1 <?xml version='
1.0' encoding='UTF-
8'
?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href=
"docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type=
"text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012 with input from Martin Borg. -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC
"-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
13 <!ENTITY translationblock
"">
15 <book id=
"index" lang=
"en">
17 <title>Free Culture
</title>
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
21 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
22 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY
</subtitle>
24 <pubdate>2004-
03-
25</pubdate>
26 <releaseinfo>Version
2004-
02-
10</releaseinfo>
30 <firstname>Lawrence
</firstname>
31 <surname>Lessig
</surname>
35 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
36 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
38 <subjectset scheme=
"libraryofcongress">
40 <subjectterm>Intellectual property
—United States.
</subjectterm>
43 <subjectterm>Mass media
—United States.
</subjectterm>
46 <subjectterm>Technological innovations
—United States.
</subjectterm>
49 <subjectterm>Art
—United States.
</subjectterm>
55 <publishername>The Penguin Press
</publishername>
56 <address><city>New York
</city></address>
61 <holder>Lawrence Lessig
</holder>
67 <imagedata fileref=
"images/cc.png" contentdepth=
"3em" width=
"100%" align=
"center"/>
70 <imagedata fileref=
"images/cc.svg" contentdepth=
"3em" width=
"100%" align=
"center"/>
73 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved
</phrase>
79 This version of
<citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle> is licensed under
80 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
81 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
82 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
83 <ulink url=
"http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/
1.0/
</ulink>
88 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR
</title>
91 (
<ulink url=
"http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org
</ulink>),
92 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
93 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
94 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
95 (
<ulink url=
"http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org
</ulink>).
96 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House,
2001) and Code: And
97 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books,
1999), Lessig is a member of
98 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
99 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
100 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
101 twice listed in BusinessWeek's
<quote>e.biz
25,
</quote> and named one of Scientific
102 American's
<quote>50 visionaries.
</quote> A graduate of the University of
103 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
104 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
109 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
110 <mediaobject role=
"cover">
111 <imageobject remap=
"lrg" role=
"front-large">
112 <imagedata fileref=
"images/cover.png" format=
"PNG" width=
"444" />
115 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
116 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
118 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
119 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
121 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
122 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
127 <biblioid class=
"isbn">1-
59420-
006-
8</biblioid>
130 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
132 <biblioid class=
"libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
136 <dedication id=
"salespoints">
139 You can buy a copy of this book by clicking on one of the links below:
141 <itemizedlist mark=
"number" spacing=
"compact">
142 <listitem><para><ulink url=
"http://www.amazon.com/">Amazon
</ulink></para></listitem>
143 <listitem><para><ulink url=
"http://www.barnesandnoble.com/">B
&N
</ulink></para></listitem>
144 <listitem><para><ulink url=
"http://www.penguin.com/">Penguin
</ulink></para></listitem>
145 <!-- <ulink url="">Local Bookstore</ulink> -->
148 <!-- PAGE BREAK 2 -->
149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
150 <dedication id=
"alsobylessig">
153 ALSO BY LAWRENCE LESSIG
156 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
159 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
163 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
164 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
167 THE PENGUIN PRESS, a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc.
375 Hudson Street New
171 Copyright
© Lawrence Lessig. All rights reserved.
174 Excerpt from an editorial titled
<quote>The Coming of Copyright Perpetuity,
</quote>
175 <citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>, January
16,
2003. Copyright
176 © 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted with permission.
179 Cartoon in
<xref linkend=
"fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/> by Paul Conrad, copyright Tribune
180 Media Services, Inc. All rights reserved. Reprinted with permission.
183 Diagram in
<xref linkend=
"fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership"/> courtesy of the office of FCC
184 Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
187 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
191 Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law to lock down
192 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
201 ISBN
1-
59420-
006-
8 (hardcover)
205 1. Intellectual property
—United States.
2. Mass media
—United States.
208 3. Technological innovations
—United States.
4. Art
—United States. I. Title.
214 343.7309'
9—dc22
217 This book is printed on acid-free paper.
220 Printed in the United States of America
226 Designed by Marysarah Quinn
234 Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of
235 this publication may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a
236 retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means
237 (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise),
238 without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and
239 the above publisher of this book.
242 The scanning, uploading, and distribution of this book via the
243 Internet or via any other means without the permission of the
244 publisher is illegal and punishable by law. Please purchase only
245 authorized electronic editions and do not participate in or encourage
246 electronic piracy of copyrighted materials. Your support of the
247 author's rights is appreciated.
251 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
252 <dedication><title></title>
254 To Eric Eldred
—whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
262 <title>List of figures
</title>
269 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
270 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
271 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
272 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
277 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
281 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
282 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
283 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
284 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
285 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
286 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
290 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
291 2 Architecture and Law: Force
292 2 Market: Concentration
295 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
296 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
297 2 Constraining Creators
298 2 Constraining Innovators
299 2 Corrupting Citizens
301 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
302 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
306 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
307 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
309 2 1. More Formalities
310 3 Registration and Renewal
313 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
314 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
315 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
321 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
323 <preface id=
"preface">
324 <title>PREFACE
</title>
325 <indexterm id='idxpoguedavid' class='startofrange'
><primary>Pogue, David
</primary></indexterm>
327 <emphasis role=
"bold">At the end
</emphasis> of his review of my first
328 book,
<citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
</citetitle>, David
329 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
330 computer-related texts, wrote this:
334 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
335 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
336 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
337 system, you can always flip off the modem.
<footnote id=
"preface01"><para>
338 David Pogue,
<quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
30 January
2000.
343 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book
—that
344 software, or
<quote>code,
</quote> functioned as a kind of law
—and his review
345 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
346 could always
<quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome
</quote>-like simply flip a
347 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
348 any troubles that exist in
<emphasis>that
</emphasis> space wouldn't
349 <quote>affect
</quote> us anymore.
352 Pogue might have been right in
1999—I'm skeptical, but maybe.
353 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
354 <citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
355 causes even after the modem is turned
357 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
358 on-line have fundamentally affected
<quote>people who aren't online.
</quote> There
359 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
361 <indexterm startref='idxpoguedavid' class='endofrange'
/>
363 But unlike
<citetitle>Code
</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
364 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
365 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
366 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
370 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
371 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of
<quote>free culture
</quote>—not
372 <quote>free
</quote> as in
<quote>free beer
</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
373 free software movement
<footnote>
375 Richard M. Stallman,
<citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies
</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed.
2002).
376 </para></footnote>), but
<quote>free
</quote> as in
<quote>free speech,
</quote> <quote>free markets,
</quote>
377 <quote>free trade,
</quote> <quote>free enterprise,
</quote> <quote>free will,
</quote> and
<quote>free elections.
</quote> A
378 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
379 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
380 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
381 follow-on creators and innovators remain
<emphasis>as free as
382 possible
</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
383 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
384 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
385 <quote>permission culture
</quote>—a culture in which creators get to create
386 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
390 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not
<quote>we
</quote>
391 on the Left or
<quote>you
</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
392 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
393 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
394 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
395 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
396 culture deem fundamental.
398 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'
><primary>power, concentration of
</primary></indexterm>
399 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace
</primary></indexterm>
400 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
401 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted
</primary></indexterm>
403 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
404 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
405 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
406 generated more than
700,
000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
407 As William Safire described marching
<quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
408 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
409 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,
</quote> he formulated perhaps
410 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
415 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
416 power
—political, corporate, media, cultural
—should be anathema to
417 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
418 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
419 the greatest expression of democracy.
<footnote><para> William Safire,
420 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
22 May
2003.
421 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
426 This idea is an element of the argument of
<citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle>, though my
427 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
428 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
429 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
430 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
431 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
432 you
—whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
433 Safire's left or on his right.
435 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'
/>
437 <emphasis role=
"strong">The inspiration
</emphasis> for the title and for
438 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
439 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
440 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in
<citetitle>Free Software, Free
441 Society
</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
442 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
443 that this work is
<quote>merely
</quote> derivative.
446 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
447 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
448 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
449 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
450 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
451 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
452 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
453 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
456 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
457 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
458 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
459 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
460 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
464 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
465 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
466 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
467 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
468 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
469 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
470 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
475 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
478 <chapter label=
"0" id=
"c-introduction">
479 <title>INTRODUCTION
</title>
480 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'
><primary>Wright brothers
</primary></indexterm>
482 <emphasis role=
"strong">On December
17</emphasis>,
1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
483 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
484 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
485 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
486 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
487 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
489 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.
</primary></indexterm>
490 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'
><primary>land ownership, air traffic and
</primary></indexterm>
491 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
493 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
494 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
495 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
496 and all the space above, to
<quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.
</quote><footnote><para>
497 St. George Tucker,
<citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries
</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
498 Rothman Reprints,
1969),
18.
501 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
502 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
503 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
505 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'
/>
507 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
508 law
—deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
509 by the most important legal thinkers of our past
—mattered. If
510 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
511 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
512 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
513 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
515 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
516 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
518 In
1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
519 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
520 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
521 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
522 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
523 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
524 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to
<quote>an indefinite
525 extent, upwards,
</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
526 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
528 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
529 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
530 <indexterm id='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='startofrange'
><primary>Douglas, William O.
</primary></indexterm>
531 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='startofrange'
><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on airspace vs. land rights
</secondary></indexterm>
533 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
534 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
535 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
536 <quote>taking
</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
537 that
<quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
538 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.
</quote> But Justice Douglas
539 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
540 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
544 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
545 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
546 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
547 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
548 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
549 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
550 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
551 the public has a just claim.
<footnote>
553 United States v. Causby, U.S.
328 (
1946):
256,
261. The Court did find
554 that there could be a
<quote>taking
</quote> if the government's use of its land
555 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
556 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece,
<quote>(Intellectual)
557 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
558 Authorship,
</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review
</citetitle> 48 (
1996):
1293,
1333. See also Paul
559 Goldstein,
<citetitle>Real Property
</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press,
1984),
561 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
562 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
567 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.
</quote>
569 <indexterm startref='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='endofrange'
/>
571 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
572 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
573 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
575 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line:
<quote>Common sense revolts
576 at the idea.
</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
577 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
578 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
579 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
581 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
582 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
583 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers
</primary></indexterm>
585 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
586 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
587 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
588 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
589 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
590 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
591 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
592 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
593 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by
<quote>what
594 seemed reasonable
</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
595 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
596 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
597 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
598 end, the force of what seems
<quote>obvious
</quote> to everyone else
—the power of
599 <quote>common sense
</quote>—would prevail. Their
<quote>private interest
</quote> would not be
600 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
602 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'
/>
603 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'
/>
604 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'
/>
605 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='endofrange'
/>
606 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'
><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard
</primary></indexterm>
607 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham
</primary></indexterm>
608 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
609 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
610 <indexterm id='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='startofrange'
><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of
</secondary></indexterm>
612 <emphasis role='strong'
>Edwin Howard Armstrong
</emphasis> is one of
613 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
614 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
615 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
616 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
617 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
618 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in
1831. But
619 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
620 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
621 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
625 On the day after Christmas,
1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
626 for his most significant invention
—FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
627 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
628 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
629 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
630 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
631 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
632 much less transmitter power and static.
635 On November
5,
1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
636 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
637 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
638 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
639 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
640 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
641 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
642 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
643 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.
</quote>
646 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
650 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
651 sounded like a glass of water being poured.
… A paper was crumpled
652 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
653 fire.
… Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
654 and guitar number were performed.
… The music was projected with a
655 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio
<quote>music
656 box.
</quote><footnote><para>
657 Lawrence Lessing,
<citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong
</citetitle>
658 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company,
1956),
209.
662 <indexterm id='idxrca' class='startofrange'
><primary>RCA
</primary></indexterm>
663 <indexterm id='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='startofrange'
><primary>media
</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in
</secondary></indexterm>
665 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
666 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
667 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
668 AM radio market. By
1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
669 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
670 a handful of networks.
673 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David
</primary></indexterm>
675 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
676 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
677 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
678 that removed static from
<quote>radio.
</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
679 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
683 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
684 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
685 revolution
— start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
686 RCA.
<footnote><para> See
<quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
687 Electronic Era,
</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
688 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
690 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
1</ulink>.
694 <indexterm id='idxfmradio' class='startofrange'
><primary>FM radio
</primary></indexterm>
695 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David
</primary></indexterm>
697 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
698 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
699 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
702 <indexterm id='idxlessinglawrence' class='startofrange'
><primary>Lessing, Lawrence
</primary></indexterm>
705 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
706 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
707 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
708 unrestrained, posed
… a complete reordering of radio power
709 … and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
710 on which RCA had grown to power.
<footnote><para>Lessing,
226.
714 <indexterm id='idxfcconfmradio' class='startofrange'
><primary>FCC
</primary><secondary>on FM radio
</secondary></indexterm>
716 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
717 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
718 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
719 FM radio's deployment generally. In
1936, RCA hired the former head
720 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
721 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM
—principally by moving FM
722 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
723 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
724 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
725 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
726 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
728 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
731 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
732 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
733 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
734 deviousness.
<footnote><para>
739 <indexterm startref='idxlessinglawrence' class='endofrange'
/>
740 <indexterm><primary>AT
&T
</primary></indexterm>
742 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
743 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
744 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
745 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
746 (This change was strongly supported by AT
&T, because the loss of
747 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
748 wired links from AT
&T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
751 <indexterm startref='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='endofrange'
/>
752 <indexterm startref='idxfcconfmradio' class='endofrange'
/>
754 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
755 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
756 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
757 invalid
—baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
758 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
759 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
760 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
761 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
762 now broke, in
1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
763 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
765 <indexterm startref='idxfmradio' class='endofrange'
/>
766 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'
/>
768 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
769 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
770 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
771 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
772 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
773 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
774 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
775 course always public spirited; the reality is something
776 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
777 to themselves, would crumble in
779 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
780 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
781 effect of technological change.
783 <indexterm startref='idxrca' class='endofrange'
/>
784 <indexterm startref='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='endofrange'
/>
785 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>development of
</secondary></indexterm>
787 <emphasis role=
"strong">There's no
</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
788 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
789 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
790 Internet and American Life Project,
58 percent of Americans had access
791 to the Internet in
2002, up from
49 percent two years
792 before.
<footnote><para>
793 Amanda Lenhart,
<quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
794 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,
</quote> Pew Internet and American
795 Life Project,
15 April
2003:
6, available at
796 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
2</ulink>.
798 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
802 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
803 changed things. Some of these changes are technical
—the Internet has
804 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
805 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
806 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
807 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
808 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
809 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
810 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
813 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
814 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
815 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
816 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
817 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
818 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
821 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'
/>
822 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel
</primary></indexterm>
823 <indexterm id='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='startofrange'
><primary>culture
</primary><secondary>commercial vs. noncommercial
</secondary></indexterm>
824 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah
</primary></indexterm>
826 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
827 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
828 regulation of each. By
<quote>commercial culture
</quote> I mean that part of our
829 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
830 <quote>noncommercial culture
</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
832 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
833 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
834 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his
<quote>Reader,
</quote> or
835 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
838 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
839 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
840 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
841 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
842 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
843 left this culture
<quote>free.
</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
844 individuals shared and transformed their culture
—telling
845 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
846 clubs, sharing music, making tapes
—were left alone by the law.
848 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>commercial creativity as primary purpose of
</secondary></indexterm>
850 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
851 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
852 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
853 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
854 marketplace.
<footnote>
856 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
857 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
858 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
859 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
860 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
861 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
862 D. Brandeis,
<quote>The Right to Privacy,
</quote> Harvard Law Review
4 (
1890):
193,
864 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
866 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
867 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
868 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
869 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
871 <indexterm><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
872 <indexterm><primary>permission culture
</primary><secondary> free culture vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
874 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
875 been erased.
<footnote><para>
876 See Jessica Litman,
<citetitle>Digital Copyright
</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
878 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica
</primary></indexterm>
880 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
881 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
882 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
883 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
884 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
885 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
886 the balance of our history
—between uses of our culture that were
887 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission
—has
888 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
889 culture, more and more a permission culture.
891 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
892 <indexterm><primary>protection of artists vs. business interests
</primary></indexterm>
894 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
895 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
896 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
897 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
898 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
899 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
900 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
901 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
902 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
903 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
906 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='endofrange'
/>
908 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
909 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
910 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
911 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
912 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
913 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
914 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
915 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
916 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
917 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
918 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
919 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
920 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
921 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
922 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
923 than creators do today
—all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
924 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
927 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
928 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
929 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
930 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
931 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
932 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
935 <indexterm startref='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='endofrange'
/>
936 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack
</primary><secondary> on creative property rights
</secondary></indexterm>
938 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
939 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
940 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
941 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions
—whether
<quote>piracy
</quote> will
942 be permitted, and whether
<quote>property
</quote> will be protected. The
<quote>war
</quote> that
943 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet
—what
944 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
945 calls his
<quote>own terrorist war
</quote><footnote><para>
946 Amy Harmon,
<quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
947 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,
</quote> <citetitle>New York
948 Times
</citetitle>,
17 January
2002.
949 </para></footnote>—has been framed as a battle about the
950 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
951 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
955 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
956 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
957 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
958 <quote>creative property.
</quote> I believe that
<quote>piracy
</quote> is wrong, and that the
959 law, properly tuned, should punish
<quote>piracy,
</quote> whether on or off the
963 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
964 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
965 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet
<quote>pirates
</quote> will also rid our
966 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
968 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>First Amendment to
</secondary></indexterm>
969 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>as protection of creators
</secondary></indexterm>
970 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment
</primary></indexterm>
971 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
973 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first
180 years of
974 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
975 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
976 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
977 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,
<footnote>
979 Neil W. Netanel,
<quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,
</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
980 Journal
</citetitle> 106 (
1996):
283.
981 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
983 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
984 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
985 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
986 could cultivate and extend our culture.
989 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
990 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
991 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
992 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist
–like,
993 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
994 granted
—but it is not often granted to the critical or the
995 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
996 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
997 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Should "Is it" be "It is" ? -->
1001 The story that follows is about this war. Is it not about the
1002 <quote>centrality of technology
</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
1003 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
1004 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
1005 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
1006 against an industry.
1009 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
1010 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
1011 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
1012 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
1013 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
1014 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
1015 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
1017 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
1018 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
1019 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='startofrange'
><primary>intellectual property rights
</primary></indexterm>
1021 <emphasis role=
"strong">Like the Causbys'
</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about
<quote>property.
</quote> The
1022 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
1023 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
1024 this
<quote>property
</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
1025 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
1026 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
1027 of
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
1028 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
1029 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
1030 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
1031 <quote>trespassing
</quote> upon legitimate claims of
<quote>property.
</quote> It is as plain to
1032 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
1035 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
1036 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
1037 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers
</primary></indexterm>
1039 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
1040 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
1041 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
1042 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
1044 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
1045 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
1048 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of
</primary></indexterm>
1050 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
1051 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
1052 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
1053 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
1054 our
<quote>culture
</quote> was as
<quote>owned
</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
1055 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
1056 <emphasis>uses
</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
1057 accepted as it is now.
1060 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
1061 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
1062 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
1063 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1066 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1067 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1070 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1071 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1072 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1073 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1074 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1077 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1078 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1079 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1080 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1083 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
1084 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
1086 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1087 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1088 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1089 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of
<quote>intellectual
1090 property.
</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1091 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1092 this silliness will be much more profound.
1093 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1095 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='endofrange'
/>
1097 <emphasis role=
"strong">The struggle
</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas:
<quote>piracy
</quote> and
1098 <quote>property.
</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1102 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1103 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1104 obscure French theorists
—however natural that is for the weird
1105 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1106 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1107 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1110 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1111 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1112 government, pushed by big media to respond to this
<quote>something new,
</quote> is
1113 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1114 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let
<quote>common
1115 sense
</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1116 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1117 law
—and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1118 fundamental about who we have always been.
1121 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1122 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1123 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1124 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1125 of one more consequence of this form of corruption
—a consequence
1126 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1129 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1130 <part id=
"c-piracy">
1131 <title><quote>PIRACY
</quote></title>
1133 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1134 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>English
</secondary></indexterm>
1135 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord
</primary></indexterm>
1136 <indexterm><primary>music publishing
</primary></indexterm>
1137 <indexterm><primary>sheet music
</primary></indexterm>
1139 <emphasis role=
"strong">Since the inception
</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1140 been a war against
<quote>piracy.
</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1141 <quote>piracy,
</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1142 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1143 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1147 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1148 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1149 of them for his own use.
<footnote><para>
1151 <citetitle>Bach
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Longman
</citetitle>,
98 Eng. Rep.
1274 (
1777) (Mansfield).
1154 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='endofrange'
/>
1156 <indexterm><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary> efficient content distribution on
</secondary></indexterm>
1157 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='startofrange'
><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing
</primary><secondary>efficiency of
</secondary></indexterm>
1159 Today we are in the middle of another
<quote>war
</quote> against
<quote>piracy.
</quote> The
1160 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1161 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1162 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1163 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1164 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1165 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1168 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1169 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1170 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1171 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1172 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will
<quote>rob the author of the
1175 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='endofrange'
/>
1177 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1178 increasingly to technology to defend their
<quote>property
</quote> against this
1179 <quote>piracy.
</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1180 raised to believe that
<quote>property
</quote> should be
<quote>free.
</quote> Forget tattoos,
1181 never mind body piercing
—our kids are becoming
1182 <emphasis>thieves
</emphasis>!
1185 There's no doubt that
<quote>piracy
</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1186 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1187 notion of
<quote>piracy
</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1188 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1191 The idea goes something like this:
1195 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1196 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1197 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1198 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1199 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1203 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP
</primary></indexterm>
1204 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle
</primary></indexterm>
1205 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts
</primary></indexterm>
1206 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='startofrange'
><primary>creative property
</primary><secondary><quote>if value, then right
</quote> theory of
</secondary></indexterm>
1207 <indexterm id='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='startofrange'
><primary><quote>if value, then right
</quote> theory
</primary></indexterm>
1209 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1210 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the
<quote>if value, then right
</quote>
1211 theory of creative property
<footnote><para>
1213 See Rochelle Dreyfuss,
<quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1214 in the Pepsi Generation,
</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review
</citetitle> 65 (
1990):
397.
1216 —if there is value, then someone must have a
1217 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1218 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1219 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.
<footnote><para>
1221 Lisa Bannon,
<quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1222 Up,
</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal
</citetitle>,
21 August
1996, available at
1223 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
3</ulink>; Jonathan
1224 Zittrain,
<quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1225 Speech, No One Wins,
</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe
</citetitle>,
24 November
2002.
1226 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
1228 There was
<quote>value
</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1229 <quote>right
</quote>—even against the Girl Scouts.
1231 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='endofrange'
/>
1233 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1234 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1235 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1236 of law protecting creative property. But the
<quote>if value, then right
</quote>
1237 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1238 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1240 <indexterm startref='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='endofrange'
/>
1241 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
1242 <indexterm id='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='startofrange'
><primary>creativity
</primary><secondary>legal restrictions on
</secondary></indexterm>
1244 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1245 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1246 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1247 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1248 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1251 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1252 takes care to draw
—the distinction between republishing someone's
1253 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1254 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1255 copyright law today regulates both.
1257 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='endofrange'
/>
1259 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1260 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1261 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1262 entities could bear the burden of the law
—even the burden of the
1263 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1264 more expense of doing business.
1266 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>creativity impeded by
</secondary></indexterm>
1267 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
1268 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)
</primary></indexterm>
1270 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1271 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1272 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1273 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1274 <quote>copying,
</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1275 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1276 outweighs any original benefit
—certainly as it affects
1277 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1278 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1279 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1280 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1281 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1282 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1283 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1284 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1285 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1286 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the
<quote>Rise of the Creative
1287 Class.
</quote><footnote>
1290 In
<citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class
</citetitle> (New York:
1291 Basic Books,
2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1292 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1293 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1294 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1295 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1296 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1298 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
1299 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)
</primary></indexterm>
1301 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1302 this creative class.
1304 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='endofrange'
/>
1306 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1307 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1308 context the current battles about behavior labeled
<quote>piracy.
</quote>
1312 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1313 <chapter label=
"1" id=
"creators">
1314 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators
</title>
1315 <indexterm id='idxanimatedcartoons' class='startofrange'
><primary>animated cartoons
</primary></indexterm>
1316 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'
><primary>cartoon films
</primary></indexterm>
1317 <indexterm id='idxfilmsanimated' class='startofrange'
><primary>films
</primary><secondary>animated
</secondary></indexterm>
1318 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatwillie' class='startofrange'
><primary>Steamboat Willie
</primary></indexterm>
1319 <indexterm id='idxmickeymouse' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mickey Mouse
</primary></indexterm>
1321 <emphasis role=
"strong">In
1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1322 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called
<citetitle>Plane Crazy
</citetitle>.
1323 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1324 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound,
<citetitle>Steamboat Willie
</citetitle> brought
1325 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1327 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1329 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1330 movie
<citetitle>The Jazz Singer
</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1331 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1332 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1333 Disney ran a test in the summer of
1928, the results were unambiguous.
1334 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1338 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1339 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1340 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1341 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1342 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1345 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1346 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1347 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1348 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1349 synchronization was pretty close.
1352 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1353 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1354 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1355 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1356 it was something new!
<footnote><para>
1358 Leonard Maltin,
<citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1359 Cartoons
</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books,
1987),
34–35.
1363 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub
</primary></indexterm>
1365 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1366 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly:
<quote>I have never been so thrilled
1367 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.
</quote>
1370 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1371 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1372 rarely
—except in Disney's hands
—been anything more than
1373 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1374 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1375 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1376 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1378 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt' class='endofrange'
/>
1379 <indexterm id='idxkeatonbuster' class='startofrange'
><primary>Keaton, Buster
</primary></indexterm>
1380 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='startofrange'
><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
1382 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that
1928 also marks
1383 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1384 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1385 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was
<citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr
</citetitle>.
1388 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in
1895. In the era of silent
1389 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1390 uncontrollable laughter from his audience.
<citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1391 Jr
</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1392 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton
—wildly popular
1393 and among the best of its genre.
1395 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1396 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1398 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr
</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1400 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1401 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1402 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,
<footnote><para>
1404 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1405 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
4</ulink>.
1406 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1407 use the music for five songs in
<citetitle>Steamboat Willie
</citetitle>:
<quote>Steamboat Bill,
</quote> <quote>The
1408 Simpleton
</quote> (Delille),
<quote>Mischief Makers
</quote> (Carbonara),
<quote>Joyful Hurry No.
1</quote>
1409 (Baron), and
<quote>Gawky Rube
</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song,
<quote>The Turkey in the
1410 Straw,
</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1411 Harry Surden,
10 July
2003, on file with author.
1413 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1414 the invention of synchronized sound in
<citetitle>The Jazz Singer
</citetitle> that we
1415 get
<citetitle>Steamboat Willie
</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1416 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song
<quote>Steamboat Bill,
</quote>
1417 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1420 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatwillie' class='endofrange'
/>
1421 <indexterm startref='idxmickeymouse' class='endofrange'
/>
1422 <indexterm startref='idxkeatonbuster' class='endofrange'
/>
1423 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='endofrange'
/>
1424 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='startofrange'
><primary>creativity
</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works
</secondary></indexterm>
1425 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Inc.
</primary></indexterm>
1427 This
<quote>borrowing
</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1428 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1429 films of his day.
<footnote><para>
1431 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman,
<quote>The Mouse
1432 that Ate the Public Domain,
</quote> Findlaw,
5 March
2002, at
1433 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
5</ulink>.
1435 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1436 knockoffs
—slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1437 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1438 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1439 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1440 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1441 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1442 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1445 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales' class='startofrange'
><primary>Grimm fairy tales
</primary></indexterm>
1447 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1448 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1449 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1450 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1451 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1452 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1453 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1456 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1457 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1458 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1459 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1460 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1461 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1462 work of others is astonishing when set together:
<citetitle>Snow White
</citetitle>
1463 (
1937),
<citetitle>Fantasia
</citetitle> (
1940),
<citetitle>Pinocchio
</citetitle> (
1940),
<citetitle>Dumbo
</citetitle>
1464 (
1941),
<citetitle>Bambi
</citetitle> (
1942),
<citetitle>Song of the South
</citetitle> (
1946),
1465 <citetitle>Cinderella
</citetitle> (
1950),
<citetitle>Alice in Wonderland
</citetitle> (
1951),
<citetitle>Robin
1466 Hood
</citetitle> (
1952),
<citetitle>Peter Pan
</citetitle> (
1953),
<citetitle>Lady and the Tramp
</citetitle>
1467 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1468 (
1955),
<citetitle>Mulan
</citetitle> (
1998),
<citetitle>Sleeping Beauty
</citetitle> (
1959),
<citetitle>101
1469 Dalmatians
</citetitle> (
1961),
<citetitle>The Sword in the Stone
</citetitle> (
1963), and
1470 <citetitle>The Jungle Book
</citetitle> (
1967)
—not to mention a recent example
1471 that we should perhaps quickly forget,
<citetitle>Treasure Planet
</citetitle>
1472 (
2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1473 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1474 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1475 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1477 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales' class='endofrange'
/>
1479 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1480 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1481 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1482 its importance. We could call this
<quote>Disney creativity,
</quote> though that
1483 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely,
<quote>Walt Disney
1484 creativity
</quote>—a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1485 culture around us and makes it something different.
1487 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='endofrange'
/>
1488 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='endofrange'
/>
1489 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='endofrange'
/>
1490 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
1491 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>defined
</secondary></indexterm>
1492 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>traditional term for conversion to
</secondary></indexterm>
1493 <para> In
1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1494 relatively fresh. The public domain in
1928 was not very old and was
1495 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1496 thirty years
—for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1497 copyrighted.
<footnote><para>
1499 Until
1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1500 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the
<quote>average
</quote> term by
1502 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1503 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if
100 copyrights are registered in year
1504 1, and only
15 are renewed, and the renewal term is
28 years, then the
1506 term is
32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1507 Web site associated with this book, available at
1508 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
6</ulink>.
1510 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1511 copyright holders of a creative work had an
<quote>exclusive right
</quote> to control
1512 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1513 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1516 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1517 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1518 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a
<quote>lawyer-free
1519 zone.
