emphasis> more obvious way in
10225 which this war has harmed innovation&mdash;again, a story that will be
10226 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
10227 </para>
10228 <para>
10229 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
10230 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
10231 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
10232 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
10233 </para>
10234 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
10235 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
10236 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
10237 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
10238 <para>
10239 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10240 linkend="property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
10241 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
10242 Jessica Litman in her book <citetitle>Digital
10243 Copyright</citetitle>,<footnote><para>
10244 <!-- f9. -->
10245 Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (Amherst,
10246 N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 2001).
10247 <indexterm><primary>Digital Copyright (Litman)</primary></indexterm>
10248 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
10249 </para></footnote>
10250 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter
10251 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/> details,
10252 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
10253 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
10254 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
10255 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
10256 </para>
10257 <para>
10258 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
10259 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
10260 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
10261 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
10262 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
10263 </para>
10264 <indexterm id='idxinternetradioon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>radio on</secondary></indexterm>
10265 <indexterm id='idxradiooninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
10266 <para>
10267 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.<footnote><para>
10268 <!-- f10. -->
10269 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.</primary></indexterm>
10270 The only circuit court exception is found in <citetitle>Recording Industry
10271 Association of America (RIAA)</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems</citetitle>, 180 F. 3d
10272 1072 (9th Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
10273 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
10274 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
10275 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
10276 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
10277 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
10278 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Grokster, Ltd</citetitle>., 259 F. Supp. 2d
10279 1029 (C.D. Cal., 2003), where the court found the link between the
10280 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
10281 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
10282 liability.
10283 </para></footnote>
10284 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
10285 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
10286 here.<footnote><para>
10287 <!-- f11. -->
10288 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy</primary></indexterm>
10289 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
10290 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz</primary></indexterm>
10291 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10292 For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
10293 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize
10294 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
10295 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
10296 August 2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
10297 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
10298 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that
10299 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
10300 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
10301 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
10302 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, <quote>Copyright and
10303 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003, 33&ndash;34,
10304 available at
10305 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10306 </para></footnote>
10307 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
10308 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
10309 </para>
10310 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10311 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
10312 <indexterm><primary>Monroe, Marilyn</primary></indexterm>
10313 <indexterm id='idxradiomusicrecordingsplayedon2' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>music recordings played on</secondary></indexterm>
10314 <para>
10315
10316 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
10317 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10318 linkend="pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
10319 artist doesn't get paid for that <quote>radio performance</quote> unless he or she
10320 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
10321 version of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote>&mdash;to memorialize her famous
10322 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden&mdash;
10323 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
10324 copyright owners of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> would get some money, whereas
10325 Marilyn Monroe would not.
10326 </para>
10327 <para>
10328 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
10329 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
10330 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
10331 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
10332 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
10333 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
10334 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
10335 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
10336 recording artists.
10337 </para>
10338 <indexterm startref='idxradiomusicrecordingsplayedon2' class='endofrange'/>
10339 <para>
10340 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
10341 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
10342 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
10343 spectrum. Thus, I can <quote>tune in</quote> to an Internet radio station in
10344 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
10345 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
10346 metropolitan area.
10347 </para>
10348 <para>
10349 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
10350 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
10351 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
10352 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
10353 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
10354 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
10355 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
10356 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
10357 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
10358 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
10359 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
10360 </para>
10361 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
10362 <para>
10363
10364 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
10365 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
10366 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
10367 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
10368 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
10369 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
10370 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
10371 FM radio,
10372 </para>
10373 <blockquote>
10374 <para>
10375 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
10376 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
10377 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
10378 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
10379 than by technical restrictions. &hellip; Armstrong likened the situation
10380 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
10381 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
10382 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
10383 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
10384 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
10385 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
10386 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
10387 shackles.<footnote><para>
10388 <!-- f12. -->
10389 Lessing, 239.
10390 </para></footnote>
10391 </para>
10392 </blockquote>
10393 <para>
10394 This potential for FM radio was never realized&mdash;not
10395 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
10396 underestimated the power of <quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
10397 legislation</quote><footnote><para>
10398 <!-- f13. -->
10399 Ibid., 229.
10400 </para></footnote>
10401 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
10402 </para>
10403 <para>
10404 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
10405 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
10406 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
10407 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
10408 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
10409 radio?
10410 </para>
10411 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10412 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
10413 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on radio</secondary></indexterm>
10414 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
10415 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10416 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
10417 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>Internet radio hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
10418 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10419 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
10420 <para>
10421 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
10422 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
10423
10424 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
10425 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
10426 of Internet radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
10427 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
10428 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
10429 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
10430 of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> on the air, <emphasis>Internet radio
10431 does</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
10432 radio&mdash;the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
10433 burdens terrestrial radio.
10434 </para>
10435 <para>
10436 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
10437 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
10438 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
10439 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
10440 over $1 million a year.<footnote>
10441 <para>
10442 <!-- f14. -->
10443 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
10444 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
10445 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
10446 iLaw (Stanford), 3 July 2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
10447 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
10448 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
10449 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP
10450 DTRA 1 and 2, available at
10451 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #45</ulink>.
10452 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
10453 C. Picker, <quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
10454 Distribution,</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin</citetitle> (Summer/Fall 2002): 461: <quote>This was
10455 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
10456 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
10457 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
10458 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
10459 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.</quote>
10460 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)</primary></indexterm>
10461 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
10462 </para></footnote>
10463 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
10464 equivalent fee.
10465 </para>
10466 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='endofrange'/>
10467 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='endofrange'/>
10468 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='endofrange'/>
10469 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='endofrange'/>
10470 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='endofrange'/>
10471 <para>
10472 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
10473 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
10474 station) would have to collect the following data from <emphasis>every
10475 listening transaction</emphasis>:
10476 </para>
10477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
10478 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
10479 <listitem><para>
10480 name of the service;
10481 </para></listitem>
10482 <listitem><para>
10483 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
10484 </para></listitem>
10485 <listitem><para>
10486 type of program (archived/looped/live);
10487 </para></listitem>
10488 <listitem><para>
10489 date of transmission;
10490 </para></listitem>
10491 <listitem><para>
10492 time of transmission;
10493 </para></listitem>
10494 <listitem><para>
10495 time zone of origination of transmission;
10496 </para></listitem>
10497 <listitem><para>
10498 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
10499 </para></listitem>
10500 <listitem><para>
10501 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
10502 </para></listitem>
10503 <listitem><para>
10504 sound recording title;
10505 </para></listitem>
10506 <listitem><para>
10507 ISRC code of the recording;
10508 </para></listitem>
10509 <listitem><para>
10510 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
10511 </para></listitem>
10512 <listitem><para>
10513 featured recording artist;
10514 </para></listitem>
10515 <listitem><para>
10516 retail album title;
10517 </para></listitem>
10518 <listitem><para>
10519 recording label;
10520 </para></listitem>
10521 <listitem><para>
10522 UPC code of the retail album;
10523 </para></listitem>
10524 <listitem><para>
10525 catalog number;
10526 </para></listitem>
10527 <listitem><para>
10528 copyright owner information;
10529 </para></listitem>
10530 <listitem><para>
10531 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
10532 </para></listitem>
10533 <listitem><para>
10534 name of the service or entity;
10535 </para></listitem>
10536 <listitem><para>
10537 channel or program;
10538 </para></listitem>
10539 <listitem><para>
10540 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
10541 </para></listitem>
10542 <listitem><para>
10543 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
10544 </para></listitem>
10545 <listitem><para>
10546 time zone where the signal was received (user);
10547 </para></listitem>
10548 <listitem><para>
10549 unique user identifier;
10550 </para></listitem>
10551 <listitem><para>
10552 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
10553 </para></listitem>
10554 </orderedlist>
10555 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
10556 <para>
10557 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
10558 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
10559 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
10560 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
10561 Internet radio has to pay a <emphasis>type of copyright fee</emphasis>
10562 that terrestrial radio does not.
10563 </para>
10564 <para>
10565 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
10566 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
10567 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
10568 </para>
10569 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
10570 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
10571 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10572 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10573 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10574 <para>
10575 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
10576 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
10577 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
10578 </para>
10579 <blockquote>
10580 <para>
10581 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
10582 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
10583 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
10584 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
10585 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
10586 webcasters asked the RIAA, &hellip; <quote>How do you come up with a
10587
10588 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
10589 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
10590 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
10591 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
10592 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
10593 business. &hellip;</quote>
10594 </para>
10595 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10596 <para>
10597 And the RIAA experts said, <quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
10598 industry with thousands of webcasters, <emphasis>we think it should be
10599 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
10600 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market</emphasis>.</quote> (Emphasis
10601 added.)
10602 </para>
10603 </blockquote>
10604 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'/>
10605 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='endofrange'/>
10606 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='endofrange'/>
10607 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='endofrange'/>
10608 <para>
10609 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
10610 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
10611 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
10612 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
10613 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
10614 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
10615 effective to prevent it.
10616 </para>
10617 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10618 <indexterm startref='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='endofrange'/>
10619 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='endofrange'/>
10620 <indexterm startref='idxinternetradioon' class='endofrange'/>
10621 <indexterm startref='idxradiooninternet' class='endofrange'/>
10622 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10623 </section>
10624 <section id="corruptingcitizens">
10625 <title>Corrupting Citizens</title>
10626 <para>
10627 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
10628 dinosaurs
10629 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
10630 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
10631 </para>
10632 <para>
10633 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
10634 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
10635 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
10636 </para>
10637 <para>
10638 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
10639 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
10640 large number of citizens. According to <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, 43 million
10641 Americans downloaded music in May 2002.<footnote><para>
10642 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, <quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,</quote> Pew
10643 Internet and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at
10644 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #46</ulink>.
10645 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that 37 million
10646 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early 2001.
10647 </para></footnote>
10648 According to the RIAA,
10649 the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
10650 set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As the
10651
10652 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
10653 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
10654 the world, but against students building search engines, and
10655 increasingly
10656 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
10657 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
10658 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
10659 extreme
10660 response by the other.
10661 </para>
10662 <para>
10663 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
10664 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
10665 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
10666 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
10667 ($15,000,000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
10668 paying all the money in the world in damages ($250,000 in legal fees)
10669 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
10670 ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
10671 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September 2003, the RIAA
10672 sued 261 individuals&mdash;including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
10673 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
10674 was.<footnote><para>
10675 <!-- f16. -->
10676 Alex Pham, <quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,</quote> <citetitle>Los
10677 Angeles Times</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, Business.
10678 </para></footnote>
10679 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
10680 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
10681 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000
10682 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
10683 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
10684 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
10685 they oppose.
10686 </para>
10687 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition</primary></indexterm>
10688 <para>
10689 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
10690 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
10691 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
10692 consumption of alcohol was 1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
10693 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just 30 percent
10694 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10695 consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition
10696 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10697 number were criminals.<footnote><para>
10698 <!-- f17. -->
10699 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, <quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10700 Prohibition,</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review</citetitle> 81, no. 2 (1991): 242.
10701 </para></footnote>
10702 We have
10703 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10704 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10705 narcotics that 7 percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.<footnote><para>
10706 <!-- f18. -->
10707 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10708 Reform Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of
10709 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10710 </para></footnote>
10711 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of
10712 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10713 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10714 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10715 cheat.<footnote><para>
10716 <!-- f19. -->
10717 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, <quote>Tax
10718 Compliance,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature</citetitle> 36 (1998): 818 (survey of
10719 compliance literature).
10720 </para></footnote>
10721 We pride ourselves on our <quote>free society,</quote> but an endless array of
10722 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10723 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10724 </para>
10725 <indexterm><primary>law schools</primary></indexterm>
10726 <para>
10727 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10728 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10729 students about the importance of <quote>ethics.</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10730 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10731 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10732 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10733 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10734 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10735 teach them how to behave ethically&mdash;how to say no to bribes, or
10736 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10737 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10738 Americans&mdash;more significantly in some parts of America than in
10739 others, but still, everywhere in America today&mdash;can't live their
10740 lives both normally and legally, since <quote>normally</quote> entails a certain
10741 degree of illegality.
10742 </para>
10743 <para>
10744 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10745 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10746 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10747 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10748 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10749 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10750 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10751 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10752 to consider the alternative.
10753 </para>
10754 <para>
10755
10756 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10757 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10758 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10759 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10760 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10761 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10762 </para>
10763 <para>
10764 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10765 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10766 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10767 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10768 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10769 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10770 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10771 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10772 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10773 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10774 introduced this different idea of <quote>sharing.</quote> We need to be able to
10775 call these twenty million Americans <quote>citizens,</quote> not <quote>felons.</quote>
10776 </para>
10777 <para>
10778 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10779 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10780 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10781 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10782 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10783 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10784 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10785 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10786 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10787 a nation of felons?
10788 </para>
10789 <para>
10790 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10791 </para>
10792 <para>
10793 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10794 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10795 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10796 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10797 used
10798
10799 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10800 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That <quote>use</quote> of the
10801 recordings is free.
10802 </para>
10803 <para>
10804 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10805 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10806 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am <quote>free</quote> to copy,
10807 or <quote>rip,</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10808 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that <quote>freedom</quote> was a
10809 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the <quote>Rip, Mix, Burn</quote>
10810 capacities of digital technologies.
10811 </para>
10812 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda</primary></indexterm>
10813 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>mix technology and</secondary></indexterm>
10814 <para>
10815 This <quote>use</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10816 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10817 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10818 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10819 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10820 Others&mdash;the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10821 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10822 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10823 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10824 </para>
10825 <para>
10826 This use is enabled by unprotected media&mdash;either CDs or records.
10827 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10828 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10829 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10830 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10831 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10832 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10833 on people's machines.
10834 </para>
10835 <para>
10836 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10837 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10838 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10839 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10840 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10841 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10842
10843 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10844 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10845 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10846 plastic or were part of a massively complex <quote>digital rights
10847 management</quote> system.
10848 </para>
10849 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'/>
10850 <para>
10851 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10852 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10853 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10854 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10855 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10856 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10857 freedom to move content easily?
10858 </para>
10859 <para>
10860 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10861 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10862 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10863 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10864 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10865 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10866 alternative&mdash;namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10867 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10868 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10869 </para>
10870 <para>
10871 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10872 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10873 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10874 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10875 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10876 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10877 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10878 </para>
10879 <para>
10880 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10881 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10882 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10883 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10884 </para>
10885 <para>
10886 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10887 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10888
10889 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10890
10891 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10892 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10893 </para>
10894 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
10895 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
10896 <para>
10897 <emphasis role='strong'>There's one more</emphasis> aspect to this
10898 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10899 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10900 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10901 <quote>collateral damage</quote> that <quote>arises whenever you turn
10902 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.</quote> This
10903 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10904 </para>
10905 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10906 <para>
10907 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,</quote> von Lohmann
10908 explains,
10909 </para>
10910 <blockquote>
10911 <para>
10912 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10913 evaporate to one degree or another. &hellip; If you're a copyright
10914 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10915 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10916 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10917 access? &hellip; Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, <quote>Oh, well,
10918 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.</quote> Well, what this campaign
10919 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10920 American Internet-using population into <quote>lawbreakers.</quote>
10921 </para>
10922 </blockquote>
10923 <para>
10924 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10925 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10926 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10927 </para>
10928 <para>
10929 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA
10930 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10931 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10932 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10933 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10934 an Internet user is revealed.