</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1520 for Disney to use and build upon in
1928. It was free for
1521 anyone
— whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1522 approved or not
—to use and build upon.
1524 <indexterm startref='idxanimatedcartoons' class='endofrange'
/>
1525 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsanimated' class='endofrange'
/>
1527 This is the ways things always were
—until quite recently. For most
1528 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1529 until
1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1530 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1532 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1533 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1534 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the
1960s and
1970s
1535 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1536 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1537 content from before the Great Depression.
1539 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'
/>
1540 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc' class='endofrange'
/>
1541 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='endofrange'
/>
1542 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='endofrange'
/>
1543 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='endofrange'
/>
1544 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1546 <emphasis role=
"strong">Of course
</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on
<quote>Walt Disney creativity.
</quote>
1547 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1548 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1551 <indexterm id='idxcomicsjapanese' class='startofrange'
><primary>comics, Japanese
</primary></indexterm>
1552 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1553 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics' class='startofrange'
><primary>Japanese comics
</primary></indexterm>
1554 <indexterm id='idxmanga' class='startofrange'
><primary>manga
</primary></indexterm>
1555 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1557 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1558 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture:
<citetitle>manga
</citetitle>, or
1559 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some
40 percent of
1560 publications are comics, and
30 percent of publication revenue derives
1561 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1562 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1563 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1566 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1567 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1568 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1569 the stories that these
<quote>graphic novels
</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1570 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are
<quote>men in tights.
</quote>
1571 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1572 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1573 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1574 interestingly different way.
1577 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1578 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1579 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1581 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='startofrange'
><primary>creativity
</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works
</secondary></indexterm>
1582 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics' class='startofrange'
><primary>doujinshi comics
</primary></indexterm>
1584 This is the phenomenon of
<citetitle>doujinshi
</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1585 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1586 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is
<emphasis>just
</emphasis> a
1587 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1588 transforming it either subtly or
1589 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1590 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1591 develop it differently
—with a different story line. Or the comic can
1592 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1593 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently
<quote>different.
</quote> But they
1594 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1595 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1596 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1598 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1600 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1601 huge. More than
33,
000 <quote>circles
</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1602 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than
450,
000 Japanese come
1603 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1604 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1605 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1606 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1607 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1608 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1610 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>Japanese
</secondary></indexterm>
1611 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
1613 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1614 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1615 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1616 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1617 one. Doujinshi are plainly
<quote>derivative works.
</quote> There is no general
1618 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1619 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1620 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with
<citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1621 Jr
</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that
<quote>taking
</quote> without
1622 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1623 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1624 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1626 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt2' class='endofrange'
/>
1627 <indexterm id='idxwinickjudd' class='startofrange'
><primary>Winick, Judd
</primary></indexterm>
1629 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1630 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1631 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me,
<quote>The
1632 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1633 in Japan now.
… American comics were born out of copying each
1634 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1635 other.
… That's how [the artists] learn to draw
—by going into comic
1636 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them
</quote>
1637 and building from them.
<footnote><para>
1639 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud,
<citetitle>Reinventing Comics
</citetitle> (New
1640 York: Perennial,
2000).
1643 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='endofrange'
/>
1644 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics
</primary></indexterm>
1646 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1647 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1648 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me,
<quote>there are these rules
1649 and you have to stick to them.
</quote> There are things Superman
<quote>cannot
</quote>
1650 do.
<quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1651 which are fifty years old.
</quote>
1653 <indexterm startref='idxwinickjudd' class='endofrange'
/>
1654 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>Japanese
</secondary></indexterm>
1655 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese
</primary></indexterm>
1656 <indexterm id='idxmehrasalil' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mehra, Salil
</primary></indexterm>
1658 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1659 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1660 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1661 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1662 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1663 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1664 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.
<footnote><para>
1666 See Salil K. Mehra,
<quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1667 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?
</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1668 Review
</citetitle> 55 (
2002):
155,
182.
<quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1669 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1670 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1671 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1672 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1673 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.
</quote>
1676 <indexterm startref='idxcomicsjapanese' class='endofrange'
/>
1677 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics' class='endofrange'
/>
1678 <indexterm startref='idxmanga' class='endofrange'
/>
1680 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1681 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1682 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1683 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1684 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1685 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1686 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1687 a more general pattern of blocking this
<quote>free taking
</quote> by the doujinshi
1690 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='endofrange'
/>
1691 <indexterm startref='idxmehrasalil' class='endofrange'
/>
1693 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1694 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1695 a friend from a major Japanese law firm.
<quote>We don't have enough
1696 lawyers,
</quote> he told me one afternoon. There
<quote>just aren't enough resources
1697 to prosecute cases like this.
</quote>
1700 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1701 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1702 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1703 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1704 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1705 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1706 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1707 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1708 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1709 their clients or hurt them?
1711 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics' class='endofrange'
/>
1713 <emphasis role='strong'
>Let's pause
</emphasis> for a moment.
1716 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1717 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1718 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1721 We live in a world that celebrates
<quote>property.
</quote> I am one of those
1722 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1723 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1724 <quote>intellectual property.
</quote><footnote><para>
1726 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
1727 The term
<citetitle>intellectual property
</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1728 Siva Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
11 (New York: New York
1729 University Press,
2001). See also Lawrence Lessig,
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle>
1730 (New York: Random House,
2001),
293 n.
26. The term accurately
1731 describes a set of
<quote>property
</quote> rights
—copyright, patents,
1732 trademark, and trade-secret
—but the nature of those rights is
1735 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1736 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1739 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt3' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1740 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Grimm fairy tales
</primary></indexterm>
1741 <indexterm><primary>Keaton, Buster
</primary></indexterm>
1743 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1744 plenty of value out there that
<quote>property
</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1745 mean
<quote>money can't buy you love,
</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1746 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1747 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1748 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1749 condemning that taking as wrong
— even though trivial, even if
1750 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1751 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1752 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1753 Disney's use would have been considered
<quote>fair.
</quote> There was nothing
1754 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1757 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='startofrange'
><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary>derivative works based on
</secondary></indexterm>
1759 Thus, even though the things that Disney took
—or more generally,
1760 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity
—are
1761 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1763 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1764 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1767 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='endofrange'
/>
1768 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>Japanese
</secondary></indexterm>
1769 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese
</primary></indexterm>
1770 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='startofrange'
><primary>doujinshi comics
</primary></indexterm>
1771 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Japanese comics
</primary></indexterm>
1772 <indexterm id='idxmanga2' class='startofrange'
><primary>manga
</primary></indexterm>
1774 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1775 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1776 work
—or even one copy
—without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1777 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1778 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1779 form, whether large or small.
1781 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='endofrange'
/>
1783 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1784 say that the copycat comic artists are
<quote>stealing.
</quote> This form of Walt
1785 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1786 particular find it hard to say why.
1788 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='endofrange'
/>
1789 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='endofrange'
/>
1790 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='endofrange'
/>
1791 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='endofrange'
/>
1792 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics2' class='endofrange'
/>
1793 <indexterm startref='idxmanga2' class='endofrange'
/>
1794 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
1796 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1797 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1798 without asking or paying for the privilege. (
<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1799 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1800 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?
</quote>) Acting companies
1801 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1802 permission from anyone. (Does
<emphasis>anyone
</emphasis> believe
1803 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1804 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1805 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1806 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late
1990s;
1807 two volcano disaster films in
1997.
1810 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1811 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1812 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1813 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1814 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1815 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1816 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking
—free
1817 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1818 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1820 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt3' class='endofrange'
/>
1822 The hard question is therefore not
<emphasis>whether
</emphasis> a
1823 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1824 question instead is
<quote><emphasis>How
</emphasis> free is this culture?
</quote>
1825 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1826 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1827 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1828 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1829 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1830 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1834 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1835 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1836 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1838 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='endofrange'
/>
1840 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1842 <chapter label=
"2" id=
"mere-copyists">
1843 <title>CHAPTER TWO:
<quote>Mere Copyists
</quote></title>
1844 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis
</primary></indexterm>
1845 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology' class='startofrange'
><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
1846 <indexterm id='idxphotography' class='startofrange'
><primary>photography
</primary></indexterm>
1848 <emphasis role='strong'
>In
1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1849 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1850 <quote>photographs.
</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1851 <quote>daguerreotypes.
</quote> The process was complicated and
1852 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1853 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1854 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1855 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1857 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William
</primary></indexterm>
1859 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1860 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1861 <quote>automatic pictures.
</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1862 making
<quote>negatives.
</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1863 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1864 the
1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1865 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1866 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1869 <indexterm id='idxeastmangeorge' class='startofrange'
><primary>Eastman, George
</primary></indexterm>
1871 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1872 didn't happen until
1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1873 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1874 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1875 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1876 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1877 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1878 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1879 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1880 population of photographers.
1882 <indexterm id='idxkodakcameras' class='startofrange'
><primary>Kodak cameras
</primary></indexterm>
1883 <indexterm id='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='startofrange'
><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)
</primary></indexterm>
1885 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1886 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1887 marketed on the basis of its simplicity.
<quote>You press the button and we
1888 do the rest.
</quote><footnote><para>
1890 Reese V. Jenkins,
<citetitle>Images and Enterprise
</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1975),
112.
1891 </para></footnote> As he described in
<citetitle>The Kodak Primer
</citetitle>:
1895 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1896 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1897 that only an expert can do.
… We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1898 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1899 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1900 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1901 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1902 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1903 chemicals.
<footnote>
1906 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian
</primary></indexterm>
1907 Brian Coe,
<citetitle>The Birth of Photography
</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1912 <indexterm startref='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='endofrange'
/>
1914 For $
25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1915 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1916 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1917 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1918 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1919 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in
1888; one
1920 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1921 From
1888 through
1909, while industrial production was rising by
4.7
1922 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by
11
1923 percent.
<footnote><para>
1926 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1927 an average annual increase of over
17 percent.
<footnote><para>
1929 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p.
178.
1932 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian
</primary></indexterm>
1935 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1936 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1937 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1938 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1939 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1940 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes,
<quote>For the
1941 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1942 permanent record of his family and its activities.
… For the first
1943 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1944 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1945 interpretation or bias.
</quote><footnote><para>
1950 <indexterm><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression
</secondary></indexterm>
1951 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>democratic
</secondary></indexterm>
1953 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1954 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1955 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1956 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1957 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1958 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its
<quote>quality
</quote>;
1959 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1960 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1961 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1962 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1965 <indexterm startref='idxkodakcameras' class='endofrange'
/>
1966 <indexterm id='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='startofrange'
><primary>permissions
</primary><secondary>photography exempted from
</secondary></indexterm>
1968 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1969 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1970 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1971 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1972 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1973 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1974 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1975 he wanted. Their answer was no.
<footnote><para>
1977 For illustrative cases, see, for example,
<citetitle>Pavesich
</citetitle>
1978 v.
<citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co
</citetitle>.,
50 S.E.
68 (Ga.
1905);
1979 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Chinn
</citetitle>,
123090 S.W.
364,
366
1980 (Ky.
1909);
<citetitle>Corliss
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Walker
</citetitle>,
64 F.
280 (Mass.
1984 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology' class='endofrange'
/>
1985 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt4' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1986 <indexterm id='idximagesownershipof' class='startofrange'
><primary>images, ownership of
</primary></indexterm>
1988 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1989 familiar. The photographer was
<quote>taking
</quote> something from the person or
1990 building whose photograph he shot
—pirating something of
1991 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1992 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1995 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1996 that they thought valuable.
1998 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
1999 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
2000 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology2' class='startofrange'
><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
2002 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
2003 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
2004 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
2005 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
2006 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.
<footnote>
2009 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis,
<quote>The Right to Privacy,
</quote>
2010 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review
</citetitle> 4 (
1890):
193.
2011 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
2012 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.
</primary></indexterm>
2013 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
2014 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
2015 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr
</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
2016 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
2018 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt4' class='endofrange'
/>
2020 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
2021 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
2022 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
2023 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
2024 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
2025 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
2026 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
2027 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
2028 clearing the rights to do the capturing.
<footnote><para>
2030 See Melville B. Nimmer,
<quote>The Right of Publicity,
</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
2031 Problems
</citetitle> 19 (
1954):
203; William L. Prosser,
<quote>Privacy,
</quote> <citetitle>California Law
2032 Review
</citetitle> 48 (
1960)
398–407;
<citetitle>White
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
2033 Inc
</citetitle>.,
971 F.
2d
1395 (
9th Cir.
1992), cert. denied,
508 U.S.
951
2037 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras
</primary></indexterm>
2038 <indexterm><primary>Napster
</primary></indexterm>
2040 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
2041 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
2042 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
2043 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
2044 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
2045 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
2046 Kodak would be benefiting from the
<quote>theft
</quote> committed by the
2047 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
2048 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
2049 from the
<quote>image-right
</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
2050 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
2051 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
2052 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
2054 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology2' class='endofrange'
/>
2055 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology3' class='startofrange'
><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
2056 <indexterm><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression
</secondary></indexterm>
2057 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>democratic
</secondary></indexterm>
2060 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
2061 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
2062 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
2063 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
2064 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
2065 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
2066 technology as they did
—since professionals could have more
2067 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
2068 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
2069 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
2070 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
2073 <indexterm startref='idxphotography' class='endofrange'
/>
2074 <indexterm startref='idxeastmangeorge' class='endofrange'
/>
2075 <indexterm startref='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='endofrange'
/>
2076 <indexterm startref='idximagesownershipof' class='endofrange'
/>
2078 <emphasis role='strong'
>If you drive
</emphasis> through San
2079 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
2080 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
2081 <quote>Just Think!
</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
2082 there's little that's
<quote>just
</quote> cerebral in the projects
2083 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
2084 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
2085 the film of your VCR. Rather the
<quote>film
</quote> of digital
2086 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
2087 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
2088 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
2089 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
2090 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
2091 think. By tinkering, they learn.
2094 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
2095 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
2096 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it,
<quote>Five years ago, a good
2097 real-time digital video editing system cost $
25,
000. Today you can get
2098 professional quality for $
595.
</quote><footnote><para>
2100 H. Edward Goldberg,
<quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
2101 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,
</quote>
2102 cadalyst, February
2002, available at
2103 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
7</ulink>.
2105 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
2106 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
2107 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
2108 learning more and more of something teachers call
<quote>media literacy.
</quote>
2110 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave
</primary></indexterm>
2112 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
2113 <quote>Media literacy,
</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
2114 Think!, puts it,
<quote>is the ability
… to understand, analyze, and
2115 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2116 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2117 the way people access it.
</quote>
2120 This may seem like an odd way to think about
<quote>literacy.
</quote> For most
2121 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2122 and noticing split infinitives are the things that
<quote>literate
</quote> people know
2125 <indexterm><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
2126 <indexterm><primary>commercials
</primary></indexterm>
2127 <indexterm><primary>television
</primary><secondary>advertising on
</secondary></indexterm>
2129 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average
390 hours of
2130 television commercials per year, or between
20,
000 and
45,
000
2131 commercials generally,
<footnote><para>
2133 Judith Van Evra,
<citetitle>Television and Child Development
</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2134 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates,
1990);
<quote>Findings on Family and TV
2135 Study,
</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post
</citetitle>,
25 May
1997, B6.
2137 it is increasingly important to understand the
<quote>grammar
</quote> of media. For
2138 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2139 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2140 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2141 (at least at first) terrible media.
2144 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2145 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2146 has written understands how difficult writing is
—how difficult
2147 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2148 language to be understandable
—few of us have any real sense of
2149 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2150 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2151 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2153 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology3' class='endofrange'
/>
2155 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2156 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2157 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2158 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2159 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2160 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2162 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
2163 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='startofrange'
><primary>Daley, Elizabeth
</primary></indexterm>
2165 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2166 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2167 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2169 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2170 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2171 about
<quote>the placement of objects, color,
… rhythm, pacing, and
2172 texture.
</quote><footnote>
2175 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish,
13 December
2177 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2178 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth
</primary></indexterm>
2180 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2181 <quote>played
</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2182 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2183 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2184 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2185 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2186 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2187 to a wildly successful author.
<footnote><para>
2189 See Scott Steinberg,
<quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,
</quote> E!online,
4
2190 November
2000, available at
2191 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
8</ulink>;
<quote>Timeline,
</quote> 22 November
2000,
2193 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
9</ulink>.
2196 <indexterm><primary>computer games
</primary></indexterm>
2198 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2199 describes,
<quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2200 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2201 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2202 led.
</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2205 Yet the push for an expanded literacy
—one that goes beyond text
2206 to include audio and visual elements
—is not about making better
2207 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2208 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2212 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2213 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2214 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2215 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2220 <quote>Read-only.
</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2221 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2225 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2226 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2227 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2228 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2230 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2231 and this literacy in particular, is to
<quote>empower people to choose the
2232 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2233 express.
</quote><footnote>
2236 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2237 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2238 </para></footnote> It is to enable students
<quote>to communicate in the
2239 language of the twenty-first century.
</quote><footnote><para>
2244 <indexterm id='idxbarishstephanie' class='startofrange'
><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2246 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2247 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2248 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2249 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2250 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2251 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2252 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2253 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2254 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2255 students know something about
—gun violence.
2257 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='endofrange'
/>
2259 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2260 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2261 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2262 away. The
<quote>kids were showing up at
6 A.M. and leaving at
5 at night,
</quote>
2263 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2264 what education should be about
—learning how to express themselves.
2267 Using whatever
<quote>free web stuff they could find,
</quote> and relatively simple
2268 tools to enable the kids to mix
<quote>image, sound, and text,
</quote> Barish said
2269 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2270 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2271 close to the lives of these students. The project
<quote>gave them a tool
2272 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2273 it,
</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2274 expression
—far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2275 been created using only text.
<quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2276 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2277 gone and done something else,
</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2278 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2279 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2280 <emphasis>these
</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2281 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2283 <indexterm startref='idxbarishstephanie' class='endofrange'
/>
2286 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2287 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?
</quote> I asked. In part,
2288 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2289 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of
<quote>constructing
2290 meaning.
</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2291 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2292 part
—and increasingly, not the most powerful part
—of
2293 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2298 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2299 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2300 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2301 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2302 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2303 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2304 you say,
<quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.
</quote>
2305 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2306 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2307 you. [But i]nstead, if you say,
<quote>Well, with all these things that you
2308 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2309 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2310 for me something that reflects that.
</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2311 camera and
… saying,
<quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2312 make a little movie.
</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2313 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2314 about the topic.
…
2317 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2318 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2319 bump up against the fact,
<quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2320 to write something.
</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2321 they would rewrite a paragraph
5,
6,
7,
8 times, till they got it right.
2324 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2325 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2326 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2327 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2328 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2329 had a lot of power with this language.
2331 <!-- FIXME removed a " from the end of the previous paragraph that did
2332 not match with any start quote. -->
2334 <indexterm id='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='startofrange'
><primary>September
11,
2001, terrorist attacks of
</primary></indexterm>
2335 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center
</primary></indexterm>
2336 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage' class='startofrange'
><primary>news coverage
</primary></indexterm>
2338 <emphasis role='strong'
>When two planes
</emphasis> crashed into the
2339 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2340 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2341 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2342 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2343 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2344 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2345 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2346 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2350 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2351 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2352 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was
<quote>balance,
</quote>
2353 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2354 increasingly come to expect it,
<quote>news as entertainment,
</quote> even if the
2355 entertainment is tragedy.
2357 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
2358 <indexterm><primary>CBS
</primary></indexterm>
2360 But in addition to this produced news about the
<quote>tragedy of September
2361 11,
</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2362 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2363 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2364 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2365 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2366 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2367 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2368 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2369 the term in his book
<citetitle>Cyber Rights
</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2370 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2371 was also the Internet.
2373 <indexterm startref='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='endofrange'
/>
2375 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet
—though I do think the
2376 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2377 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2378 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2380 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2381 by a student on the
<quote>Just Think!
</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2385 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2386 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2387 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2388 tradition
—not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2389 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2390 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2391 spread practically instantaneously.
2393 <indexterm><primary>September
11,
2001, terrorist attacks of
</primary></indexterm>
2394 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs' class='startofrange'
><primary>blogs (Web-logs)
</primary></indexterm>
2395 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>blogs on
</secondary></indexterm>
2396 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs' class='startofrange'
><primary>Web-logs (blogs)
</primary></indexterm>
2398 September
11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2399 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2400 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2401 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2402 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2403 cultures, it records private facts in a public way
—it's a kind
2404 of electronic
<citetitle>Jerry Springer
</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2406 <indexterm><primary>political discourse
</primary></indexterm>
2407 <indexterm id='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>public discourse conducted on
</secondary></indexterm>
2409 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2410 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2411 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2412 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2413 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2414 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2415 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2416 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2417 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2418 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2419 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2420 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2422 <indexterm id='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='startofrange'
><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression
</secondary></indexterm>
2423 <indexterm id='idxelections' class='startofrange'
><primary>elections
</primary></indexterm>
2424 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='startofrange'
><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>democratic
</secondary></indexterm>
2426 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2427 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2428 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2429 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2430 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2432 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2433 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2434 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2436 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs' class='endofrange'
/>
2437 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson' class='endofrange'
/>
2438 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs' class='endofrange'
/>
2439 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de
</primary></indexterm>
2440 <indexterm id='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='startofrange'
><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>public discourse in
</secondary></indexterm>
2441 <indexterm><primary>jury system
</primary></indexterm>
2443 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2444 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2445 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2446 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2447 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2448 most important account of early
<quote>Democracy in America.
</quote> It wasn't
2449 popular elections that fascinated him
—it was the jury, an
2450 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2451 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2452 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2453 deliberated. Members argued about the
<quote>right
</quote> result; they tried to
2454 persuade each other of the
<quote>right
</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2455 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2456 come to an end.
<footnote><para>
2458 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville,
<citetitle>Democracy in America
</citetitle>,
2459 bk.
1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books,
2000), ch.
16.
2462 <indexterm startref='idxelections' class='endofrange'
/>
2464 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2465 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2466 are pushing to create just such an institution.
<footnote><para>
2468 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin,
<quote>Deliberation Day,
</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2469 Political Philosophy
</citetitle> 10 (
2) (
2002):
129.
2471 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2472 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2473 place for
<quote>democratic deliberation
</quote> to occur.
2475 <indexterm id='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='startofrange'
><primary>political discourse
</primary></indexterm>
2477 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2478 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2479 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2480 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2481 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2482 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.
<footnote><para>
2484 Cass Sunstein,
<citetitle>Republic.com
</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2001),
2485 65–80,
175,
182,
183,
192.
2486 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2487 little beyond what our friends say.
2489 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>blogs (Web-logs)
</primary></indexterm>
2490 <indexterm><primary>e-mail
</primary></indexterm>
2491 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>blogs on
</secondary></indexterm>
2492 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Web-logs (blogs)
</primary></indexterm>
2493 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='endofrange'
/>
2494 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='endofrange'
/>
2495 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='endofrange'
/>
2497 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2498 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2499 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2500 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2501 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2503 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2504 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2508 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2509 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2510 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2511 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2512 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2513 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2515 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard
</primary></indexterm>
2517 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2518 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the
2004 presidential race
2519 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2520 is having an effect.
2522 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent
</primary></indexterm>
2523 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom
</primary></indexterm>
2525 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2526 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2527 <quote>misspoke
</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2528 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2529 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2530 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2531 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2532 more instances of the same
<quote>misspeaking
</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2533 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2534 resign as senate majority leader.
<footnote><para>
2536 Noah Shachtman,
<quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,
</quote> New
2537 York Times,
16 January
2003, G5.
2541 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2542 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2543 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2544 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2548 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2549 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2550 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2551 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2552 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2553 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2554 peer-generated rankings.
2556 <indexterm id='idxwinerdave' class='startofrange'
><primary>Winer, Dave
</primary></indexterm>
2558 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2559 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2560 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2561 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2562 difference is the absence of a financial
<quote>conflict of interest.
</quote> <quote>I think you
2563 have to take the conflict of interest
</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2564 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2565 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2566 get it out of the way.
</quote>
2568 <indexterm><primary>CNN
</primary></indexterm>
2569 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war
</primary></indexterm>
2571 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2572 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2573 from the public than an unconcentrated media can
—as CNN admitted
2574 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2575 its own employees.
<footnote><para>
2577 Telephone interview with David Winer,
16 April
2003.
2579 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2580 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2581 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2582 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2583 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2584 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2585 told her that
<emphasis>they
</emphasis> were writing
<quote>the story.
</quote>)
2587 <para> Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2588 debate
—<quote>amateur
</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced, but in the
2589 sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to give their
2590 reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a story, as
2591 reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds from across
2592 the southwest United States turned to the Internet to retell what they
2593 had seen.
<footnote><para>
2595 John Schwartz,
<quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2596 Information Online,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
2 February
2003, A28; Staci
2597 D. Kramer,
<quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,
</quote>
2598 Online Journalism Review,
2 February
2003, available at
2599 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
10</ulink>.
2601 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2602 <quote>triangulate,
</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2603 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2604 out of it
</quote>—with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2607 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2608 with blogs.
<quote>It's going to become an essential skill,
</quote> Winer predicts,
2609 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2610 not clear that
<quote>journalism
</quote> is happy about this
—some journalists
2611 have been told to curtail their blogging.
<footnote>
2614 <indexterm><primary>CNN
</primary></indexterm>
2615 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war
</primary></indexterm>
2616 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
2617 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)
</primary></indexterm>
2618 See Michael Falcone,
<quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?
</quote> <citetitle>New
2619 York Times
</citetitle>,
29 September
2003, C4. (
<quote>Not all news organizations have
2620 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2621 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2622 war on March
9, stopped posting
12 days later at his bosses'
2623 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a
<citetitle>Houston Chronicle
</citetitle> reporter, was
2624 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2625 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.
</quote>)
2627 But it is clear that we are still in transition.
<quote>A
2629 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2630 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,
</quote> Winer told me.
2631 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2632 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2633 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said,
<quote>we will
2634 be the last thing that gets shut down.
</quote>
2637 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because
<quote>you
2638 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.
</quote>
2639 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2640 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2641 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2642 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2643 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2644 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2645 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2646 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2647 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2648 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2649 extraordinary to report.
2651 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage' class='endofrange'
/>
2652 <indexterm startref='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='endofrange'
/>
2653 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs2' class='endofrange'
/>
2654 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson2' class='endofrange'
/>
2655 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs2' class='endofrange'
/>
2656 <indexterm startref='idxwinerdave' class='endofrange'
/>
2657 <indexterm startref='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='endofrange'
/>
2658 <indexterm id='idxbrownjohnseely' class='startofrange'
><primary>Brown, John Seely
</primary></indexterm>
2659 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'
><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
2661 <emphasis role='strong'
>John Seely Brown
</emphasis> is the chief
2662 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2663 describes it, is
<quote>human learning and
… the creation of
2664 knowledge ecologies for creating
… innovation.
</quote>
2667 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2668 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2669 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2670 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2674 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When
<quote>a lot of us grew up,
</quote>
2675 he explains, that tinkering was done
<quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2676 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.
</quote> But digital technologies
2677 enable a different kind of tinkering
—with abstract ideas though
2678 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2679 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2680 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2681 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2682 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2683 or
<quote>free collage,
</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2684 the tinkering of many others.
2687 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2688 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2689 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2690 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2691 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2694 This opportunity creates a
<quote>completely new kind of learning platform,
</quote>
2695 as Brown describes.
<quote>As soon as you start doing that, you
…
2696 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2697 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2698 if they can improve it.
</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2699 apprenticeship.
<quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.
</quote>
2702 In this process,
<quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2703 They are code.
</quote> Kids are
<quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2704 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2705 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2706 platform.
… You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2707 you tinker the more you improve.
</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2711 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2712 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2713 it,
<quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2714 intelligence.
</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2715 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2716 text.
<quote>The Web
… says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2717 you are visual, if you are interested in film
… [then] there is a
2718 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2719 these multiple forms of intelligence.
</quote>
2721 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'
/>
2722 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2724 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2725 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2727 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2728 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2729 kind of recognition.
2732 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2733 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2734 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2735 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2736 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2737 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2738 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2741 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2742 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2743 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>)
2744 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the
<quote>right to
2745 tinker
</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2746 general.
<footnote><para>
2748 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel,
<quote>Technological Access
2749 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,
</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2750 of the Association for Computer Machinery
</citetitle> 43 (
2000):
9.
2752 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2753 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2756 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,
</quote> Brown
2757 explains. We need to
<quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2758 and want to learn.
</quote>
2761 <quote>Yet,
</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2762 evince,
<quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2763 natural tendencies of today's digital kids.
… We're building an
2764 architecture that unleashes
60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2765 system that closes down that part of the brain.
</quote>
2767 <indexterm startref=
"idxbrownjohnseely" class='endofrange'
/>
2769 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2770 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2771 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2772 the law to close down that technology.
2775 <quote>No way to run a culture,
</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2776 chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"collectors"/>,
2777 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2779 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2781 <chapter label=
"3" id=
"catalogs">
2782 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
</title>
2783 <indexterm><primary>RPI
</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)
</see></indexterm>
2784 <indexterm id='idxrensselaer' class='startofrange'
><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)
</primary></indexterm>
2786 <emphasis role='strong'
>In the fall
</emphasis> of
2002, Jesse Jordan
2787 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2788 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2789 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2790 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2791 was available on the RPI network.
2794 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2795 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2796 to information sciences. More than
65 percent of its five thousand
2797 undergraduates finished in the top
10 percent of their high school
2798 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2799 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2802 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2803 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2804 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2805 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2806 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2809 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2810 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2811 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2812 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2813 engines can do this even better. The idea of
<quote>intranet
</quote> search
2814 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2815 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2816 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2817 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2818 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2821 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2822 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2823 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2824 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2825 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2826 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2827 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2830 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2831 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2832 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2833 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2834 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2835 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2836 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2837 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2838 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2842 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2843 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2844 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2845 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2846 be on users' computers.
2849 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2850 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2851 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2852 might have created; university brochures
—basically anything that
2853 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2854 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2858 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2859 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2860 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and
—so that this
2861 point is absolutely clear
—Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2862 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2863 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2864 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2865 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2866 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2867 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2868 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2869 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2873 On April
3,
2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2874 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2875 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2876 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2877 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2878 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2879 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2882 <quote>It was absurd,
</quote> he told me.
<quote>I don't think I did anything
2883 wrong.
… I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2884 engine that I ran or
… what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2885 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2886 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2887 easier to use
</quote>—again, a
<emphasis>search engine
</emphasis>,
2888 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2889 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2890 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2891 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2894 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages
</primary></indexterm>
2896 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2897 network and had therefore
<quote>willfully
</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2898 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2899 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2900 <quote>willful infringement,
</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2901 call
<quote>statutory damages.
</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2902 claim $
150,
000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2903 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2904 Jesse pay them at least $
15,
000,
000.
2906 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University
</primary></indexterm>
2907 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University
</primary></indexterm>
2909 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2910 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2911 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2912 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2913 huge demands for
<quote>damages
</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2914 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2915 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $
100
2916 <emphasis>billion
</emphasis>—six times the
2917 <emphasis>total
</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2918 2001.
<footnote><para>
2921 Tim Goral,
<quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-
2-P Networks:
2922 Suit Alleges $
97.8 Billion in Damages,
</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC
</citetitle> 6
2923 (
2003):
5, available at
2003 WL
55179443.
2926 <indexterm startref=
"idxrensselaer" class='endofrange'
/>
2928 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2929 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2930 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2931 $
12,
000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2932 $
12,
000 to dismiss the case.
2934 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt
</primary></indexterm>
2936 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2937 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2938 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2939 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2940 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2941 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2942 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse,
<quote>You don't want to pay another
2943 visit to a dentist like me.
</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2944 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2947 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2948 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2949 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2950 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2951 at least $
250,
000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2952 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2953 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2954 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2957 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $
250,
000 and a chance at winning,
2958 or $
12,
000 and a settlement.
2960 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
2962 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2963 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2964 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2965 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2966 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $
1 million a year.
2967 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2968 artist makes $
45,
900.
<footnote><para>
2970 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (
2001)
2971 (
27–2042—Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2972 the Arts,
<citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon
</citetitle> (
2000).
2974 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2975 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2976 student for running a search engine?
<footnote><para>
2978 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in
<quote>KaZaA and Punishment,
</quote>
2979 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, A24.
2983 On June
23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2984 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2985 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $
15 million lawsuit became an
2990 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2991 an activist.
… [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2992 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2993 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2997 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2998 his father told me, Jesse
<quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
2999 I.
… He's not a tree hugger.
… I think it's bizarre that they would
3000 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
3001 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.
</quote>
3003 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
3005 <chapter label=
"4" id=
"pirates">
3006 <title>CHAPTER FOUR:
<quote>Pirates
</quote></title>
3007 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right
</quote> theory
</primary></indexterm>
3009 <emphasis role='strong'
>If
<quote>piracy
</quote> means
</emphasis>
3010 using the creative property of others without their
3011 permission
—if
<quote>if value, then right
</quote> is
3012 true
—then the history of the content industry is a history of
3013 piracy. Every important sector of
<quote>big media
</quote>
3014 today
—film, records, radio, and cable TV
—was born of a
3015 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
3016 generation's pirates join this generation's country club
—until
3022 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.
<footnote><para>
3024 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
3025 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
3026 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
87–93,
3027 which details Edison's
<quote>adventures
</quote> with copyright and patent.
3029 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
3030 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
3031 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
3032 exercised through a monopoly
<quote>trust,
</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
3033 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
3034 property
—patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
3035 this creative property
3036 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
3037 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
3040 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
3044 A January
1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
3045 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
3046 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
3047 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
3048 summer of
1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
3049 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
3050 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
3052 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William
</primary></indexterm>
3053 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company
</primary></indexterm>
3054 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
3056 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
3057 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
3058 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
3059 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
3060 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
3061 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
3062 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
3063 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
3064 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
3065 license was revoked.
<footnote><para>
3067 J. A. Aberdeen,
<citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
3068 Picture Producers
</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment,
2000) and expanded texts
3069 posted at
<quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
3070 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,
</quote> available at
3071 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
11</ulink>. For a
3072 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
3073 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker,
<quote>From
3074 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
3075 the Propertization of Copyright
</quote> (September
2002), University of
3076 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
3077 Working Paper No.
159.
3078 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
3083 The Napsters of those days, the
<quote>independents,
</quote> were companies like
3084 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
3085 resisted.
<quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
3086 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
3087 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.
</quote><footnote><para>
3089 Marc Wanamaker,
<quote>The First Studios,
</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority
</citetitle>, archived at
3090 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
12</ulink>.
3092 That led the independents to flee the East
3093 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
3094 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
3095 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
3099 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
3100 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
3101 patent holder a truly
<quote>limited
</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
3103 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
3104 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
3105 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
3106 Edison's creative property.
3109 <section id=
"recordedmusic">
3110 <title>Recorded Music
</title>
3111 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on music recordings
</secondary></indexterm>
3113 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
3114 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
3116 <indexterm id=
"idxfourneauxhenri" class='startofrange'
><primary>Fourneaux, Henri
</primary></indexterm>
3117 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil
</primary></indexterm>
3119 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
3120 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
3121 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
3122 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
3123 their music. In other words, in
1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
3124 1899 hit
<quote>Happy Mose,
</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
3125 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
3126 right to perform it publicly.
3128 <indexterm><primary>Beatles
</primary></indexterm>
3130 But what if I wanted to record
<quote>Happy Mose,
</quote> using Edison's phonograph
3131 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
3132 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
3133 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
3134 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
3135 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
3136 <quote>public performance
</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
3137 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
3138 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
3139 brain are not
—yet
— regulated by copyright law). So if I
3140 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
3141 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
3142 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
3143 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
3144 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
3145 its composer anything.
3147 <indexterm startref=
"idxfourneauxhenri" class='endofrange'
/>
3149 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
3150 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
3151 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
3153 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred
</primary></indexterm>
3157 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3158 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3159 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3160 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3161 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3162 rights.
<footnote><para>
3164 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3165 S.
6330 and H.R.
19853 Before the ( Joint) Committees on Patents,
59th
3166 Cong.
59,
1st sess. (
1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3167 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in
<citetitle>Legislative History of the
3168 Copyright Act
</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3169 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints,
1976).
3170 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred
</primary></indexterm>
3174 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip
</primary></indexterm>
3176 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3177 people's works were
<quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3178 genius of American composers,
</quote><footnote><para>
3180 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
223
3181 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3183 and the
<quote>music publishing industry
</quote>
3184 was thereby
<quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.
</quote><footnote><para>
3186 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
226
3187 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3190 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible,
<quote>When they make money
3191 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.
</quote><footnote><para>
3193 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
23
3194 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3197 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company
</primary></indexterm>
3198 <indexterm><primary>player pianos
</primary></indexterm>
3199 <indexterm><primary>sheet music
</primary></indexterm>
3201 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3202 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3203 player piano argued that
<quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3204 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3205 of anything he had before their introduction.
</quote> Rather, the machines
3206 increased the sales of sheet music.
<footnote><para>
3209 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
283–84
3210 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3211 Perforating Company of New York).
3212 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3213 Congress was
<quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3214 they represent, and whose servants they are.
</quote> <quote>All talk about
3215 `theft,'
</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3216 wrote,
<quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3217 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3218 statute.
</quote><footnote><para>
3220 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
376 (prepared
3221 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3222 Graphophone Company Association).
3226 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3227 <emphasis>and
</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3228 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the
<quote>mechanical
3229 reproductions
</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3230 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3231 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3232 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3233 recorded once. This is the part of
3235 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3236 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3237 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3238 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3241 American law ordinarily calls this a
<quote>compulsory license,
</quote> but I will
3242 refer to it as a
<quote>statutory license.
</quote> A statutory license is a license
3243 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3244 Copyright Act in
1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3245 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3246 the fee set by the statute.
3248 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John
</primary></indexterm>
3250 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3251 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3252 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3253 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3254 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3255 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3258 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='endofrange'
/>
3260 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3261 thus, in effect, the law
<emphasis>subsidizes
</emphasis> the recording
3262 industry through a kind of piracy
—by giving recording artists a
3263 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3264 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3265 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3266 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3267 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3268 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3269 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3270 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3271 creativity.
<footnote><para>
3274 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S.
2499, S.
2900, H.R.
243, and
3275 H.R.
11794 Before the ( Joint) Committee on Patents,
60th Cong.,
1st
3276 sess.,
217 (
1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3277 in
<citetitle>Legislative History of the
1909 Copyright Act
</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3278 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints,
1976).
3280 <indexterm><primary>Beatles
</primary></indexterm>
3283 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3284 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3285 records. As a
1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3290 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3291 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3292 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3293 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3294 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3295 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3296 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3297 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3298 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before
1909 and
3299 the
1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3300 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3301 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3302 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3303 choice.
<footnote><para>
3305 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R.
2512, House Committee
3306 on the Judiciary,
90th Cong.,
1st sess., House Document no.
83, (
8
3307 March
1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3308 this report.
</para></footnote>
3312 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3313 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3316 <section id=
"radio">
3317 <title>Radio
</title>
3318 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments1' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
3320 Radio was also born of piracy.
3323 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3324 <quote>public performance
</quote> of the composer's work.
<footnote><para>
3326 See
17 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, sections
106 and
110. At the beginning,
3327 record companies printed
<quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast
</quote> and other
3328 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3329 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3330 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3331 station. See
<citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Whiteman
</citetitle>,
114 F.
2d
86 (
2nd
3332 Cir.
1940). See also Randal C. Picker,
<quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3333 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3334 Copyright,
</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review
</citetitle> 70 (
2003):
281.
3335 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned
</primary></indexterm>
3336 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
3338 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3339 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3340 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3343 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3344 copy of the
<emphasis>composer's
</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3345 also performing a copy of the
<emphasis>recording artist's
</emphasis>
3346 work. It's one thing to have
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote> sung on the radio by the
3347 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3348 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3349 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3350 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3351 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3353 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
3355 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3358 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3359 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3360 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3361 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3362 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3363 of playing the song.
3365 <indexterm id=
"idxmadonna" class='startofrange'
><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
3367 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3368 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3369 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3370 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3373 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3374 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3375 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3376 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3377 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3378 <quote>protected
</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3379 <emphasis>pirate
</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3382 <indexterm startref=
"idxmadonna" class='endofrange'
/>
3384 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3385 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3386 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3387 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3388 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3389 to take something for nothing.
3391 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments1' class='endofrange'
/>
3393 <section id=
"cabletv">
3394 <title>Cable TV
</title>
3395 <indexterm id='idxcabletv1' class='startofrange'
><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
3397 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3400 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3401 television in
1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3402 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3403 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3404 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3405 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3406 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3407 did
— Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3410 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas
</primary></indexterm>
3411 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin
</primary></indexterm>
3412 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.
</primary></indexterm>
3414 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3415 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3416 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.
</quote><footnote><para>
3418 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV: Hearing on S.
1006 Before the
3419 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3420 Committee on the Judiciary,
89th Cong.,
2nd sess.,
78 (
1966)
3421 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3423 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.
</primary></indexterm>
3425 There may have been a
<quote>public interest
</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3426 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3427 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony,
<quote>Does public
3428 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?
</quote><footnote><para>
3430 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3431 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3433 As another broadcaster put it,
3437 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3438 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3439 paid for.
<footnote><para>
3441 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3442 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3447 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3451 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3452 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3453 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3454 think there are harsher words which would fit it.
<footnote><para>
3456 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3457 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3458 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3462 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton
</primary></indexterm>
3464 These were
<quote>free-ride[rs],
</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3465 Heston said, who were
<quote>depriving actors of
3466 compensation.
</quote><footnote><para>
3468 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3469 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3470 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton
</primary></indexterm>
3475 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3476 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3480 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3481 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3482 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3483 should be permitted to extend that monopoly.
… The
3485 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3486 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3487 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.
<footnote><para>
3489 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
216 (statement of Edwin M.
3490 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3491 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin
</primary></indexterm>
3493 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin
</primary></indexterm>
3497 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3498 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3501 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3502 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they
<quote>pirated.
</quote>
3503 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3504 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3505 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3506 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3507 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3508 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3509 companies thus built their empire in part upon a
<quote>piracy
</quote> of the value
3510 created by broadcasters' content.
3512 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv1' class='endofrange'
/>
3514 <emphasis role='strong'
>These separate stories
</emphasis> sing a
3515 common theme. If
<quote>piracy
</quote> means using value from someone
3516 else's creative property without permission from that creator
—as
3517 it is increasingly described today
<footnote><para>
3519 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association,
<citetitle>The Engine
3520 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet
—The Myth of Free
3521 Information
</citetitle>, available at
3522 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
13</ulink>.
<quote>The
3523 threat of piracy
—the use of someone else's creative work without
3524 permission or compensation
—has grown with the Internet.
</quote>
3526 — then
<emphasis>every
</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3527 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3528 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV.
… The list is long and
3529 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3530 last. Every generation
—until now.
3532 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3535 <chapter label=
"5" id=
"piracy">
3536 <title>CHAPTER FIVE:
<quote>Piracy
</quote></title>
3538 <emphasis role='strong'
>There is piracy
</emphasis> of copyrighted
3539 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3540 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3541 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3542 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3543 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3546 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of
<quote>taking
</quote>
3547 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3548 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3549 taking
<quote>piracy,
</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3550 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3551 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3552 has so often done in the past.
3553 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3555 <section id=
"piracy-i">
3556 <title>Piracy I
</title>
3557 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
3558 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of
</secondary></indexterm>
3560 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3561 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3562 content, copy it, and sell it
—all without the permission of a copyright
3563 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $
4.6 billion
3564 every year to physical piracy
<footnote><para>
3566 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry),
<citetitle>The
3567 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report
2003</citetitle>, July
2003, available
3568 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
14</ulink>. See
3569 also Ben Hunt,
<quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,
</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3570 Times
</citetitle>,
14 February
2003,
11.
3572 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3573 estimates that it loses $
3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3576 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3577 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3578 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3579 This piracy is wrong.
3582 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3583 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3584 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3585 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3586 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3587 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3588 of our existence, treated as right.
3591 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3592 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3593 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3594 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3595 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3596 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3597 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3598 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3599 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3602 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3603 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3604 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3605 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3606 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3610 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3611 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3612 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3613 of intellectual property law.
<footnote><para>
3615 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3616 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?
</citetitle> (New York: The
3617 New Press,
2003),
10–13,
209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3618 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3619 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3620 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3621 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3622 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3623 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3624 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3625 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3626 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3627 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3628 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3630 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents
</primary></indexterm>
3631 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
3632 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3633 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3634 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3637 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
3639 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3640 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3641 to American CDs at
50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3642 bought those American CDs at $
15 a copy. So no one really has any
3643 less money than they otherwise would have had.
<footnote><para>
3645 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3646 Liebowitz,
<citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy
</citetitle> (New York: Amacom,
2002),
3647 144–90.
<quote>In some instances
… the impact of piracy on the
3648 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3649 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3650 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3651 pirating were not an option.
</quote> Ibid.,
149.
3652 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
3656 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3657 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3658 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3659 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3660 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes
& Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3661 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?
</quote>
3662 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes
&
3663 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3664 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3665 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3666 piracy of the tangible.
3668 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'
/>
3670 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3671 property right of a very special sort, it
<emphasis>is
</emphasis> a
3672 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3673 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3674 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3675 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3676 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3677 give people the right to
<quote>take
</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3678 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3680 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3681 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3682 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3683 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3684 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3685 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what
<quote>property
</quote> means.
3687 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
3688 <indexterm><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>in Asia
</secondary></indexterm>
3689 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)
</primary></indexterm>
3690 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3691 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3692 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of
</secondary></indexterm>
3693 <indexterm><primary>Windows
</primary></indexterm>
3694 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>international software piracy of
</secondary></indexterm>
3695 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of
</secondary></indexterm>
3697 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3698 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese
<quote>steal
</quote>
3699 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3700 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3701 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3702 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3703 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3704 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3705 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3706 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3707 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3709 <indexterm><primary>law
</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in
</secondary></indexterm>
3711 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3712 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3713 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3714 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3715 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3716 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3718 <indexterm><primary>Netscape
</primary></indexterm>
3719 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer
</primary></indexterm>
3720 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3721 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3723 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3724 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3725 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3726 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3727 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3728 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3729 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3730 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3731 what
—at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3732 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3733 violating the law is still wrong.
3736 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3737 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3738 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3739 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3740 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3741 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3742 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3743 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3747 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3748 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all
<quote>piracy
</quote> is. Or
3749 at least, not all
<quote>piracy
</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3750 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of
<quote>piracy
</quote> are useful
3751 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3752 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3753 <quote>piracy
</quote> in that sense of the term.
3756 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3757 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3758 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3759 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3762 For (
1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3763 controlling industry; and (
2) like the original recording industry, it
3764 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (
3) unlike cable
3765 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3768 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3769 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3773 <section id=
"piracy-ii">
3774 <title>Piracy II
</title>
3776 The key to the
<quote>piracy
</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that
<quote>rob[s]
3777 the author of [his] profit.
</quote><footnote><para>
3779 <citetitle>Bach
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Longman
</citetitle>,
98 Eng. Rep.
1274 (
1777).
3781 This means we must determine whether
3782 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3783 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3784 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3785 author of his profit.
3787 <indexterm><primary>innovation
</primary></indexterm>
3788 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn
</primary></indexterm>
3790 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3791 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3792 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3793 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well
<footnote><para>
3795 <indexterm><primary>innovation
</primary></indexterm>
3796 See Clayton M. Christensen,
<citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3797 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business
</citetitle> (New York:
3798 HarperBusiness,
2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3799 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3800 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3801 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3802 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3803 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig,
<citetitle>Future
</citetitle>,
89–92,
139.
3805 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.
</primary></indexterm>
3806 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3807 put together components that had been developed independently.
3810 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July
1999,
3811 Napster amassed over
10 million users within nine months. After
3812 eighteen months, there were close to
80 million registered users of the
3813 system.
<footnote><para>
3815 See Carolyn Lochhead,
<quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,
</quote> <citetitle>San
3816 Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
24 September
2002, A1;
<quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,
</quote>
3817 <citetitle>New Scientist
</citetitle>,
6 July
2002,
42; Benny Evangelista,
<quote>Napster Names CEO,
3818 Secures New Financing,
</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
23 May
2003, C1;
3819 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,
</quote> <citetitle>Economist
</citetitle>,
24 June
2000,
23; John Naughton,
3820 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet
</quote> (London)
<citetitle>Times
</citetitle>,
26 July
2002,
18.
3822 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3823 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3824 boasts over
100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3825 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3826 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3827 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend
—
3828 or your
20,
000 best friends.
3831 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3832 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3833 September
2002 estimated that
60 million Americans had downloaded
3834 music
—28 percent of Americans older than
12.
<footnote><para>
3837 See Ipsos-Insight,
<citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution
</citetitle>
3838 (September
2002), reporting that
28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3839 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and
30 percent have
3840 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3842 A survey by the NPD group quoted in
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>
3843 estimated that
43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3844 exchange content in May
2003.
<footnote><para>
3846 Amy Harmon,
<quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,
</quote> <citetitle>New
3847 York Times
</citetitle>,
6 June
2003, A1.
3849 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3850 massive quantity of content is being
<quote>taken
</quote> on these networks. The
3851 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3852 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3855 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3856 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3857 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3858 complicated than one might think. So consider
—a bit more
3859 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3860 do
—the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3864 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3865 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3866 different kinds into four types.
3868 <orderedlist numeration=
"upperalpha">
3870 <indexterm><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
3873 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3874 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3875 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3876 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3877 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3878 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3879 users who download instead of purchasing.
3883 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3884 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3885 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3886 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3887 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3888 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3889 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3894 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3895 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3896 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3897 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3898 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3899 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3900 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend
<quote>recalling
</quote> old
3901 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3902 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3903 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3904 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero
—the same
3905 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of
1960s
45-rpm records to
3909 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3911 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3912 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3917 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3920 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3921 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3922 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3923 harmful.
<footnote><para>
3925 See Liebowitz,
<citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy
</citetitle>,
148–49.
3926 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
3928 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3929 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3930 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3931 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3932 answer
—and certainly much more difficult than the current
3933 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3936 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3937 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3938 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3939 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3940 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of
<quote>theft
</quote> that is
3941 <quote>devastating
</quote> the industry.
3943 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'
><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
3945 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3946 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3947 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3948 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3949 & Young put it,
<quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3950 technology, the labels fought it.
</quote><footnote><para>
3952 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary></indexterm>
3953 See Cap Gemini Ernst
& Young,
<citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
3954 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis
</citetitle> (
2003),
3. This report
3955 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3956 practice of cassette taping in the
1970s, including an advertising
3957 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption
<quote>Home taping
3958 is killing music.
</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3959 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3960 behavior. In
1988,
40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3961 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3962 Assessment,
<citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law
</citetitle>,
3963 OTA-CIT-
422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3964 October
1989),
145–56.
</para></footnote>
3965 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3966 when record sales fell by
11.4 percent in
1981, the industry claimed
3967 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3968 regulating technology was the answer.
3970 <indexterm><primary>MTV
</primary></indexterm>
3972 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3973 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3974 turnaround.
<quote>In the end,
</quote> Cap Gemini concludes,
<quote>the `crisis'
… was
3975 not the fault of the tapers
—who did not [stop after MTV came into
3976 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
3977 being]
—but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
3978 innovation at the major labels.
</quote><footnote><para>
3980 U.S. Congress,
<citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying
</citetitle>,
4.
3983 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'
/>
3985 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
3986 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
3987 the industry in particular, and society in general
—or at least
3988 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
3989 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
3990 VCR
—the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
3991 harmful. The question is also
<emphasis>how
</emphasis> harmful type A
3992 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
3995 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
3996 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
3997 The
<quote>net harm
</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
3998 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
3999 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
4000 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
4001 therefore have little
<emphasis>static
</emphasis> reason to resist
4005 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>sales levels of
</secondary></indexterm>
4007 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
4008 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
4009 actually suggest it might be close.
4012 In
2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by
8.9 percent,
4013 from
882 million to
803 million units; revenues fell
6.7
4014 percent.
<footnote><para>
4016 See Recording Industry Association of America,
<citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics
</citetitle>,
4018 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
15</ulink>. A later
4019 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
4020 Association of America,
<citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy
</citetitle>,
25 June
2003,
4021 available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
4022 #
16</ulink>:
<quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
4023 have fallen by
26 percent from
1.16 billion units in to
860 million
4024 units in
2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
4025 of sales, revenues are down
14 percent, from $
14.6 billion in to $
12.6
4026 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
4027 industry worldwide has gone from a $
39 billion industry in
2000 down
4028 to a $
32 billion industry in
2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
4031 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
4032 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
4033 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
4034 than
20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since
1999. That no
4035 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
4036 account for at least some of the loss.
<quote>From
1999 to
2001, the average
4037 price of a CD rose
7.2 percent, from $
13.04 to $
14.19.
</quote><footnote>
4040 Jane Black,
<quote>Big Music's Broken Record,
</quote> BusinessWeek online,
13
4041 February
2003, available at
4042 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
17</ulink>.
4043 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane
</primary></indexterm>
4046 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
4047 the decline. As Jane Black of
<citetitle>BusinessWeek
</citetitle> notes,
<quote>The
4048 soundtrack to the film
<citetitle>High Fidelity
</citetitle> has a list price of
4049 $
18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
4050 $
19.99.
</quote><footnote><para>
4057 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
4058 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
4059 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
4060 that the RIAA estimates that
803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
4061 estimates that
2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
4062 although
2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4063 free, sales revenue fell by just
6.7 percent.
4066 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
4067 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
4068 The recording industry constantly asks,
<quote>What's the difference between
4069 downloading a song and stealing a CD?
</quote>—but their own numbers
4070 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
4071 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
4072 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
4073 downloads. If every download were a lost sale
—if every use of
4074 Kazaa
<quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit
</quote>—then the industry
4075 would have suffered a
100 percent drop in sales last year, not a
7
4076 percent drop. If
2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4077 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just
6.7 percent, then there is
4078 a huge difference between
<quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.
</quote>
4080 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'
/>
4082 These are the harms
—alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
4083 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
4084 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
4088 One benefit is type C sharing
—making available content that
4089 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
4090 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
4091 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
4092 available.
<footnote><para>
4094 By one estimate,
75 percent of the music released by the major labels
4095 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
4096 Law
—Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
4097 Senate Committee on the Judiciary,
107th Cong.,
1st sess. (
3 April
4098 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
4099 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
18</ulink>.
4101 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
4102 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
4103 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
4104 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
4105 sense
<emphasis>to the company
</emphasis> to make it available.
4107 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
4109 In real space
—long before the Internet
—the market had a simple
4110 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
4111 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
4112 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
4113 today.
<footnote><para>
4115 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
4116 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
4117 in existence, in
2002, there were
7,
198 used book dealers in the
4118 United States, an increase of
20 percent since
1993. See Book Hunter
4119 Press,
<citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
4120 Market
</citetitle> (
2002), available at
4121 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
19</ulink>. Used
4122 records accounted for $
260 million in sales in
2002. See National
4123 Association of Recording Merchandisers,
<quote>2002 Annual Survey
4124 Results,
</quote> available at
4125 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
20</ulink>.
4127 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
4128 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
4129 content,
<emphasis>even if the content is still under
4130 copyright
</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
4131 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
4132 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
4133 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
4134 the content they sell.
4136 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard
</primary></indexterm>
4137 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
4139 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
4140 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
4141 the content available isn't making money from making the content
4142 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
4143 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
4144 when someone shares my
1949 recording of Bernstein's
<quote>Two Love Songs,
</quote>
4145 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
4146 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
4147 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
4148 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
4149 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
4152 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
4153 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
4154 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
4155 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
4156 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
4159 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of
</secondary></indexterm>
4161 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4162 type D sharing to occur
—the sharing of content that copyright owners
4163 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4164 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4165 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel,
<citetitle>Down and Out in
4166 the Magic Kingdom
</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4168 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4169 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4170 would be a great advertisement for the
<quote>real
</quote> book. People would read
4171 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4172 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4173 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4174 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4177 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'
/>
4179 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4180 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4181 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4182 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4185 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4186 understandably says,
<quote>This is how much we've lost,
</quote> we must also ask,
4187 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4188 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4189 unavailable?
</quote>
4192 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4193 chapter, much of the
<quote>piracy
</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4194 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4195 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"pirates"/>, much of
4196 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4197 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4198 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4199 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4200 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4201 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4202 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4203 found only with time.
4206 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4207 just what you call type A sharing?
</quote>
4210 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The
4212 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4213 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4215 case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4217 a technology to block the transfer of
99.4 percent of identified
4218 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4219 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster
99.4
4220 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4221 <quote>down to zero.
</quote><footnote><para>
4223 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at
34-
4224 35 (N.D. Cal.,
11 July
2001), nos. MDL-
00-
1369 MHP, C
99-
5183
4227 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
21</ulink>. For an
4228 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4229 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster
</citetitle> (New
4230 York: Crown Business,
2003),
269–82.
4234 If
99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4235 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4236 assure that a p2p system is used
100 percent of the time in compliance
4237 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that
100 percent of
4238 VCRs or
100 percent of Xerox machines or
100 percent of handguns
4239 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4240 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4241 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4242 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4245 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4246 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4247 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4248 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4249 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4250 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4251 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4253 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
4254 <indexterm><primary>composers, copyright protections of
</primary></indexterm>
4255 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
4256 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
4257 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on music recordings
</secondary></indexterm>
4258 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in
</secondary></indexterm>
4259 <indexterm><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>music recordings played on
</secondary></indexterm>
4260 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in
</secondary></indexterm>
4261 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>copyright protections in
</secondary></indexterm>
4262 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and
</secondary></indexterm>
4263 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses
</primary></indexterm>
4264 <indexterm><primary>composer's rights vs. producers' rights in
</primary></indexterm>
4266 So, as we've seen, when
<quote>mechanical reproduction
</quote> threatened the
4267 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4268 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4269 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4270 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4271 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4272 complained to Congress that their
<quote>creative property
</quote> was not being
4273 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4274 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4277 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'
><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
4279 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4280 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4281 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4282 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4283 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4286 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='endofrange'
/>
4289 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4290 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4291 pianos, served two important goals
—indeed, the two central goals
4292 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4293 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4294 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4295 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4296 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4297 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4298 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4299 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4300 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4301 Congress chose a path that would assure
4302 <emphasis>compensation
</emphasis> without giving the past
4303 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4305 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='endofrange'
/>
4306 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='endofrange'
/>
4307 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'
/>
4308 <indexterm><primary>Betamax
</primary></indexterm>
4309 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'
><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
4311 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4312 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4313 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4314 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4315 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4316 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4317 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4318 <quote>record
</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4319 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4320 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4321 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4323 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='endofrange'
/>
4325 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4326 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4327 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4328 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4329 machine to copy only if there were a special
<quote>copy me
</quote> signal on the
4330 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4331 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4332 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4333 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4334 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4335 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4336 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4337 for the architecture it chose.
4340 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4341 champion. Valenti called VCRs
<quote>tapeworms.
</quote> He warned,
<quote>When there are
4342 20,
30,
40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4343 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4344 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4345 copyright.
</quote><footnote><para>
4347 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4348 S.
1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary,
97th Cong.,
1st
4349 and
2nd sess.,
459 (
1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4350 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4352 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4353 creative judgment,
</quote> he told Congress,
<quote>to understand the devastation
4354 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4355 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4356 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4357 and plain common sense.
</quote><footnote><para>
4359 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders),
475.
4361 Indeed, as surveys would later show,
45
4362 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more
<footnote><para>
4364 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle>,
480 F. Supp.
429,
4367 — a use the Court would later hold was not
<quote>fair.
</quote> By
4368 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4369 copyright infringement without creating a mechanism to compensate
4370 copyright owners,
</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would
<quote>take from the
4371 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4372 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4373 profit from its reproduction.
</quote><footnote><para>
4375 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders),
485 (testimony
4380 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4381 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4382 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction
—leading Judge Alex
4383 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the
<quote>Hollywood
4384 Circuit
</quote>—held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4385 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4386 rule, this totally familiar technology
—which Jack Valenti had
4387 called
<quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry
</quote> (worse
4388 yet, it was a
<emphasis>Japanese
</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4389 American film industry)
—was an illegal
4390 technology.