10935 </para>
10936 <para>
10937 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10938 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10939 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10940 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10941 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10942 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10943 the family could be liable for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10944 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10945 Jesse Jordan.<footnote><para>
10946 <!-- f20. -->
10947 See Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10948 Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,</quote>
10949 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, <quote>Worried Parents
10950 Pull Plug on File <quote>Stealing</quote>; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10951 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10952 Being Sued,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson
10953 Graham, <quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 15 September
10954 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, <quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10955 Fan, Either,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 25 September 2003, C1; Margo Varadi, <quote>Is
10956 Brianna a Criminal?</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star</citetitle>, 18 September 2003, P7.
10957 </para></footnote>
10958
10959 </para>
10960 <indexterm id='idxnapsterrecordingindustrytrackingusersof' class='startofrange'><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>recording industry tracking users of</secondary></indexterm>
10961 <para>
10962 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10963 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10964 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.<footnote><para>
10965 <!-- f21. -->
10966 See <quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10967 Some Methods Used,</quote> CNN.com, available at
10968 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #47</ulink>.
10969 </para></footnote>
10970 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10971 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10972 one of those MP3s will have the same <quote>fingerprint.</quote>
10973 </para>
10974 <para>
10975 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10976 friend gives a CD to your daughter&mdash;a collection of songs just
10977 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10978 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10979 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10980 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10981 network is <quote>cooperating</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10982 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10983 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10984 as a <quote>criminal.</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10985 to deploy,<footnote><para>
10986 <!-- f22. -->
10987 See Jeff Adler, <quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,</quote>
10988 <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, <quote>Four
10989 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10990 Colleges,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10991 <quote>Students <quote>Rip, Mix, Burn</quote> at Their Own Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10992 Monitor</citetitle>, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, <quote>Music
10993 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10994 Lawsuit Possible,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 16 July 2003, 1C; Beth Cox, <quote>RIAA
10995 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,</quote> <citetitle>Internet News</citetitle>, 30 January
10996 2003, available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10997 #48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Download Warning 101: Freshman
10998 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10999 Sharing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 11 August 2003, E11; <quote>Raid, Letters
11000 Are Weapons at Universities,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 26 September 2000, 3D.
11001 </para></footnote>
11002 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
11003 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
11004 </para>
11005 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'/>
11006 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
11007 <para>
11008 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
11009 a lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
11010 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
11011 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
11012 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
11013 this <quote>contraband</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
11014 college students
11015
11016 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
11017 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
11018 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
11019 Says von Lohmann,
11020 </para>
11021 <indexterm startref='idxnapsterrecordingindustrytrackingusersof' class='endofrange'/>
11022 <blockquote>
11023 <para>
11024 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
11025 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
11026 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
11027 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
11028 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
11029 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
11030 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
11031 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
11032 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
11033 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
11034 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
11035 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
11036 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
11037 larger number of Americans than drug use. &hellip; If forty to sixty
11038 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
11039 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
11040 million of them.
11041 </para>
11042 </blockquote>
11043 <para>
11044 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered <quote>criminals</quote> under
11045 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective&mdash;
11046 securing rights to authors&mdash;without these millions being
11047 considered <quote>criminals,</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
11048 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
11049 effort through our democracy to change our law?
11050 </para>
11051
11052 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
11053 </section>
11054 </chapter>
11055 </part>
11056 <part id="c-balances">
11057 <title>Balances</title>
11058 <partintro>
11059
11060 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
11061 <para>
11062 <emphasis role='strong'>So here's</emphasis> the picture: You're
11063 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
11064 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
11065 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
11066 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
11067 </para>
11068 <para>
11069 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
11070 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
11071 stop&mdash;or before she understands just why she should
11072 stop&mdash;the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
11073 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
11074 everything around.
11075 </para>
11076 <para>
11077 <emphasis role='strong'>A war</emphasis> about copyright rages all
11078 around&mdash;and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
11079 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
11080 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
11081 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
11082 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
11083 that if let alone would burn itself out.
11084 </para>
11085 <para>
11086 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
11087 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
11088 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
11089 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
11090 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
11091 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
11092 made that is happening all around.
11093 </para>
11094 <para>
11095 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
11096 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
11097 gasoline onto this fire.
11098 </para>
11099 <para>
11100 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
11101 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
11102 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
11103 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
11104 </para>
11105 <para>
11106 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
11107 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
11108 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
11109 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
11110 success will require.
11111 </para>
11112 </partintro>
11113
11114 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
11115 <chapter label="13" id="eldred">
11116 <title>Chapter Thirteen: Eldred</title>
11117 <indexterm id='idxeldrederic' class='startofrange'><primary>Eldred, Eric</primary></indexterm>
11118 <indexterm id='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='startofrange'><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel</primary></indexterm>
11119 <para>
11120 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
11121 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
11122 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
11123 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
11124 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
11125 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
11126 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
11127 </para>
11128 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>of public-domain literature</secondary></indexterm>
11129 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>library of works derived from</secondary></indexterm>
11130 <para>
11131 It didn't work&mdash;at least for his daughters. They didn't find
11132 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
11133 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
11134 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
11135 them available for free.
11136 </para>
11137 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt5' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11138 <indexterm><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
11139 <para>
11140 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
11141 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
11142 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
11143 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
11144 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
11145 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
11146 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
11147 many others, into a form more accessible&mdash;technically
11148 accessible&mdash;today.
11149 </para>
11150 <indexterm><primary>Scarlet Letter, The (Hawthorne)</primary></indexterm>
11151 <para>
11152 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
11153 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's <citetitle>Scarlet Letter</citetitle> had passed into the
11154 public domain in 1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
11155 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
11156 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
11157 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
11158 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
11159 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (<citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle>), sometimes not
11160 (<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame</citetitle>, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>). These are all
11161 commercial publications of public domain works.
11162 </para>
11163 <indexterm startref='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='endofrange'/>
11164 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt5' class='endofrange'/>
11165 <para>
11166 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
11167 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
11168 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
11169 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
11170 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
11171 call the <quote>noncommercial publishing industry,</quote> which before the
11172 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
11173 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
11174 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
11175 generally.<footnote><para>
11176 <!-- f1. -->
11177 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
11178 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
11179 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
11180 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers&mdash;people who
11181 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
11182 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
11183 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
11184 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
11185 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
11186 Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on
11187 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
11188 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
11189 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
11190 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
11191 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
11192 protect noncommercial pornographers.</para></footnote>
11193 </para>
11194 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
11195 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11196 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
11197 <indexterm><primary>Frost, Robert</primary></indexterm>
11198 <indexterm><primary>New Hampshire (Frost)</primary></indexterm>
11199 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
11200 <indexterm id='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
11201 <para>
11202 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's
11203 collection of poems <citetitle>New Hampshire</citetitle> was slated to
11204 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
11205 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
11206 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
11207 linkend="property-i"/>, in 1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
11208 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights&mdash;this time by
11209 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
11210 than 1923 to his collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
11211 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
11212 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
11213 more than 1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
11214 </para>
11215 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='endofrange'/>
11216 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
11217 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11218 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11219 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
11220 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11221 <para>
11222
11223 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
11224 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
11225 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
11226 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
11227 <quote>copyrights should be forever.</quote><footnote><para>
11228 <!-- f2. -->
11229 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11230 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11231 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>perpetual copyright term proposed by</secondary></indexterm>
11232 The full text is: <quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
11233 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
11234 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
11235 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
11236 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
11237 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
11238 Congress,</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998).
11239 </para></footnote>
11240 </para>
11241 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
11242 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>felony punishment for infringement of</secondary></indexterm>
11243 <indexterm><primary>NET (No Electronic Theft) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11244 <indexterm><primary>No Electronic Theft (NET) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11245 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>felony punishments for</secondary></indexterm>
11246 <para>
11247 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
11248 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
11249 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
11250 second law passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
11251 of publishing would make Eldred a felon&mdash;whether or not anyone
11252 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
11253 to undertake.
11254 </para>
11255 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='endofrange'/>
11256 <indexterm id='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
11257 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
11258 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause2' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
11259 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11260 <para>
11261 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
11262 constitutional
11263 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
11264 interpretation.
11265 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
11266 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
11267 importantly
11268 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
11269 </para>
11270 <blockquote>
11271 <para>
11272 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science &hellip;
11273 by securing for limited Times to Authors &hellip; exclusive Right to
11274 their &hellip; Writings. &hellip;
11275 </para>
11276 </blockquote>
11277 <indexterm startref='idxeldrederic' class='endofrange'/>
11278 <para>
11279 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
11280 clause of Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
11281 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
11282 something&mdash;for example, to regulate <quote>commerce among the several
11283 states</quote> or <quote>declare War.</quote> But here, the <quote>something</quote> is something quite
11284 specific&mdash;to <quote>promote &hellip; Progress</quote>&mdash;through means that
11285 are also specific&mdash; by <quote>securing</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights</quote> (i.e.,
11286 copyrights) <quote>for limited Times.</quote>
11287 </para>
11288 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='endofrange'/>
11289 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause2' class='endofrange'/>
11290 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='endofrange'/>
11291 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
11292 <para>
11293 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
11294 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
11295 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
11296 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be <quote>limited</quote> will have
11297 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
11298 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
11299 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
11300 what the Constitution plainly forbids&mdash;perpetual terms <quote>on the
11301 installment plan,</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
11302 </para>
11303 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='endofrange'/>
11304 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='endofrange'/>
11305 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11306 <para>
11307 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
11308 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
11309 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
11310 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
11311 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
11312 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
11313 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
11314 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
11315 this gravy train going.
11316 </para>
11317 <para>
11318 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
11319 government. <quote>Corruption</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
11320 bribed. Rather, <quote>corruption</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
11321 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
11322 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
11323 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
11324 do&mdash;and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
11325 </para>
11326 <para>
11327 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
11328 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
11329 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
11330 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry
11331 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
11332 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
11333 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
11334 published by anyone for free.
11335 </para>
11336 <para>
11337 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from
11338 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
11339 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
11340 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
11341 report:
11342 </para>
11343 <para>
11344 <quote>Next year,</quote> the adviser announces, <quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
11345
11346 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
11347 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
11348 receiving the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of
11349 those works.</quote>
11350 </para>
11351 <para>
11352 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,</quote> she continues, <quote>that
11353 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
11354 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
11355 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.</quote>
11356 </para>
11357 <para>
11358 <quote>Hope?</quote> a fellow board member says. <quote>Can't we be doing something
11359 about it?</quote>
11360 </para>
11361 <para>
11362 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>We could contribute
11363 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
11364 they support the bill.</quote>
11365 </para>
11366 <para>
11367 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
11368 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. <quote>How much
11369 would we get if this extension were passed?</quote> you ask the adviser. <quote>How
11370 much is it worth?</quote>
11371 </para>
11372 <para>
11373 <quote>Well,</quote> the adviser says, <quote>if you're confident that you will continue
11374 to get at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
11375 <quote>discount rate</quote> that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent),
11376 then this law would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate.</quote>
11377 </para>
11378 <para>
11379 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
11380 correct conclusion:
11381 </para>
11382 <para>
11383 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
11384 $1,000,000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
11385 contributions
11386 would assure that the bill was passed?</quote>
11387 </para>
11388 <para>
11389 <quote>Absolutely,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>It is worth it to you to
11390 contribute
11391 up to the <quote>present value</quote> of the income you expect from these
11392 copyrights. Which for us means over $1,000,000.</quote>
11393 </para>
11394 <para>
11395 You quickly get the point&mdash;you as the member of the board and, I
11396 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
11397 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
11398 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
11399 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
11400 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
11401 copyrights
11402 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
11403 the copyright term extended.
11404 </para>
11405 <para>
11406 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
11407 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
11408 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
11409 </para>
11410 <para>
11411 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
11412 Copyright
11413 Term Extension Act, this <quote>theory</quote> about incentives was proved
11414 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
11415 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
11416 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
11417 contributions.<footnote><para>
11418 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, <quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
11419 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years,</quote>
11420 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 17 October 1998, 22.
11421 </para></footnote>
11422 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
11423 $1.5 million lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more
11424 than $200,000 in campaign contributions.<footnote><para>
11425 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, <quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
11426 Age,</quote> available at
11427 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #49</ulink>.
11428 </para></footnote>
11429 Disney is estimated to have
11430 contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in the
11431 cycle.<footnote><para>
11432 <!-- f5. -->
11433 Alan K. Ota, <quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,</quote>
11434 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week</citetitle>, 8 August 1990, available at
11435 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #50</ulink>.
11436 </para></footnote>
11437
11438 </para>
11439 <para>
11440 <emphasis role='strong'>Constitutional law</emphasis> is not oblivious
11441 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
11442 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
11443 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
11444 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
11445 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
11446 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
11447 constitutional requirement that terms be <quote>limited.</quote> If
11448 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
11449 again.
11450 </para>
11451 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='endofrange'/>
11452 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='endofrange'/>
11453 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='endofrange'/>
11454 <para>
11455 It was also my judgment that <emphasis>this</emphasis> Supreme Court
11456 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
11457 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
11458 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
11459 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
11460 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
11461 Supreme Court's
11462
11463 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
11464 decision in 1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
11465 guns near schools.
11466 </para>
11467 <indexterm id='idxcommerceinterstate' class='startofrange'><primary>commerce, interstate</primary></indexterm>
11468 <indexterm id='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
11469 <indexterm id='idxinterstatecommerce' class='startofrange'><primary>interstate commerce</primary></indexterm>
11470 <para>
11471 Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
11472 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
11473 power to regulate only <quote>commerce among the several states</quote> (aka
11474 <quote>interstate
11475 commerce</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
11476 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
11477 interstate
11478 commerce.
11479 </para>
11480 <para>
11481 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
11482 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
11483 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
11484 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
11485 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
11486 </para>
11487 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
11488 <indexterm id='idxunitedstatesvlopez' class='startofrange'><primary>United States v. Lopez</primary></indexterm>
11489 <para>
11490 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
11491 that in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The government had
11492 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
11493 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
11494 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
11495 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
11496 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
11497 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
11498 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
11499 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
11500 position to second-guess Congress.
11501 </para>
11502 <para>
11503 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,</quote>
11504 the Chief Justice wrote.<footnote><para>
11505 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995).
11506 </para></footnote>
11507 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
11508 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
11509 Congress's power. The decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
11510 later in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>.<footnote><para>
11511 <!-- f7. -->
11512 <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>, 529 U.S. 598 (2000).
11513 <indexterm><primary>United States v. Morrison</primary></indexterm>
11514 </para></footnote>
11515 </para>
11516 <indexterm startref='idxcommerceinterstate' class='endofrange'/>
11517 <indexterm startref='idxunitedstatesvlopez' class='endofrange'/>
11518 <para>
11519 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
11520 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.<footnote><para>
11521 <!-- f8. -->
11522 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
11523 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
11524 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
11525 by the government would allow the government unending power to
11526 regulate commerce&mdash;the limitation to interstate commerce
11527 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
11528 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
11529 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights&mdash;the
11530 limitation to <quote>limited times</quote> notwithstanding.
11531 </para></footnote>
11532 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
11533 yield the conclusion that Congress
11534 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
11535 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
11536 term, then there would be no <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power over
11537 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
11538 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
11539 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
11540 term of existing copyrights.
11541 </para>
11542 <indexterm startref='idxinterstatecommerce' class='endofrange'/>
11543 <indexterm id='idxcongressussupremecourtrestrainton2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>Supreme Court restraint on</secondary></indexterm>
11544 <indexterm><primary>United States v. Lopez</primary></indexterm>
11545 <para>
11546 <emphasis>If</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
11547 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> stood for
11548 politics&mdash;a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
11549 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
11550 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
11551 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
11552 demonstrating the <quote>fidelity</quote> in such an interpretation of the
11553 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
11554 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
11555 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
11556 were going to be petty politicians.
11557 </para>
11558 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof2' class='endofrange'/>
11559 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
11560 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
11561 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11562 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11563 <para>
11564 <emphasis role='strong'>Now let's pause</emphasis> for a moment to
11565 make sure we understand what the argument in
11566 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
11567 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
11568 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
11569 piracy&mdash;piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
11570 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
11571 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
11572 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
11573 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
11574 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
11575 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
11576 power&mdash;expressed through the power of lobbyists' money&mdash;to
11577 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
11578 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
11579 piracy that affects us all.