<footnote><para>
4392 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle>,
659 F.
2d
963 (
9th Cir.
4395 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
4398 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4400 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4401 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4402 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4407 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4408 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4410 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4412 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4413 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4415 by such new technology.
<footnote><para>
4417 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>.,
464 U.S.
417,
431 (
1984).
4422 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4423 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4424 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4425 enough, this
<quote>taking
</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4426 together, a pattern is clear:
4429 <informaltable id=
"t1">
4430 <tgroup cols=
"4" align=
"left">
4434 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS
<quote>PIRATED
</quote></entry>
4435 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS
</entry>
4436 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS
</entry>
4441 <entry>Recordings
</entry>
4442 <entry>Composers
</entry>
4443 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4444 <entry>Statutory license
</entry>
4447 <entry>Radio
</entry>
4448 <entry>Recording artists
</entry>
4450 <entry>Nothing
</entry>
4453 <entry>Cable TV
</entry>
4454 <entry>Broadcasters
</entry>
4455 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4456 <entry>Statutory license
</entry>
4460 <entry>Film creators
</entry>
4461 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4462 <entry>Nothing
</entry>
4467 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'
/>
4469 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4470 way content was distributed.
<footnote><para>
4472 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4473 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4474 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4475 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4476 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4477 1992 (Title
17 of the
<citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>), Pub. L. No.
102-
563,
106 Stat.
4478 4237, codified at
17 U.S.C. §
1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4479 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4480 Lessig,
<citetitle>Future
</citetitle>,
71. See also Picker,
<quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,
</quote>
4481 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review
</citetitle> 70 (
2003):
293–96.
4482 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
4483 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
4485 In each case, throughout our history,
4486 that change meant that someone got a
<quote>free ride
</quote> on someone else's
4490 In
<emphasis>none
</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4491 Congress eliminate all free riding. In
<emphasis>none
</emphasis> of
4492 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4493 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4494 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of
<quote>piracy.
</quote>
4495 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4496 the behavior of the
<quote>pirates.
</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4497 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4499 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4501 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
4503 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4504 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4505 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4506 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4507 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4509 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4510 to $
15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4511 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4512 permission to record a song?
4515 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4516 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4517 copyright
<quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4518 over all possible uses of his work.
</quote><footnote><para>
4520 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>.,
464 U.S.
417,
4523 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4524 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4525 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4526 balancing has historically been done
<emphasis>after
</emphasis> a
4527 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4528 facilitate the distribution of content.
4531 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4532 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4533 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4534 should not become a tool for
<quote>stealing
</quote> from artists. But neither
4535 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4536 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4537 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4538 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4539 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4540 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4541 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4542 public interest that innovation continue.
4546 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4547 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4548 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4549 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4550 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4551 efficient. Yet these
<quote>potential public benefits,
</quote> as John Schwartz
4552 writes in
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>,
<quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4553 fight.
</quote><footnote><para>
4555 John Schwartz,
<quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4556 Echoes Past Efforts,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
22 September
2003, C3.
4560 <emphasis role='strong'
>Yet when anyone
</emphasis> begins to talk
4561 about
<quote>balance,
</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4562 argument.
<quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4563 incentives,
</quote> they say,
<quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4564 content,
</quote> the warriors insist,
<quote>is our
4565 <emphasis>property
</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4566 `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4567 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4568 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether
4569 the car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?
</quote>
4572 <quote>It is
<emphasis>our property
</emphasis>,
</quote> the warriors
4573 insist.
<quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4574 is protected.
</quote>
4576 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4580 <part id=
"c-property">
4581 <title><quote>PROPERTY
</quote></title>
4585 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4586 <emphasis role='strong'
>The copyright warriors
</emphasis> are right: A
4587 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4588 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4589 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4590 that partially determine the price she can get.
4593 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a
<quote>property
</quote> right is a
4594 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4595 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4596 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4597 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4598 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4599 when I take the good
<emphasis>idea
</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4600 table in the backyard
—by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4601 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4605 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4606 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4607 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4608 in the ordinary case
—indeed, in practically every case except for a
4610 range of exceptions
—ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4611 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress
—though I
4612 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4613 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4614 when I copy the way someone else dresses),
<quote>He who receives an idea
4615 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4616 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.
</quote><footnote><para>
4618 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (
13 August
1813) in
4619 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson
</citetitle>, vol.
6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4620 Ellery Bergh, eds.,
1903),
330,
333–34.
4624 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4625 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4626 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4628 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4632 But how, and to what extent, and in what form
—the details,
4633 in other words
—matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4634 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4635 <quote>property
</quote> in its proper context.
<footnote><para>
4637 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4638 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4639 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4640 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4641 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4642 Adam Mossoff,
<quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,
</quote>
4643 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review
</citetitle> 45 (
2003):
373,
429 n.
241.
4647 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4648 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4649 <quote>copyright material is property
</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4650 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4651 these stories, the significance of this true
4652 statement
—<quote>copyright material is property
</quote>— will be a bit
4653 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4654 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4658 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4659 <chapter label=
"6" id=
"founders">
4660 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders
</title>
4661 <indexterm><primary>Henry V
</primary></indexterm>
4662 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
4663 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishlaw' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for
</secondary></indexterm>
4665 <emphasis role='strong'
>William Shakespeare
</emphasis> wrote
4666 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> in
1595. The play was first
4667 published in
1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4668 written. He would continue to write plays through
1613, and the plays
4669 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4670 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4671 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4672 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4673 Henry V:
<quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4677 In
1774, almost
180 years after
<citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> was written, the
4678 <quote>copy-right
</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4679 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.
<footnote><para>
4681 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben
</primary></indexterm>
4682 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John
</primary></indexterm>
4683 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4684 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4685 handsome
<quote>definitive editions
</quote> of classic works. In addition to
<citetitle>Romeo and
4686 Juliet
</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4687 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4688 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker,
<quote>Jacob Tonson,
4689 Bookseller,
</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar
</citetitle> 61:
3 (
1992):
424–31.
4691 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4692 the Conger
<footnote><para>
4694 Lyman Ray Patterson,
<citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective
</citetitle> (Nashville:
4695 Vanderbilt University Press,
1968),
151–52.
4697 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4698 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the
<quote>copy
</quote> of
4699 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4701 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4702 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4703 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4704 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4706 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'
><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
4708 Now, there's something puzzling about the year
1774 to anyone who
4709 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4710 history of copyright is
1710, the year that the British Parliament
4711 adopted the first
<quote>copyright
</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4712 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4713 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4714 works already published by
1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4715 additional years.
<footnote><para>
4717 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
4718 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4719 <quote>copyright law.
</quote> See Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
40.
4720 </para></footnote> Under this law,
<citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> should have been
4721 free in
1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4722 Tonson's control in
1774?
4724 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (
1662)
</primary></indexterm>
4726 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a
<quote>copyright
</quote>
4727 was
—indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4728 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4729 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of
1662, had
4730 expired in
1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4731 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4732 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4733 that the publishers, or
<quote>Stationers,
</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4737 There was no
<emphasis>positive
</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4738 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4739 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4740 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4741 from legislatures
<quote>positive law.
</quote> We call the words from judges
4742 <quote>common law.
</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4743 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4744 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4745 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4746 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4749 This question was important to the publishers, or
<quote>booksellers,
</quote> as
4750 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4751 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4752 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4754 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4755 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4756 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4758 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4761 The Statute of Anne granted the author or
<quote>proprietor
</quote> of a book an
4762 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4763 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4764 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4765 copyright
<quote>expired,
</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4766 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4770 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4771 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4772 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4773 <emphasis>at all?
</emphasis>
4776 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4777 strong claim. Take
<citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> as an example: That play
4778 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4779 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4780 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4781 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4782 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4783 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4784 reason is there to allow someone else to
<quote>steal
</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4787 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4788 about the notion of
<quote>copyright
</quote> that existed at the time of the
4789 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4790 <quote>booksellers.
</quote>
4793 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4794 to apply the concept of
<quote>copyright
</quote> ever more broadly. But in
1710, it
4795 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4796 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4797 others from reprinting a book. In
1710, the
<quote>copy-right
</quote> was a right
4798 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4799 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4801 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4802 a work could be
<emphasis>used
</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4803 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4804 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4805 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4807 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
4809 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4810 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4811 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4812 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4813 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4814 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4815 allowed to make his films. The
<quote>copy-right
</quote> was only an exclusive
4816 right to print
—no less, of course, but also no more.
4818 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England
</primary></indexterm>
4819 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (
1656)
</primary></indexterm>
4821 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4822 They had had a long and ugly experience with
<quote>exclusive rights,
</quote>
4823 especially
<quote>exclusive rights
</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4824 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4825 monopolies
—especially monopolies for works that already
4826 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4827 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4828 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In
1656, it passed the
4829 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4830 inventions. And by
1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4831 monopoly in publishing.
4834 Thus the
<quote>copy-right,
</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4835 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4836 claim that
<quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,
</quote> try
4837 sounding convincing when uttering,
<quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4838 have it forever.
</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4839 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4840 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4842 <indexterm id='idxbooksellers' class='startofrange'
><primary>booksellers, English
</primary></indexterm>
4844 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4845 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4846 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4847 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4848 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4850 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4851 kind
—tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4852 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4853 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as
<quote>old patentees
4854 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling
</quote>; they were
<quote>men who do
4855 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4856 indetted.
</quote><footnote><para>
4859 Philip Wittenberg,
<citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4860 Property
</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc.,
1937),
31.
4864 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4865 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4866 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4867 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4868 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4872 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4873 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4874 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4875 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4876 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4877 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4879 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4880 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4881 construction and spread of culture.
4884 When
1731 (
1710 +
21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4885 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4886 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4887 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4888 to control publication. But in
1735 and
1737, they tried to persuade
4889 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4890 they said; they needed more time.
4893 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4894 words that echo today,
4898 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4899 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4900 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4901 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4902 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4903 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4904 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4905 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4906 Booksellers.
<footnote><para>
4908 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4909 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4910 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4911 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4912 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4913 mentioned (London,
1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4914 al.,
8,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618).
4919 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4920 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4921 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
4922 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
4923 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
4924 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
4925 creative
<quote>property
</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
4926 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
4927 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
4928 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
4929 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
4930 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
4931 way to protect authors.
4933 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond
</primary></indexterm>
4935 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
4936 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
4937 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
4938 <quote>The publishers
… had as much concern for authors as a cattle
4939 rancher has for cattle.
</quote><footnote><para>
4941 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond
</primary></indexterm>
4942 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
4943 Lyman Ray Patterson,
<quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,
</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
4944 Law Review
</citetitle> 40 (
1987):
28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
4945 Vaidhyanathan,
37–48.
4947 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
4948 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
4951 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
4952 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
4953 Donaldson.
<footnote><para>
4955 For a compelling account, see David Saunders,
<citetitle>Authorship and Copyright
</citetitle>
4956 (London: Routledge,
1992),
62–69.
4959 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James
</primary></indexterm>
4960 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew
</primary></indexterm>
4962 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
4963 career in Edinburgh in
1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
4964 reprints
<quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,
</quote> at least
4965 under the Statute of Anne.
<footnote><para>
4967 Mark Rose,
<citetitle>Authors and Owners
</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
4969 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark
</primary></indexterm>
4971 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
4972 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
4973 and became
<quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.
</quote> <quote>[A]mong
4974 them,
</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was
<quote>the young James Boswell
4975 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
4976 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.
</quote><footnote><para>
4982 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
4983 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
4984 inexpensive editions
<quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
4985 of the supposed common law right of Literary
4986 Property.
</quote><footnote><para>
4988 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond
</primary></indexterm>
4989 Lyman Ray Patterson,
<citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective
</citetitle>,
167 (quoting
4992 His books undercut the Conger prices by
30 to
50 percent, and he
4993 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
4994 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
4997 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block
<quote>piracy
</quote> like
4998 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the
<quote>pirates,
</quote>
4999 the most important early victory being
<citetitle>Millar
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Taylor
</citetitle>.
5001 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)
</primary></indexterm>
5002 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert
</primary></indexterm>
5004 Millar was a bookseller who in
1729 had purchased the rights to James
5005 Thomson's poem
<quote>The Seasons.
</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
5006 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
5007 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
5008 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
5009 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.
<footnote><para>
5011 Howard B. Abrams,
<quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
5012 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,
</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review
</citetitle> 29
5016 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord
</primary></indexterm>
5018 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
5019 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
5020 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
5021 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
5022 law would protect the author against subsequent
<quote>pirates.
</quote>
5023 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
5024 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
5025 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
5026 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
5029 Considered as a matter of abstract justice
—reasoning as if
5030 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
5031 principles
—Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
5032 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
5033 with in
1710: How best to limit
5034 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
5035 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
5036 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in
1710, but
5037 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
5038 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
5039 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
5040 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
5042 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='endofrange'
/>
5044 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
5045 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
5047 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
5049 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
5050 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
5051 Thomas Beckett.
<footnote><para>
5055 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
5056 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in
<citetitle>Millar
</citetitle>,
5057 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
5058 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
5059 Court. In February of
1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
5060 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
5063 As few legal cases ever do,
<citetitle>Donaldson
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Beckett
</citetitle> drew an
5064 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
5065 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
5066 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
5067 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
5068 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
5069 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
5070 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
5073 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
5074 presented to the House and voted upon first by the
<quote>law lords,
</quote>
5075 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
5076 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
5077 House of Lords generally voted.
5080 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
5081 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
5082 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
5083 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
5084 (
22 to
11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
5085 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
5086 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
5087 passed into the public domain.
5090 <quote>The public domain.
</quote> Before the case of
<citetitle>Donaldson
</citetitle>
5091 v.
<citetitle>Beckett
</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
5092 England. Before
1774, there was a strong argument that common law
5093 copyrights were perpetual. After
1774, the public domain was
5094 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
5095 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
5096 history
—including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
5097 and Bunyan
—were free of legal restraint.
5098 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis
</primary></indexterm>
5099 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John
</primary></indexterm>
5100 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel
</primary></indexterm>
5101 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John
</primary></indexterm>
5102 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
5105 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
5106 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
5107 where most of the
<quote>pirate publishers
</quote> did their work, people
5108 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the
<citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser
</citetitle>
5109 reported,
<quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
5110 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
5111 decision of which so many individuals were interested.
</quote> <quote>Great
5112 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
5113 and illuminations.
</quote><footnote><para>
5119 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
5120 equally strong in the opposite direction. The
<citetitle>Morning Chronicle
</citetitle>
5125 By the above decision
… near
200,
000 pounds worth of what was
5126 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
5127 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
5128 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
5129 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
5130 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
5131 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
5132 successors.
<footnote><para>
5139 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
5140 <quote>Ruined
</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
5141 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
5142 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
5143 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
5144 <emphasis>free
</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
5145 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
5146 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
5147 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
5148 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
5149 book from someone. But
<emphasis>free
</emphasis> in the sense that the
5150 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
5151 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
5152 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
5153 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
5154 develop
— chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
5155 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a
<emphasis>competitive
5156 context
</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
5157 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
5158 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
5160 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellers' class='endofrange'
/>
5162 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
5163 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
5164 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
5167 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'
/>
5168 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishlaw' class='endofrange'
/>
5169 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
5171 <chapter label=
"7" id=
"recorders">
5172 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
</title>
5174 <emphasis role='strong'
>Jon Else
</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5175 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5176 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5177 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5178 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5181 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5182 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5186 In
1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5187 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5188 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5189 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5190 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5192 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera
</primary></indexterm>
5195 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5196 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5197 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5198 and the opera company played Wagner, was
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>. As Else judged
5199 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5200 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5204 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5205 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>.
5206 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5207 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5208 unless
<quote>fair use
</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5210 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films
</primary></indexterm>
5212 Else called
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5213 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5214 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5215 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5216 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5218 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films
</primary></indexterm>
5220 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5221 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5222 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5223 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5224 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5227 Then, as Else told me,
<quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5228 … that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation
—or at
5229 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.
</quote>
5230 And second, Fox
<quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5231 to use this four-point-five seconds of
… entirely unsolicited
5232 <citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.
</quote>
5234 <indexterm><primary>Herrera, Rebecca
</primary></indexterm>
5236 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5237 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5238 explained to her,
<quote>There must be some mistake here.
… We're
5239 asking for your educational rate on this.
</quote> That was the educational
5240 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5241 confirm what he had been told.
5244 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,
</quote> he told me.
<quote>Yes, you
5245 have your facts straight,
</quote> she said. It would cost $
10,
000 to use the
5246 clip of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5249 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5250 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else,
<quote>And
5251 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.
</quote> As an assistant
5252 to Herrera told Else later on,
<quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5255 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera
</primary></indexterm>
5256 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The
</primary></indexterm>
5258 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5259 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5260 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5261 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5262 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5263 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity
</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5266 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5267 copyright to
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5268 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5269 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5270 <citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5271 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5272 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5273 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5274 says the owner gets to control.
5277 For example,
<quote>public performance
</quote> is a use of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle> that the
5278 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5279 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see
<quote>My
5280 Favorite
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle>,
</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5281 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5282 whatever she wants
—$
10 or $
1,
000,
000. That's her right, as set
5286 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5287 thought is
<quote>fair use.
</quote><footnote><para>
5289 For an excellent argument that such use is
<quote>fair use,
</quote> but that
5290 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is
<quote>fair use,
</quote> see Richard
5291 A. Posner with William F. Patry,
<quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5292 Wake of
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5293 Law School,
5 August
2003.
5295 Else's use of just
4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle>
5296 episode is clearly a fair use of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>—and fair use does
5297 not require the permission of anyone.
5300 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5301 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon
<quote>fair use.
</quote> Here's his reply:
5305 The
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5306 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5307 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5308 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was
<quote>clearly
5309 fair use
</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5310 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5312 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
5315 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5316 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5317 <quote>visual cue sheet
</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5318 shot in the film. They take a dim view of
<quote>fair use,
</quote> and a claim of
5319 <quote>fair use
</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5322 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars
</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5323 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George
</primary></indexterm>
5326 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5327 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5328 tracking down and stopping unlicensed
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> usage, just as George
5329 Lucas had a very high profile litigating
<citetitle>Star Wars
</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5330 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5331 license to four seconds of
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5332 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5333 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5338 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5339 School
… who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5340 that Fox would
<quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5341 life,
</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5342 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5343 pockets, me or them.
5344 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5348 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5349 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5355 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5356 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5357 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5358 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5359 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5360 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5363 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5364 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5365 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5366 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5369 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5371 <chapter label=
"8" id=
"transformers">
5372 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
</title>
5373 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
5374 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'
><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5375 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary></indexterm>
5377 <emphasis role='strong'
>In
1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5378 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5379 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5380 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5381 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5382 anticipation of the power of networks.
5384 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on
</secondary></indexterm>
5385 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'
><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in
</primary></indexterm>
5387 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5388 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology
—not to distribute
5389 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5390 difficult. In
1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5391 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5392 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5393 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5394 important to his career.
5397 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5398 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5399 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5400 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5403 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5404 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5405 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5406 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5407 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5408 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5411 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips.
<quote>Our
5412 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5413 Eastwood's films,
</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5414 arose.
<quote>No one had ever really done this before,
</quote> Alben explained.
<quote>No
5415 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5416 actor's career.
</quote>
5419 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5420 Slade asked,
<quote>Well, what will it take?
</quote>
5423 Alben replied,
<quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5424 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5425 else that we want to use in these film clips.
</quote> Slade said,
<quote>Great! Go
5426 for it.
</quote><footnote>
5429 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5430 publicity
—rights an artist has to control the commercial
5431 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden
<quote>Rip, Mix,
5432 Burn
</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5433 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of
</secondary></indexterm>
5434 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5438 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5439 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5440 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5441 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5442 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5445 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5446 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5447 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5451 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5452 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include
—of
5453 course we were going to use the
<quote>Make my day
</quote> clip from
<citetitle>Dirty
5454 Harry
</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5455 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5456 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5459 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5460 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5461 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5462 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5463 rate at the time was about $
600. So we had to identify the
5464 people
—some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5465 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5466 glass
—is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5467 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5468 started calling people.
5471 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald
</primary></indexterm>
5473 Some actors were glad to help
—Donald Sutherland, for example,
5474 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5475 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5476 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $
600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5477 know, $
1,
200?
</quote> And they would say,
<quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5478 to get $
1,
200.
</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5479 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5480 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5484 It was one
<emphasis>year
</emphasis> later
—<quote>and even then we
5485 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.
</quote>
5488 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5489 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5490 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5494 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5495 hands and said,
<quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5496 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5497 actors.
</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5498 constituent parts and said,
<quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5499 directors,
… this many musicians,
</quote> and we just went at it very
5500 systematically and cleared the rights.
5505 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5506 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5507 loved it, and it sold very well.
5509 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
5511 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5512 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5513 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped,
<quote>There is
5514 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5515 at all.
</quote><footnote><para>
5517 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management,
<citetitle>Seven
5518 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition
</citetitle>, available at
5519 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
22</ulink>.
5521 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5525 For, as he acknowledged,
<quote>very few
… have the time and resources,
5526 and the will to do this,
</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5527 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5528 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5529 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5533 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5534 he or she gets paid very well.
… And then when
30 seconds of
5535 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5536 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person
… should be
5537 compensated for that.
5541 Or at least, is this
<emphasis>how
</emphasis> the artist should be
5542 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5543 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5544 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5545 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5546 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5547 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5548 made to be more clean?
5552 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5553 mechanism
—where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5554 subject to estranged former spouses
—you'd see a lot more of this
5555 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5556 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5557 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5558 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5559 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5560 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5561 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5562 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5563 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5564 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5565 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say,
<quote>Oh, I
5566 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5567 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5568 money,
</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5572 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5573 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5574 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5575 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5576 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5578 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'
/>
5579 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'
/>
5581 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5582 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5583 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5584 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5585 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5586 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5587 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5588 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5589 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5590 <quote>Does this still make sense?
</quote>
5592 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'
/>
5594 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5595 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5596 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5597 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5599 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5600 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5601 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5604 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5605 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a
<citetitle>60 Minutes
</citetitle> episode.
5606 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5607 judges loved every minute of it.
5609 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David
</primary></indexterm>
5611 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5612 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5613 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5614 room of over
250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5615 began his talk with a question:
<quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5616 were just violated in this room?
</quote>
5618 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David
</primary></indexterm>
5619 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5621 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5622 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5623 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5624 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5625 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of
250 judges and a gaggle
5626 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5627 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5628 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5629 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5630 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5631 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5632 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5633 couldn't easily do them legally.
5636 We live in a
<quote>cut and paste
</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5637 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5638 and paste architecture of the Internet created
—in a second you can
5639 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5640 planted in your presentation.
5642 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos
</primary></indexterm>
5644 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5645 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5646 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5647 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5648 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5649 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5650 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5651 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5652 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5655 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5656 wanted to be
<quote>legal,
</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5657 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5658 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5659 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5662 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5663 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5664 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5665 necessarily requiring that the
<quote>free
</quote> use be free as in
<quote>free beer.
</quote>
5666 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5667 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5668 along: a rule, for example, that says
<quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5669 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5670 will be a flat
1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5671 copyright owner.
</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5672 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5673 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5677 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5678 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5679 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5680 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5683 <emphasis role='strong'
>In February
2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5684 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5685 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live
</citetitle> and
5686 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5687 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5688 would work together to form a
<quote>unique filmmaking pact.
</quote> Under the
5689 agreement, DreamWorks
<quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5690 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and
—with the use
5691 of stateof-the-art digital technology
—insert Myers and other
5692 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5693 entertainment.
</quote>
5696 The announcement called this
<quote>film sampling.
</quote> As Myers explained,
5697 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5698 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5699 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5700 to take that same concept and apply it to film.
</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5701 quoted as saying,
<quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5702 new audiences, it is Mike.
</quote>
5705 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5706 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5707 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5708 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5709 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5710 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5711 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5712 privilege reserved for the funny and famous
—and presumably rich.
5715 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5716 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of
<quote>fair use.
</quote>
5717 Much of
<quote>sampling
</quote> should be considered
<quote>fair use.
</quote> But few would
5718 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5719 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5720 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5721 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5722 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5723 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5724 process is a process of paying lawyers
—again a privilege, or perhaps a
5725 curse, reserved for the few.
5727 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5729 <chapter label=
"9" id=
"collectors">
5730 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
</title>
5731 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'
><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
5732 <indexterm><primary>bots
</primary></indexterm>
5734 <emphasis role='strong'
>In April
1996</emphasis>, millions of
5735 <quote>bots
</quote>—computer codes designed to
5736 <quote>spider,
</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5737 content
—began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5738 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5739 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5740 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5741 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5742 Internet and stored them.
5744 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine
</primary></indexterm>
5746 By October
2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5747 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5748 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5749 the world. Using a technology called
<quote>the Way Back Machine,
</quote> you could
5750 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to
1996, as
5751 well as when those pages changed.
5753 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'
><primary>Orwell, George
</primary></indexterm>
5755 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5756 appreciated. In the dystopia described in
<citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5757 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5758 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5762 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5763 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5764 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5765 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5768 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5769 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5770 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5771 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5772 library
—constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5774 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'
/>
5775 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine
</primary></indexterm>
5777 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5778 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5779 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5780 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5781 what others might prefer you forget.
<footnote><para>
5783 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war
</primary></indexterm>
5784 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases
</primary></indexterm>
5785 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5786 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May
13,
2003,
5787 press release stated,
<quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.
</quote> That was
5788 later changed, without notice, to
<quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5789 Have Ended.
</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle,
1 December
2003.
5792 <indexterm><primary>history, records of
</primary></indexterm>
5794 <emphasis role='strong'
>We take it
</emphasis> for granted that we can
5795 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5796 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5797 race riots in Watts in
1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in
1963,
5798 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5799 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5800 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
5801 remember
—not just what it is convenient to remember, but
5802 remember something close to the truth.
5805 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5806 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We
<emphasis>all
</emphasis>
5807 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
5808 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
5809 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
5810 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
5811 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
5814 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5815 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5816 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5817 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5818 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5819 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5820 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5821 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet
—the
5822 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5825 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5826 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5827 researcher. In the
1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5828 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5829 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5830 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5831 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of
2002, the archive had over
10
5832 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5834 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress
</primary></indexterm>
5835 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive
</primary></indexterm>
5836 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University
</primary></indexterm>
5837 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine
</primary></indexterm>
5838 <indexterm><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>archival function of
</secondary></indexterm>
5839 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage2' class='startofrange'
><primary>news coverage
</primary></indexterm>
5841 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
5842 human history. At the end of
2002, it held
<quote>two hundred and thirty
5843 terabytes of material
</quote>—and was
<quote>ten times larger than the
5844 Library of Congress.
</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
5845 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
5846 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
5847 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
5848 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
5849 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
5850 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University
—thanks to a
5851 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
5852 is available to scholars for a very low fee.
<quote>But other than that,
5853 [television] is almost unavailable,
</quote> Kahle told me.
<quote>If you were
5854 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
5855 just a graduate student?
</quote> As Kahle put it,
5858 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan
</primary></indexterm>
5859 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes
</primary></indexterm>
5861 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
5862 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
5863 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
5864 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
5865 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
5867 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
5868 <citetitle>60 Minutes
</citetitle> episode that came out after it
… it would be almost
5869 impossible.
… Those materials are almost unfindable.
…
5872 <indexterm><primary>newspapers
</primary><secondary>archives of
</secondary></indexterm>
5874 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
5875 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
5876 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
5877 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
5878 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
5879 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
5882 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
5883 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
5884 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
5885 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
5886 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
5889 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress
</primary></indexterm>
5890 <indexterm><primary>films
</primary><secondary>archive of
</secondary></indexterm>
5892 These rules applied to film as well. But in
1915, the Library
5893 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
5894 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
5895 borrow back the deposits
—for an unlimited time at no cost. In
5896 1915 alone, there were more than
5,
475 films deposited and
<quote>borrowed
5897 back.
</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
5898 held by any library. The copy exists
—if it exists at
5899 all
—in the library archive of the film company.
<footnote><para>
5901 Doug Herrick,
<quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
5902 the Library of Congress,
</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly
</citetitle> 13 nos.
2–3
5903 (
1980):
5; Anthony Slide,
<citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
5904 Preservation in the United States
</citetitle> ( Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland
&
5909 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
5910 were originally not copyrighted
—there was no way to capture the
5911 broadcasts, so there was no fear of
<quote>theft.
</quote> But as technology enabled
5912 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
5913 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
5914 <quote>copyrighted.
</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
5915 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
5916 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
5917 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
5919 <indexterm><primary>September
11,
2001, terrorist attacks of
</primary></indexterm>
5921 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September
11,
2001, he and
5922 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
5923 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
5924 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
5925 September
11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
5926 stations from around the world and, beginning October
11,
2001, made
5927 their coverage during the week of September
11 available free on-line.
5928 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
5931 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive
</primary></indexterm>
5932 <indexterm><primary>archive.org
</primary><seealso>Internet Archive
</seealso></indexterm>
5933 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage2' class='endofrange'
/>
5934 <indexterm><primary>films
</primary><secondary>archive of
</secondary></indexterm>
5935 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive
</primary></indexterm>
5936 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film
</primary></indexterm>
5937 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films
</primary></indexterm>
5938 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick
</primary></indexterm>
5940 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
5941 archive of film includes close to
45,
000 <quote>ephemeral films
</quote> (meaning
5942 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
5943 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
5944 1,
300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
5945 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
5946 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
5947 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
5948 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
5949 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
5950 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
5951 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
5952 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the
<quote>Duck and Cover
</quote> film
5953 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
5954 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
5955 few minutes
—for free.
5958 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
5959 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
5960 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
5961 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
5962 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
5966 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
5967 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
5968 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
5969 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
5970 property, but during a second life that all creative property
5971 has
—a noncommercial life.
5974 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
5975 of creative property goes through different
<quote>lives.
</quote> In its first
5978 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
5979 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
5980 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
5981 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
5982 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
5983 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
5986 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
5987 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
5988 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
5989 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
5990 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
5991 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
5994 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
5996 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
5997 very quickly (the average today is after about a year
<footnote><para>
5999 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
6000 Dave Barns,
<quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
6001 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,
</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune
</citetitle>,
6002 5 September
1997, at Metro Lake
1L. Of books published between
1927
6003 and
1946, only
2.2 percent were in print in
2002. R. Anthony Reese,
6004 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,
</quote> <citetitle>Boston
6005 College Law Review
</citetitle> 44 (
2003):
593 n.
51.
6006 </para></footnote>). After
6007 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
6008 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
6009 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
6010 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
6011 important to the spread and stability of culture.
6014 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
6015 creative property does not hold true with the most important
6016 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
6017 centuries. For these
—television, movies, music, radio, the
6018 Internet
—there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
6019 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes
&
6020 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
6021 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
6025 <emphasis role='strong'
>For most of
</emphasis> the twentieth century,
6026 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
6027 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
6028 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
6029 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
6030 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
6031 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
6032 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
6033 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
6034 little practical effect.
6037 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
6038 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
6039 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
6040 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
6041 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
6042 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
6045 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
6046 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
6047 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
6051 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>total number of
</secondary></indexterm>
6053 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
6054 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
6055 movies,
… and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
6056 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
6057 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
6058 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
6059 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
6060 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
6061 … thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
6062 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
6063 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
6066 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
6068 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
6069 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
6070 libraries or archives could be.
<emphasis>When
</emphasis> the
6071 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
6072 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
6073 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
6074 will draw upon it to understand it;
6075 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
6076 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
6077 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
6078 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past
—a
6079 future
<emphasis>for
</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
6080 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
6083 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
6084 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
6085 call these
<quote>archives,
</quote> as warm as the idea of a
<quote>library
</quote> might seem,
6086 the
<quote>content
</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
6087 someone's
<quote>property.
</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
6088 that Kahle and others would exercise.
6090 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'
/>
6091 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
6093 <chapter label=
"10" id=
"property-i">
6094 <title>CHAPTER TEN:
<quote>Property
</quote></title>
6095 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon
</primary></indexterm>
6096 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.
</primary></indexterm>
6098 <emphasis role='strong'
>Jack Valenti
</emphasis> has been the president
6099 of the Motion Picture Association of America since
1966. He first came
6100 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
6101 administration
—literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
6102 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
6103 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
6104 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
6105 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
6107 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.
</primary></indexterm>
6108 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment
</primary></indexterm>
6109 <indexterm><primary>MGM
</primary></indexterm>
6110 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures
</primary></indexterm>
6111 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox
</primary></indexterm>
6112 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures
</primary></indexterm>
6113 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
6115 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
6116 Association. It was formed in
1922 as a trade association whose goal
6117 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
6118 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
6119 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
6120 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
6121 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
6122 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
6123 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
6127 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
6128 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
6129 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
6130 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
6131 political skill of a Southerner
—the ability to appear simple and
6132 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
6133 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
6134 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
6135 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
6136 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
6140 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
6141 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
6142 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
6143 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
6144 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
6145 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
6146 redefine the meaning of
<quote>creative property.
</quote>
6149 In
1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
6154 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
6155 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
6156 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
6157 theme which animates this entire debate:
<emphasis>Creative property
6158 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
6159 other property owners in the nation
</emphasis>. That is the issue.
6160 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
6161 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.
<footnote><para>
6163 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R.
4783, H.R.
6164 4794, H.R.
4808, H.R.
5250, H.R.
5488, and H.R.
5705 Before the
6165 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
6166 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
6167 Representatives,
97th Cong.,
2nd sess. (
1982):
65 (testimony of Jack
6173 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
6174 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
6175 <quote>central theme
</quote> to which
<quote>reasonable men and women
</quote> will return is
6177 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6178 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6179 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.
</quote>
6180 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6181 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6184 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6185 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6186 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6187 extreme a claim made by
<emphasis>anyone
</emphasis> who is serious in
6188 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6189 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6190 it comes to the nature and scope of
<quote>creative property.
</quote> His views
6191 have
<emphasis>no
</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6192 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6193 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6196 While
<quote>creative property
</quote> is certainly
<quote>property
</quote> in a nerdy and
6197 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,
<footnote><para>
6199 Lawyers speak of
<quote>property
</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6200 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6201 object. Thus, my
<quote>property right
</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6202 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at
150 miles an hour. For
6203 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of
<quote>property
</quote> to
6204 <quote>lawyer talk,
</quote> see Bruce Ackerman,
<citetitle>Private Property and the
6205 Constitution
</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1977),
26–27.
6206 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6207 <quote>creative property owners
</quote> have been
<quote>accorded the same rights and
6208 protection resident in all other property owners.
</quote> Indeed, if creative
6209 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6210 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6214 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6215 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6216 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6217 overturned in
1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6218 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6219 culture would develop.
6222 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6223 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6224 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6225 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6226 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6227 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6228 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6229 the same would be to
6231 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6232 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6233 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6237 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6238 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6239 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6240 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6241 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6242 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6243 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6246 <emphasis role='strong'
>To get
</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6247 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6248 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6251 The framers of our Constitution loved
<quote>property.
</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6252 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6253 important requirement. If the government takes your property
—if
6254 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6255 farm
—it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's
<quote>Takings
6256 Clause,
</quote> to pay you
<quote>just compensation
</quote> for that taking. The
6257 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6258 sacred. It cannot
<emphasis>ever
</emphasis> be taken from the property
6259 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6262 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6263 Valenti calls
<quote>creative property.
</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6264 power to create
<quote>creative property,
</quote> the Constitution
6265 <emphasis>requires
</emphasis> that after a
<quote>limited time,
</quote> Congress
6266 take back the rights that it has granted and set the
<quote>creative
6267 property
</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6268 the expiration of a copyright term
<quote>takes
</quote> your copyright and turns it
6269 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6270 pay
<quote>just compensation
</quote> for this
<quote>taking.
</quote> Instead, the same
6271 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6272 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6273 requires that you lose your
<quote>creative property
</quote> right without any
6274 compensation at all.
6277 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6278 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6279 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6280 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6281 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6282 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6286 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6287 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6288 The Constitution of
1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6289 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6290 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6291 president (as it did in
1800). The framers were no doubt
6292 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6293 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6294 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6295 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6298 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6299 least try to understand
<emphasis>why
</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6300 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6301 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6302 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6306 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6307 history of these
<quote>creative property
</quote> rights, and the control that they
6308 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6309 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6310 should be at the core of this war: Not
<emphasis>whether
</emphasis>
6311 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6312 <emphasis>whether
</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6313 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6314 ought to be. Not
<emphasis>whether
</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6315 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6316 also control how culture develops.
6320 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6321 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6322 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6323 than the narrow language of the law allows. In
<citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6324 Cyberspace
</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6325 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6326 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6327 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6329 <figure id=
"fig-1331">
6330 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.
</title>
6331 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.png"></graphic>
6334 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6335 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6336 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6337 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6338 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6339 be regulated
— either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6340 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6341 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6342 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6343 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6344 Web, you can be punished
6345 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6346 with a $
150,
000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6347 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6348 <indexterm><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
6350 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of
</primary></indexterm>
6352 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6353 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6354 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6355 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6356 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6357 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6358 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6359 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6360 the source of the enforcement.
6362 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6364 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6365 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6366 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6367 norms
—it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6368 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6369 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6370 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6371 individual or group might behave.
6373 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6375 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6376 <quote>architecture
</quote>—the physical world as one finds it
—is a
6377 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6378 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6379 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6380 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6381 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6382 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6383 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6384 theft, but by nature, by
<quote>architecture.
</quote> If a
500-pound boulder
6385 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6386 constraint. If a $
500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6387 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6391 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6392 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6393 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6394 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6395 undermined by another.
6398 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6399 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6400 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6401 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6402 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6403 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6404 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6406 <indexterm id=
"idxdrivespeed" class='startofrange'
><primary>driving speed, constraints on
</primary></indexterm>
6407 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6408 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6409 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of
</primary></indexterm>
6411 So, for example, consider the
<quote>freedom
</quote> to drive a car at a high
6412 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6413 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6414 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6415 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6416 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6417 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6418 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6419 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6420 the freedom to speed. Drive at
50 mph by a school in your own
6421 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6422 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6425 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6426 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6427 special role in affecting the three.
<footnote><para>
6429 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6430 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6431 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6432 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6433 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig,
<citetitle>Code: And
6434 Other Laws of Cyberspace
</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books,
1999):
90–95;
6435 Lawrence Lessig,
<quote>The New Chicago School,
</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies
</citetitle>,
6438 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6439 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6440 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6441 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6442 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6443 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6444 used to require that other laws be more
6445 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6446 strict
—a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6447 limit, for example
—so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6450 <indexterm startref=
"idxdrivespeed" class='endofrange'
/>
6452 <figure id=
"fig-1361">
6453 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.
</title>
6454 <graphic fileref=
"images/1361.png"></graphic>
6456 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6458 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6459 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6460 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6461 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6462 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6466 Some people object to this way of talking about
<quote>liberty.
</quote> They object
6467 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6468 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6469 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6470 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6471 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6472 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6473 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6474 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6475 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6476 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6477 of liberty. As I argued in
<citetitle>Code
</citetitle>, we come from a
6478 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6479 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6480 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6481 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6482 <citetitle>On Liberty
</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6483 1978),
19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6484 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons,
<quote>The
6485 Right to Work,
</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6486 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays
</citetitle> (London:
6487 Routledge:
1997),
62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6488 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6489 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6490 places easier;
42 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
6491 12101 (
2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6492 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6493 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6494 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6495 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (
1990)
</primary></indexterm>
6496 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.
</primary></indexterm>
6497 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6498 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6501 <section id=
"hollywood">
6502 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right
</title>
6504 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6505 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6506 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6507 rallying makes sense.
6510 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6513 <figure id=
"fig-1371">
6514 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.
</title>
6515 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.png"></graphic>
6517 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6518 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of
</primary></indexterm>
6520 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6521 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6522 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6523 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6524 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6525 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6526 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6527 recognize
—kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6528 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6529 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6530 this form of infringement.
6533 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6534 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6535 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6536 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6537 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6538 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6541 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6542 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6543 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6544 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6546 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6547 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6548 looting that results.
6550 <figure id=
"fig-1381">
6551 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
</title>
6552 <graphic fileref=
"images/1381.png"></graphic>
6555 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6556 warriors. Indeed, in a
<quote>White Paper
</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6557 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in
1995,
6558 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6559 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6560 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (
1) Congress should
6561 strengthen intellectual property law, (
2) businesses should adopt
6562 innovative marketing techniques, (
3) technologists should push to
6563 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (
4) educators should
6564 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6566 <indexterm><primary>steel industry
</primary></indexterm>
6568 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed
—if it was to
6569 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6570 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6571 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6572 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6573 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6574 life. Homeowners living in a
6576 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6577 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6578 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6579 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6580 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6581 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6582 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6585 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6586 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6587 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6588 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6589 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6590 Brown describes it, its
<quote>architecture of revenue.
</quote>
6592 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry
</primary></indexterm>
6593 <indexterm><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
6594 <indexterm><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
6596 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6597 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6598 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6599 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6600 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as
20
6601 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6602 of digital cameras.
<footnote><para>
6604 See Geoffrey Smith,
<quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?
</quote>
6605 BusinessWeek online,
2 August
1999, available at
6606 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
23</ulink>. For a more
6607 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6608 R. Schoenberger,
<quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?
</quote> Forbes.com,
6
6609 October
2003, available at
6610 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
24</ulink>.
6613 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6614 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6615 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6616 <emphasis>for the purpose of
</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6617 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6618 weakened the
<quote>stickiness
</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6619 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf ), and it
6620 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6621 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6622 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6623 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6625 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid
</primary></indexterm>
6626 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
6628 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6629 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6630 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6631 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6632 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6633 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6634 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6635 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents,
<quote>established companies
6636 have an interest in excluding future competitors.
</quote><footnote><para>
6638 Fred Warshofsky,
<citetitle>The Patent Wars
</citetitle> (New York: Wiley,
1994),
170–71.
6641 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6642 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6643 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6644 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6645 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6649 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6650 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6651 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6652 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6653 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6654 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6655 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6656 opportunities for innovation and change.
6659 In the context of laws regulating speech
—which include,
6660 obviously, copyright law
—that duty is even stronger. When the
6661 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6662 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6663 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6664 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6665 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6666 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution:
<quote>Congress
6667 shall make no law
… abridging the freedom of speech.
</quote> So when
6668 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would
<quote>abridge
</quote> the freedom
6669 of speech, it should ask
— carefully
—whether such
6670 regulation is justified.
6673 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6674 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6675 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6676 <quote>justified.
</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6677 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6678 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6679 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6682 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6684 <indexterm id=
"idxddt" class='startofrange'
><primary>DDT
</primary></indexterm>
6685 <indexterm><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann
</primary></indexterm>
6687 In
1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In
1948, Swiss
6688 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6689 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the
1950s, the
6690 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6691 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6694 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6695 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6696 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6698 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel
</primary></indexterm>
6699 <indexterm><primary>Silent Sprint (Carson)
</primary></indexterm>
6701 But in
1962, Rachel Carson published
<citetitle>Silent Spring
</citetitle>, which argued that
6702 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6703 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6704 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6707 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6708 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6709 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6710 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6711 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6712 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6713 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6715 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James
</primary></indexterm>
6717 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6718 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an
<quote>environmentalism
</quote> for
6719 culture.
<footnote><para>
6721 See, for example, James Boyle,
<quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6722 Environmentalism for the Net?
</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal
</citetitle> 47 (
1997):
87.
6724 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6725 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6726 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6727 <quote>for free.
</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6728 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6729 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6730 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6731 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6732 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6733 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6734 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6735 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6738 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6739 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6740 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6741 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6742 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6743 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6744 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6745 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6746 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6749 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6750 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6753 <indexterm startref=
"idxddt" class='endofrange'
/>
6755 <section id=
"beginnings">
6756 <title>Beginnings
</title>
6758 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6759 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of
<quote>creative
6760 property
</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6761 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6764 The power to establish
<quote>creative property
</quote> rights is granted to
6765 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6766 odd. Article I, section
8, clause
8 of our Constitution states that:
6769 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6770 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6771 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
6773 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
6774 We can call this the
<quote>Progress Clause,
</quote> for notice what this clause
6775 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
6776 <quote>creative property rights.
</quote> It says that Congress has the power
6777 <emphasis>to promote progress
</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
6778 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
6779 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
6782 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
6783 in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"founders"/>,
6784 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
6785 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
6786 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
6787 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
6788 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
6789 copyrights extend
<quote>to Authors
</quote> only.
6792 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
6793 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
6794 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
6795 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
6796 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
6797 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
6798 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
6799 to reinforce the power of the states
—including the Senate, whose
6800 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
6801 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
6802 case, a
<emphasis>structure
</emphasis> built checks and balances into
6803 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
6804 concentrations of power.
6807 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call
<quote>copyright
</quote>
6808 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
6809 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
6810 <quote>copyright
</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the
210
6811 years since they first struck its design.
6814 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
6815 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
6816 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
6817 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
6820 <figure id=
"fig-1441">
6821 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.
</title>
6822 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.png"></graphic>
6827 <figure id=
"fig-1442">
6828 <title><quote>Copyright
</quote> today.
</title>
6829 <graphic fileref=
"images/1442.png"></graphic>
6833 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
6836 <section id=
"lawduration">
6837 <title>Law: Duration
</title>
6839 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
6840 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
6841 the English had confronted in
1774. Many states had passed laws
6842 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
6843 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
6844 authorship.
<footnote>
6847 William W. Crosskey,
<citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
6848 the United States
</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press,
1953), vol.
1,
6849 485–86:
<quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
6850 Law of the Land,'
<emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
6851 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law
</emphasis></quote>
6853 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.
</primary></indexterm>
6855 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
6856 States in
1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
6857 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
6858 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
6859 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
6860 domain to reprint and distribute works.
6863 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
6864 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
6865 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
6866 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
6867 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
6868 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
6871 In
1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
6872 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
6873 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
6874 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
6875 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
6878 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
6879 ten years of the Republic, only
5 percent of the works were actually
6880 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
6881 in the United States both before
1790 and from
1790 through
1800,
95
6882 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
6883 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
6884 likely within fourteen years.
<footnote><para>
6886 Although
13,
000 titles were published in the United States from
1790
6887 to
1799, only
556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel,
<citetitle>A
6888 History of Book Publishing in the United States
</citetitle>, vol.
1,
<citetitle>The Creation
6889 of an Industry,
1630–1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker,
1972),
141. Of the
21,
000
6890 imprints recorded before
1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
6891 1790 act; William J. Maher,
<citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
6892 and the Copyright Law of
1790 in Historical Context
</citetitle>,
7–10 (
2002),
6893 available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
6894 #
25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
6895 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
6896 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
6897 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
6898 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
6899 Act of May
31,
1790, §
1,
1 stat.
124.
</para></footnote>
6902 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
6903 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
6904 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
6905 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
6906 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
6907 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
6911 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
6912 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
6913 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
6914 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
6915 domain.
<footnote><para>
6917 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
6918 instance, of the
25,
006 copyrights registered in
1883, only
894 were
6919 renewed in
1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
6920 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer,
<quote>Study No.
31: Renewal of Copyright,
</quote>
6921 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright
</citetitle>, vol.
1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
6922 1963),
618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
6923 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner,
<quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,
</quote>
6924 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review
</citetitle> 70 (
2003):
471,
498–501, and
6925 accompanying figures.
</para></footnote>
6927 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
6928 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
6930 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
6931 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
6932 out of print after one year.
<footnote><para>
6934 See Ringer, ch.
9, n.
2.
</para></footnote> When that happens, the
6935 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
6936 no longer
<emphasis>effectively
</emphasis> controlled by
6937 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
6938 is to sell the books as used books; that use
—because it does not
6939 involve publication
—is effectively free.
6942 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
6943 changed once. In
1831, the term was increased from a maximum of
28
6944 years to a maximum of
42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
6945 from
14 years to
28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
6946 the term increased once again. In
1909, Congress extended the renewal
6947 term of
14 years to
28 years, setting a maximum term of
56 years.
6950 Then, beginning in
1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
6951 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
6952 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
6953 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
6954 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
6955 In
1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
6956 And in
1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
6957 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
6960 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
6961 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
6962 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
6963 years, or
70 percent of the time since
1962. Thus, in the twenty years
6965 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
6966 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
6967 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
6968 of the expiration of a copyright term.
6971 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
6972 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
6973 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
6974 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
6975 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
6976 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
6977 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
6981 The United States abandoned this sensible system in
1976. For
6982 all works created after
1978, there was only one copyright term
—the
6983 maximum term. For
<quote>natural
</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
6984 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in
1992,
6985 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
6986 before
1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
6987 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
6988 was ninety-five years.
6991 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
6992 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
6993 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
6994 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
6995 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
6996 that terms be
<quote>limited,
</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
7000 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
7001 dramatic. In
1973, more than
85 percent of copyright owners failed to
7002 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
7003 in
1973 was just
32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
7004 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
7005 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from
32.2 years to
95
7006 years.
<footnote><para>
7008 These statistics are understated. Between the years
1910 and
1962 (the
7009 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
7010 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
7011 Posner,
<quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,
</quote> loc. cit.
7014 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
7016 <section id=
"lawscope">
7017 <title>Law: Scope
</title>
7019 The
<quote>scope
</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
7020 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
7021 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
7022 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
7025 In
1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only
<quote>maps,
7026 charts, and books.
</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
7027 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
7028 the author the exclusive right to
<quote>publish
</quote> copyrighted works. That
7029 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
7030 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
7031 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
7032 did not extend to what lawyers call
<quote>derivative works.
</quote> It would not,
7033 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
7034 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
7035 (such as a drama based on a published book).
7038 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
7039 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
7040 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
7041 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
7042 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
7043 work not only the exclusive right to
<quote>publish
</quote> the work, but also the
7044 exclusive right of control over any
<quote>copies
</quote> of that work. And most
7045 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
7046 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
7047 <quote>derivative work
</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
7048 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
7049 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
7050 on the initial creative work.
7053 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
7054 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
7055 complete removal of the renewal requirement in
1992. In addition
7056 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
7057 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
7058 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
7059 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
7060 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
7061 famous
© or the word
<emphasis>copyright
</emphasis>. And for most
7062 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
7063 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
7067 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
7068 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
7069 in the first ten years of the Republic,
95 percent of works eligible
7070 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
7071 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
7072 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
7073 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
7074 copyrighted
—that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
7075 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
7076 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
7077 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
7081 All of these
<quote>formalities
</quote> were abolished in the American system when
7082 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
7083 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
7084 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
7085 a
©; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
7086 copy available for others to copy.
7089 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
7093 If, in
1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the
5 percent who
7094 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
7095 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
7096 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
7097 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In
1790, there were
7098 174 publishers in the United States.
<footnote><para>
7100 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner,
<quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
7101 Creation of American Literature,
</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
7102 International Law and Politics
</citetitle> 255 (
1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
7103 Federal Copyright Records,
1790–1800 (U.S. G.P.O.,
1987).
7106 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
7107 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
7108 the United States
—publishers.
7111 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
7112 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
7113 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
7114 was totally unregulated by the
1790 act. If I took your novel and made
7115 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
7116 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
7117 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
7121 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
7122 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
7123 every note to your spouse, every doodle,
<emphasis>every
</emphasis>
7124 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form
—all of this is
7125 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
7126 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
7130 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
7131 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
7132 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
7135 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
7137 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
7138 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of
<quote>derivative
7139 rights.
</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
7140 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
7141 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
7142 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
7143 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
7145 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
7146 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
7149 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
7150 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
7152 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
7154 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
7155 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
7156 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
7157 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
7160 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
7161 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
7162 within a free culture
—at least, it's astonishing when you
7163 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
7164 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
7165 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
7166 <emphasis>that
</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
7167 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
7168 all
—they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
7169 not protect derivative rights at all.
<footnote><para>
7171 Jonathan Zittrain,
<quote>The Copyright Cage,
</quote> <citetitle>Legal
7172 Affairs
</citetitle>, July/August
2003, available at
7173 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
26</ulink>.
7174 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
7176 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
7177 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7178 the wrong of direct piracy.
7181 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7182 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7183 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7184 of my book.
<footnote><para>
7186 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7187 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7188 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere
<quote>copies
</quote> and
7189 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld,
<quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7190 Copyright's Constitutionality,
</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7191 Journal
</citetitle> 112 (
2002):
1–60 (see especially
7193 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb
</primary></indexterm>
7195 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7197 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
7198 <indexterm><primary>Mickey Mouse
</primary></indexterm>
7200 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7201 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7202 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7203 called
<quote>Mickey Mouse,
</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7204 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7208 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7209 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7210 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7211 the rights originally granted.
7214 <section id=
"lawreach">
7215 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach
</title>
7217 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7218 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7219 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7220 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.
<footnote><para>
7222 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7223 certainly regulates more than
<quote>copies
</quote>—a public performance of a
7224 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7225 per se doesn't make a copy;
17 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
7226 106(
4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a
<quote>copy
</quote>;
17
7227 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
112(a). But the presumption under the
7228 existing law (which regulates
<quote>copies;
</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
7229 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7233 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7234 <quote>Copies.
</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7235 <emphasis>copy
</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7236 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that
<quote>creative
7237 property
</quote> deserves the
<quote>same rights
</quote> as all other property, it is the
7238 <emphasis>obvious
</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7239 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7240 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7241 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7242 copies should
<emphasis>not
</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7243 law. More precisely, they should not
<emphasis>always
</emphasis> be
7244 the trigger for copyright law.
7247 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7248 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7249 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7250 the law of copyright automatically applies,
<footnote><para>
7252 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7253 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7254 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7255 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7258 because it is clear that the
7259 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7260 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7263 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7266 <figure id=
"fig-1521">
7267 <title>All potential uses of a book.
</title>
7268 <graphic fileref=
"images/1521.png"></graphic>
7270 <indexterm id='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>three types of uses of
</secondary></indexterm>
7271 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of
</secondary></indexterm>
7272 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>copyright applicability altered by technology of
</secondary></indexterm>
7273 <indexterm id='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='startofrange'
><primary>technology
</primary><secondary>copyright intent altered by
</secondary></indexterm>
7274 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7275 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7277 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7278 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7279 all its potential
<emphasis>uses
</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7280 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7281 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7282 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7283 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7284 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7285 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7286 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7287 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7288 acts do not make a copy.
7290 <figure id=
"fig-1531">
7291 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.
</title>
7292 <graphic fileref=
"images/1531.png"></graphic>
7295 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7296 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7297 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7298 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7299 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see first
7300 diagram on next page).
7302 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='endofrange'
/>
7303 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='endofrange'
/>
7305 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7306 that remain unregulated because the law considers these
<quote>fair uses.
</quote>
7308 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7309 <figure id=
"fig-1541">
7310 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.
</title>
7311 <graphic fileref=
"images/1541.png"></graphic>
7314 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7315 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7316 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7317 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7318 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7319 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7320 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such
<quote>fair uses
</quote>
7321 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7323 <figure id=
"fig-1542">
7324 <title>Unregulated copying considered
<quote>fair uses.
</quote></title>
7325 <graphic fileref=
"images/1542.png"></graphic>
7328 <figure id=
"fig-1551">
7329 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.
</title>
7330 <graphic fileref=
"images/1551.png"></graphic>
7333 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7334 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7335 sorts: (
1) unregulated uses, (
2) regulated uses, and (
3) regulated uses that
7336 are nonetheless deemed
<quote>fair
</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7338 <indexterm startref='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='endofrange'
/>
7339 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>on Internet
</secondary></indexterm>
7341 Enter the Internet
—a distributed, digital network where every use
7342 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.
<footnote><para>
7344 I don't mean
<quote>nature
</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7345 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7346 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7347 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7350 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7351 digital network, the scope of category
1 changes dramatically. Uses
7352 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7353 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7354 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7355 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7356 a copy
—category
1 gets sucked into category
2. And those who
7357 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7358 exclusively to category
3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7362 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7363 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7364 be no plausible
<emphasis>copyright
</emphasis>-related argument that
7365 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7366 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7367 the book once, ten times, or every
7368 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7369 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7370 use
—reading
— could be regulated by copyright law because
7371 none of those uses produced a copy.
7373 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>on Internet
</secondary></indexterm>
7374 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>technological developments and
</secondary></indexterm>
7376 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7377 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7378 only once or only once a month, then
<emphasis>copyright
7379 law
</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7380 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7381 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7382 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7383 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7384 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7385 copyright owner's wish.
7388 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7389 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7390 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7391 points also become clear:
7394 First, making category
1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7395 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7396 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7397 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7398 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7399 part of free culture before the Internet.
7401 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
7403 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7404 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7405 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7406 <emphasis>any
</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7407 using a machine.
<quote>Copy and paste
</quote> and
<quote>cut and paste
</quote> become
7408 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7409 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7410 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7411 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7415 Third, this shift from category
1 to category
2 puts an extraordinary
7417 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7418 burden on category
3 (
<quote>fair use
</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7419 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7420 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7421 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7422 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7423 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7424 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7425 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7428 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='endofrange'
/>
7429 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='endofrange'
/>
7430 <indexterm startref='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='endofrange'
/>
7431 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='endofrange'
/>
7432 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='endofrange'
/>
7434 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7435 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7436 depend upon fair use
—never even addressing the earlier question
7437 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7438 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7439 <emphasis>unregulated
</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7440 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7443 <indexterm id='idxadvertising2' class='startofrange'
><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
7445 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7446 in the business of making
<quote>trailer
</quote> advertisements for movies available
7447 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7448 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7449 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7451 <indexterm><primary>browsing
</primary></indexterm>
7453 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in
1997, it began
7454 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7455 previews. The idea was to expand their
<quote>selling by sampling
</quote>
7456 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7457 <quote>browsing.
</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7458 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7459 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7462 In
1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7463 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7464 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7465 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7466 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7467 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter
—he had built a
7468 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7469 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7470 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7471 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7472 <quote>fair use
</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7473 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7477 Disney countersued
—for $
100 million in damages. Those damages
7478 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had
<quote>willfully
7479 infringed
</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7480 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7481 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7482 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7483 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7484 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $
100 million.
7487 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7488 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7489 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7490 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7491 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7492 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7493 Disney's permission.
7495 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising2' class='endofrange'
/>
7497 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7498 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7499 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7500 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7501 was in the marketplace, the
<quote>first-sale doctrine
</quote> would free the
7502 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7503 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7504 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7505 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7506 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7507 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7508 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7510 <indexterm><primary>Barnes
& Noble
</primary></indexterm>
7511 <indexterm><primary>browsing
</primary></indexterm>
7513 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7514 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7515 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes
& Noble has the
7516 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7517 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7518 abuse. If Barnes
& Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7519 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7520 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7521 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7522 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7523 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7524 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7525 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7526 happening are quite slight.
7529 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7530 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7531 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7532 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7533 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7534 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7537 <section id=
"lawforce">
7538 <title>Architecture and Law: Force
</title>
7540 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7541 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7542 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7543 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7546 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7547 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7548 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7549 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7550 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7553 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca
</primary></indexterm>
7554 <indexterm id=
"idxmarxbrothers" class='startofrange'
><primary>Marx Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
7555 <indexterm id=
"idxwarnerbrothers" class='startofrange'
><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
7557 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7558 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7559 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7560 <citetitle>Casablanca
</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7561 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7562 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7563 plan.
<footnote><para>
7565 See David Lange,
<quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,
</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7566 Contemporary Problems
</citetitle> 44 (
1981):
172–73.
7570 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7571 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers
<quote>were brothers long before
7572 you were.
</quote><footnote><para>
7574 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
7575 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and
7576 Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
1–3.
7578 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7579 <citetitle>brothers
</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7580 trying to control
<citetitle>Casablanca
</citetitle>, then the Marx
7581 Brothers would insist on control over
<citetitle>brothers
</citetitle>.