11580 </para>
11581 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association</primary></indexterm>
11582 <para>
11583 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
11584
11585 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
11586 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
11587 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than <quote>legal piracy.</quote><footnote><para>
11588 <!-- f9. -->
11589 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11590 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available
11591 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #51</ulink>.
11592 </para></footnote>
11593 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
11594 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
11595 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
11596 charter.
11597 </para>
11598 <para>
11599 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
11600 copyright
11601 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
11602 influence
11603 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
11604 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
11605 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
11606 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
11607 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
11608 bought to extend them again.
11609 </para>
11610 <indexterm startref='idxcongressussupremecourtrestrainton2' class='endofrange'/>
11611
11612 <para>
11613 <emphasis role='strong'>It is valuable</emphasis> copyrights that are
11614 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
11615 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.</quote> These works are too valuable for
11616 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
11617 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
11618 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
11619 the 1920s and 1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
11620 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
11621 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
11622 and no longer available as a result.
11623 </para>
11624 <para>
11625 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to
11626 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
11627 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
11628 copyright holders for that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
11629 But the law and its effect were not limited to that 2 percent. The law
11630 extended the terms of copyright generally.<footnote><para>
11631 <!-- f10. --> The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
11632 Congressional
11633 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
11634 of Petitioners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 7, available at
11635 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #52</ulink>.
11636 </para></footnote>
11637
11638 </para>
11639 <indexterm><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
11640 <para>
11641 Think practically about the consequence of this
11642 extension&mdash;practically,
11643 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
11644
11645 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
11646 work. In 1930, 10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those
11647 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
11648 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
11649 remaining
11650 9,873. What would you have to do?
11651 </para>
11652 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11653 <para>
11654 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were
11655 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
11656 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
11657 titles and authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration
11658 and renewal records for works published in 1930. That will produce a
11659 list of books still under copyright.
11660 </para>
11661 <para>
11662 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
11663 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
11664 </para>
11665 <para>
11666 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
11667 owners
11668 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
11669 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
11670 being at least a list?
11671 </para>
11672 <para>
11673 But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in
11674 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
11675 practically
11676 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
11677 thousands
11678 of such records&mdash;especially since the person who registered is
11679 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930!
11680 </para>
11681 <para>
11682 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,</quote> the
11683 apologists for the system respond. <quote>Why should there be a list of
11684 copyright owners?</quote>
11685 </para>
11686 <para>
11687 Well, actually, if you think about it, there <emphasis>are</emphasis>
11688 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
11689 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
11690 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
11691 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
11692 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
11693 what tangible property.
11694 </para>
11695 <para>
11696 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
11697 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
11698 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
11699
11700 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
11701 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
11702 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
11703 happen
11704 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
11705 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
11706 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
11707 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
11708 know quite well who owns what property.
11709 </para>
11710 <para>
11711 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
11712 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
11713 already
11714 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
11715 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
11716 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
11717 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
11718 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
11719 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
11720 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
11721 </para>
11722 <para>
11723 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
11724 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
11725 consequence
11726 for other creative works is much more dire.
11727 </para>
11728 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'><primary>Agee, Michael</primary></indexterm>
11729 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
11730 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films</primary></indexterm>
11731 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The</primary></indexterm>
11732 <para>
11733 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
11734 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
11735 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
11736 made between 1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, <citetitle>The Lucky Dog</citetitle>, is
11737 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923
11738 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
11739 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
11740 money. According to one estimate, <quote>Roach has sold about 60,000
11741 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's silent
11742 films.</quote><footnote><para>
11743 <!-- f11. -->
11744 See David G. Savage, <quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,</quote>
11745 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, <quote>Classic Movies,
11746 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
11747 Down Copyright Extension,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 9 October 2002.
11748 </para></footnote>
11749 </para>
11750 <para>
11751 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
11752 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
11753 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11754 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11755 </para>
11756 <para>
11757 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11758
11759 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11760 any continuing commercial value. The rest&mdash;to the extent it
11761 survives at all&mdash;sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11762 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11763 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11764 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11765 work available for distribution.
11766 </para>
11767 <para>
11768 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11769 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11770 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11771 it cost more than $10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11772 film in 1993, it can now cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of
11773 8 mm film.<footnote><para>
11774 <!-- f12. -->
11775 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11776 Supporting the Petitoners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11777 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01- 618), 12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11778 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11779 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, available at
11780 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #53</ulink>.
11781 </para></footnote>
11782
11783 </para>
11784 <para>
11785 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11786 important.
11787 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11788 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11789 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11790 locate the copyright owner.
11791 </para>
11792 <para>
11793 Or more accurately, <emphasis>owners</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11794 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11795 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11796 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11797 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11798 to these films is exceptionally high.
11799 </para>
11800 <para>
11801 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11802 copyright owner when she shows up?</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11803 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11804 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11805 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11806 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11807 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11808 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11809 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11810 </para>
11811 <para>
11812 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11813
11814 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11815 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11816 benefit
11817 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11818 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11819 the copyright expires.
11820 </para>
11821 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'/>
11822 <para>
11823 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11824 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11825 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11826 canisters
11827 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11828 than dust.
11829 </para>
11830 <para>
11831 <emphasis role='strong'>Of all the</emphasis> creative work produced
11832 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11833 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11834 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11835 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11836 the copyright acts as an <quote>engine of free expression.</quote>
11837 </para>
11838 <para>
11839 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11840 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11841 indicated,
11842 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11843 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11844 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11845 distributors,
11846 the commercial life ends.
11847 </para>
11848 <para>
11849 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11850 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes &amp; Noble, and
11851 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11852 between
11853 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11854 Friday
11855 night watching a 1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11856 of culture is important and valuable&mdash;for entertainment but also, and
11857 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11858 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11859 have, we need to have access to this history.
11860 </para>
11861 <para>
11862 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11863
11864 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11865 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11866 this context do no good.
11867 </para>
11868 <para>
11869 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11870 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11871 <emphasis>copyright-related use</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11872 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11873 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11874 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11875 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11876 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11877 was independent of copyright law.
11878 </para>
11879 <para>
11880 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11881 a film&mdash;the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs&mdash;were
11882 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11883 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11884 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11885 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11886 market didn't have more to offer.
11887 </para>
11888 <para>
11889 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11890 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11891 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11892 would not have interfered with anything.
11893 </para>
11894 <para>
11895 But this situation has now changed.
11896 </para>
11897 <indexterm id='idxkahlebrewster2' class='startofrange'><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
11898 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11899 <para>
11900 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11901 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11902 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11903 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11904 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11905 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11906 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11907 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11908 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11909 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11910 </para>
11911 <para>
11912 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11913 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11914 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11915 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11916 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11917 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11918 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11919 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11920 written for a radically different context.
11921 </para>
11922 <para>
11923 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11924 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11925 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11926 <emphasis>copyright</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11927 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11928 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11929 context, copyright is serving no purpose <emphasis>at all</emphasis>
11930 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11931 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11932 </para>
11933 <para>
11934 You may well ask, <quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11935 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11936 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11937 culture widely?</quote>
11938 </para>
11939 <indexterm startref='idxkahlebrewster2' class='endofrange'/>
11940 <para>
11941 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11942 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes &amp; Noble
11943 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11944 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11945 of a library is to serve what <quote>the market</quote> would demand. But if you
11946 think the role of a library is bigger than this&mdash;if you think its
11947 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11948 particular bit of that culture or not&mdash;then we can't count on the
11949 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11950 </para>
11951 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'/>
11952 <para>
11953 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11954 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11955 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11956 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11957
11958 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11959 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11960 culture, 94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11961 1923 and 1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11962 commercial market, if access is a value, then 6 percent is a failure
11963 to provide that value.<footnote><para>
11964 <!-- f13. -->
11965 Jason Schultz, <quote>The Myth of the 1976 Copyright
11966 <quote>Chaos</quote> Theory,</quote> 20 December 2002, available at
11967 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #54</ulink>.
11968 </para></footnote>
11969
11970 </para>
11971 <para>
11972 <emphasis role='strong'>In January 1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11973 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11974 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11975 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (1)
11976 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11977 <quote>limited Times</quote> requirement, and (2) that extending terms
11978 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11979 </para>
11980 <para>
11981 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11982 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11983 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11984 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11985 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11986 </para>
11987 <para>
11988 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11989 copyrights be for <quote>limited Times</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11990 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11991 <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11992 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11993 terms that are <quote>limited.</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11994 to interpret the term <quote>limited Times</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11995 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11996 power to extend existing terms.
11997 </para>
11998 <para>
11999 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
12000 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
12001 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
12002 whole, where the court will sit <quote>en banc</quote> to hear the case.
12003 </para>
12004 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David</primary></indexterm>
12005 <para>
12006 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
12007 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
12008
12009 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
12010 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
12011 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
12012 overstepped its bounds.
12013 </para>
12014 <para>
12015 It was here that most expected <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
12016 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle> would die, for the Supreme Court
12017 rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It hears about one
12018 hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand appeals.) And it
12019 practically never reviews a decision that upholds a statute when no
12020 other court has yet reviewed the statute.
12021 </para>
12022 <para>
12023 But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
12024 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
12025 was set for October of 2002. The summer would be spent writing
12026 briefs and preparing for argument.
12027 </para>
12028 <para>
12029 <emphasis role='strong'>It is over</emphasis> a year later as I write
12030 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
12031 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
12032 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
12033 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
12034 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
12035 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
12036 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
12037 client, Eric Eldred.
12038 </para>
12039 <para>
12040 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
12041 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
12042 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
12043 mistake lost it.
12044 </para>
12045 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
12046 <indexterm id='idxjonesdayreavisandpoguejonesday' class='startofrange'><primary>Jones, Day, Reavis and Pogue (Jones Day)</primary></indexterm>
12047 <para>
12048 <emphasis role='strong'>The mistake</emphasis> was made early, though
12049 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
12050 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
12051 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
12052 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
12053 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
12054 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
12055 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
12056 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
12057 </para>
12058 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12059 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan</primary></indexterm>
12060 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
12061 <para>
12062 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
12063 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
12064 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
12065 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
12066 told me, if we could make the issue seem <quote>important</quote> to the Supreme
12067 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
12068 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against <quote>the
12069 most powerful media companies in the world.</quote>
12070 </para>
12071 <indexterm startref='idxjonesdayreavisandpoguejonesday' class='endofrange'/>
12072 <para>
12073 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
12074 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
12075 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
12076 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
12077 <quote>right</quote> as in <quote>true,</quote> I thought, but it is <quote>wrong</quote> as in <quote>it just shouldn't be
12078 that way.</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
12079 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
12080 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
12081 interpretation
12082 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
12083 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
12084 unconstitutional,
12085 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
12086 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
12087 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
12088 Constitution,
12089 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
12090 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
12091 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
12092 </para>
12093 <para>
12094 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
12095 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
12096 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
12097 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
12098 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
12099 why it was unconstitutional.
12100 </para>
12101 <para>
12102 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
12103
12104 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
12105 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
12106 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
12107 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
12108 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
12109 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
12110 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
12111 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
12112 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
12113 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
12114 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
12115 <emphasis>law</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
12116 the widest range of credible critics&mdash;credible not because they
12117 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
12118 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
12119 </para>
12120 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
12121 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis</primary></indexterm>
12122 <para>
12123 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
12124 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
12125 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
12126 Congress. In November 1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
12127 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
12128 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
12129 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
12130 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
12131 to get bogged down?</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
12132 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
12133 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
12134 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
12135 </para>
12136 <para>
12137 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
12138 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
12139 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
12140 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
12141 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
12142 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
12143 </para>
12144 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12145 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
12146 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12147 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
12148 <para>
12149 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
12150 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
12151
12152 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
12153 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/Linux
12154 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
12155 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
12156 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
12157 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
12158 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
12159 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
12160 </para>
12161 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries</primary></indexterm>
12162 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union</primary></indexterm>
12163 <para>
12164 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
12165 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
12166 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
12167 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
12168 </para>
12169 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
12170 <para>
12171 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
12172 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
12173 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
12174 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
12175 clear.
12176 </para>
12177 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George</primary></indexterm>
12178 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
12179 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James</primary></indexterm>
12180 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12181 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton</primary></indexterm>
12182 <para>
12183 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
12184 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
12185 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
12186 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
12187 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
12188 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
12189 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
12190 nothing more than <quote>rent-seeking</quote>&mdash;the fancy term economists use
12191 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
12192 </para>
12193 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12194 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan</primary></indexterm>
12195 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen</primary></indexterm>
12196 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12197 <indexterm><primary>Jones, Day, Reavis and Pogue (Jones Day)</primary></indexterm>
12198 <para>
12199 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
12200 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
12201 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
12202 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
12203 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
12204 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
12205 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
12206 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
12207
12208 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
12209 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
12210 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
12211 </para>
12212 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12213 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
12214 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Commerce Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
12215 <para>
12216 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
12217 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
12218 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
12219 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
12220 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
12221 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
12222 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
12223 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
12224 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
12225 confidence in our argument.
12226 </para>
12227 <para>
12228 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
12229 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these <quote>friends</quote> included
12230 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
12231 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
12232 copyright holders.
12233 </para>
12234 <para>
12235 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
12236 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either&mdash;they
12237 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
12238 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
12239 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
12240 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
12241 wanted to control.
12242 </para>
12243 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George</primary></indexterm>
12244 <indexterm><primary>Porgy and Bess</primary></indexterm>
12245 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
12246 <para>
12247 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
12248 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
12249 Dr. Seuss's work&mdash; better than allowing it to fall into the
12250 public domain&mdash;because if this creativity were in the public
12251 domain, then people could use it to <quote>glorify drugs or to create
12252 pornography.</quote><footnote><para>
12253 <!-- f14. -->
12254 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
12255 U.S. (2003) (No. 01-618), 19.
12256 </para></footnote>
12257 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
12258 <quote>protection</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
12259 to license <citetitle>Porgy and Bess</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
12260 Americans in the cast.<footnote><para>
12261 <!-- f15. -->
12262 Dinitia Smith, <quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
12263 Mouse Joins the Fray,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 28 March 1998, B7.
12264 </para></footnote>
12265 That's
12266 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
12267 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
12268 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
12269 </para>
12270 <para>
12271 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
12272 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
12273 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
12274 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
12275 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, <quote>Give us twenty years
12276 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
12277 better with them than anyone else.</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
12278 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
12279 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
12280 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
12281 </para>
12282 <para>
12283 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
12284 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
12285 copyrights&mdash;extensions that would further concentrate the market;
12286 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
12287 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
12288 </para>
12289 <para>
12290 <emphasis role='strong'>Between February</emphasis> and October, there
12291 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
12292 I set the strategy.
12293 </para>
12294 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, Anthony</primary></indexterm>
12295 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12296 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
12297 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12298 <indexterm><primary>Thomas, Clarence</primary></indexterm>
12299 <indexterm><primary>United States v. Lopez</primary></indexterm>
12300 <indexterm><primary>United States v. Morrison</primary></indexterm>
12301 <indexterm><primary>Scalia, Antonin</primary></indexterm>
12302 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>Supreme Court restraint on</secondary></indexterm>
12303 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>congressional actions restrained by</secondary></indexterm>
12304 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusfactionsof' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>factions of</secondary></indexterm>
12305 <para>
12306 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
12307 called <quote>the Conservatives.</quote> The other we called <quote>the Rest.</quote> The
12308 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
12309 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
12310 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
12311 five who had supported the <citetitle>Lopez/Morrison</citetitle> line
12312 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
12313 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
12314 </para>
12315 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12316 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12317 <para>
12318 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
12319 Congress's power. These four&mdash;Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
12320 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer&mdash;had repeatedly argued that
12321 the Constitution
12322 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
12323 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
12324 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
12325 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
12326 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
12327 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
12328 </para>
12329 <para>
12330 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
12331 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
12332 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
12333 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
12334 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
12335 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
12336 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
12337 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
12338 sense.
12339 </para>
12340 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12341 <para>
12342 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
12343 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
12344 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
12345 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
12346 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
12347 these retrospective extensions.
12348 </para>
12349 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusfactionsof' class='endofrange'/>
12350 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'/>
12351 <para>
12352 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
12353 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
12354 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
12355 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
12356 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
12357 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
12358 </para>
12359 <para>
12360 This analysis of <quote>the Rest</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
12361 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
12362 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
12363 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
12364 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation&mdash;the
12365 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
12366 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
12367 powers have limits.
12368 </para>
12369 <indexterm><primary>United States v. Lopez</primary></indexterm>
12370 <indexterm><primary>commerce, interstate</primary></indexterm>
12371 <indexterm><primary>interstate commerce</primary></indexterm>
12372 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>in constitutional Progress Clause</secondary></indexterm>
12373 <indexterm><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
12374 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby5' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
12375 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
12376 <para>
12377 This then was the core of our strategy&mdash;a strategy for which I am
12378 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
12379 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
12380 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
12381 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
12382 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
12383 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
12384 supposed to be <quote>limited.</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
12385 reconcile <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> with
12386 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
12387 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
12388 be limited.
12389 </para>
12390 <para>
12391 <emphasis role='strong'>The argument</emphasis> on the government's
12392 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
12393 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
12394 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
12395 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
12396 that practice is unconstitutional.
12397 </para>
12398 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby5' class='endofrange'/>
12399 <para>
12400 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
12401 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in 1831
12402 and in 1909. And of course, in 1962, Congress began extending
12403 existing
12404 terms regularly&mdash;eleven times in forty years.
12405 </para>
12406 <para>
12407 But this <quote>consistency</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
12408 extended
12409 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
12410 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
12411 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
12412 existing
12413 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
12414 restraint
12415 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
12416 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
12417 hesitated
12418 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
12419 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
12420 </para>
12421 <para>
12422 <emphasis role='strong'>Oral argument</emphasis> was scheduled for the
12423 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
12424 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
12425 <quote>mooted</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
12426
12427 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
12428 help in the case. Such <quote>moots</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
12429 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
12430 </para>
12431 <para>
12432 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
12433 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
12434 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
12435 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
12436 Congress
12437 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
12438 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
12439 this central idea.
12440 </para>
12441 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12442 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12443 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12444 <indexterm><primary>Jones, Day, Reavis and Pogue (Jones Day)</primary></indexterm>
12445 <para>
12446 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
12447 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
12448 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
12449 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
12450 </para>
12451 <para>
12452 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
12453 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
12454 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
12455 the harm&mdash;passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
12456 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.</quote>
12457 </para>
12458 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12459 <para>
12460 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
12461 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
12462 right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
12463 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
12464 does the right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it is right. As
12465 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
12466 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
12467 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
12468 </para>
12469 <para>
12470 <emphasis role='strong'>The night before</emphasis> the argument, a
12471 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
12472 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
12473 culture. Hundreds stood in line
12474
12475 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
12476 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
12477 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
12478 </para>
12479 <para>
12480 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
12481 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
12482 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
12483 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
12484 congressmen
12485 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
12486 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
12487 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
12488 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
12489 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
12490 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
12491 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
12492 family of the Justices.
12493 </para>
12494 <para>
12495 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
12496 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
12497 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
12498 those enumerated powers had any limit.
12499 </para>
12500 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12501 <para>
12502 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
12503 The history was bothering her.
12504 </para>
12505 <blockquote>
12506 <para>
12507 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
12508 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
12509 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
12510 practice that began with the very first act.
12511 </para>
12512 </blockquote>
12513 <para>
12514 She was quite willing to concede <quote>that this flies directly in the face
12515 of what the framers had in mind.</quote> But my response again and again
12516 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
12517 </para>
12518 <blockquote>
12519 <para>
12520 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
12521 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
12522 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
12523 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
12524 is yes.
12525 </para>
12526 </blockquote>
12527 <para>
12528 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
12529 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
12530 Kennedy, who observed,
12531 </para>
12532 <blockquote>
12533 <para>
12534 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
12535 the '76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
12536 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
12537 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
12538 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
12539 </para>
12540 </blockquote>
12541 <para>
12542 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
12543 student,
12544 I answered,
12545 </para>
12546 <blockquote>
12547 <para>
12548 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
12549 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
12550 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
12551 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
12552 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
12553 </para>
12554 </blockquote>
12555 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12556 <para>
12557 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
12558 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
12559 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
12560 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
12561 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
12562 </para>
12563 <indexterm><primary>United States v. Lopez</primary></indexterm>
12564 <para>
12565 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
12566 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> ruling,
12567 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
12568 </para>
12569 <para>
12570 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
12571 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
12572
12573 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
12574 </para>
12575 <blockquote>
12576 <para>
12577 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
12578 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
12579 </para>
12580 <para>
12581 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
12582 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
12583 domain
12584 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
12585 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
12586 into the Copyright Clause.
12587 </para>
12588 </blockquote>
12589 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.</primary></indexterm>
12590 <para>
12591 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
12592 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
12593 asked Solicitor General Olson,
12594 </para>
12595 <blockquote>
12596 <para>
12597 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12598 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
12599 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
12600 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12601 time.
12602 </para>
12603 </blockquote>
12604 <para>
12605 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
12606 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
12607 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
12608 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
12609 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
12610 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
12611 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
12612 Patent Clause&mdash; indeed, the very first case striking a law of
12613 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
12614 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
12615 Court to my side.
12616 </para>
12617 <para>
12618 <emphasis role='strong'>As I left</emphasis> the court that day, I
12619 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
12620 hundred questions I wished I had
12621
12622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
12623 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
12624 optimistic.
12625 </para>
12626 <para>
12627 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
12628 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
12629 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
12630 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
12631 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
12632 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
12633 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
12634 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
12635 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
12636 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
12637 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court&mdash;in particular,
12638 the Conservatives&mdash;would feel itself constrained by the rule of
12639 law that it had established elsewhere.
12640 </para>
12641 <para>
12642 <emphasis role='strong'>The morning</emphasis> of January 15, 2003, I
12643 was five minutes late to the office and missed the 7:00 A.M. call from
12644 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
12645 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
12646 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
12647 majority. There were two dissents.
12648 </para>
12649 <para>
12650 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
12651 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
12652 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
12653 </para>
12654 <para>
12655 My <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
12656 money in the world against <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. And here
12657 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
12658 reasoning.
12659 </para>
12660 <indexterm id='idxunitedstatesvlopez2' class='startofrange'><primary>United States v. Lopez</primary></indexterm>
12661 <para>
12662 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
12663 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
12664 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
12665 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
12666 even appear in the Court's opinion.
12667 </para>
12668 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12669 <para>
12670
12671 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
12672 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
12673 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
12674 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
12675 </para>
12676 <para>
12677 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable&mdash;for her, and for Justice
12678 Souter. Neither believes in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
12679 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
12680 they had worked so hard to defeat.
12681 </para>
12682 <para>
12683 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
12684 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
12685 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
12686 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
12687 reconcile the two simply <emphasis>by not addressing the
12688 argument</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
12689 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
12690 followed from the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
12691 be limited, but in this context it would not.
12692 </para>
12693 <indexterm startref='idxunitedstatesvlopez2' class='endofrange'/>
12694 <para>
12695 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
12696 they would respect? By what right did they&mdash;the silent
12697 five&mdash;get to select the part of the Constitution they would
12698 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
12699 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
12700 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
12701 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
12702 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
12703 the system we have.
12704 </para>
12705 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12706 <para>
12707 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
12708 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
12709 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
12710 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
12711 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
12712 the Court discounted the parallel&mdash;without explaining how the
12713 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
12714 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
12715 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
12716 </para>
12717 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12718 <para>
12719 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
12720 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
12721 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
12722 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
12723 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8
12724 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
12725 that the actual number was 99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
12726 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
12727 <quote>limited,</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
12728 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
12729 </para>
12730 <indexterm id='idxunitedstatesvlopez3' class='startofrange'><primary>United States v. Lopez</primary></indexterm>
12731 <para>
12732 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
12733 because neither believed in the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
12734 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
12735 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
12736 Sentelle. It was <citetitle>Hamlet</citetitle> without the Prince.
12737 </para>
12738 <para>
12739 <emphasis role='strong'>Defeat brings depression</emphasis>. They say
12740 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
12741 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
12742 sorts.
12743 </para>
12744 <indexterm><primary>originalism</primary></indexterm>
12745 <para>
12746 It was first anger with the five <quote>Conservatives.</quote> It would have been
12747 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> didn't
12748 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
12749 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
12750 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
12751 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
12752 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is <quote>originalism</quote>&mdash;to
12753 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
12754 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
12755 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> and many other <quote>originalist</quote> rulings. Where was their
12756 <quote>originalism</quote> now?
12757 </para>
12758 <indexterm startref='idxunitedstatesvlopez3' class='endofrange'/>
12759 <para>
12760 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
12761 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
12762 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
12763 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
12764
12765 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
12766 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
12767 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
12768 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
12769 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
12770 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
12771 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
12772 own principles.
12773 </para>
12774 <para>
12775 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
12776 myself.
12777 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
12778 the law as it is.
12779 </para>
12780 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12781 <para>
12782 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
12783 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
12784 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
12785 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
12786 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
12787 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12788 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12789 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12790 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12791 </para>
12792 <para>
12793 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12794 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12795 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12796 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12797 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12798 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12799 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12800 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12801 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12802 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12803 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12804 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12805 effort to persuade; but I
12806 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12807 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12808 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12809 should decide the issue.
12810 </para>
12811 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12812 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12813 <para>
12814 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12815 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12816 Kathleen Sullivan?
12817 </para>
12818 <para>
12819 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12820 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12821 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12822 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12823 </para>
12824 <para>
12825 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12826 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12827 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12828 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12829 have persuaded.
12830 </para>
12831 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12832 <para>
12833 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12834 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12835 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12836 case was a mistake. <quote>The Court is not ready,</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12837 issue should not be raised until it is.
12838 </para>
12839 <para>
12840 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12841 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12842 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12843 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12844 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12845 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12846 this case&mdash;a decision I had made four years before&mdash;was wrong.
12847 </para>
12848 <para>
12849 <emphasis role='strong'>While the reaction</emphasis> to the Sonny
12850 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12851 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12852 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12853 that battle over ideas. Where
12854
12855 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12856 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12857 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12858 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12859 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12860 harmful law. <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12861 </para>
12862 <blockquote>
12863 <para>
12864 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12865 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12866 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12867 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12868 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12869 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12870 </para>
12871 </blockquote>
12872 <para>
12873 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12874 hilarious images&mdash;of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12875 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced in figure
12876 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-18"/>. The <quote>powerful
12877 and wealthy</quote> line is a bit unfair. But the punch in the face
12878 felt exactly like that.
12879 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12880 </para>
12881 <figure id="fig-18" float="1">
12882 <title></title>
12883 <graphic fileref="images/tom-the-dancing-bug.png" align="center" width="100%"></graphic>
12884 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12885 </figure>
12886 <para>
12887 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12888 quote from <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>. That <quote>grand experiment</quote> we call the
12889 <quote>public domain</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think, <quote>Honey,
12890 I shrunk the Constitution.</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12891 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12892 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12893 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12894 </para>
12895 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12896 </chapter>
12897 <chapter label="14" id="eldred-ii">
12898 <title>Chapter Fourteen: Eldred II</title>
12899 <para>
12900 <emphasis role='strong'>The day</emphasis>
12901 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12902 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12903 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was denied&mdash;meaning the case was
12904 really finally over&mdash;fate would have it that I was giving a
12905 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12906 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12907 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12908 wrote an op-ed piece.
12909 </para>
12910 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12911 <para>
12912 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12913 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12914 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12915 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12916 Justice Kennedy: <quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12917 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12918 that.</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12919 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12920 </para>
12921 <para>
12922 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12923 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12924 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12925 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12926 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12927 the work passed into the public domain.
12928 </para>
12929 <para>
12930 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12931 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12932 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12933 </para>
12934 <para>
12935 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12936 is either the <quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act</quote> or the <quote>Copyright
12937 Term Deregulation Act.</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12938 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12939 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12940 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $1. But for
12941 everything else, let the content go.
12942 </para>
12943 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12944 <indexterm><primary>Democratic Party</primary></indexterm>
12945 <indexterm><primary>Republican Party</primary></indexterm>
12946 <para>
12947 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12948 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12949 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12950 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12951 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12952 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12953 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12954 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12955 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12956 the stupid harm of the present system.
12957 </para>
12958 <para>
12959 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12960 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12961 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12962 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12963 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12964 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12965 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12966 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12967 where copyright owners could be identified.
12968 </para>
12969 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12970 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12971 <para>
12972 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12973 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
12974 linkend="property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12975 removed in 1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12976 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.<footnote><para>
12977 <!-- f1. -->
12978 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law</primary></indexterm>
12979 Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12980 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12981 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12982 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act,
12983 every text of the Convention has provided that <quote>the enjoyment and the
12984 exercise</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention <quote>shall not be subject
12985 to any formality.</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12986 embodied in Article 5(2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12987 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12988 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12989 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12990 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12991 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12992 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12993 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12994 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>International
12995 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12996 Press, 2001), 153&ndash;54. </para></footnote>
12997 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a <quote>natural right.</quote> Natural
12998 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12999 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
13000 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
13001 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
13002 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
13003 </para>
13004 <para>
13005 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
13006 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
13007 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
13008 <quote>Walt Disney creativity</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
13009 know what's protected and what's not.
13010 </para>
13011 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
13012 <para>
13013 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
13014 Berlin in 1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
13015 Convention in 1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
13016 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
13017 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
13018 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
13019 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an <citetitle>i</citetitle> or cross a
13020 <citetitle>t</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
13021 </para>
13022 <para>
13023 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
13024 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
13025 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
13026 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
13027 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
13028 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
13029 </para>
13030 <para>
13031 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
13032 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
13033 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
13034 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
13035 burden
13036 imposed upon creators.
13037 </para>
13038 <para>
13039 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was
13040 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
13041
13042 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
13043 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
13044 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
13045 the government. He has a property right over the table <quote>naturally,</quote>
13046 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
13047 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
13048 table.
13049 </para>
13050 <para>
13051 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
13052 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
13053 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
13054 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
13055 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
13056 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
13057 spread.
13058 </para>
13059 <para>
13060 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
13061 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
13062 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
13063 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
13064 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
13065 important reason to secure registration&mdash;both because it makes
13066 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
13067 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
13068 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
13069 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
13070 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
13071 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
13072 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
13073 system of protection for property generally.
13074 </para>
13075 <para>
13076 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
13077 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
13078 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
13079 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
13080 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
13081 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
13082 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
13083 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
13084
13085 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
13086 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
13087 <emphasis>lawyer</emphasis> transactions take their place.
13088 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
13089 </para>
13090 <para>
13091 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
13092 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
13093 didn't <quote>get.</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
13094 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
13095 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, <quote>short,</quote> then this
13096 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
13097 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
13098 be presumptively uncontrolled.
13099 </para>
13100 <para>
13101 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
13102 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
13103 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
13104 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
13105 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
13106 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
13107 seen before <emphasis>because there are no formalities</emphasis>.
13108 </para>
13109 <para>
13110 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
13111 it is worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
13112 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
13113 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
13114 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
13115 </para>
13116 <para>
13117 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
13118 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
13119 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
13120 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
13121 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you.
13122 </para>
13123 <para>
13124 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
13125 registering the work mean that the $1 is really misleading? Isn't the
13126 hassle worth more than $1? Isn't that the real problem with
13127 registration?