7584 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7585 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7586 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7587 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7589 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>on Internet
</secondary></indexterm>
7591 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7592 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7593 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7594 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7595 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7596 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7597 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7598 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7600 <indexterm startref=
"idxwarnerbrothers" class='endofrange'
/>
7601 <indexterm startref=
"idxmarxbrothers" class='endofrange'
/>
7603 <indexterm id=
"idxadobeebookreader" class='startofrange'
><primary>Adobe eBook Reader
</primary></indexterm>
7605 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7608 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7609 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7610 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7611 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7615 On the next page is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook
7619 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7620 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7621 public domain:
<citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle>, for example, is in
7622 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7623 public domain: My own book
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle>
7624 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7625 <citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7627 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7628 <citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7629 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
7631 <figure id=
"fig-1611">
7632 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader
</title>
7633 <graphic fileref=
"images/1611.png"></graphic>
7636 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7637 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7639 <figure id=
"fig-1612">
7640 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.
</title>
7641 <graphic fileref=
"images/1612.png"></graphic>
7644 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7645 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
7646 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
7647 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
7648 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
7649 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear
<citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle>
7650 read aloud through the computer.
7652 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle
</primary></indexterm>
7653 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics
</citetitle>, (Aristotle)
</primary></indexterm>
7655 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7656 translation): Aristotle's
<citetitle>Politics
</citetitle>.
7658 <figure id=
"fig-1621">
7659 <title>E-book of Aristotle;s
<quote>Politics
</quote></title>
7660 <graphic fileref=
"images/1621.png"></graphic>
7663 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7664 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
7667 <figure id=
"fig-1622">
7668 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle;s
<quote>Politics
</quote>.
</title>
7669 <graphic fileref=
"images/1622.png"></graphic>
7671 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)
</primary></indexterm>
7672 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence
</primary></indexterm>
7674 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
7675 original e-book version of my last book,
<citetitle>The Future of
7678 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
7679 <figure id=
"fig-1631">
7680 <title>List of the permissions for
<quote>The Future of Ideas
</quote>.
</title>
7681 <graphic fileref=
"images/1631.png"></graphic>
7684 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
7687 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
7688 <quote>permissions
</quote>— as if the publisher has the power to control how
7689 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
7690 certainly does have the power
—up to the limits of the copyright
7691 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
7692 power.
<footnote><para>
7694 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
7695 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
7696 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
7697 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
7698 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
7699 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
7700 subsequently acquired the book.
7702 When my e-book of
<citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle> says I have the
7703 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
7704 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
7705 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
7706 control that the law would enable.
7709 The control comes instead from the code
—from the technology
7710 within which the e-book
<quote>lives.
</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
7711 permissions, they are not the sort of
<quote>permissions
</quote> that most of us
7712 deal with. When a teenager gets
<quote>permission
</quote> to stay out till
7713 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
7714 till
2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
7715 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
7716 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
7717 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
7718 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
7719 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
7720 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
7721 aloud
—it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
7722 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
7725 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
7726 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
7728 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
7729 These are
<emphasis>controls
</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
7730 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
7731 you tried to type
<quote>Warner Brothers,
</quote> erased
<quote>Brothers
</quote> from the
7735 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
7736 <emphasis>law
</emphasis> as copyright
<emphasis>code
</emphasis>. The
7737 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
7738 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
7739 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
7740 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
7741 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
7744 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
7745 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
7746 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
7747 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
7748 to defeat these protections as well?
7751 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
7754 <indexterm id='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='startofrange'
><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)
</primary></indexterm>
7755 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>e-book restrictions on
</secondary></indexterm>
7757 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
7758 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
7759 on the Adobe site was a copy of
<citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
7760 Wonderland
</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
7761 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
7764 <figure id=
"fig-1641">
7765 <title>List of the permissions for
<quote>Alice's Adventures in
7766 Wonderland
</quote>.
</title>
7767 <graphic fileref=
"images/1641.png"></graphic>
7769 <beginpage pagenum=
"164"/>
7771 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
7772 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
7773 <quote>permissions
</quote> indicated, not allowed to
<quote>read aloud
</quote>!
7776 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
7777 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
7778 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
7779 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
7780 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
7781 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
7784 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
7785 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
7786 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
7787 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
7788 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
7789 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
7790 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
7791 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
7792 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
7793 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
7794 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
7796 <indexterm startref='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='endofrange'
/>
7797 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='endofrange'
/>
7799 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
7800 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
7801 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
7802 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
7803 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
7806 <indexterm startref=
"idxadobeebookreader" class='endofrange'
/>
7807 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'
/>
7809 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
7810 story of mine that makes the same point.
7812 <indexterm id=
"idxaibo1" class='startofrange'
><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
7813 <indexterm id=
"idxroboticdog1" class='startofrange'
><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
7814 <indexterm id=
"idxsonyaibo1" class='startofrange'
><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
7816 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named
<quote>Aibo.
</quote> The Aibo
7817 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
7818 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
7821 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
7822 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
7823 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
7824 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
7825 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
7826 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
7827 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
7830 <quote>Teach
</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
7831 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
7832 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
7833 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
7834 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
7835 their computer
<quote>dog
</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
7837 <indexterm><primary>hacks
</primary></indexterm>
7839 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
7840 <citetitle>hack
</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
7841 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
7842 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
7843 them,
<citetitle>hack
</citetitle> is a much more positive
7844 term.
<citetitle>Hack
</citetitle> just means code that enables the
7845 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
7846 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
7847 old computer doesn't run, or
<quote>drive,
</quote> the printer. If you discovered
7848 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
7849 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
7853 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
7854 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
7855 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
7856 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
7860 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
7861 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
7862 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
7863 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
7864 than Sony had built.
7866 <indexterm startref=
"idxsonyaibo1" class='endofrange'
/>
7867 <indexterm startref=
"idxroboticdog1" class='endofrange'
/>
7868 <indexterm startref=
"idxaibo1" class='endofrange'
/>
7870 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
7871 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
7872 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
7873 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
7876 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
7877 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
7878 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
7879 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
7880 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
7881 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
7882 thought,
<emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
7883 a robot dog to dance?
</emphasis>
7885 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>government case against
</secondary></indexterm>
7887 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show
—
7888 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
7889 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
7890 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
7891 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
7892 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
7893 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
7894 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
7895 into being silent about something he knew very well.
7898 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April
2001.
<footnote><para>
7900 See Pamela Samuelson,
<quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,
</quote>
7901 <citetitle>Science
</citetitle> 293 (
2001):
2028; Brendan I. Koerner,
<quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
7902 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,
</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect
</citetitle>,
7903 January
2002;
<quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
7904 DMCA,
</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter
</citetitle>,
11 December
2001; Bill
7905 Holland,
<quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,
</quote> <citetitle>Billboard
</citetitle>,
7906 May
2001; Janelle Brown,
<quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?
</quote> Salon.com,
7907 April
2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation,
<quote>Frequently Asked
7908 Questions about
<citetitle>Felten and USENIX
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>RIAA
</citetitle> Legal Case,
</quote> available at
7909 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
27</ulink>.
7910 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation
</primary></indexterm>
7912 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
7913 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
7914 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
7915 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
7918 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
7919 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
7920 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
7921 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
7922 <quote>this music cannot be copied,
</quote> and have a computer respect that
7923 command. The technology was to be part of a
<quote>trusted system
</quote> of
7924 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
7928 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
7929 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
7930 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
7931 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
7934 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
7935 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
7936 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
7937 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
7938 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
7941 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
7942 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
7943 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
7944 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
7945 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
7946 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
7949 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
7950 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
7951 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
7952 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
7953 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
7954 constituted, succeed.
7956 <indexterm id=
"idxaibo2" class='startofrange'
><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
7957 <indexterm id=
"idxroboticdog2" class='startofrange'
><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
7958 <indexterm id=
"idxsonyaibo2" class='startofrange'
><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
7960 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
7961 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
7962 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
7967 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
7968 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
7969 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
7972 <indexterm startref=
"idxsonyaibo2" class='endofrange'
/>
7973 <indexterm startref=
"idxroboticdog2" class='endofrange'
/>
7974 <indexterm startref=
"idxaibo2" class='endofrange'
/>
7976 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
7977 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
7978 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
7982 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
7983 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
7984 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
7985 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
7986 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (
<quote>DMCA
</quote>).
7990 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
7991 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
7992 spreading such information an offense.
7995 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
7996 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
7997 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
7998 These new technologies would be copyright protection
7999 technologies
— technologies to control the replication and
8000 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
8001 <emphasis>code
</emphasis> to modify the original
8002 <emphasis>code
</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
8003 protection for copyright owners.
8006 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
8007 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
8008 <emphasis>legal code
</emphasis> intended to buttress
8009 <emphasis>software code
</emphasis> which itself was intended to
8010 support the
<emphasis>legal code of copyright
</emphasis>.
8013 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
8014 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
8015 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
8016 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
8017 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
8018 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
8019 have been a copyright violation.
8021 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8022 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8023 <indexterm><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8025 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
8026 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
8027 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
8028 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
8029 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
8030 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
8031 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
8032 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
8033 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
8034 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
8037 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
8038 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
8039 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
8040 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
8041 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
8042 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
8044 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
8045 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
8047 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
8048 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
8049 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
8050 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
8051 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
8052 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka
<quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers
</citetitle>,
</quote>
8053 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
8054 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
8055 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
8059 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
8060 <quote>Neighborhood
</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
8061 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
8062 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
8063 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
8064 <quote>Neighborhood
</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the
<quote>Neighborhood
</quote>
8065 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
8066 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
8067 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
8068 broadcasting has always been
<quote>You are an important person just the way
8069 you are. You can make healthy decisions.
</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
8070 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
8071 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
8072 important.
<footnote><para>
8074 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
8075 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>.,
464 U.S.
417,
8076 455 fn.
27 (
1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
8077 James Lardner,
<citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
8078 the VCR
</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton,
1987),
270–71.
8079 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
8084 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
8085 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
8086 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
8087 the VCR responsible.
8090 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
8092 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
8095 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
8098 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
8099 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
8100 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
8101 pirating of copyrighted material
—a bad end. Or they can be used
8102 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
8103 would be considered fair use
—a good end.
8105 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'
><primary>handguns
</primary></indexterm>
8107 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
8108 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
8109 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
8110 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
8111 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
8114 <figure id=
"fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig">
8115 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.
</title>
8116 <graphic fileref=
"images/1711.png"></graphic>
8118 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
8120 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
8121 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
8122 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash:
<emphasis>No one ever
8123 died from copyright circumvention
</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
8124 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
8125 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
8127 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'
/>
8128 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'
/>
8129 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8130 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8131 <indexterm><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8133 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
8134 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
8135 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
8136 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
8137 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
8138 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
8141 This is how
<emphasis>code
</emphasis> becomes
8142 <emphasis>law
</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
8143 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
8144 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
8145 law
—increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
8146 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
8147 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
8148 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect
—at
8149 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
8150 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
8153 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
8154 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
8155 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
8156 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
8157 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
8158 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
8159 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
8160 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
8161 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
8165 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
8166 For example, imagine you were part of a
<citetitle>Star Trek
</citetitle> fan club. You
8167 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
8168 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
8169 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
8170 simply continue it.
<footnote><para>
8172 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet,
<quote>Legal Fictions,
8173 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,
</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
8174 Entertainment Law Journal
</citetitle> 17 (
1997):
651.
8178 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
8179 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
8180 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
8181 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
8182 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
8184 <indexterm><primary>bots
</primary></indexterm>
8186 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
8187 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
8188 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
8189 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
8190 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
8191 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
8192 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
8193 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
8196 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
8197 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
8198 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
8199 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8200 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8201 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8204 <section id=
"marketconcentration">
8205 <title>Market: Concentration
</title>
8207 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically
—tripled in
8208 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8209 well
—from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8210 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8211 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8213 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8214 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8215 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8216 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8217 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8218 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8219 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8220 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8221 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8225 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8226 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8227 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8228 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8229 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8232 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8233 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8234 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8235 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8236 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8237 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8238 announced in June
2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8239 live in a world where just three companies control more than percent
8243 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8246 <indexterm><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
8247 <indexterm><primary>BMG
</primary></indexterm>
8248 <indexterm><primary>EMI
</primary></indexterm>
8249 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John
</primary></indexterm>
8250 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group
</primary></indexterm>
8251 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group
</primary></indexterm>
8253 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8254 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8255 ownership,
<quote>five companies control
85 percent of our media sources.
</quote><footnote><para>
8257 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8258 Transportation Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st sess. (
22 May
2003)
8259 (statement of Senator John McCain).
</para></footnote>
8260 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8261 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control
84.8 percent of the
8262 U.S. music market.
<footnote><para>
8264 Lynette Holloway,
<quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8265 Slide,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
23 December
2002.
8267 The
<quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8268 programming to
74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.
</quote><footnote><para>
8270 Molly Ivins,
<quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,
</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette
</citetitle>,
8275 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8276 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8277 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8278 seventy-five stations. Today
<emphasis>one
</emphasis> company owns
8279 more than
1,
200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8280 total number of radio owners dropped by
34 percent. Today, in most
8281 markets, the two largest broadcasters control
74 percent of that
8282 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control
90 percent of
8283 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8285 <indexterm><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
8287 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8288 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8289 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8290 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8291 the United States. The top ten film studios receive
99 percent of all
8292 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for
85 percent
8293 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8294 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8295 protected
— by the market.
8298 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8299 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8300 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8301 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James
</primary></indexterm>
8305 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8306 unmatched in its integration. They supply content
—Fox movies
8307 … Fox TV shows
… Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8308 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8309 advertisers
—in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8310 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8311 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8312 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8313 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8314 the same function in the United States.
<footnote><para>
8316 James Fallows,
<quote>The Age of Murdoch,
</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly
</citetitle> (September
8318 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James
</primary></indexterm>
8323 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8324 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8325 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8326 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8328 <figure id=
"fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership">
8329 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.
</title>
8330 <graphic fileref=
"images/1761.png"></graphic>
8333 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8334 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8335 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8339 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8340 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8341 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8342 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8345 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8346 integration may matter.
8348 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman
</primary></indexterm>
8349 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
8350 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family
</primary></indexterm>
8352 In
1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for
<citetitle>All in the Family
</citetitle>. He took
8353 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8354 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8355 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8356 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8359 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8360 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8361 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8362 control.
<footnote><para>
8364 Leonard Hill,
<quote>The Axis of Access,
</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8365 Forum,
<quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,
</quote> St. Louis,
8366 Missouri,
3 April
2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8367 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
28</ulink>;
8368 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8369 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
29</ulink>).
8374 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8375 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8376 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8377 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8378 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as
1992,
8379 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8380 television
—75 percent of it
—was
<quote>independent
</quote> of the
8384 In
1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8385 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In
1985,
8386 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8387 2002, only five independent television studios remained.
<quote>In
1992,
8388 only
15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8389 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8390 controlled companies more than quintupled to
77 percent.
</quote> <quote>In
1992,
16
8391 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8392 year there was one.
</quote><footnote><para>
8394 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8395 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st
8396 sess. (
2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8397 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8398 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8399 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8400 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia,
27 February
8403 In
2002,
75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8404 that ran it.
<quote>In the ten-year period between
1992 and
2002, the number
8405 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8406 increased over
200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8407 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8408 63%.
</quote><footnote><para>
8413 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family
</primary></indexterm>
8415 Today, another Norman Lear with another
<citetitle>All in the Family
</citetitle> would
8416 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8417 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8418 owned by the network.
8420 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry
</primary></indexterm>
8421 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
8423 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8424 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8425 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8429 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8430 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8431 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8432 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8433 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8434 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8435 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8436 handful.
<footnote><para>
8438 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,
</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers
</citetitle>, Bill
8439 Moyers,
25 April
2003, edited transcript available at
8440 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
31</ulink>.
8445 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8446 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8447 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8448 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8449 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8450 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8451 question without risk of consequence
—not necessarily banishment
8452 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8453 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8456 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.
</primary></indexterm>
8458 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8459 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the
<quote>Innovator's
8460 Dilemma
</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8461 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8462 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8463 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.
<footnote><para>
8465 Clayton M. Christensen,
<citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8466 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business
</citetitle>
8467 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press,
1997). Christensen
8468 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8469 Kim B. Clark,
<quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8470 Concepts in Technological Evolution,
</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy
</citetitle> 14 (
1985):
8471 235–51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8472 Kaplan,
<citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8473 Underperform the Market
—and How to Successfully Transform Them
</citetitle>
8474 (New York: Currency/Doubleday,
2001).
</para></footnote>
8476 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8477 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8479 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.
</primary></indexterm>
8482 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8483 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8484 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8488 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8489 suggest the concern.
8492 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8493 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8494 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8497 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8498 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8499 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8501 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8502 wrecked by drugs
—though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8503 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8504 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8505 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8506 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8507 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8508 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8509 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8510 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8511 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8512 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8513 outweigh these costs.
8516 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8517 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8518 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8521 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'
><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
8523 Beginning in
1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8524 a media campaign as part of the
<quote>war on drugs.
</quote> The campaign produced
8525 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8526 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8527 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8528 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8529 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8530 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8531 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8532 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8535 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8536 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8539 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8540 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8541 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8545 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8546 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8547 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8548 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8549 message will be heard then?
8552 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8553 <quote>controversial
</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8554 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8555 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8556 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8557 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8558 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8559 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8560 rights of the stations to be this biased.
<footnote><para>
8562 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February
2003, sought to place ads
8563 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8564 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as
<quote>against
8565 [their] policy.
</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8566 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8567 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8568 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8569 Neal Levine,
15 October
2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8570 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives,
<quote>On the Issue of
8571 an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV Networks,
</quote> <citetitle>New
8572 York Times
</citetitle>,
13 March
2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time
8573 there is very little that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to
8574 even the playing field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown,
<quote>Ad
8575 Hoc Access: The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8576 Radio,
</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review
</citetitle> 6 (
1988):
449–79, and for a
8577 more recent summary of the stance of the FCC and the courts, see
8578 <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors Association
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>FCC
</citetitle>,
184 F.
3d
872
8579 (D.C. Cir.
1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8580 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8581 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8582 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross,
<quote>Antidiesel Group Fuming
8583 After Muni Rejects Ad,
</quote> SFGate.com,
16 June
2003, available at
8584 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
32</ulink>. The ground
8585 was that the criticism was
<quote>too controversial.
</quote>
8586 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
8587 <indexterm><primary>Comcast
</primary></indexterm>
8588 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project
</primary></indexterm>
8589 <indexterm><primary>NBC
</primary></indexterm>
8590 <indexterm><primary>WJOA
</primary></indexterm>
8591 <indexterm><primary>WRC
</primary></indexterm>
8592 <indexterm><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
8596 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well
—if we lived
8597 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8598 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8599 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8600 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8601 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8602 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8603 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8604 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8606 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'
/>
8608 <section id=
"together">
8609 <title>Together
</title>
8611 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8612 copyright warriors that the government should
<quote>protect my property.
</quote>
8613 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8614 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8617 But when we see how dramatically this
<quote>property
</quote> has changed
—
8618 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8619 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8620 cultivate our culture is dramatically different
—the claim begins
8623 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8624 less innocent and obvious. Given (
1) the power of technology to
8625 supplement the law's control, and (
2) the power of concentrated
8626 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8627 the massively expanded
<quote>property
</quote> rights granted by copyright
8628 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8629 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8633 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8634 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8635 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8639 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8640 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8641 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8642 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8643 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8644 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8645 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8646 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8647 traditionally defined copyright's regulation
—a weakening of that
8648 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
8651 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
8652 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
8653 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
8654 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
8655 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
8656 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
8657 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
8658 future. And these changes have to be
<emphasis>reductions
</emphasis>
8659 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
8660 in control that technology and the market enable.
8663 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
8664 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
8665 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
8666 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
8667 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
8668 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
8669 more of the development of our culture than now
</emphasis>.
8672 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
8673 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
8674 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
8675 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
8676 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
8677 were independent of the networks.
<emphasis>Never
</emphasis> has
8678 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
8679 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
8680 regulation
—a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
8681 energy of a nation at the founding
—is now a massive regulation
8682 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
8683 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
8684 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
8685 known.
<footnote><para>
8687 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
8688 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his
<quote>four surrenders
</quote> of
8689 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan,
159–60.
8693 <emphasis role='strong'
>This has been
</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
8694 point can now be briefly stated.
8697 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
8698 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
8699 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
8700 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
8701 that copyright law has undergone. In
1790, the law looked like this:
8704 <informaltable id=
"t2">
8705 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
8709 <entry>PUBLISH
</entry>
8710 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
8715 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
8716 <entry>©</entry>
8720 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
8729 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
8730 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
8731 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
8733 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
8734 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
8735 noncommercial work was also free.
8738 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
8741 <informaltable id=
"t3">
8742 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
8746 <entry>PUBLISH
</entry>
8747 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
8752 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
8753 <entry>©</entry>
8754 <entry>©</entry>
8757 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
8766 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law
—if
8767 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
8768 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
8769 transformation were still essentially free.
8772 In
1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
8773 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
8774 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
8775 expanded. Thus by
1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
8776 we could say the law began to look like this:
8779 <informaltable id=
"t4">
8780 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
8785 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
8790 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
8791 <entry>©</entry>
8792 <entry>©</entry>
8795 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
8796 <entry>©/Free
</entry>
8804 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
8805 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
8806 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
8807 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
8808 that the law now looks like this:
8811 <informaltable id=
"t5">
8812 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
8817 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
8822 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
8823 <entry>©</entry>
8824 <entry>©</entry>
8827 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
8828 <entry>©</entry>
8829 <entry>©</entry>
8836 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
8837 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
8839 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
8840 commercial or not, transformative or not
—with the same rules
8841 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
8844 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
8845 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
8846 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
8847 these domains actually does any good.
8850 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
8851 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
8852 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
8853 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
8854 reasons sketched especially in chapters
8855 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"recorders"/> and
8856 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"transformers"/>, one
8857 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
8858 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
8859 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
8862 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
8863 course copyright is a kind of
<quote>property,
</quote> and of course, as with any
8864 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
8865 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
8866 property rights
<footnote><para>
8868 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
8869 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
8870 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey,
<quote>The
8871 Disintegration of Property,
</quote> in
<citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property
</citetitle>, J. Roland
8872 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
8874 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement
</primary></indexterm>
8876 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
8877 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
8878 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
8879 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the
<quote>copyright
</quote>
8880 did not control
<emphasis>at all
</emphasis> the freedom of others to
8881 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
8882 free, and for almost
180 years our country consistently protected a
8883 vibrant and rich free culture.
8885 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
8887 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
8888 limits on the scope of the interests protected by
<quote>property.
</quote> The very
8889 birth of
<quote>copyright
</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
8890 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
8891 story of chapter
6). The tradition of
<quote>fair use
</quote> is animated by a
8892 similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the costs of
8893 exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the story of
8895 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
8896 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
8897 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter
8898 8). And granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect,
8899 claims of property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing
8900 the soul of a culture (chapter
9). Free cultures, like free markets,
8901 are built with property. But the nature of the property that builds a
8902 free culture is very different from the extremist vision that
8903 dominates the debate today.
8906 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
8907 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
8908 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
8909 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
8910 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
8911 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
8912 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
8913 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
8914 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
8915 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
8918 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
8922 <part id=
"c-puzzles">
8923 <title>PUZZLES
</title>
8925 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
8926 <chapter label=
"11" id=
"chimera">
8927 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
</title>
8928 <indexterm id=
"idxchimera" class='startofrange'
><primary>chimeras
</primary></indexterm>
8929 <indexterm id=
"idxwells" class='startofrange'
><primary>Wells, H. G.
</primary></indexterm>
8930 <indexterm id=
"idxtcotb" class='startofrange'
><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The
</quote> (Wells)
</primary></indexterm>
8933 <emphasis role='strong'
>In a well-known
</emphasis> short story by
8934 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
8935 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
8936 Andes.
<footnote><para>
8938 H. G. Wells,
<quote>The Country of the Blind
</quote> (
1904,
1911). See H. G. Wells,
8939 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories
</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
8940 York: Oxford University Press,
1996).
8942 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with
<quote>sweet water, pasture,
8943 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
8944 that bore an excellent fruit.
</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
8945 takes this as an opportunity.
<quote>In the Country of the Blind,
</quote> he tells
8946 himself,
<quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.
</quote> So he resolves to live with the
8947 villagers to explore life as a king.
8950 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
8951 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
8952 <quote>blind.
</quote> They don't have the word
<citetitle>blind
</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
8953 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
8954 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
8955 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated.
<quote>`You
8956 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
8957 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
8961 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
8962 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
8963 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
8964 affection, a young woman who to him seems
<quote>the most beautiful thing in
8965 the whole of creation,
</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
8966 description of what he sees
<quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
8967 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
8968 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
8969 indulgence.
</quote> <quote>She did not believe,
</quote> Wells tells us, and
<quote>she could
8970 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.
</quote>
8973 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his
<quote>mysteriously delighted
</quote>
8974 love, the father and the village object.
<quote>You see, my dear,
</quote> her
8975 father instructs,
<quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
8976 anything right.
</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
8979 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion.
<quote>His brain
8980 is affected,
</quote> he reports.
8983 <quote>What affects it?
</quote> the father asks.
<quote>Those queer things that are
8984 called the eyes
… are diseased
… in such a way as to affect
8988 The doctor continues:
<quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
8989 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
8990 simple and easy surgical operation
—namely, to remove these
8991 irritant bodies [the eyes].
</quote>
8994 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!
</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
8995 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
8996 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
8997 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
9000 <emphasis role='strong'
>It sometimes
</emphasis> happens that the eggs
9001 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
9002 <quote>chimera.
</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
9003 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
9004 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
9006 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
9007 plot for murder mysteries.
<quote>But the DNA shows with
100 percent
9008 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
9009 scene.
…</quote>
9011 <indexterm startref=
"idxtcotb" class='endofrange'
/>
9012 <indexterm startref=
"idxwells" class=
"endofrange"/>
9014 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
9015 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
9016 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
9017 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
9018 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
9019 understanding of a
<quote>person
</quote> should reflect this reality.
9022 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
9023 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
9024 unfairly enough,
<quote>the copyright wars,
</quote> the more I think we're dealing
9025 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question
<quote>What is
9026 p2p file sharing?
</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
9027 wrong. One side says,
<quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
9028 others' records
—the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
9029 thirty years without any question at all.
</quote> That's true, at least in
9030 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
9031 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
9032 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
9033 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
9036 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
9037 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
9038 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
9039 <quote>friends
</quote> beyond recognition to say
<quote>my ten thousand best friends
</quote> can
9040 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
9041 what
<quote>we have always been allowed to do,
</quote> we have not always been
9042 allowed to share music with
<quote>our ten thousand best friends.
</quote>
9045 Likewise, when the other side says,
<quote>File sharing is just like walking
9046 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
9047 with it,
</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
9048 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
9049 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
9051 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
9055 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
9056 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
9057 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
9058 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
9059 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
9060 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
9061 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
9062 $
1,
000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
9063 CD, I'm liable for $
1,
500,
000 in damages.)
9066 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
9067 that it is both
—both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
9068 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
9069 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
9070 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
9073 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
9074 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
9075 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
9076 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
9077 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
9078 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
9079 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
9080 implemented.
<footnote><para>
9082 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by
</primary></indexterm>
9083 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
9084 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
9085 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,
</quote> 27 June
2003,
9087 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9088 #
33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
9089 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
9090 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
9091 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey,
<quote>House Bill Aims to Up
9092 Stakes on Piracy,
</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times
</citetitle>,
17 July
2003, available at
9093 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
34</ulink>. Civil
9094 penalties are currently set at $
150,
000 per copied song. For a recent
9095 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
9096 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than
600 songs
9097 through a family computer, see
<citetitle>RIAA
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
9098 re. Verizon Internet Services)
</citetitle>,
240 F. Supp.
2d
24
9099 (D.D.C.
2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $
90
9100 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
9101 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
9102 $
12,
000 to $
17,
500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
9103 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $
98
9104 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
9105 Elizabeth Young,
<quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,
</quote> redandblack.com,
9106 August
2003, available at
9107 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
35</ulink>. For an
9108 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
9109 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
9110 identities, see James Collins,
<quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
9111 Name Students,
</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe
</citetitle>,
8 August
2003, D3, available at
9112 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
36</ulink>.
9113 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
9114 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.
</primary></indexterm>
9118 <indexterm startref=
"idxchimera" class='endofrange'
/>
9120 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
9121 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
9122 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
9123 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
9124 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
9127 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
9128 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
9129 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
9130 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
9131 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
9132 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe
<emphasis>either
</emphasis> extreme
9133 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
9134 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
9138 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
9139 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
9140 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
9141 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
9142 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
9143 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
9144 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
9147 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to
<quote>steal
</quote> music. My
9148 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
9149 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
9150 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
9151 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
9152 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
9153 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
9154 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
9155 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
9156 protection for copyrighted material,
9160 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
9161 material, and we want to protect those rights.
9164 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
9165 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
9166 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
9167 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
9168 produce a totally different industry model.
9171 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
9172 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
9173 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
9174 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
9175 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
9176 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
9177 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
9178 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
9179 interests.
<footnote><para>
9181 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
9182 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
9183 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
9184 House Committee on Commerce,
106th Cong.
29 (
1999) (statement of Peter
9185 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
9186 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
9187 Congressional Testimony File.
</para></footnote>
9190 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
9192 In April
2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
9193 one of
<quote>the major labels.
</quote> Its position on these matters has now
9195 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal
</primary></indexterm>
9198 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
9199 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9200 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9203 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9205 <chapter label=
"12" id=
"harms">
9206 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
</title>
9208 <emphasis role='strong'
>To fight
</emphasis> <quote>piracy,
</quote> to
9209 protect
<quote>property,
</quote> the content industry has launched a
9210 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9211 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9212 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9213 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9216 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9217 particular, the consequences for
<quote>free culture.
</quote> But my aim now is to
9218 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9222 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9223 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9224 power of the property called
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> is at its greatest in
9227 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
9228 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
9230 Yet
<quote>common sense
</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9231 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9232 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9233 rejection of
<quote>piracy
</quote> still has play.
9235 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard
</primary></indexterm>
9237 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9238 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9239 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9240 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9241 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9242 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9244 <section id=
"constrain">
9245 <title>Constraining Creators
</title>
9247 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9248 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9249 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9250 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9251 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9252 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9253 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9254 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9255 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9256 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9257 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9258 weave together a string
—a mash-up
— of songs from your
9259 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9262 This digital
<quote>capturing and sharing
</quote> is in part an extension of the
9263 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9264 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9265 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9266 of digital
<quote>capturing and sharing
</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9267 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9268 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9269 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9270 the culture all around.