13128 </para>
13129 <para>
13130 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
13131 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
13132 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
13133
13134 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
13135 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
13136 address the real problem of <emphasis>governments</emphasis> standing
13137 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
13138 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
13139 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
13140 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
13141 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
13142 upon historical data, that system would move up to 98 percent of
13143 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
13144 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
13145 </para>
13146 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
13147 <para>
13148 <emphasis role='strong'>When Steve Forbes</emphasis> endorsed the
13149 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
13150 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
13151 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
13152 willing to take the first step.
13153 </para>
13154 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe</primary></indexterm>
13155 <para>
13156 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
13157 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
13158 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
13159 possible. In May 2003, it looked as if the bill would be
13160 introduced. On May 16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, <quote>we are
13161 close.</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
13162 something good might happen here.
13163 </para>
13164 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>Eldred Act opposed by</secondary></indexterm>
13165 <para>
13166 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
13167 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
13168 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
13169 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
13170 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
13171 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
13172 </para>
13173 <para>
13174 The MPAA argued first that Congress had <quote>firmly rejected the central
13175 concept in the proposed bill</quote>&mdash;that copyrights be renewed. That
13176 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's <quote>firm rejection</quote> had occurred
13177 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
13178 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
13179 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
13180 owners&mdash;apparently those who could not afford the $1 fee. Third,
13181 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
13182 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
13183 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
13184 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
13185 off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
13186 argued that the bill would impose <quote>enormous</quote> costs, since a
13187 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
13188 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
13189 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
13190 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
13191 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
13192 film is a valid derivative use.
13193 </para>
13194 <para>
13195 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
13196 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
13197 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
13198 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
13199 or not&mdash;a controversial claim in any case&mdash;unless they know
13200 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
13201 </para>
13202 <para>
13203 <emphasis role='strong'>At the beginning</emphasis> of this book, I
13204 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
13205 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
13206 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
13207 opposition&mdash;the power of the side that fought to defend the
13208 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
13209 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
13210 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
13211 </para>
13212 <para>
13213 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
13214 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
13215 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
13216 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
13217 sense?
13218 </para>
13219 <para>
13220
13221 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
13222 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
13223 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
13224 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
13225 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
13226 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
13227 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
13228 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
13229 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
13230 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
13231 </para>
13232 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin</primary></indexterm>
13233 <para>
13234 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
13235 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
13236 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
13237 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
13238 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
13239 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the <quote>Dark
13240 Content</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
13241 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
13242 </para>
13243 <para>
13244 What does this industry really want?
13245 </para>
13246 <para>
13247 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
13248 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
13249 protecting <emphasis>their</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
13250 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
13251 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
13252 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
13253 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
13254 content that doesn't require <emphasis>their</emphasis> permission
13255 first.
13256 </para>
13257 <para>
13258 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
13259 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
13260 its aim not the protection of <quote>property</quote> but the rejection of a
13261 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
13262 theirs. <emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
13263 theirs</emphasis>.
13264 </para>
13265 <para>
13266 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
13267 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
13268
13269 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
13270 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
13271 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
13272 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
13273 and to share its own creation.
13274 </para>
13275 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13276 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13277 <para>
13278 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
13279 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
13280 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
13281 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
13282 block the progress of others.
13283 </para>
13284 <para>
13285 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
13286 <quote>property</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
13287 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
13288 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing <quote>permission
13289 society.</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
13290 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
13291 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
13292 </para>
13293 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
13294 </chapter>
13295 </part>
13296 <chapter label="" id="c-conclusion">
13297 <title>Conclusion</title>
13298 <indexterm id='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='startofrange'><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in</primary></indexterm>
13299 <indexterm id='idxaidsmedications' class='startofrange'><primary>AIDS medications</primary></indexterm>
13300 <indexterm id='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='startofrange'><primary>antiretroviral drugs</primary></indexterm>
13301 <indexterm id='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>developing countries, foreign patent costs in</primary></indexterm>
13302 <indexterm id='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='startofrange'><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13303 <indexterm id='idxhivaidstherapies' class='startofrange'><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies</primary></indexterm>
13304 <para>
13305 <emphasis role='strong'>There are more</emphasis> than 35 million
13306 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
13307 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
13308 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
13309 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
13310 </para>
13311 <para>
13312 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
13313 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
13314 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
13315 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
13316 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
13317 the disease almost invisible.
13318 </para>
13319 <para>
13320 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
13321 United States, they cost between $10,000 and $15,000 per person per
13322 year. Today, some cost $25,000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
13323 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
13324 population:
13325 $15,000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
13326 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.<footnote><para>
13327 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, <quote>Final Report: Integrating
13328 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy</quote> (London, 2002),
13329 available at
13330 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
13331 release
13332 issued 9 July 2002, only 230,000 of the 6 million who need drugs in
13333 the developing world receive them&mdash;and half of them are in Brazil.
13334 </para></footnote>
13335 </para>
13336 <indexterm id='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13337 <indexterm id='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>pharmaceutical patents</primary></indexterm>
13338 <para>
13339 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
13340 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
13341 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
13342 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
13343 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
13344 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
13345 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
13346 </para>
13347 <para>
13348 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
13349 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
13350 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
13351 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
13352 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
13353 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
13354 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
13355 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
13356 changes.
13357 </para>
13358 <para>
13359 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
13360 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
13361 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
13362 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
13363 costs significantly below the market price.
13364 </para>
13365 <indexterm id='idxinternationallaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>international law</primary></indexterm>
13366 <indexterm id='idxparallelimportation' class='startofrange'><primary>parallel importation</primary></indexterm>
13367 <indexterm id='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='startofrange'><primary>South Africa, Republic of, pharmaceutical imports by</primary></indexterm>
13368 <para>
13369 In 1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
13370 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
13371 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
13372 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
13373 Africa from India. This is called <quote>parallel importation,</quote> and it is
13374 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
13375 permitted within the European Union.<footnote>
13376 <para>
13377 <!-- f2. -->
13378 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
13379 Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37.
13380 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13381 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13382 </para></footnote>
13383 </para>
13384 <indexterm><primary>United States Trade Representative (USTR)</primary></indexterm>
13385 <para>
13386 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
13387 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
13388 characterized it, <quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa &hellip;
13389 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
13390 imports.</quote><footnote><para>
13391 <!-- f3. -->
13392 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13393 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13394 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13395 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 14, available at
13396 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #56</ulink>. For a
13397 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
13398 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
13399 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess.,
13400 Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150&ndash;57 (statement of James
13401 Love).
13402 </para></footnote>
13403 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
13404 government asked South Africa to change the law&mdash;and to add
13405 pressure to that request, in 1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
13406 possible trade sanctions.
13407 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
13408 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
13409 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
13410 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
13411 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
13412 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
13413 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
13414 patent&mdash; pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
13415 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
13416 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
13417 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.<footnote><para>
13418 <!-- f4. -->
13419 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13420 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13421 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13422 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 15. </para></footnote>
13423 </para>
13424 <indexterm startref='idxparallelimportation' class='endofrange'/>
13425 <para>
13426 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
13427 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
13428 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
13429 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
13430 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
13431 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
13432 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
13433 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
13434 </para>
13435 <para>
13436 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
13437 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
13438 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
13439 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
13440 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
13441 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save 15 to 30 million lives.
13442 </para>
13443 <para>
13444 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
13445 profits of United States drug companies&mdash;at least, not substantially. It
13446 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
13447 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
13448 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
13449 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
13450 by U.S. companies.
13451 </para>
13452 <para>
13453 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
13454 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
13455 argument
13456 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
13457 about the sanctity of property.<footnote><para>
13458 <!-- f5. -->
13459 See Sabin Russell, <quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
13460 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24
13461 May 1999, A1, available at
13462 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #57</ulink>
13463 (<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
13464 system of intellectual property protection</quote>); Robert Weissman, <quote>AIDS
13465 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
13466 Medicines,</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus</citetitle> 4:23 (August 1999), available at
13467 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #58</ulink>
13468 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, <quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
13469 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
13470 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
13471 Symposium Journal</citetitle> (Spring 2001): 175.
13472 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
13473 </para></footnote>
13474 It was because <quote>intellectual property</quote> would be violated that these
13475 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
13476 importance of <quote>intellectual property</quote> that led these government actors
13477 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
13478 </para>
13479 <indexterm startref='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='endofrange'/>
13480 <para>
13481 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
13482 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
13483 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
13484 direct cost would be to speed the death of 15 to 30 million Africans,
13485 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the <quote>sanctity</quote> of an
13486 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
13487 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
13488 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
13489 </para>
13490 <indexterm id='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>in pharmaceutical industry</secondary></indexterm>
13491 <para>
13492 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
13493 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
13494 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
13495 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
13496 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system&mdash;
13497 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
13498 </para>
13499 <para>
13500 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
13501 drug companies would love&mdash;they say, and I believe them&mdash;to
13502 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
13503 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
13504 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
13505 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
13506 </para>
13507 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>of drug patents</secondary></indexterm>
13508 <para>
13509 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
13510 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
13511 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, <quote>How
13512 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $1 a pill, but the same
13513 drug would cost an American $1,500?</quote> Because there is no <quote>sound
13514 bite</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
13515 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
13516 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
13517 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
13518 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
13519 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
13520 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal&mdash;the sanctity of an
13521 idea called <quote>intellectual property.</quote>
13522 </para>
13523 <indexterm startref='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='endofrange'/>
13524 <indexterm startref='idxaidsmedications' class='endofrange'/>
13525 <indexterm startref='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='endofrange'/>
13526 <indexterm startref='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='endofrange'/>
13527 <indexterm startref='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='endofrange'/>
13528 <indexterm startref='idxhivaidstherapies' class='endofrange'/>
13529 <indexterm startref='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='endofrange'/>
13530 <para>
13531 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
13532 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
13533 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
13534 What is the argument?
13535 </para>
13536 <para>
13537 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
13538 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
13539 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
13540 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
13541 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
13542 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
13543 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
13544 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
13545 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
13546 were balanced in just this sense.
13547 </para>
13548 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='endofrange'/>
13549 <indexterm startref='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13550 <indexterm startref='idxinternationallaw2' class='endofrange'/>
13551 <para>
13552 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
13553 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
13554 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
13555 our tradition, now reigns in this culture&mdash;bizarrely, and with
13556 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
13557 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
13558 </para>
13559 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13560 <para>
13561 <emphasis role='strong'>A simple idea</emphasis> blinds us, and under
13562 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
13563 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
13564 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
13565 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
13566 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
13567 control of that property removes our
13568 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
13569 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
13570 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
13571 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
13572 this common sense open its eyes.
13573 </para>
13574 <para>
13575 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
13576 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
13577 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
13578 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
13579 to fight <quote>piracy,</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
13580 the idea of <quote>creative property,</quote> while transforming real creators into
13581 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
13582 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
13583 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
13584 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
13585 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
13586 produce the <quote>perfect storm</quote> for free culture.
13587 </para>
13588 <indexterm><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
13589 <indexterm><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13590 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13591 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
13592 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13593 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
13594 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
13595 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>public projects in</secondary></indexterm>
13596 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)</primary></indexterm>
13597 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust</primary></indexterm>
13598 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13599 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web</primary></indexterm>
13600 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System</primary></indexterm>
13601 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
13602 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13603 <para>
13604 <emphasis role='strong'>In August 2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
13605 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
13606 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.<footnote><para>
13607 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>,
13608 August 2003, E1, available at
13609 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #59</ulink>; William New, <quote>Global Group's
13610 Shift on <quote>Open Source</quote> Meeting Spurs Stir,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13611 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13612 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #60</ulink>; William New, <quote>U.S. Official
13613 Opposes <quote>Open Source</quote> Talks at WIPO,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13614 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13615 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #61</ulink>.
13616 </para></footnote>
13617 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
13618 a meeting to discuss <quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
13619 goods.</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
13620 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
13621 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
13622 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
13623 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
13624 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
13625 that I describe in chapter
13626 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="c-afterword"/>. It
13627 included a project to develop single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs),
13628 which are thought to have great significance in biomedical
13629 research. (That nonprofit project comprised a consortium of the
13630 Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and technological companies,
13631 including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
13632 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
13633 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
13634 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
13635 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
13636 in the early 1980s. And it included <quote>open source and free software.</quote>
13637 </para>
13638 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'/>
13639 <para>
13640 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
13641 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
13642 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
13643 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
13644 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
13645 </para>
13646 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>in international debate on intellectual property</secondary></indexterm>
13647 <para>
13648 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.<footnote><para>
13649 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
13650 meeting.
13651 </para></footnote>
13652 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
13653 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
13654 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
13655 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
13656 property issues.
13657 </para>
13658 <indexterm id='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='startofrange'><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13659 <para>
13660 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
13661 about WIPO. In February 2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
13662 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
13663 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
13664 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
13665 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
13666 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
13667 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
13668 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
13669 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
13670 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
13671 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
13672 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
13673 talk about an <quote>Information Society</quote> unless one also talked about the
13674 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
13675 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
13676 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
13677 stuff of
13678 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
13679 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
13680 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
13681 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
13682 </para>
13683 <para>
13684 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
13685 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
13686 thus the meeting about <quote>open and collaborative projects to create
13687 public goods</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
13688 </para>
13689 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='endofrange'/>
13690 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='endofrange'/>
13691 <indexterm startref='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='endofrange'/>
13692 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
13693 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
13694 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>on free software</secondary></indexterm>
13695 <para>
13696 But there is one project within that list that is highly
13697 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is <quote>open source
13698 and free software.</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
13699 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
13700 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
13701 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
13702 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
13703 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
13704 rather than <quote>proprietary software,</quote> for their own internal uses.
13705 </para>
13706 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft</quote> licenses</primary></indexterm>
13707 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13708 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13709 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13710 <para>
13711 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
13712 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
13713 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
13714 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
13715 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
13716 operating system, the most famous bit of <quote>free software</quote>&mdash;and IBM
13717 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support <quote>open source and
13718 free software</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
13719 to support a mode of software development that is different from
13720 Microsoft's.<footnote><para>
13721 <!-- f8. -->
13722 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
13723 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
13724 <quote>open source</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
13725 principal opposition is to <quote>free software</quote> licensed under a <quote>copyleft</quote>
13726 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
13727 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, <quote>The Future
13728 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
13729 Toward Open Source Software</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
13730 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
13731 Public Policy Research, 2002), 69, available at
13732 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #62</ulink>. See also
13733 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, <citetitle>The Commercial Software
13734 Model</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (3
13735 May 2001), available at
13736 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #63</ulink>.
13737 </para></footnote>
13738 </para>
13739 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='endofrange'/>
13740 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)</primary></indexterm>
13741 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)</primary></indexterm>
13742 <para>
13743 More important for our purposes, to support <quote>open source and free
13744 software</quote> is not to oppose copyright. <quote>Open source and free software</quote>
13745 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
13746 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
13747 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
13748 by
13749 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
13750 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
13751 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
13752 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
13753 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
13754 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
13755 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
13756 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
13757 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
13758 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
13759 </para>
13760 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13761 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13762 <indexterm id='idxkrimjonathan' class='startofrange'><primary>Krim, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
13763 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by</secondary></indexterm>
13764 <para>
13765 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
13766 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
13767 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
13768 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
13769 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
13770 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
13771 States government to veto the meeting.<footnote><para>
13772 <!-- f9. -->
13773 Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> available at <ulink
13774 url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #64</ulink>.
13775 </para></footnote>
13776 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
13777 </para>
13778 <para>
13779 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
13780 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
13781 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
13782 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
13783 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
13784 its lobbying efforts.
13785 </para>
13786 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='endofrange'/>
13787 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13788 <indexterm id='idxpatentandtrademarkofficeus' class='startofrange'><primary>Patent and Trademark Office, U.S.</primary></indexterm>
13789 <para>
13790 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
13791 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
13792 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
13793 Office, explained that <quote>open-source software runs counter to the
13794 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.</quote>
13795 She is quoted as saying, <quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
13796 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
13797 goals of WIPO.</quote>
13798 </para>
13799 <indexterm startref='idxkrimjonathan' class='endofrange'/>
13800 <para>
13801 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
13802 </para>
13803 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='endofrange'/>
13804 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
13805 <para>
13806 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
13807 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
13808 right called <quote>copyright</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
13809 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it <quote>runs counter</quote> to the mission
13810 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
13811 in understanding&mdash;the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
13812 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
13813 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
13814 </para>
13815 <indexterm><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13816 <indexterm><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13817 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs</primary></indexterm>
13818 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13819 <para>
13820 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to <quote>promote</quote>
13821 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
13822 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
13823 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
13824 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
13825 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
13826 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
13827 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
13828 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
13829 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
13830 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
13831 </para>
13832 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
13833 <para>
13834 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
13835 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
13836 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13837 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13838 <emphasis>their</emphasis> rights. If they want to <quote>waive</quote> or
13839 <quote>disclaim</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13840 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $20 billion to do
13841 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13842 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13843 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13844 to do with <emphasis>their</emphasis> property.
13845 </para>
13846 <indexterm id='idxbolandlois' class='startofrange'><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13847 <para>
13848 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13849 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,</quote> she's
13850 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13851 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13852 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13853 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from <quote>waiving</quote> or
13854 <quote>disclaiming</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13855 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13856 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13857 way possible.
13858 </para>
13859 <indexterm id='idxfeudalsystem' class='startofrange'><primary>feudal system</primary></indexterm>
13860 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>feudal system of</secondary></indexterm>
13861 <para>
13862 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13863 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called <quote>feudalism.</quote> Under
13864 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13865 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13866 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13867 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13868 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13869 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13870 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13871 that control.
13872 </para>
13873 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13874 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13875 <para>
13876 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13877 choice we are now making about intellectual property.<footnote><para>
13878 <!-- f10. -->
13879 See Drahos with Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism</citetitle>, 210&ndash;20.
13880 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13881 </para></footnote>
13882 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13883 choice now is whether that information society will be
13884 <emphasis>free</emphasis> or <emphasis>feudal</emphasis>. The trend is
13885 toward the feudal.
13886 </para>
13887 <indexterm startref='idxfeudalsystem' class='endofrange'/>
13888 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='endofrange'/>
13889 <para>
13890 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13891 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13892 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13893 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13894 </para>
13895 <blockquote>
13896 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='endofrange'/>
13897 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='endofrange'/>
13898 <para>
13899 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13900 it should be (<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13901 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13902 not simply to promote intellectual property rights</quote>), not as it is. If
13903 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13904 say anything wrong. But in the world
13905 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13906 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13907 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13908 </para>
13909 </blockquote>
13910 <para>
13911 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13912 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13913 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13914 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13915 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13916 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13917 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13918 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13919 </para>
13920 <indexterm startref='idxbolandlois' class='endofrange'/>
13921 <para>
13922 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13923 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13924 <quote>goal</quote> of a government should be <quote>to promote the right balance</quote> of
13925 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13926 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. <quote>Typical for
13927 an academic,</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13928 </para>
13929 <para>
13930 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13931 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13932 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13933 our own country's history).
13934 </para>
13935 <para>
13936 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13937 government should be to <quote>seek balance,</quote> then count me with the silly,
13938 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13939 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13940 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13941 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13942 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13943 not lies is just na&iuml;ve, then who have we, the most powerful
13944 democracy in the world, become?
13945 </para>
13946 <para>
13947 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13948 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13949 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13950 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13951 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13952 been part of our tradition for most of our history&mdash;free culture.
13953 </para>
13954 <indexterm startref='idxpatentandtrademarkofficeus' class='endofrange'/>
13955 <para>
13956 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13957 </para>
13958 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
13959 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
13960 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted</primary></indexterm>
13961 <para>
13962 <emphasis role='strong'>There are moments</emphasis> of hope in this
13963 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13964 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13965 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13966 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13967 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13968 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13969 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing 700,000 letters were
13970 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13971 </para>
13972 <para>
13973 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13974 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13975 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13976 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13977 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13978 concentration in the media.
13979 </para>
13980 <para>
13981 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13982 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13983 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13984 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13985 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13986 </para>
13987 <para>
13988 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13989 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13990 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13991 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13992 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13993 range of rights&mdash;property rights of a historically extreme
13994 form&mdash;that makes their bigness bad.
13995 </para>
13996 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13997 <para>
13998 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13999 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
14000 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
14001 Americans have a long history of fighting <quote>big,</quote> wisely or not. That
14002 we could be motivated to fight <quote>big</quote> again is not something new.
14003 </para>
14004 <para>
14005 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
14006 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
14007 the idea of <quote>intellectual property.</quote> Not because balance is alien to
14008 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
14009 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
14010 called <quote>property</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
14011 </para>
14012 <para>
14013 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
14014 of our tragedy.
14015 </para>
14016 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob</primary></indexterm>
14017 <para>
14018 <emphasis role='strong'>As I write</emphasis> these final words, the
14019 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
14020 three hundred individuals.<footnote><para>
14021 <!-- f11. -->
14022 John Borland, <quote>RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers,</quote> CNET News.com, September
14023 2003, available at
14024 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #65</ulink>; Paul
14025 R. La Monica, <quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,</quote> CNN/Money, 8 September
14026 2003, available at
14027 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #66</ulink>; Soni
14028 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, <quote>Sued for a Song,
14029 N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among 261 Cited as Sharers,</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News</citetitle>, 9
14030 September 2003, 3; Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
14031 Targets; Single Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
14032 Defendants,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Katie Dean,
14033 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,</quote> <citetitle>Wired News</citetitle>, 10 September 2003,
14034 available at
14035 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #67</ulink>.
14036 </para></footnote>
14037 Eminem has just been sued for <quote>sampling</quote> someone else's
14038 music.<footnote><para>
14039 <!-- f12. -->
14040 Jon Wiederhorn, <quote>Eminem Gets Sued &hellip; by a Little Old Lady,</quote>
14041 mtv.com, 17 September 2003, available at
14042 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #68</ulink>.
14043 </para></footnote>
14044 The story about Bob Dylan <quote>stealing</quote> from a Japanese author has just
14045 finished making the rounds.<footnote><para>
14046 <!-- f13. -->
14047 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, <quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
14048 Dylan Songs,</quote> Kansascity.com, 9 July 2003, available at
14049 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #69</ulink>.
14050 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
14051 </para></footnote>
14052 An insider from Hollywood&mdash;who insists he must remain
14053 anonymous&mdash;reports <quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
14054 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
14055 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
14056 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
14057 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.</quote> Congressmen are
14058 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
14059 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
14060 kids who use a computer to share content.
14061 </para>
14062 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
14063 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
14064 <indexterm><primary>BBC</primary></indexterm>
14065 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in</primary></indexterm>
14066 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
14067 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto</primary></indexterm>
14068 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>public creative archive in</secondary></indexterm>
14069 <para>
14070 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
14071 that it will build a <quote>Creative Archive,</quote> from which British citizens can
14072 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.<footnote><para>
14073 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,</quote> BBC press release,
14074 24 August 2003, available at
14075 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #70</ulink>.
14076 </para></footnote>
14077 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
14078 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
14079 content and free licenses in that Latin American
14080 country.<footnote><para>
14081 <!-- f15. -->
14082 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,</quote> Creative Commons Weblog, 6 August 2003,
14083 available at
14084 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #71</ulink>.
14085 </para></footnote>
14086 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
14087 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
14088 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
14089 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
14090 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
14091 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
14092 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
14093 day into the Causbys.
14094 </para>
14095 <para>
14096 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
14097 potential is ever to be realized.
14098
14099 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
14100
14101 </para>
14102 </chapter>
14103 <chapter label="" id="c-afterword">
14104 <title>Afterword</title>
14105 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightvoluntaryreformeffortson' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>voluntary reform efforts on</secondary></indexterm>
14106 <para>
14107
14108 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
14109 <emphasis role='strong'>At least some</emphasis> who have read this
14110 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
14111 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
14112 </para>
14113 <para>
14114 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
14115 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
14116 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
14117 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
14118 </para>
14119 <para>
14120 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
14121 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
14122 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists&mdash;all to tell this
14123 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
14124 is so important.
14125 </para>
14126 <indexterm><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
14127 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightvoluntaryreformeffortson' class='endofrange'/>
14128 <para>
14129 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
14130 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
14131 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
14132 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
14133 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
14134 </para>
14135 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
14136
14137 <section id="usnow">
14138 <title>Us, now</title>
14139 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightvoluntaryreformeffortson2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>voluntary reform efforts on</secondary></indexterm>
14140 <para>
14141 <emphasis role='strong'>Common sense</emphasis> is with the copyright
14142 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
14143 extremes&mdash;as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
14144 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
14145 choice, then the warriors should win.
14146 </para>
14147 <para>
14148 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
14149 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
14150 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright&mdash;<quote>All Rights
14151 Reserved</quote>&mdash; and those who reject copyright&mdash;<quote>No Rights
14152 Reserved.</quote> The <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
14153 permission before you <quote>use</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The <quote>No
14154 Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
14155 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
14156 </para>
14157 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
14158 <indexterm id='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>initial free character of</secondary></indexterm>
14159 <para>
14160 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
14161 tilted in the <quote>no rights reserved</quote> direction. Content could be copied
14162 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
14163 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
14164 the
14165
14166 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
14167 original design of the Internet was <quote>no rights reserved.</quote> Content was
14168 <quote>taken</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
14169 unprotected.
14170 </para>
14171 <para>
14172 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
14173 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
14174 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
14175 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
14176 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
14177 architecture made the effective default <quote>no rights reserved,</quote> the
14178 future architecture will make the effective default <quote>all rights
14179 reserved.</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
14180 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
14181 content requires permission. The <quote>cut and paste</quote> world that defines
14182 the Internet today will become a <quote>get permission to cut and paste</quote>
14183 world that is a creator's nightmare.
14184 </para>
14185 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='endofrange'/>
14186 <indexterm startref='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='endofrange'/>
14187 <para>
14188 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle&mdash;neither
14189 <quote>all rights reserved</quote> nor <quote>no rights reserved</quote> but <quote>some rights
14190 reserved</quote>&mdash; and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
14191 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
14192 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
14193 before.
14194 </para>
14195 <section id="examples">
14196 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples</title>
14197 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>restoration efforts on previous aspects of</secondary></indexterm>
14198 <indexterm id='idxbrowsing' class='startofrange'><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
14199 <indexterm id='idxprivacyrights2' class='startofrange'><primary>privacy rights</primary></indexterm>
14200 <para>
14201 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
14202 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
14203 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
14204 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
14205 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
14206 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
14207 to your neighbors or boss. The <quote>privacy</quote> of your browsing habits was
14208 assured.
14209 </para>
14210 <para>
14211 What made it assured?
14212 </para>
14213 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
14214 <para>
14215 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
14216 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>, your
14217 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
14218 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
14219 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
14220 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
14221 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
14222 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
14223 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
14224 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
14225 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
14226 (there is no law protecting <quote>privacy</quote> in public places), and in many
14227 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
14228 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
14229 </para>
14230 <indexterm id='idxamazon' class='startofrange'><primary>Amazon</primary></indexterm>
14231 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet</primary></indexterm>
14232 <indexterm id='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>privacy protection on</secondary></indexterm>
14233 <para>
14234 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
14235 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
14236 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
14237 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
14238 <quote>recently viewed</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
14239 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
14240 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any <quote>privacy</quote>
14241 protected by the friction disappears, too.
14242 </para>
14243 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>privacy rights in use of</secondary></indexterm>
14244 <para>
14245 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
14246 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
14247 people should have the <quote>right</quote> to browse in a library without the
14248 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
14249 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
14250 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
14251 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
14252 disappears.
14253 </para>
14254 <indexterm startref='idxbrowsing' class='endofrange'/>
14255 <indexterm startref='idxamazon' class='endofrange'/>
14256 <para>
14257 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define <quote>privacy</quote>
14258 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
14259 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
14260 friction did.<footnote><para>
14261 <!-- f1. -->
14262
14263 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, <quote>Fair Information Practices and the
14264 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
14265 Law Review</citetitle> 1 (2001): par. 6&ndash;18, available at
14266
14267 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>
14268 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
14269 also Jeffrey Rosen, <citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
14270 in an Anxious Age</citetitle> (New York: Random House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs
14271 between technology and privacy).</para></footnote>
14272 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
14273 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
14274
14275 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
14276 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
14277 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
14278 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
14279 </para>
14280 <indexterm startref='idxprivacyrights2' class='endofrange'/>
14281 <indexterm startref='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='endofrange'/>
14282 <indexterm><primary>Data General</primary></indexterm>
14283 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
14284 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
14285 <para>
14286 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
14287 movement. When computers with software were first made available
14288 commercially, the software&mdash;both the source code and the
14289 binaries&mdash; was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
14290 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
14291 care much about controlling their software.
14292 </para>
14293 <indexterm id='idxstallmanrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Stallman, Richard</primary></indexterm>
14294 <para>
14295 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
14296 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
14297 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
14298 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
14299 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
14300 people's work.
14301 </para>
14302 <para>
14303 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
14304 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
14305 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
14306 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
14307 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
14308 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
14309 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
14310 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
14311 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
14312 anything else?
14313 </para>
14314 <indexterm id='idxproprietarycode' class='startofrange'><primary>proprietary code</primary></indexterm>
14315 <para>
14316 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
14317 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
14318 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
14319 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
14320 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
14321 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
14322 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
14323 </para>
14324 <para>
14325 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
14326 early 1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
14327 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
14328 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
14329 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
14330 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
14331 fundamentally weakened.
14332 </para>
14333 <indexterm startref='idxproprietarycode' class='endofrange'/>
14334 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus</primary></indexterm>
14335 <para>
14336 Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
14337 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
14338 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's <quote>Linux</quote>
14339 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
14340 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14341 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14342 </para>
14343 <para>
14344 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
14345 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
14346 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
14347 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
14348 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
14349 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
14350 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
14351 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
14352 byproduct.
14353 </para>
14354 <para>
14355 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
14356 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
14357 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
14358 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
14359 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
14360 what before had been passively guaranteed.
14361 </para>
14362 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='endofrange'/>
14363 <indexterm startref='idxstallmanrichard' class='endofrange'/>
14364 <indexterm id='idxacademicjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
14365 <indexterm id='idxscientificjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>scientific journals</primary></indexterm>
14366 <para>
14367 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
14368 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
14369 scientific journals are produced.
14370 </para>
14371 <indexterm id='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>Lexis and Westlaw</primary></indexterm>
14372 <indexterm id='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
14373 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14374 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>access to opinions of</secondary></indexterm>
14375 <para>
14376 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
14377 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
14378 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
14379 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
14380 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
14381 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
14382 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
14383 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
14384 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
14385 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
14386 and Westlaw are also free
14387 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
14388 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
14389 Court opinion through their respective services.
14390 </para>
14391 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>access fees for material in</secondary></indexterm>
14392 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>license system for rebuilding of</secondary></indexterm>
14393 <para>
14394 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
14395 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
14396 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
14397 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
14398 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
14399 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
14400 access to material that is not in the public domain.
14401 </para>
14402 <indexterm startref='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='endofrange'/>
14403 <indexterm startref='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='endofrange'/>
14404 <para>
14405 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
14406 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
14407 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
14408 </para>
14409 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14410 <para>
14411 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
14412 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
14413 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
14414 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
14415 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
14416 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
14417 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
14418 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
14419 the technology of paper journals (architecture)&mdash;namely, that it
14420 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
14421 </para>
14422 <para>
14423 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
14424 that libraries not give the general public access to the
14425 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
14426 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
14427 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
14428 granted before.