9273 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9274 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9276 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9278 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9279 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9280 storytelling extended across the globe.
9283 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9284 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9285 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9286 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9287 that catalog cartoons from the
1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9288 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9289 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9290 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9291 work is presumptively illegal.
9293 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom
</primary></indexterm>
9295 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9296 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9297 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9298 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9299 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9300 by the RIAA ( Jesse Jordan of chapter
3 was just one) were threatened
9301 with a $
98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted
9302 songs to be copied. Yet World-Com
—which defrauded investors of
9303 $
11 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization
9304 of over $
200 billion
—received a fine of a mere $
750
9305 million.
<footnote><para>
9307 See Lynne W. Jeter,
<citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom
</citetitle>
9308 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley
& Sons,
2003),
176,
204; for details of
9309 the settlement, see MCI press release,
<quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9310 Approval for SEC Settlement
</quote> (
7 July
2003), available at
9311 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
37</ulink>.
9312 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom
</primary></indexterm>
9314 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9315 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9316 no more than $
250,
000 in damages for pain and
9317 suffering.
<footnote>
9319 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9320 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July
2003. For
9321 an overview, see Tanya Albert,
<quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9322 Say Tort Reformers,
</quote> amednews.com,
28 July
2003, available at
9323 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
38</ulink>,
9324 and
<quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,
</quote> CBSNews.com,
9 July
2003,
9326 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9328 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.
</primary></indexterm>
9330 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9331 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9332 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9334 <indexterm><primary>art, underground
</primary></indexterm>
9336 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9337 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9338 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9339 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9340 Disneys
<quote>pirates.
</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9341 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9344 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9345 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9346 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9347 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9348 we will begin to see a world of underground art
—not because the
9349 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9350 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9351 fraught. Already, exhibits of
<quote>illegal art
</quote> tour the United
9352 States.
<footnote><para>
9355 See Danit Lidor,
<quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,
</quote> <citetitle>Wired
</citetitle>,
7 July
9357 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9358 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
41</ulink>.
9360 In what does their
<quote>illegality
</quote> consist?
9361 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9362 critical or reflective.
9364 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by
</primary></indexterm>
9366 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9367 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9368 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>. But an
9369 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9370 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9371 discovered in
2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9372 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9373 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9374 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9375 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9377 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of
</primary></indexterm>
9379 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9380 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9381 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9382 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9383 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9384 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9385 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9386 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9387 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9390 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9391 described in chapter
9392 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"recorders"/>, in
9393 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9394 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9395 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9400 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9401 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9402 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9403 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad
—in
9404 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9405 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9406 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9407 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9408 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9411 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9412 <quote>breathing room
</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9413 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9414 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9415 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9416 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9417 journalists
— these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9418 these rules have little relationship to the
<quote>law
</quote> with which judges
9422 For in a world that threatens $
150,
000 for a single willful
9423 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9424 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9425 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9426 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak
—in that
9427 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9428 <quote>copyright
</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9429 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9430 culture that is free.
9433 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9437 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9438 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9439 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9440 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made
… you're not
9441 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9442 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9443 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying,
<quote>This has been
9444 cleared.
</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9445 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9449 <section id=
"innovators">
9450 <title>Constraining Innovators
</title>
9452 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9453 story
—creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9454 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9455 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9456 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9457 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9460 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9461 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9462 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9463 one at that,
188 pages into a book like this), then you can see this
9464 other aspect by substituting
<quote>free market
</quote> every place I've spoken of
9465 <quote>free culture.
</quote> The point is the same, even if the interests
9466 affecting culture are more fundamental.
9468 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
9470 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9471 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9472 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary
—at
9473 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9474 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9475 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9476 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9477 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9478 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9479 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9480 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9482 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
9484 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9485 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9486 strategy that I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select:
9487 labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9488 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9489 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9490 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9491 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9492 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9493 lesson. That lesson
—what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9494 <quote>nuclear pall
</quote> that has fallen over the Valley
—has been learned.
9497 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9498 I told in
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9499 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9501 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
9503 In
1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9504 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9505 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9506 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9507 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9508 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9510 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
9511 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>preference data on
</secondary></indexterm>
9513 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9514 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9515 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9516 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9520 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9521 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9522 preference data. In January
2000, the company launched a service
9523 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9524 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9525 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9526 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9527 wherever you were
—at work or at home
—you could get access
9528 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9529 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9532 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9533 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9535 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9536 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9537 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9538 the kind of content the users liked.
9540 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'
/>
9542 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy
50,
000
9543 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9544 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9545 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9546 therefore purchased
50,
000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9547 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9548 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9549 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was
50,
000
9550 copies, it was
50,
000 copies directed at giving customers something
9551 they had already bought.
9553 <indexterm id=
"idxvivendiuniversal" class='startofrange'
><primary>Vivendi Universal
</primary></indexterm>
9555 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9556 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9557 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9558 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9559 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9560 MP3.com of $
118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9561 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $
54 million. Vivendi
9562 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9565 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9568 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9569 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9570 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9571 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9572 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9573 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9574 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9578 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9579 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9580 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9582 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9583 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9584 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9585 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9586 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9588 <indexterm startref=
"idxvivendiuniversal" class='endofrange'
/>
9589 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John
</primary></indexterm>
9590 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
9591 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad
</primary></indexterm>
9592 <indexterm><primary>EMI
</primary></indexterm>
9593 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group
</primary></indexterm>
9595 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April
2003,
9596 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9597 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9598 its development, its cofounder ( John Hummer), and general partner
9599 (Hank Barry).
<footnote><para>
9601 See Joseph Menn,
<quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,
</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9602 Times
</citetitle>,
23 April
2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9603 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown,
<quote>The Music
9604 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,
</quote> Salon.com,
1 June
2001, available
9605 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
42</ulink>.
9606 See also Jon Healey,
<quote>Online Music Services Besieged,
</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9607 Times
</citetitle>,
28 May
2001.
9609 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
9610 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
9611 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
9612 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
9613 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
9614 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
9615 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
9616 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
9617 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
9618 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
9619 <citetitle>Business
2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
9620 discussion with BMW:
9623 <indexterm><primary>BMW
</primary></indexterm>
9624 <indexterm><primary>cars, MP3 sound system in
</primary></indexterm>
9626 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
9627 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
9628 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
9629 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
9630 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
9631 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
9632 United States with bona fide MP3 players.
… <footnote>
9635 Rafe Needleman,
<quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,
</quote> <citetitle>Business
2.0</citetitle>,
16 June
9637 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
43</ulink>. I am grateful
9638 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
9639 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe
</primary></indexterm>
9644 This is the world of the mafia
—filled with
<quote>your money or your
9645 life
</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
9646 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
9647 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
9648 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
9649 constantly threatened by litigation.
9653 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
9654 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
9655 enterprises. The point is the definition of
<quote>illegal.
</quote> The law is a
9656 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
9657 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
9658 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
9659 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
9660 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
9661 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
9662 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
9663 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
9664 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
9665 much less creativity.
9667 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
9669 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
9670 use. Whatever the
<quote>real
</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
9671 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
9672 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
9673 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
9674 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
9675 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
9676 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
9677 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
9678 produce an overregulatedregulated market.
9681 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
9682 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
9683 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
9684 culture
—a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
9685 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
9686 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
9687 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
9688 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
9689 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
9690 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
9691 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
9692 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
9693 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
9694 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
9695 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
9696 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
9700 <emphasis role='strong'
>The uncertainty
</emphasis> of the law is one
9701 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
9702 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
9703 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
9704 better protects their content.
9707 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
9708 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
9709 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
9710 this feature is a
<quote>bug.
</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
9711 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
9712 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
9713 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables
<quote>piracy,
</quote> then,
9714 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
9716 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
9718 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
9719 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
9720 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
9721 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.
<footnote><para>
9722 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,
</quote> GartnerG2 and
9723 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
9724 (
2003),
33–35, available at
9725 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
44</ulink>.
9727 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
9728 <quote>broadcast flag
</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
9729 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
9730 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
9731 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
9732 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
9733 copyright violators and disable their machines.
<footnote><para>
9735 GartnerG2,
26–27.
9739 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
9740 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
9741 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
9742 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
9744 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
9745 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
9748 <indexterm><primary>Intel
</primary></indexterm>
9750 In March
2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
9751 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
9752 would impose.
<footnote><para>
9754 See David McGuire,
<quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,
</quote> Newsbytes,
9755 February
2002 (Entertainment).
9757 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
9758 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
9762 <emphasis role='strong'
>There is one
</emphasis> more obvious way in
9763 which this war has harmed innovation
—again, a story that will be
9764 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
9767 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
9768 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
9769 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
9770 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
9772 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
9773 <indexterm><primary>VCRs
</primary></indexterm>
9775 As I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
9776 linkend=
"property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
9777 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
9778 Jessica Litman in her book
<citetitle>Digital
9779 Copyright
</citetitle>,
<footnote><para>
9781 Jessica Litman,
<citetitle>Digital Copyright
</citetitle> (Amherst,
9782 N.Y.: Prometheus Books,
2001).
9783 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica
</primary></indexterm>
9785 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter
10 details,
9786 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
9787 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
9788 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
9789 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
9792 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
9793 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
9794 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
9795 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
9796 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
9799 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.
<footnote><para>
9801 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.
</primary></indexterm>
9802 The only circuit court exception is found in
<citetitle>Recording Industry
9803 Association of America (RIAA)
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems
</citetitle>,
180 F.
3d
9804 1072 (
9th Cir.
1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
9805 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
9806 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
9807 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
9808 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
9809 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
9810 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Grokster, Ltd
</citetitle>.,
259 F. Supp.
2d
9811 1029 (C.D. Cal.,
2003), where the court found the link between the
9812 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
9813 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
9816 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
9817 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
9818 here.
<footnote><para>
9820 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy
</primary></indexterm>
9821 For example, in July
2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
9822 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R.
5211), which would immunize
9823 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
9824 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
9825 August
2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
9826 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
9827 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a
<quote>broadcast flag
</quote> that
9828 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
9829 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
9830 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
9831 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2,
<quote>Copyright and
9832 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,
</quote> 27 June
2003,
33–34,
9834 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
44</ulink>.
9835 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.
</primary></indexterm>
9836 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz
</primary></indexterm>
9837 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
9839 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
9840 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
9842 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
9843 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.
</primary></indexterm>
9846 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
9847 As I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
9848 linkend=
"pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
9849 artist doesn't get paid for that
<quote>radio performance
</quote> unless he or she
9850 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
9851 version of
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote>—to memorialize her famous
9852 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden
—
9853 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
9854 copyright owners of
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote> would get some money, whereas
9855 Marilyn Monroe would not.
9858 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
9859 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
9860 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
9861 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
9862 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
9863 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
9864 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
9865 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
9869 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
9870 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
9871 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
9872 spectrum. Thus, I can
<quote>tune in
</quote> to an Internet radio station in
9873 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
9874 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
9878 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
9879 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
9880 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
9881 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
9882 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
9883 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
9884 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
9885 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
9886 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
9887 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
9888 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
9890 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard
</primary></indexterm>
9893 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
9894 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
9895 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
9896 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
9897 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
9898 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
9899 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
9904 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
9905 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
9906 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
9907 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
9908 than by technical restrictions.
… Armstrong likened the situation
9909 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
9910 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
9911 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
9912 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
9913 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
9914 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
9915 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
9916 shackles.
<footnote><para>
9923 This potential for FM radio was never realized
—not
9924 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
9925 underestimated the power of
<quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
9926 legislation
</quote><footnote><para>
9930 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
9933 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
9934 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
9935 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
9936 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
9937 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
9940 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments2' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
9942 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
9943 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
9945 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
9946 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
9947 of Internet radio in
1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
9948 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
9949 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
9950 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
9951 of
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote> on the air,
<emphasis>Internet radio
9952 does
</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
9953 radio
—the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
9954 burdens terrestrial radio.
9957 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
9958 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
9959 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
9960 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
9961 over $
1 million a year.
<footnote>
9964 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
9965 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
9966 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
9967 iLaw (Stanford),
3 July
2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
9968 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
9969 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
9970 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No.
2000-
9, CARP
9971 DTRA
1 and
2, available at
9972 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
45</ulink>.
9973 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
9974 C. Picker,
<quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
9975 Distribution,
</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin
</citetitle> (Summer/Fall
2002):
461:
<quote>This was
9976 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
9977 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
9978 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
9979 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
9980 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.
</quote>
9981 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)
</primary></indexterm>
9982 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
9984 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
9987 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments2' class='endofrange'
/>
9989 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
9990 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
9991 station) would have to collect the following data from
<emphasis>every
9992 listening transaction
</emphasis>:
9994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
9995 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
9997 name of the service;
10000 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
10003 type of program (archived/looped/live);
10006 date of transmission;
10009 time of transmission;
10012 time zone of origination of transmission;
10015 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
10018 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
10021 sound recording title;
10024 ISRC code of the recording;
10027 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
10030 featured recording artist;
10033 retail album title;
10039 UPC code of the retail album;
10045 copyright owner information;
10048 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
10051 name of the service or entity;
10054 channel or program;
10057 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
10060 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
10063 time zone where the signal was received (user);
10066 unique user identifier;
10069 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
10074 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
10075 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
10076 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
10077 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
10078 Internet radio has to pay a
<emphasis>type of copyright fee
</emphasis>
10079 that terrestrial radio does not.
10082 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
10083 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
10084 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
10086 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks
</primary></indexterm>
10087 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
10089 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
10090 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
10091 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
10095 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
10096 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
10097 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
10098 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
10099 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
10100 webcasters asked the RIAA,
… <quote>How do you come up with a
10102 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
10103 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
10104 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
10105 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
10106 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
10107 business.
…</quote>
10109 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
10111 And the RIAA experts said,
<quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
10112 industry with thousands of webcasters,
<emphasis>we think it should be
10113 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
10114 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market
</emphasis>.
</quote> (Emphasis
10118 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'
/>
10120 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
10121 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
10122 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
10123 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
10124 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
10125 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
10126 effective to prevent it.
10129 <section id=
"corruptingcitizens">
10130 <title>Corrupting Citizens
</title>
10132 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
10134 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
10135 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
10138 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
10139 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
10140 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
10143 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
10144 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
10145 large number of citizens. According to
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>,
43 million
10146 Americans downloaded music in May
2002.
<footnote><para>
10147 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie,
<quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,
</quote> Pew
10148 Internet and American Life Project (
24 April
2001), available at
10149 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
46</ulink>.
10150 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that
37 million
10151 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early
2001.
10153 According to the RIAA,
10154 the behavior of those
43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
10155 set of rules that transform
20 percent of America into criminals. As the
10157 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
10158 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
10159 the world, but against students building search engines, and
10161 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
10162 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
10163 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
10165 response by the other.
10168 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
10169 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
10170 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
10171 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
10172 ($
15,
000,
000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
10173 paying all the money in the world in damages ($
250,
000 in legal fees)
10174 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
10175 ($
12,
000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
10176 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September
2003, the RIAA
10177 sued
261 individuals
—including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
10178 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
10179 was.
<footnote><para>
10181 Alex Pham,
<quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,
</quote> <citetitle>Los
10182 Angeles Times
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, Business.
10184 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
10185 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
10186 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $
2,
000
10187 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
10188 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
10189 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
10192 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition
</primary></indexterm>
10194 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
10195 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
10196 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
10197 consumption of alcohol was
1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
10198 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just
30 percent
10199 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10200 consumption was up to
70 percent of the preprohibition
10201 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10202 number were criminals.
<footnote><para>
10204 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel,
<quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10205 Prohibition,
</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review
</citetitle> 81, no.
2 (
1991):
242.
10208 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10209 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10210 narcotics that
7 percent (or
16 million) Americans now use.
<footnote><para>
10212 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10213 Reform Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st sess. (
5 March
2003) (statement of
10214 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10216 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in
1979 of
14 percent of
10217 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10218 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10219 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10220 cheat.
<footnote><para>
10222 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein,
<quote>Tax
10223 Compliance,
</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature
</citetitle> 36 (
1998):
818 (survey of
10224 compliance literature).
10226 We pride ourselves on our
<quote>free society,
</quote> but an endless array of
10227 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10228 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10230 <indexterm><primary>law schools
</primary></indexterm>
10232 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10233 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10234 students about the importance of
<quote>ethics.
</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10235 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10236 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10237 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10238 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10239 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10240 teach them how to behave ethically
—how to say no to bribes, or
10241 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10242 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10243 Americans
—more significantly in some parts of America than in
10244 others, but still, everywhere in America today
—can't live their
10245 lives both normally and legally, since
<quote>normally
</quote> entails a certain
10246 degree of illegality.
10249 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10250 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10251 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10252 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10253 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10254 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10255 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10256 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10257 to consider the alternative.
10261 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10262 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10263 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10264 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10265 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10266 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10269 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10270 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10271 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10272 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10273 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10274 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10275 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10276 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10277 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10278 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10279 introduced this different idea of
<quote>sharing.
</quote> We need to be able to
10280 call these twenty million Americans
<quote>citizens,
</quote> not
<quote>felons.
</quote>
10283 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10284 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10285 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10286 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10287 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10288 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10289 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10290 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10291 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10292 a nation of felons?
10295 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10298 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10299 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10300 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10301 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10304 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10305 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That
<quote>use
</quote> of the
10306 recordings is free.
10309 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10310 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10311 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am
<quote>free
</quote> to copy,
10312 or
<quote>rip,
</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10313 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that
<quote>freedom
</quote> was a
10314 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the
<quote>Rip, Mix, Burn
</quote>
10315 capacities of digital technologies.
10317 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda
</primary></indexterm>
10318 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>mix technology and
</secondary></indexterm>
10320 This
<quote>use
</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10321 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10322 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10323 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10324 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10325 Others
—the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10326 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10327 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10328 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10331 This use is enabled by unprotected media
—either CDs or records.
10332 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10333 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10334 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10335 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10336 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10337 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10338 on people's machines.
10341 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10342 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10343 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10344 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10345 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10346 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10348 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10349 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10350 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10351 plastic or were part of a massively complex
<quote>digital rights
10352 management
</quote> system.
10354 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'
/>
10356 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10357 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10358 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10359 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10360 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10361 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10362 freedom to move content easily?
10365 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10366 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10367 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10368 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10369 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10370 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10371 alternative
—namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10372 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10373 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10376 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10377 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10378 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10379 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10380 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10381 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10382 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10385 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10386 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10387 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10388 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10391 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10392 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10394 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10396 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10397 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10399 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation
</primary></indexterm>
10400 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'
><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by
</primary></indexterm>
10402 <emphasis role='strong'
>There's one more
</emphasis> aspect to this
10403 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10404 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10405 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10406 <quote>collateral damage
</quote> that
<quote>arises whenever you turn
10407 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.
</quote> This
10408 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10410 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
10412 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,
</quote> von Lohmann
10417 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10418 evaporate to one degree or another.
… If you're a copyright
10419 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10420 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10421 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10422 access?
… Our sensibilities change as soon as we think,
<quote>Oh, well,
10423 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.
</quote> Well, what this campaign
10424 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10425 American Internet-using population into
<quote>lawbreakers.
</quote>
10429 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10430 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10431 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10434 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in
2003 as the RIAA
10435 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10436 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10437 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10438 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10439 an Internet user is revealed.
10442 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10443 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10444 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10445 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10446 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10447 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10448 the family could be liable for $
2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10449 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10450 Jesse Jordan.
<footnote><para>
10452 See Frank Ahrens,
<quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10453 Mother in Calif.,
12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,
</quote>
10454 <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, E1; Chris Cobbs,
<quote>Worried Parents
10455 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10456 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10457 Being Sued,
</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune
</citetitle>,
30 August
2003, C1; Jefferson
10458 Graham,
<quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,
</quote> <citetitle>USA Today
</citetitle>,
15 September
10459 2003,
4D; John Schwartz,
<quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10460 Fan, Either,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
25 September
2003, C1; Margo Varadi,
<quote>Is
10461 Brianna a Criminal?
</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star
</citetitle>,
18 September
2003, P7.
10466 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10467 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10468 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.
<footnote><para>
10470 See
<quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10471 Some Methods Used,
</quote> CNN.com, available at
10472 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
47</ulink>.
10474 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10475 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10476 one of those MP3s will have the same
<quote>fingerprint.
</quote>
10479 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10480 friend gives a CD to your daughter
—a collection of songs just
10481 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10482 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10483 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10484 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10485 network is
<quote>cooperating
</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10486 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10487 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10488 as a
<quote>criminal.
</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10489 to deploy,
<footnote><para>
10491 See Jeff Adler,
<quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,
</quote>
10492 <citetitle>Boston Globe
</citetitle>,
18 May
2003, City Weekly,
1; Frank Ahrens,
<quote>Four
10493 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10494 Colleges,
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
4 April
2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10495 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,
</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10496 Monitor
</citetitle>,
2 September
2003,
20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas,
<quote>Music
10497 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10498 Lawsuit Possible,
</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune
</citetitle>,
16 July
2003,
1C; Beth Cox,
<quote>RIAA
10499 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,
</quote> <citetitle>Internet News
</citetitle>,
30 January
10500 2003, available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10501 #
48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista,
<quote>Download Warning
101: Freshman
10502 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10503 Sharing,
</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
11 August
2003, E11;
<quote>Raid, Letters
10504 Are Weapons at Universities,
</quote> <citetitle>USA Today
</citetitle>,
26 September
2000,
3D.
10506 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10507 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10509 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'
/>
10510 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
10512 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10513 a lawyer for her (at $
300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10514 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10515 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10516 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10517 this
<quote>contraband
</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10520 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10521 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10522 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10527 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10528 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10529 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10530 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10531 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10532 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10533 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10534 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10535 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10536 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10537 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10538 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10539 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10540 larger number of Americans than drug use.
… If forty to sixty
10541 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10542 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10547 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered
<quote>criminals
</quote> under
10548 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective
—
10549 securing rights to authors
—without these millions being
10550 considered
<quote>criminals,
</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10551 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10552 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10555 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10559 <part id=
"c-balances">
10560 <title>BALANCES
</title>
10563 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10565 <emphasis role='strong'
>So here's
</emphasis> the picture: You're
10566 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
10567 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
10568 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
10569 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10572 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10573 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10574 stop
—or before she understands just why she should
10575 stop
—the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10576 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10580 <emphasis role='strong'
>A war
</emphasis> about copyright rages all
10581 around
—and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
10582 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
10583 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
10584 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
10585 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
10586 that if let alone would burn itself out.
10589 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
10590 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
10591 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
10592 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
10593 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
10594 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
10595 made that is happening all around.
10598 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
10599 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
10600 gasoline onto this fire.
10603 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
10604 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
10605 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
10606 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
10609 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
10610 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
10611 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
10612 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
10613 success will require.
10617 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
10618 <chapter label=
"13" id=
"eldred">
10619 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
</title>
10620 <indexterm id=
"idxhawthornenathaniel" class='startofrange'
><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel
</primary></indexterm>
10622 <emphasis role='strong'
>In
1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
10623 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
10624 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
10625 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
10626 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
10627 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
10628 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
10631 It didn't work
—at least for his daughters. They didn't find
10632 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
10633 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
10634 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
10635 them available for free.
10637 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt5' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
10638 <indexterm><primary>Grimm fairy tales
</primary></indexterm>
10640 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
10641 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
10642 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
10643 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
10644 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
10645 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
10646 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
10647 many others, into a form more accessible
—technically
10648 accessible
—today.
10651 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
10652 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's
<citetitle>Scarlet Letter
</citetitle> had passed into the
10653 public domain in
1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
10654 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
10655 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
10656 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
10657 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
10658 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (
<citetitle>Cinderella
</citetitle>), sometimes not
10659 (
<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame
</citetitle>,
<citetitle>Treasure Planet
</citetitle>). These are all
10660 commercial publications of public domain works.
10662 <indexterm startref='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='endofrange'
/>
10663 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt5' class='endofrange'
/>
10665 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
10666 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
10667 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
10668 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
10669 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
10670 call the
<quote>noncommercial publishing industry,
</quote> which before the
10671 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
10672 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
10673 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
10674 generally.
<footnote><para>
10676 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
10677 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
10678 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers
—people who
10679 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
10680 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
10681 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
10682 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
10683 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
10684 Decency Act of
1996. It was partly because of the burden on
10685 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
10686 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
10687 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
10688 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
10689 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
10690 protect noncommercial pornographers.
</para></footnote>
10693 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In
1998, Robert Frost's
10694 collection of poems
<citetitle>New Hampshire
</citetitle> was slated to
10695 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
10696 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
10697 in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
10698 linkend=
"property-i"/>, in
1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
10699 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights
—this time by
10700 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
10701 than
1923 to his collection until
2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
10702 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
10703 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
10704 more than
1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
10706 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary
</primary></indexterm>
10707 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny
</primary></indexterm>
10710 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
10711 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
10712 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
10713 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
10714 <quote>copyrights should be forever.
</quote><footnote><para>
10716 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary
</primary></indexterm>
10717 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny
</primary></indexterm>
10718 The full text is:
<quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
10719 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
10720 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
10721 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
10722 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
10723 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
10724 Congress,
</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946,
9951-
2 (October
7,
1998).
10729 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
10730 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
10731 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
10732 second law passed in
1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
10733 of publishing would make Eldred a felon
—whether or not anyone
10734 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
10738 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
10740 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
10742 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
10743 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
10745 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
10749 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science
…
10750 by securing for limited Times to Authors
… exclusive Right to
10751 their
… Writings.
…
10755 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
10756 clause of Article I, section
8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
10757 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
10758 something
—for example, to regulate
<quote>commerce among the several
10759 states
</quote> or
<quote>declare War.
</quote> But here, the
<quote>something
</quote> is something quite
10760 specific
—to
<quote>promote
… Progress
</quote>—through means that
10761 are also specific
— by
<quote>securing
</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights
</quote> (i.e.,
10762 copyrights)
<quote>for limited Times.
</quote>
10764 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
10766 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
10767 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
10768 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
10769 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be
<quote>limited
</quote> will have
10770 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
10771 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
10772 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
10773 what the Constitution plainly forbids
—perpetual terms
<quote>on the
10774 installment plan,
</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
10777 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
10778 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
10779 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
10780 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
10781 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
10782 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
10783 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
10784 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
10785 this gravy train going.
10788 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
10789 government.
<quote>Corruption
</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
10790 bribed. Rather,
<quote>corruption
</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
10791 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
10792 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
10793 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
10794 do
—and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
10797 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
10798 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
10799 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
10800 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in
1963. His poetry
10801 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
10802 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
10803 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
10804 published by anyone for free.
10807 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $
100,
000 a year from
10808 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
10809 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
10810 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
10814 <quote>Next year,
</quote> the adviser announces,
<quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
10816 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
10817 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
10818 receiving the annual royalty check of $
100,
000 from the publishers of
10819 those works.
</quote>
10822 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,
</quote> she continues,
<quote>that
10823 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
10824 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
10825 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.
</quote>
10828 <quote>Hope?
</quote> a fellow board member says.
<quote>Can't we be doing something
10832 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,
</quote> the adviser responds.
<quote>We could contribute
10833 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
10834 they support the bill.
</quote>
10837 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
10838 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it.
<quote>How much
10839 would we get if this extension were passed?
</quote> you ask the adviser.
<quote>How
10840 much is it worth?
</quote>
10843 <quote>Well,
</quote> the adviser says,
<quote>if you're confident that you will continue
10844 to get at least $
100,
000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
10845 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (
6 percent),
10846 then this law would be worth $
1,
146,
000 to the estate.
</quote>
10849 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
10850 correct conclusion:
10853 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
10854 $
1,
000,
000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
10856 would assure that the bill was passed?
</quote>
10859 <quote>Absolutely,
</quote> the adviser responds.
<quote>It is worth it to you to
10861 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
10862 copyrights. Which for us means over $
1,
000,
000.
</quote>
10865 You quickly get the point
—you as the member of the board and, I
10866 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
10867 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
10868 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
10869 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
10870 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
10872 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
10873 the copyright term extended.
10876 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
10877 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
10878 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
10881 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
10883 Term Extension Act, this
<quote>theory
</quote> about incentives was proved
10884 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
10885 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
10886 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
10887 contributions.
<footnote><para>
10888 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press,
<quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
10889 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators
20 More Years,
</quote>
10890 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune
</citetitle>,
17 October
1998,
22.
10892 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
10893 $
1.5 million lobbying in the
1998 election cycle. They paid out more
10894 than $
200,
000 in campaign contributions.
<footnote><para>
10895 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown,
<quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
10896 Age,
</quote> available at
10897 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
49</ulink>.
10899 Disney is estimated to have
10900 contributed more than $
800,
000 to reelection campaigns in the
10901 cycle.
<footnote><para>
10903 Alan K. Ota,
<quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,
</quote>
10904 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week
</citetitle>,
8 August
1990, available at
10905 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
50</ulink>.
10910 <emphasis role='strong'
>Constitutional law
</emphasis> is not oblivious
10911 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
10912 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
10913 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
10914 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
10915 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
10916 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
10917 constitutional requirement that terms be
<quote>limited.
</quote> If
10918 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
10922 It was also my judgment that
<emphasis>this
</emphasis> Supreme Court
10923 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
10924 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
10925 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
10926 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
10927 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
10930 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
10931 decision in
1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
10935 Since
1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
10936 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
10937 power to regulate only
<quote>commerce among the several states
</quote> (aka
10939 commerce
</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
10940 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
10945 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
10946 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
10947 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
10948 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
10949 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
10951 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.
</primary></indexterm>
10953 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
10954 that in
<citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>. The government had
10955 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
10956 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
10957 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
10958 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
10959 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
10960 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
10961 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
10962 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
10963 position to second-guess Congress.
10966 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,
</quote>
10967 the Chief Justice wrote.
<footnote><para>
10968 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>,
514 U.S.
549,
564 (
1995).
10970 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
10971 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
10972 Congress's power. The decision in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
10973 later in
<citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Morrison
</citetitle>.
<footnote><para>
10975 <citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Morrison
</citetitle>,
529 U.S.
598 (
2000).