14429 </para>
14430 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
14431 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
14432 <para>
14433 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
14434 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
14435 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
14436 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
14437 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
14438 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
14439 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
14440 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
14441 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
14442 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
14443 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
14444 </para>
14445 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='endofrange'/>
14446 <para>
14447 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
14448 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
14449 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
14450 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
14451 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
14452 presumptively a good&mdash;especially when it helps spread knowledge
14453 and science.
14454 </para>
14455 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='endofrange'/>
14456 <indexterm startref='idxacademicjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14457 <indexterm startref='idxscientificjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14458 </section>
14459 <section id="oneidea">
14460 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea</title>
14461 <indexterm id='idxcreativecommons' class='startofrange'><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
14462 <para>
14463 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
14464 increasing control effected through law and technology.
14465 </para>
14466 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University</primary></indexterm>
14467 <para>
14468 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
14469 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
14470 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
14471 <emphasis>reasonable</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
14472 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
14473 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
14474 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
14475 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
14476 make this possible.
14477 </para>
14478 <para>
14479 <emphasis>Simple</emphasis>&mdash;which means without a middleman, or
14480 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
14481 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
14482 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
14483 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
14484 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
14485 shared. These three expressions together&mdash;a legal license, a
14486 human-readable description, and
14487 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
14488 machine-readable tags&mdash;constitute a Creative Commons license. A
14489 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
14490 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
14491 that the person associated with the license believes in something
14492 different than the <quote>All</quote> or <quote>No</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
14493 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
14494 certain freedoms are given.
14495 </para>
14496 <para>
14497 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
14498 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
14499 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
14500 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
14501 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
14502 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (<quote>share and share
14503 alike</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
14504 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
14505 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
14506 </para>
14507 <para>
14508 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
14509 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
14510 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
14511 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
14512 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
14513 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
14514 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
14515 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
14516 a public domain.
14517 </para>
14518 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia</primary></indexterm>
14519 <para>
14520 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
14521 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
14522 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
14523 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
14524 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
14525 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
14526 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
14527 of content (<quote>content conducers,</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
14528 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
14529 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
14530 </para>
14531 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
14532 <para>
14533 The aim is not to fight the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts. The aim is to
14534 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
14535 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
14536 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
14537 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
14538 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
14539 the background of digital technologies. New rules&mdash;with different
14540 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
14541 them&mdash;are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
14542 to begin to build those rules.
14543 </para>
14544 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
14545 <para>
14546 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
14547 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
14548 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
14549 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
14550 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
14551 </para>
14552 <para>
14553 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
14554 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1)
14555 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
14556 and (2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
14557 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (1) will download
14558 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2)
14559 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
14560 them (2)-goods. If there are more (2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the
14561 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
14562 <emphasis>increase</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
14563 </para>
14564 <para>
14565 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
14566 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
14567 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
14568 was a total success.
14569 </para>
14570 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)</primary></indexterm>
14571 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter</primary></indexterm>
14572 <para>
14573 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
14574 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
14575 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
14576 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled <citetitle>Free for All</citetitle>,
14577 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
14578 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
14579 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
14580 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
14581 well.
14582 </para>
14583 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'/>
14584 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter</primary></indexterm>
14585 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy</primary></indexterm>
14586 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightvoluntaryreformeffortson2' class='endofrange'/>
14587 <indexterm><primary>rap music</primary></indexterm>
14588 <para>
14589 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
14590 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
14591 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
14592 reasons. Many who use the <quote>sampling license</quote> do so because anything
14593 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
14594 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
14595 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
14596 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
14597 art&mdash;they, too, sample from others. Because the
14598 <emphasis>legal</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
14599 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
14600 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not <quote>allow</quote>
14601 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
14602 high<footnote><para>
14603 <!-- f2. -->
14604 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
14605 Culture Wars</citetitle> (2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
14606 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
14607 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>.
14608 </para></footnote>),
14609 these artists release into the creative environment content
14610 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
14611 </para>
14612 <para>
14613 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
14614 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
14615 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
14616 you are effectively saying you believe in the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote>
14617 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
14618 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
14619 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
14620 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
14621 this notion of <quote>Some Rights Reserved,</quote> and gives many the chance to
14622 say it to others.
14623 </para>
14624 <para>
14625 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
14626 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
14627 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
14628 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
14629
14630 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
14631 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
14632 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
14633 </para>
14634 <para>
14635 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
14636 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
14637 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
14638 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
14639 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
14640 steps are possible.
14641 </para>
14642 <para>
14643 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
14644 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
14645 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
14646 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
14647 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
14648 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
14649 creativity to spread more easily.
14650 </para>
14651 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='endofrange'/>
14652 <indexterm startref='idxcreativecommons' class='endofrange'/>
14653 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
14654 </section>
14655 </section>
14656 <section id="themsoon">
14657 <title>Them, soon</title>
14658 <para>
14659 <emphasis role='strong'>We will</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
14660 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
14661 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
14662 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
14663 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
14664 </para>
14665 <para>
14666 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
14667 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
14668 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
14669 to our end.
14670 </para>
14671
14672 <section id="formalities">
14673 <title>1. More Formalities</title>
14674 <para>
14675 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
14676 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
14677 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
14678 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
14679 </para>
14680 <para>
14681 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
14682 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
14683 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
14684 protected.
14685 </para>
14686 <para>
14687 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
14688 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
14689 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
14690 default is control, and <quote>formalities</quote> are banished.
14691 </para>
14692 <para>
14693 Why?
14694 </para>
14695 <para>
14696 As I suggested in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
14697 linkend="property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
14698 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
14699 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
14700 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
14701 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
14702 formalities were getting in the way.
14703 </para>
14704 <para>
14705 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
14706 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
14707 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
14708 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
14709 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
14710 trace&mdash; there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
14711 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
14712 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
14713 past. And thus, the <emphasis>lack</emphasis> of formalities forces
14714 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
14715 </para>
14716 <para>
14717 The law should therefore change this requirement<footnote><para>
14718 <!-- f1. -->
14719 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
14720 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
14721 adopted by other countries as well.</para></footnote>&mdash;but it
14722 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
14723 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
14724 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
14725 </para>
14726 <para>
14727 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
14728 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
14729 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
14730 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
14731 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
14732 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
14733 developed by others.
14734 </para>
14735
14736 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
14737
14738 <section id="registration">
14739 <title>Registration and renewal</title>
14740 <para>
14741 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
14742 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
14743 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
14744 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
14745 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
14746 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
14747 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
14748 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
14749 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
14750 panic&mdash;nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
14751 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
14752 </para>
14753 <para>
14754 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
14755 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
14756 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
14757 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
14758 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
14759 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
14760 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
14761 </para>
14762 <indexterm><primary>domain names</primary></indexterm>
14763 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>domain name registration on</secondary></indexterm>
14764 <indexterm><primary>Web sites, domain name registration of</primary></indexterm>
14765 <para>
14766 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
14767 There are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world.
14768 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
14769 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
14770 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
14771 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
14772 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
14773 with which registration occurs up.
14774 </para>
14775 <para>
14776 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
14777 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
14778 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
14779 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
14780 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
14781 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
14782 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
14783 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
14784 formality&mdash;while producing a database
14785 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
14786 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
14787 </para>
14788
14789 </section>
14790 <section id="marking">
14791 <title>Marking</title>
14792 <para>
14793 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
14794 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
14795 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule&mdash;akin to
14796 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
14797 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
14798 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
14799 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
14800 uniformly across all media.
14801 </para>
14802 <para>
14803 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
14804 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
14805 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
14806 use the work.
14807 </para>
14808 <para>
14809 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
14810 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
14811 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
14812 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
14813 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
14814 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
14815 signal from the failure to mark&mdash;not the loss of the copyright, but the
14816 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
14817 </para>
14818 <para>
14819 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
14820 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
14821 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
14822 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
14823 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
14824 doesn't give permission.<footnote><para>
14825 <!-- f2. -->
14826 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
14827 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
14828 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
14829 </para></footnote>
14830 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be <quote>use unless someone
14831 complains.</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
14832 stop using the work in any new
14833 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
14834 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
14835 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
14836 their work.
14837 </para>
14838 <para>
14839 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
14840 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
14841 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
14842 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
14843 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
14844 </para>
14845 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>copyright marking of</secondary></indexterm>
14846 <para>
14847 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
14848 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
14849 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
14850 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
14851 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
14852 <emphasis>solely</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
14853 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
14854 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
14855 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
14856 other important functions.
14857 </para>
14858 <para>
14859 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
14860 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
14861 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
14862 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
14863 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
14864 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
14865 </para>
14866 <para>
14867 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
14868 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
14869 make things unclear.
14870 </para>
14871 <para>
14872 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
14873 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
14874 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
14875 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
14876 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
14877 that assertion at the appropriate time.
14878 </para>
14879
14880 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
14881 </section>
14882 </section>
14883 <section id="shortterms">
14884 <title>2. Shorter Terms</title>
14885 <para>
14886 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14887 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14888 natural authors.
14889 </para>
14890 <para>
14891 In <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14892 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14893 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14894 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14895 radical. <citetitle>The Economist</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14896 copyright term.<footnote><para>
14897
14898 <!-- f3. -->
14899 <quote>A Radical Rethink,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 366:8308 (25 January 2003): 15,
14900 available at
14901 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #74</ulink>.
14902 </para></footnote>
14903 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14904 </para>
14905 <para>
14906 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14907 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14908 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14909 terms.
14910 </para>
14911 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14912 <listitem><para>
14913 <!-- (1) -->
14914 <emphasis>Keep it short:</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14915 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14916 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14917 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14918 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14919 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14920 </para></listitem>
14921 <listitem><para>
14922 <!-- (2) -->
14923 <emphasis>Keep it simple:</emphasis> The line between the public
14924 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14925 fuzziness of <quote>fair use,</quote> and the distinction between <quote>ideas</quote> and
14926 <quote>expression.</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14927 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14928 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14929 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14930 <quote>lawyer-free zone</quote> makes the complexities of <quote>fair use</quote> and
14931 <quote>idea/expression</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14932 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14933 </para></listitem>
14934 <listitem>
14935 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions</primary></indexterm>
14936 <para>
14937 <!-- (3) -->
14938 <emphasis>Keep it alive:</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14939 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14940 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14941 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14942 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14943 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14944 pension.<footnote><para>
14945 <!-- f4. -->
14946 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14947 and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001),
14948 available at
14949 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #75</ulink>.
14950 </para></footnote>
14951 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14952 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14953 single form.
14954 </para></listitem>
14955 <listitem><para>
14956 <!-- (4) -->
14957 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14958 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14959 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14960 in 1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14961 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14962 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in 1923 than we
14963 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14964 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14965 the number of authors who wrote in 1923. Of course, we can increase
14966 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14967 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14968 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14969 creativity in 1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14970 we can do about that now. </para></listitem>
14971 </orderedlist>
14972 <para>
14973 These changes together should produce an <emphasis>average</emphasis>
14974 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until 1976,
14975 the average term was just 32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14976 same.
14977 </para>
14978 <para>
14979 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas <quote>radical.</quote> (After all, I
14980 call them <quote>extremists.</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14981 than the term under Richard Nixon. How <quote>radical</quote> can it be to ask for
14982 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14983 </para>
14984
14985 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14986
14987 </section>
14988 <section id="freefairuse">
14989 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use</title>
14990 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
14991 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
14992 <para>
14993 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14994 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14995 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14996 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14997 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14998 the emergence of that new technology.
14999 </para>
15000 <para>
15001 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors <quote>exclusive
15002 right</quote> to <quote>their writings.</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
15003 right to <quote>their writings</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
15004 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
15005 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
15006 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
15007 though that movie is not <quote>my writing.</quote>
15008 </para>
15009 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin</primary></indexterm>
15010 <para>
15011 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it
15012 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
15013 control translations and dramatizations of a work.<footnote><para>
15014 <!-- f5. -->
15015 Benjamin Kaplan, <citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
15016 University Press, 1967), 32.
15017 </para></footnote>
15018 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
15019 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
15020 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
15021 </para>
15022 <blockquote>
15023 <para>
15024 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
15025 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
15026 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
15027 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.<footnote><para>
15028 <!-- f6. --> Ibid., 56.
15029 </para></footnote>
15030 </para>
15031 </blockquote>
15032 <para>
15033 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
15034 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
15035 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
15036 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
15037 Consider each limitation in turn.
15038 </para>
15039 <para>
15040 <emphasis>Term:</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
15041 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
15042 sense to protect John
15043
15044 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
15045 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
15046 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
15047 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
15048 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
15049 after the creative work is done.
15050 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
15051 </para>
15052 <para>
15053 <emphasis>Scope:</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
15054 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
15055 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
15056 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
15057 material. When all <quote>reuse</quote> of creative material was within the control
15058 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
15059 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
15060 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
15061 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
15062 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
15063 the creative process. Smothers it.
15064 </para>
15065 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
15066 <para>
15067 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
15068 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
15069 foreseeable derivative rights&mdash;turning a book into a movie, or a
15070 poem into a musical score&mdash;it doesn't make sense to require
15071 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
15072 much more sense.
15073 </para>
15074 <para>
15075 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
15076 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
15077 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
15078 Paul Goldstein.<footnote>
15079 <para>
15080 <!-- f7. -->
15081 Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
15082 Jukebox</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187&ndash;216.
15083 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul</primary></indexterm>
15084 </para></footnote>
15085 His view is that the law should be written so that
15086 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
15087 </para>
15088 <para>
15089 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
15090 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
15091 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
15092 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
15093 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
15094 </para>
15095 <para>
15096 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
15097 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
15098 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
15099 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
15100 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
15101 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
15102 </para>
15103 </section>
15104
15105 <section id="liberatemusic">
15106 <title>4. Liberate the Music&mdash;Again</title>
15107 <para>
15108 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
15109 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
15110 is, to most people, most pressing&mdash;music. There is no other
15111 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
15112 battles around the sharing of music.
15113 </para>
15114 <para>
15115 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
15116 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
15117 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
15118 killer app&mdash;possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
15119 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
15120 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
15121 innovation on the network.
15122 </para>
15123 <para>
15124 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
15125 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
15126 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
15127 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
15128 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
15129 </para>
15130 <para>
15131 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
15132 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
15133 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
15134 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="piracy"/>, they enable
15135 four different kinds of sharing:
15136 </para>
15137 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
15138 <listitem><para>
15139 <!-- A. -->
15140 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
15141 for purchasing CDs.
15142 </para></listitem>
15143 <listitem><para>
15144 <!-- B. -->
15145 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
15146 on the way to purchasing CDs.
15147 </para></listitem>
15148 <listitem><para>
15149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
15150 <!-- C. -->
15151 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15152 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
15153 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
15154 </para></listitem>
15155 <listitem><para>
15156 <!-- D. -->
15157 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15158 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
15159 owner plainly endorses.
15160 </para></listitem>
15161 </orderedlist>
15162 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
15163 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
15164 <para>
15165 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
15166 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
15167 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
15168 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
15169 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
15170 significantly weakened.
15171 </para>
15172 <para>
15173 As I said in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
15174 linkend="piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
15175 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
15176 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
15177 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
15178 networks.
15179 </para>
15180 <para>
15181 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
15182 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
15183 should respond.
15184 </para>
15185 <para>
15186 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
15187 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
15188 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
15189 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
15190 is cumbersome and slow&mdash;we in the United States are lucky to have
15191 broadband service at 1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
15192 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
15193 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
15194 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
15195 Internet is mainly just an idea.
15196 </para>
15197 <para>
15198 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
15199 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
15200 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
15201 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
15202 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
15203 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
15204 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
15205 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
15206 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
15207 where everywhere you are&mdash;except maybe the desert or the
15208 Rockies&mdash;you can instantaneously be connected to the
15209 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
15210 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
15211 </para>
15212 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over</primary></indexterm>
15213 <para>
15214 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
15215 give you access to content on the fly&mdash;such as Internet radio,
15216 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
15217 then, is the critical point: When it is <emphasis>extremely</emphasis>
15218 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
15219 <emphasis>easier</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
15220 access to content than it will be to download and store content
15221 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
15222 content</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
15223 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
15224 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
15225 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
15226 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
15227 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
15228 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
15229 paying for this content even though <quote>free</quote> content is available in the
15230 form of MP3s across the Web.<footnote><para>
15231 <!-- f8. -->
15232 See, for example, <quote>Music Media Watch,</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3
15233 April 2002, available at
15234 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #76</ulink>.
15235 </para></footnote>
15236
15237 </para>
15238 <para>
15239 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
15240 present: It is emphatically temporary. The <quote>problem</quote> with file
15241 sharing&mdash;to the extent there is a real problem&mdash;is a problem
15242 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
15243 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
15244 makers today to be <quote>solving</quote> this problem in light of a technology
15245 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
15246 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
15247 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
15248 artists get paid, during
15249
15250 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
15251 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
15252 and twenty-first-century technologies.
15253 </para>
15254 <para>
15255 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different <quote>problems</quote>
15256 here to solve. Let's start with type D content&mdash;uncopyrighted
15257 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
15258 <quote>problem</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
15259 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
15260 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
15261 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
15262 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
15263 order to eliminate kidnapping.
15264 </para>
15265 <para>
15266 Type C content raises a different <quote>problem.</quote> This is content that was,
15267 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
15268 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
15269 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
15270 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
15271 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
15272 way that returns something to the artist.
15273 </para>
15274 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
15275 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
15276 <para>
15277 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
15278 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
15279 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
15280 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
15281 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
15282 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
15283 from the author's perspective, this <quote>sharing</quote> of his content without
15284 his being compensated is less than ideal.
15285 </para>
15286 <para>
15287 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
15288 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
15289 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
15290 providers would be free, under this rule, to <quote>share</quote> that content,
15291 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
15292 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
15293 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
15294 </para>
15295 <para>
15296
15297 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
15298 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
15299 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
15300 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
15301 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
15302 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
15303 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
15304 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
15305 trade.
15306 </para>
15307 <para>
15308 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
15309 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
15310 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
15311 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
15312 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
15313 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
15314 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
15315 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
15316 </para>
15317 <para>
15318 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
15319 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
15320 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
15321 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
15322 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
15323 delivering and accessing content.
15324 </para>
15325 <para>
15326 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
15327 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
15328 </para>
15329 <para>
15330 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
15331 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
15332 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
15333 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
15334 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
15335 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
15336 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
15337 harmed the interests of the content industry.
15338 </para>
15339 <para>
15340 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
15341 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
15342 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
15343 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
15344 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
15345 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
15346 way to compensate those who are harmed.
15347 </para>
15348 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15349 <para>
15350 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
15351 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.<footnote>
15352 <para>
15353 <!-- f9. -->
15354 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15355 William Fisher, <citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities</citetitle> (last
15356 revised: 10 October 2000), available at
15357 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #77</ulink>; William
15358 Fisher, <citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
15359 Entertainment</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
15360 2004), ch. 6, available at
15361 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #78</ulink>. Professor
15362 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
15363 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
15364 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, <quote>Impose a
15365 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,</quote> available at
15366 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Who's Holding Back
15367 Broadband?</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
15368 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
15369 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, 26 February 2002,
15370 available at
15371 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, <citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
15372 Use Fee (IPUF)</citetitle>, 3 March 2002, available at
15373 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
15374 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 13 May
15375 2002, available at
15376 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, <quote>Getting Copyright Right,</quote>
15377 IEEE Spectrum Online, 1 July 2002, available at
15378 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #83</ulink>; Declan
15379 McCullagh, <quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,</quote> CNET News.com, 27 August
15380 2002, available at
15381 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #84</ulink>.
15382 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
15383 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
15384 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
15385 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
15386 debate by about a decade. See
15387 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #85</ulink>.
15388 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William</primary></indexterm>
15389 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
15390 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15391 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'/>
15392 </para></footnote>
15393 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
15394 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
15395 would (1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
15396 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
15397 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
15398 develop (2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
15399 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (3) artists would be
15400 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (4) an appropriate
15401 tax.
15402 </para>
15403 <para>
15404 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
15405 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
15406 <citetitle>Promises to Keep</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
15407 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
15408 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
15409 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
15410 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
15411 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
15412 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
15413 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
15414 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
15415 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
15416 controlling access.
15417 </para>
15418 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'/>
15419 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15420 <indexterm><primary>semiotic democracy</primary></indexterm>
15421 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>semiotic</secondary></indexterm>
15422 <para>
15423 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
15424 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
15425 the system supports the widest range of <quote>semiotic democracy</quote>
15426 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
15427 other changes I described were accomplished&mdash;in particular, the
15428 limits on derivative
15429
15430 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
15431 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
15432 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
15433 allowed to do with the content itself.
15434 </para>
15435 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
15436 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore</primary></indexterm>
15437 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
15438 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>prices of</secondary></indexterm>
15439 <para>
15440 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
15441 <quote>harm</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
15442 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
15443 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
15444 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
15445 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat <quote>free</quote> by being
15446 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
15447 of songs at even the very high price of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents,
15448 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
15449 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
15450 Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a song. And no doubt
15451 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
15452 on-line.
15453 </para>
15454 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
15455 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast</secondary></indexterm>
15456 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
15457 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
15458 <indexterm><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in</secondary></indexterm>
15459 <para>
15460 This competition has already occurred against the background of <quote>free</quote>
15461 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
15462 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
15463 that, there is nothing impossible at all about <quote>competing with free.</quote>
15464 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
15465 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
15466 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
15467 theaters are often luxurious&mdash;with <quote>first class</quote> seats, and meals
15468 served while you watch a movie&mdash;as they struggle and succeed in
15469 finding ways to compete with <quote>free.</quote>
15470 </para>
15471 <para>
15472 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
15473 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
15474 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
15475 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
15476 innovators&mdash;ones who would have a right to the content, and would
15477 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
15478 the law.
15479 </para>
15480 <para>
15481 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
15482 </para>
15483 <para>
15484
15485 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
15486 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
15487 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
15488 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
15489 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
15490 create.
15491 </para>
15492 <para>
15493 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
15494 by
15495 </para>
15496 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
15497 <listitem><para>
15498 <!-- 1. -->
15499 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
15500 </para></listitem>
15501 <listitem><para>
15502 <!-- 2. -->
15503 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
15504 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
15505 statute;
15506 </para></listitem>
15507 <listitem><para>
15508 <!-- 3. -->
15509 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
15510 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
15511 </para></listitem>
15512 </orderedlist>
15513 <para>
15514 But what if <quote>piracy</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
15515 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
15516 consumers continue to <quote>take</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
15517 something then?
15518 </para>
15519 <para>
15520 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
15521 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
15522 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
15523 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
15524 technology that is 95 percent secure and produces a market of size <citetitle>x</citetitle>,
15525 or (b) to have a technology that is 50 percent secure but produces a
15526 market of five times <citetitle>x</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
15527 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
15528 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
15529 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
15530 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
15531 pirates.
15532 </para>
15533 <para>
15534 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
15535 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
15536 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
15537
15538 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
15539 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
15540 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
15541 </para>
15542 </section>
15543
15544 <section id="firelawyers">
15545 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers</title>
15546 <para>
15547 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
15548 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
15549 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
15550 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
15551 </para>
15552 <para>
15553 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
15554 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
15555 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
15556 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
15557 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
15558 strong view queers the law.
15559 </para>
15560 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville</primary></indexterm>
15561 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of</secondary></indexterm>
15562 <para>
15563 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
15564 <quote>radical</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
15565 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
15566 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
15567 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
15568 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
15569 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
15570 Nimmer, thought it obvious.<footnote><para>
15571 <!-- f10. -->
15572 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Copyright's First Amendment</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
15573 Memorial Lecture), <citetitle>UCLA Law Review</citetitle> 48 (2001): 1057, 1069&ndash;70.
15574 </para></footnote>
15575
15576 </para>
15577 <para>
15578 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
15579 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
15580 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
15581 </para>
15582 <para>
15583 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
15584 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
15585 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
15586 the legal system are slight.<footnote><para>
15587 <!-- f11. -->
15588 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
15589 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
15590 leading him to question his own publicly stated
15591 position&mdash;twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
15592 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
15593 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
15594 J. Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
15595 Drive the Digital Marketplace</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002), (reviewing his
15596 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
15597 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?</quote> working paper, June 2003,
15598 available at
15599 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #86</ulink>.
15600 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
15601 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
15602 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
15603 <citetitle>Rethinking</citetitle>, 174&ndash;76.
15604 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
15605 </para></footnote>
15606 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
15607 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
15608 them it works.
15609 </para>
15610 <para>
15611 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
15612 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
15613 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
15614 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
15615 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
15616 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
15617 practically never be done.
15618 </para>
15619 <para>
15620 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
15621 billed at the largest firms at more than $400 per hour. How much time
15622 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
15623 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
15624 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
15625 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
15626 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
15627 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
15628 </para>
15629 <para>
15630 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
15631 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
15632 their duty to change the way the law works&mdash;or better, to change the
15633 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
15634 top 1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
15635 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
15636 </para>
15637 <para>
15638 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
15639 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
15640 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
15641 its review.
15642 </para>
15643 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
15644 <para>
15645 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
15646 technology&mdash;the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
15647 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
15648 technology&mdash;a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
15649 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
15650 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
15651 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
15652 </para>
15653 <para>
15654 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture&mdash;but it should
15655 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
15656
15657 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311-->
15658 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
15659 simple pragmatic question: <quote>Will it do good?</quote> When challenged about
15660 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, <quote>Why not?</quote>
15661 </para>
15662 <para>
15663 We should ask, <quote>Why?</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
15664 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
15665 keep your lawyers away.
15666 </para>
15667 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
15668 </section>
15669 </section>
15670 </chapter>
15671 <chapter label="" id="c-notes">
15672 <title>Notes</title>
15673 <para>
15674 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
15675 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
15676 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
15677 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
15678 this book. For each link below, you can go to
15679 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes"/>
15680 and locate the original source by clicking on the number after the #
15681 sign. If the original link remains alive, you will be redirected to
15682 that link. If the original link has disappeared, you will be
15683 redirected to an appropriate reference for the material.
15684 </para>
15685
15686 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
15687
15688 <index type="endnotes"/>
15689
15690 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
15691
15692 </chapter>
15693 <chapter label="" id="c-acknowledgments">
15694 <title>Acknowledgments</title>
15695 <para>
15696 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
15697 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
15698 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
15699 to him that this book is dedicated.
15700 </para>
15701 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
15702 <para>
15703 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
15704 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
15705 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
15706 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
15707 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
15708 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
15709 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
15710 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
15711 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
15712 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
15713 critical eye on much of this.
15714 </para>
15715 <para>
15716 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
15717 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
15718 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
15719 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
15720 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
15721 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
15722 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
15723 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
15724 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
15725 </para>
15726 <para>
15727 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
15728 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
15729 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
15730 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
15731 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
15732 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
15733 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
15734 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
15735 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
15736 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
15737 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
15738 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
15739 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
15740 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
15741 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, <quote>Wink,</quote> Roger Wood, <quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,</quote>
15742 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
15743 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
15744 a bunch of great replies.)
15745 </para>
15746 <para>
15747 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
15748 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
15749 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
15750 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
15751 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
15752 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
15753 throughout this book.
15754 </para>
15755 <para>
15756 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
15757 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
15758 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
15759 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
15760 </para>
15761 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->
15762
15763 </chapter>
15764
15765 <xi:include href="freeculture-about-edition-en.xml" xmlns:xi="http://www.w3.org/2001/XInclude">
15766 <xi:fallback/>
15767 </xi:include>
15768
15769 <index></index>
15770 <colophon>
15771 <title></title>
15772 <?latex {\centering
15773 ?>
15774 <para>
15775 Free culture: How big media uses technology and the law to lock down
15776 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
15777 </para>
15778 <para>
15779 Copyright &copy; 2004 Lawrence Lessig. Some rights reserved.
15780 </para>
15781
15782 <para>
15783 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/"/>
15784 </para>
15785
15786 <para>
15787 Published in 2015. First published 2004 by The Penguin Press.
15788 </para>
15789
15790 <para>
15791 This English and Norwegian Bokmål edition was published by Petter
15792 Reinholdtsen with help from many volunteers.
15793 </para>
15794
15795 <para>
15796 Typeset with
15797 <ulink url="http://dblatex.sourceforge.net">dblatex</ulink> using the
15798 font Crimson Text.
15799 </para>
15800
15801 <para>
15802 Excerpt from an editorial titled <quote>The Coming of Copyright
15803 Perpetuity,</quote> <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, January
15804 16, 2003. Copyright &copy; 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted
15805 with permission.
15806 </para>
15807 <para>
15808 Cartoon in figure
15809 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/> by
15810 Paul Conrad, copyright Tribune Media Services, Inc. All rights
15811 reserved. Reprinted with permission.
15812 </para>
15813 <para>
15814 Diagram in figure
15815 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership"/>
15816 courtesy of the office of FCC Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
15817 </para>
15818
15819 <para>
15820 Cover created by Petter Reinholdtsen using inkscape.
15821 </para>
15822
15823 <para>
15824 The quotes on the cover came from
15825 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/jacket/"/>.
15826 </para>
15827
15828 <para>
15829 Portrait on the cover was created 2013 by ActuaLitté and licensed
15830 under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 2.0 license. It was
15831 downloaded from
15832 <ulink url="https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File%3ALawrence_Lessig_(11014343366)_(cropped).jpg"/>.
15833 </para>
15834
15835 <para>
15836 Classifications:
15837 </para>
15838
15839 <para>
15840 (Dewey)
15841 306.4,
15842 306.40973,
15843 306.46,
15844 341.7582,
15845 343.7309/9
15846 </para>
15847
15848 <para>
15849 (UDK) 347.78
15850 </para>
15851
15852 <para>
15853 (US Library of Congress) KF2979.L47 2004
15854 </para>
15855
15856 <para>
15857 (ACM CRCS) K.4.1
15858 </para>
15859
15860 <para>
15861 Printing was sponsed by NUUG Foundation,
15862 <ulink url="http://www.nuugfoundation.no/"/>.
15863 </para>
15864
15865 <para>
15866 Includes index.
15867 </para>
15868
15869 <?latex } %\centering
15870 ?>
15871
15872 <para>
15873 The Docbook source is available from
15874 <ulink url="https://github.com/petterreinholdtsen/free-culture-lessig"/>.
15875 Please report any issues with the book there.
15876 </para>
15877
15878 <para>
15879 <informalfigure id="cc-logo">
15880 <graphic fileref="images/cc.svg" align="center" width="11%"></graphic>
15881 </informalfigure>
15882 </para>
15883
15884 <para>
15885 This book is licensed under a Creative Commons license. This license
15886 permits non-commercial use of this work, so long as attribution is
15887 given. For more information about the license visit
15888 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/"/>.
15889 </para>
15890
15891 <para>
15892 <informaltable id="isbn">
15893 <tgroup cols="2" align="left">
15894 <thead>
15895 <row>
15896 <entry>Format / MIME-type</entry>
15897 <entry>ISBN</entry>
15898 </row>
15899 </thead>
15900 <tbody>
15901 <row>
15902 <entry>US Trade edition from lulu.com</entry>
15903 <entry>978-82-690182-0-2</entry>
15904 </row>
15905 <row>
15906 <entry>application/pdf</entry>
15907 <entry>978-82-690182-1-9</entry>
15908 </row>
15909 <row>
15910 <entry>application/epub+zip</entry>
15911 <entry>978-82-690182-2-6</entry>
15912 </row>
15913 </tbody>
15914 </tgroup>
15915 </informaltable>
15916 </para>
15917
15918 </colophon>
15919 </book>