10979 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
10980 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.
<footnote><para>
10982 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
10983 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
10984 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
10985 by the government would allow the government unending power to
10986 regulate commerce
—the limitation to interstate commerce
10987 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
10988 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
10989 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights
—the
10990 limitation to
<quote>limited times
</quote> notwithstanding.
10992 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
10993 yield the conclusion that Congress
10994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
10995 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
10996 term, then there would be no
<quote>stopping point
</quote> to Congress's power over
10997 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
10998 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
10999 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
11000 term of existing copyrights.
11003 <emphasis>If
</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>
11004 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> stood for
11005 politics
—a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
11006 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
11007 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
11008 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
11009 demonstrating the
<quote>fidelity
</quote> in such an interpretation of the
11010 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
11011 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
11012 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
11013 were going to be petty politicians.
11015 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in
</secondary></indexterm>
11016 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of
</secondary></indexterm>
11017 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
11018 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
11020 <emphasis role='strong'
>Now let's pause
</emphasis> for a moment to
11021 make sure we understand what the argument in
11022 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
11023 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
11024 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
11025 piracy
—piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
11026 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
11027 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
11028 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
11029 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
11030 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
11031 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
11032 power
—expressed through the power of lobbyists' money
—to
11033 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
11034 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
11035 piracy that affects us all.
11037 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association
</primary></indexterm>
11039 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
11041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
11042 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
11043 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than
<quote>legal piracy.
</quote><footnote><para>
11045 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle>
11046 v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618), n
.10, available
11047 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
51</ulink>.
11049 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
11050 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
11051 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
11055 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
11057 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
11059 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
11060 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
11061 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
11062 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
11063 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
11064 bought to extend them again.
11067 <emphasis role='strong'
>It is valuable
</emphasis> copyrights that are
11068 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
11069 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.
</quote> These works are too valuable for
11070 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
11071 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
11072 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
11073 the
1920s and
1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
11074 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
11075 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
11076 and no longer available as a result.
11079 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (
1923 to
11080 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
11081 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
11082 copyright holders for that
2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
11083 But the law and its effect were not limited to that
2 percent. The law
11084 extended the terms of copyright generally.
<footnote><para>
11085 <!-- f10. --> The figure of
2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
11087 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
11088 of Petitioners,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
7, available at
11089 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
52</ulink>.
11094 Think practically about the consequence of this
11095 extension
—practically,
11096 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
11098 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
11099 work. In
1930,
10,
047 books were published. In
2000,
174 of those
11100 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
11101 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
11103 9,
873. What would you have to do?
11105 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
11107 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the
9,
873 books were
11108 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
11109 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
11110 titles and authors of the
9,
873 books with the copyright registration
11111 and renewal records for works published in
1930. That will produce a
11112 list of books still under copyright.
11115 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
11116 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
11119 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
11121 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
11122 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
11123 being at least a list?
11126 But there is no list. There may be a name from
1930, and then in
11127 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
11129 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
11131 of such records
—especially since the person who registered is
11132 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about
1930!
11135 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,
</quote> the
11136 apologists for the system respond.
<quote>Why should there be a list of
11137 copyright owners?
</quote>
11140 Well, actually, if you think about it, there
<emphasis>are
</emphasis>
11141 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
11142 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
11143 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
11144 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
11145 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
11146 what tangible property.
11149 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
11150 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
11151 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
11153 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
11154 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
11155 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
11157 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
11158 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
11159 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
11160 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
11161 know quite well who owns what property.
11164 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
11165 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
11167 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
11168 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
11169 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
11170 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
11171 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
11172 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
11173 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
11176 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
11177 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
11179 for other creative works is much more dire.
11181 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'
><primary>Agee, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
11182 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios
</primary></indexterm>
11183 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films
</primary></indexterm>
11184 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The
</primary></indexterm>
11186 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
11187 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
11188 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
11189 made between
1921 and
1951. Only one of these films,
<citetitle>The Lucky Dog
</citetitle>, is
11190 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after
1923
11191 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
11192 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
11193 money. According to one estimate,
<quote>Roach has sold about
60,
000
11194 videocassettes and
50,
000 DVDs of the duo's silent
11195 films.
</quote><footnote><para>
11197 See David G. Savage,
<quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,
</quote>
11198 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times
</citetitle>,
6 October
2002; David Streitfeld,
<quote>Classic Movies,
11199 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
11200 Down Copyright Extension,
</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune
</citetitle>,
9 October
2002.
11204 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
11205 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
11206 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11207 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11210 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11212 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11213 any continuing commercial value. The rest
—to the extent it
11214 survives at all
—sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11215 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11216 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11217 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11218 work available for distribution.
11221 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11222 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11223 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11224 it cost more than $
10,
000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11225 film in
1993, it can now cost as little as $
100 to digitize one hour of
11226 mm film.
<footnote><para>
11228 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11229 Supporting the Petitoners,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537
11230 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618),
12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11231 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle>
11232 v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>, available at
11233 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
53</ulink>.
11238 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11240 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11241 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11242 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11243 locate the copyright owner.
11246 Or more accurately,
<emphasis>owners
</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11247 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11248 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11249 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11250 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11251 to these films is exceptionally high.
11254 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11255 copyright owner when she shows up?
</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11256 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11257 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11258 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11259 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11260 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11261 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11262 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11265 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11267 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11268 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11270 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11271 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11272 the copyright expires.
11274 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'
/>
11276 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11277 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11278 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11280 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11284 <emphasis role='strong'
>Of all the
</emphasis> creative work produced
11285 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11286 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11287 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11288 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11289 the copyright acts as an
<quote>engine of free expression.
</quote>
11292 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11293 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11295 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11296 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11297 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11299 the commercial life ends.
11302 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11303 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes
& Noble, and
11304 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11306 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11308 night watching a
1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11309 of culture is important and valuable
—for entertainment but also, and
11310 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11311 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11312 have, we need to have access to this history.
11315 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11317 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11318 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11319 this context do no good.
11322 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11323 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11324 <emphasis>copyright-related use
</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11325 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11326 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11327 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11328 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11329 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11330 was independent of copyright law.
11333 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11334 a film
—the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs
—were
11335 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11336 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11337 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11338 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11339 market didn't have more to offer.
11342 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11343 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11344 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11345 would not have interfered with anything.
11348 But this situation has now changed.
11350 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'
><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
11352 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11353 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11354 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11355 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11356 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11357 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11358 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11359 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11360 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11361 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11364 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11365 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11366 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11367 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11368 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11369 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11370 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11371 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11372 written for a radically different context.
11375 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11376 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11377 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11378 <emphasis>copyright
</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11379 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11380 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11381 context, copyright is serving no purpose
<emphasis>at all
</emphasis>
11382 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11383 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11386 You may well ask,
<quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11387 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11388 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11389 culture widely?
</quote>
11392 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11393 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes
& Noble
11394 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11395 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11396 of a library is to serve what
<quote>the market
</quote> would demand. But if you
11397 think the role of a library is bigger than this
—if you think its
11398 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11399 particular bit of that culture or not
—then we can't count on the
11400 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11402 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'
/>
11404 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11405 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11406 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11407 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11409 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11410 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11411 culture,
94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11412 and
1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11413 commercial market, if access is a value, then
6 percent is a failure
11414 to provide that value.
<footnote><para>
11416 Jason Schultz,
<quote>The Myth of the
1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,
</quote> 20
11417 December
2002, available at
11418 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
54</ulink>.
11423 <emphasis role='strong'
>In January
1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11424 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11425 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11426 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (
1)
11427 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11428 <quote>limited Times
</quote> requirement, and (
2) that extending terms
11429 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11432 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11433 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11434 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11435 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11436 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11439 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11440 copyrights be for
<quote>limited Times
</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11441 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11442 <quote>stopping point
</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11443 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11444 terms that are
<quote>limited.
</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11445 to interpret the term
<quote>limited Times
</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11446 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11447 power to extend existing terms.
11450 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11451 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11452 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11453 whole, where the court will sit
<quote>en banc
</quote> to hear the case.
11455 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David
</primary></indexterm>
11457 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11458 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11460 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11461 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11462 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11463 overstepped its bounds.
11466 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11467 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11468 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11469 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11470 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11473 But in February
2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11474 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11475 was set for October of
2002. The summer would be spent writing
11476 briefs and preparing for argument.
11479 <emphasis role='strong'
>It is over
</emphasis> a year later as I write
11480 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
11481 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
11482 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
11483 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
11484 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
11485 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
11486 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
11487 client, Eric Eldred.
11490 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11491 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11492 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11495 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey
</primary></indexterm>
11497 <emphasis role='strong'
>The mistake
</emphasis> was made early, though
11498 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
11499 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
11500 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
11501 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
11502 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11503 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11504 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11505 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11507 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11508 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan
</primary></indexterm>
11509 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey
</primary></indexterm>
11511 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11512 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11513 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11514 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11515 told me, if we could make the issue seem
<quote>important
</quote> to the Supreme
11516 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11517 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against
<quote>the
11518 most powerful media companies in the world.
</quote>
11521 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
11522 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
11523 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
11524 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
11525 <quote>right
</quote> as in
<quote>true,
</quote> I thought, but it is
<quote>wrong
</quote> as in
<quote>it just shouldn't be
11526 that way.
</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
11527 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
11528 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
11530 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
11531 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
11533 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
11534 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
11535 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
11537 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
11538 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
11539 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
11542 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
11543 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
11544 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
11545 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
11546 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
11547 why it was unconstitutional.
11550 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
11552 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
11553 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
11554 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
11555 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
11556 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
11557 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
11558 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
11559 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
11560 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
11561 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
11562 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
11563 <emphasis>law
</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
11564 the widest range of credible critics
—credible not because they
11565 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
11566 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
11568 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum
</primary></indexterm>
11569 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis
</primary></indexterm>
11571 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
11572 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
11573 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
11574 Congress. In November
1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
11575 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
11576 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
11577 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
11578 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
11579 to get bogged down?
</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
11580 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
11581 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
11582 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
11585 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
11586 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
11587 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
11588 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
11589 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
11590 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
11592 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
11593 <indexterm><primary>Intel
</primary></indexterm>
11594 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
11595 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum
</primary></indexterm>
11597 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
11598 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
11600 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
11601 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/ Linux
11602 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
11603 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
11604 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
11605 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
11606 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
11607 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
11609 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries
</primary></indexterm>
11610 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union
</primary></indexterm>
11612 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
11613 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
11614 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
11615 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
11617 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios
</primary></indexterm>
11619 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
11620 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
11621 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
11622 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
11625 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George
</primary></indexterm>
11626 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
11627 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James
</primary></indexterm>
11628 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
11629 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton
</primary></indexterm>
11631 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
11632 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
11633 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
11634 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
11635 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
11636 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
11637 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
11638 nothing more than
<quote>rent-seeking
</quote>—the fancy term economists use
11639 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
11641 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
11642 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan
</primary></indexterm>
11643 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen
</primary></indexterm>
11644 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
11646 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
11647 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
11648 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
11649 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
11650 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
11651 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
11652 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
11653 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
11655 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
11656 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
11657 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
11659 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
11661 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
11662 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
11663 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
11664 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
11665 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
11666 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
11667 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
11668 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
11669 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
11670 confidence in our argument.
11673 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
11674 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these
<quote>friends
</quote> included
11675 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
11676 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
11680 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
11681 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either
—they
11682 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
11683 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
11684 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
11685 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
11688 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George
</primary></indexterm>
11690 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
11691 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
11692 Dr. Seuss's work
— better than allowing it to fall into the
11693 public domain
—because if this creativity were in the public
11694 domain, then people could use it to
<quote>glorify drugs or to create
11695 pornography.
</quote><footnote><para>
11697 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al.,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537
11698 U.S. (
2003) (No.
01-
618),
19.
11700 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
11701 <quote>protection
</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
11702 to license
<citetitle>Porgy and Bess
</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
11703 Americans in the cast.
<footnote><para>
11705 Dinitia Smith,
<quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
11706 Mouse Joins the Fray,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
28 March
1998, B7.
11709 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
11710 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
11711 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
11714 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
11715 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
11716 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
11717 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
11718 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say,
<quote>Give us twenty years
11719 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
11720 better with them than anyone else.
</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
11721 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
11722 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
11723 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
11726 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
11727 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
11728 copyrights
—extensions that would further concentrate the market;
11729 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
11730 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
11733 <emphasis role='strong'
>Between February
</emphasis> and October, there
11734 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
11735 I set the strategy.
11737 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.
</primary></indexterm>
11738 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day
</primary></indexterm>
11740 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
11741 called
<quote>the Conservatives.
</quote> The other we called
<quote>the Rest.
</quote> The
11742 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
11743 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
11744 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
11745 five who had supported the
<citetitle>Lopez/Morrison
</citetitle> line
11746 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
11747 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
11749 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
11750 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'
><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader
</primary></indexterm>
11752 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
11753 Congress's power. These four
—Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
11754 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer
—had repeatedly argued that
11756 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
11757 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
11758 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
11759 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
11760 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
11761 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
11764 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
11765 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
11766 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
11767 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
11768 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
11769 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
11770 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
11771 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
11774 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
11776 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
11777 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
11778 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
11779 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
11780 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
11781 these retrospective extensions.
11783 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'
/>
11785 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
11786 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
11787 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
11788 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
11789 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
11790 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
11793 This analysis of
<quote>the Rest
</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
11794 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
11795 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
11796 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
11797 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation
—the
11798 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
11799 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
11800 powers have limits.
11803 This then was the core of our strategy
—a strategy for which I am
11804 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
11805 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>
11806 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
11807 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
11808 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
11809 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
11810 supposed to be
<quote>limited.
</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
11811 reconcile
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> with
11812 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
11813 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
11817 <emphasis role='strong'
>The argument
</emphasis> on the government's
11818 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
11819 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
11820 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
11821 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
11822 that practice is unconstitutional.
11825 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
11826 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in
1831
11827 and in
1909. And of course, in
1962, Congress began extending
11829 terms regularly
—eleven times in forty years.
11832 But this
<quote>consistency
</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
11834 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
11835 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
11836 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
11838 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
11840 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
11841 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
11843 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
11844 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
11847 <emphasis role='strong'
>Oral argument
</emphasis> was scheduled for the
11848 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
11849 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
11850 <quote>mooted
</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
11852 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
11853 help in the case. Such
<quote>moots
</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
11854 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
11857 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
11858 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
11859 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
11860 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
11862 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
11863 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
11866 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11867 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
11868 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
11870 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
11871 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
11872 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
11873 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
11876 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
11877 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
11878 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
11879 the harm
—passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
11880 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.
</quote>
11882 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11884 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
11885 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
11886 right thing
—not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
11887 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
11888 does the right thing
—not because of politics but because it is right. As
11889 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
11890 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
11891 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
11894 <emphasis role='strong'
>The night before
</emphasis> the argument, a
11895 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
11896 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
11897 culture. Hundreds stood in line
11899 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
11900 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
11901 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
11904 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
11905 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
11906 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
11907 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
11909 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
11910 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
11911 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
11912 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
11913 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
11914 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
11915 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
11916 family of the Justices.
11919 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
11920 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
11921 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
11922 those enumerated powers had any limit.
11924 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day
</primary></indexterm>
11926 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
11927 The history was bothering her.
11931 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
11932 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
11933 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
11934 practice that began with the very first act.
11938 She was quite willing to concede
<quote>that this flies directly in the face
11939 of what the framers had in mind.
</quote> But my response again and again
11940 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
11944 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
11945 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
11946 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
11947 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
11952 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
11953 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
11954 Kennedy, who observed,
11958 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
11959 the '
76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
11960 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
11961 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
11962 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
11966 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
11972 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
11973 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
11974 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
11975 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
11976 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
11979 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11981 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
11982 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
11983 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
11984 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
11985 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
11988 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
11989 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> ruling,
11990 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
11993 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
11994 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
11996 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
12000 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
12001 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
12004 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
12005 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
12007 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
12008 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
12009 into the Copyright Clause.
12012 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.
</primary></indexterm>
12014 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
12015 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
12016 asked Solicitor General Olson,
12020 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12021 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
12022 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
12023 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12028 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
12029 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
12030 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
12031 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
12032 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
12033 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
12034 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
12035 Patent Clause
— indeed, the very first case striking a law of
12036 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
12037 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
12041 <emphasis role='strong'
>As I left
</emphasis> the court that day, I
12042 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
12043 hundred questions I wished I had
12045 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
12046 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
12050 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
12051 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
12052 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
12053 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
12054 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
12055 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
12056 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
12057 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
12058 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
12059 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
12060 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court
—in particular,
12061 the Conservatives
—would feel itself constrained by the rule of
12062 law that it had established elsewhere.
12065 <emphasis role='strong'
>The morning
</emphasis> of January
15,
2003, I
12066 was five minutes late to the office and missed the
7:
00 A.M. call from
12067 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
12068 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
12069 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
12070 majority. There were two dissents.
12073 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
12074 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
12075 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
12078 My
<emphasis>reasoning
</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
12079 money in the world against
<emphasis>reasoning
</emphasis>. And here
12080 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
12084 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
12085 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
12086 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
12087 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
12088 even appear in the Court's opinion.
12090 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader
</primary></indexterm>
12093 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
12094 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
12095 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
12096 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
12099 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable
—for her, and for Justice
12100 Souter. Neither believes in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
12101 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
12102 they had worked so hard to defeat.
12105 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
12106 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
12107 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
12108 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
12109 reconcile the two simply
<emphasis>by not addressing the
12110 argument
</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
12111 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
12112 followed from the
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
12113 be limited, but in this context it would not.
12116 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
12117 they would respect? By what right did they
—the silent
12118 five
—get to select the part of the Constitution they would
12119 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
12120 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
12121 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
12122 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
12123 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
12124 the system we have.
12126 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12128 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
12129 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
12130 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
12131 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
12132 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
12133 the Court discounted the parallel
—without explaining how the
12134 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
12135 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
12136 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
12138 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12140 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
12141 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
12142 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
12143 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
12144 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author
99.8
12145 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
12146 that the actual number was
99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
12147 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
12148 <quote>limited,
</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
12149 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
12152 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
12153 because neither believed in the
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
12154 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
12155 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
12156 Sentelle. It was
<citetitle>Hamlet
</citetitle> without the Prince.
12159 <emphasis role='strong'
>Defeat brings depression
</emphasis>. They say
12160 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
12161 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
12164 <indexterm><primary>originalism
</primary></indexterm>
12166 It was first anger with the five
<quote>Conservatives.
</quote> It would have been
12167 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> didn't
12168 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
12169 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
12170 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
12171 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
12172 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is
<quote>originalism
</quote>—to
12173 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
12174 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
12175 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> and many other
<quote>originalist
</quote> rulings. Where was their
12176 <quote>originalism
</quote> now?
12179 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
12180 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
12181 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
12182 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
12184 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
12185 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
12186 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
12187 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
12188 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
12189 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
12190 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
12194 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
12196 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
12199 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12201 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
12202 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
12203 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
12204 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
12205 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
12206 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12207 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12208 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12209 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12212 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12213 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12214 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12215 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12216 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12217 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12218 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12219 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12220 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12221 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12222 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12223 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12224 effort to persuade; but I
12225 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12226 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12227 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12228 should decide the issue.
12230 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12231 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
12233 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12234 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12238 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12239 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12240 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12241 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12244 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12245 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12246 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12247 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12250 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
12252 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12253 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12254 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12255 case was a mistake.
<quote>The Court is not ready,
</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12256 issue should not be raised until it is.
12259 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12260 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12261 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12262 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12263 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12264 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12265 this case
—a decision I had made four years before
—was wrong.
12268 <emphasis role='strong'
>While the reaction
</emphasis> to the Sonny
12269 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12270 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12271 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12272 that battle over ideas. Where
12274 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12275 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12276 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12277 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12278 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12279 harmful law.
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12283 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12284 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12285 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12286 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12287 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12288 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12292 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12293 hilarious images
—of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12294 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced on the next page
12295 (
<xref linkend=
"fig-18"/>). The
<quote>powerful and wealthy
</quote> line is a bit
12296 unfair. But the punch in the face felt exactly like that.
12297 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben
</primary></indexterm>
12299 <figure id=
"fig-18">
12300 <title>Tom the Dancing Bug cartoon
</title>
12301 <graphic fileref=
"images/18.png"></graphic>
12302 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben
</primary></indexterm>
12305 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12306 quote from
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>. That
<quote>grand experiment
</quote> we call the
12307 <quote>public domain
</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think,
<quote>Honey,
12308 I shrunk the Constitution.
</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12309 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12310 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12311 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12313 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12315 <chapter label=
"14" id=
"eldred-ii">
12316 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
</title>
12318 <emphasis role='strong'
>The day
</emphasis>
12319 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12320 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12321 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> was denied
—meaning the case was
12322 really finally over
—fate would have it that I was giving a
12323 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12324 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12325 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12326 wrote an op-ed piece.
12328 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12330 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12331 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12332 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12333 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12334 Justice Kennedy:
<quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12335 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12336 that.
</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12337 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12340 <citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12341 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12342 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12343 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12344 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12345 the work passed into the public domain.
12348 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12349 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12350 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12353 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12354 is either the
<quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act
</quote> or the
<quote>Copyright
12355 Term Deregulation Act.
</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12356 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12357 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12358 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $
1. But for
12359 everything else, let the content go.
12361 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
12363 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12364 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12365 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12366 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12367 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12368 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12369 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12370 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12371 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12372 the stupid harm of the present system.
12375 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12376 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12377 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12378 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12379 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12380 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12381 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12382 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12383 where copyright owners could be identified.
12385 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
12386 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
12388 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12389 As I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
12390 linkend=
"property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12391 removed in
1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12392 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.
<footnote><para>
12394 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law
</primary></indexterm>
12395 Until the
1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12396 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12397 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12398 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the
1908 act,
12399 every text of the Convention has provided that
<quote>the enjoyment and the
12400 exercise
</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention
<quote>shall not be subject
12401 to any formality.
</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12402 embodied in Article
5(
2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12403 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12404 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12405 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12406 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12407 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12408 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12409 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12410 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein,
<citetitle>International
12411 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials
</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12412 Press,
2001),
153–54.
</para></footnote>
12413 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a
<quote>natural right.
</quote> Natural
12414 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12415 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12416 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12417 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12418 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12421 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12422 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12423 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12424 <quote>Walt Disney creativity
</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12425 know what's protected and what's not.
12427 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
12429 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12430 Berlin in
1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12431 Convention in
1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12432 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12433 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12434 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12435 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an
<citetitle>i
</citetitle> or cross a
12436 <citetitle>t
</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12439 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12440 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12441 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12442 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12443 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12444 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12447 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12448 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12449 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12450 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12452 imposed upon creators.
12455 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in
1908, there was
12456 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12458 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12459 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12460 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12461 the government. He has a property right over the table
<quote>naturally,
</quote>
12462 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12463 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12467 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12468 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12469 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12470 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12471 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12472 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12476 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12477 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12478 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12479 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12480 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12481 important reason to secure registration
—both because it makes
12482 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12483 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12484 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12485 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12486 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12487 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12488 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12489 system of protection for property generally.
12492 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12493 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12494 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12495 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12496 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12497 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12498 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12499 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12501 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12502 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12503 <emphasis>lawyer
</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12504 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
12507 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12508 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12509 didn't
<quote>get.
</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
12510 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
12511 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be,
<quote>short,
</quote> then this
12512 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
12513 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
12514 be presumptively uncontrolled.
12517 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
12518 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
12519 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
12520 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
12521 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
12522 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
12523 seen before
<emphasis>because there are no formalities
</emphasis>.
12526 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
12527 it is worth $
1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
12528 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
12529 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
12530 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
12533 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
12534 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
12535 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
12536 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
12537 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $
1 to you.
12540 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
12541 registering the work mean that the $
1 is really misleading? Isn't the
12542 hassle worth more than $
1? Isn't that the real problem with
12546 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
12547 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
12548 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
12550 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
12551 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
12552 address the real problem of
<emphasis>governments
</emphasis> standing
12553 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
12554 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
12555 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
12556 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
12557 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
12558 upon historical data, that system would move up to
98 percent of
12559 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
12560 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
12562 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
12564 <emphasis role='strong'
>When Steve Forbes
</emphasis> endorsed the
12565 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
12566 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
12567 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
12568 willing to take the first step.
12570 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe
</primary></indexterm>
12572 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
12573 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
12574 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
12575 possible. In May
2003, it looked as if the bill would be
12576 introduced. On May
16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog,
<quote>we are
12577 close.
</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
12578 something good might happen here.
12581 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
12582 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
12583 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
12584 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
12585 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
12586 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
12589 The MPAA argued first that Congress had
<quote>firmly rejected the central
12590 concept in the proposed bill
</quote>—that copyrights be renewed. That
12591 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's
<quote>firm rejection
</quote> had occurred
12592 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
12593 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
12594 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
12595 owners
—apparently those who could not afford the $
1 fee. Third,
12596 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
12597 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
12598 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
12599 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
12600 off the extended term unless the $
1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
12601 argued that the bill would impose
<quote>enormous
</quote> costs, since a
12602 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
12603 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
12604 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
12605 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
12606 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
12607 film is a valid derivative use.
12610 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
12611 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
12612 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
12613 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
12614 or not
—a controversial claim in any case
—unless they know
12615 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
12618 <emphasis role='strong'
>At the beginning
</emphasis> of this book, I
12619 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
12620 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
12621 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
12622 opposition
—the power of the side that fought to defend the
12623 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
12624 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
12625 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
12628 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
12629 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
12630 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
12631 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
12636 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
12637 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
12638 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
12639 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
12640 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
12641 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
12642 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
12643 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
12644 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
12645 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
12647 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin
</primary></indexterm>
12649 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
12650 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
12651 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
12652 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
12653 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
12654 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the
<quote>Dark
12655 Content
</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
12656 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
12659 What does this industry really want?
12662 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
12663 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
12664 protecting
<emphasis>their
</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
12665 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
12666 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
12667 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
12668 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
12669 content that doesn't require
<emphasis>their
</emphasis> permission
12673 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
12674 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
12675 its aim not the protection of
<quote>property
</quote> but the rejection of a
12676 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
12677 theirs.
<emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
12681 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
12682 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
12684 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
12685 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
12686 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
12687 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
12688 and to share its own creation.
12690 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
12691 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
12693 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
12694 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
12695 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
12696 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
12697 block the progress of others.
12700 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
12701 <quote>property
</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
12702 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
12703 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing
<quote>permission
12704 society.
</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
12705 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
12706 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
12708 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
12711 <chapter label=
"15" id=
"c-conclusion">
12712 <title>CONCLUSION
</title>
12713 <indexterm id=
"idxantiretroviraldrugs" class='startofrange'
><primary>antiretroviral drugs
</primary></indexterm>
12714 <indexterm id=
"idxhivaidstherapies" class='startofrange'
><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies
</primary></indexterm>
12715 <indexterm id=
"idxafricahivmed" class='startofrange'
><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in
</primary></indexterm>
12717 <emphasis role='strong'
>There are more
</emphasis> than
35 million
12718 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
12719 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
12720 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
12721 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
12724 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
12725 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
12726 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
12727 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
12728 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
12729 the disease almost invisible.
12732 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
12733 United States, they cost between $
10,
000 and $
15,
000 per person per
12734 year. Today, some cost $
25,
000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
12735 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
12737 $
15,
000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
12738 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.
<footnote><para>
12739 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights,
<quote>Final Report: Integrating
12740 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy
</quote> (London,
2002),
12742 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
12744 issued
9 July
2002, only
230,
000 of the
6 million who need drugs in
12745 the developing world receive them
—and half of them are in Brazil.
12749 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
12750 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
12751 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
12752 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
12753 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
12754 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
12755 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
12758 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
12759 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
12760 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
12761 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
12762 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
12763 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
12764 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
12765 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
12769 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
12770 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
12771 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
12772 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
12773 costs significantly below the market price.
12776 In
1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
12777 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
12778 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
12779 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
12780 Africa from India. This is called
<quote>parallel importation,
</quote> and it is
12781 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
12782 permitted within the European Union.
<footnote>
12785 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite,
<citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
12786 Owns the Knowledge Economy?
</citetitle> (New York: The New Press,
2003),
37.
12787 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John
</primary></indexterm>
12788 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
12792 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
12793 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
12794 characterized it,
<quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa
…
12795 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
12796 imports.
</quote><footnote><para>
12798 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI),
<citetitle>Patent
12799 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12800 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12801 Organization
</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.,
2000),
14, available at
12802 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
56</ulink>. For a
12803 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
12804 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
12805 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep.,
1st sess.,
12806 Ser. No.
106-
126 (
22 July
1999),
150–57 (statement of James
12809 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
12810 government asked South Africa to change the law
—and to add
12811 pressure to that request, in
1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
12812 possible trade sanctions.
12813 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
12814 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
12815 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
12816 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
12817 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
12818 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
12819 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
12820 patent
— pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
12821 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
12822 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
12823 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.
<footnote><para>
12825 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI),
<citetitle>Patent
12826 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12827 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12828 Organization
</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.,
2000),
15.
</para></footnote>
12831 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
12832 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
12833 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
12834 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
12835 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
12836 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
12837 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
12838 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
12841 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
12842 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
12843 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
12844 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
12845 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
12846 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save
15 to
30 million lives.
12849 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
12850 profits of United States drug companies
—at least, not substantially. It
12851 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
12852 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
12853 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
12854 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
12858 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
12859 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
12861 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
12862 about the sanctity of property.
<footnote><para>
12864 See Sabin Russell,
<quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
12865 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,
</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
24
12866 May
1999, A1, available at
12867 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
57</ulink>
12868 (
<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
12869 system of intellectual property protection
</quote>); Robert Weissman,
<quote>AIDS
12870 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
12871 Medicines,
</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus
</citetitle> 4:
23 (August
1999), available at
12872 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
58</ulink>
12873 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson,
<quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
12874 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
12875 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,
</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
12876 Symposium Journal
</citetitle> (Spring
2001):
175.
12877 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
12879 It was because
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> would be violated that these
12880 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
12881 importance of
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> that led these government actors
12882 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
12885 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
12886 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
12887 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
12888 direct cost would be to speed the death of
15 to
30 million Africans,
12889 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the
<quote>sanctity
</quote> of an
12890 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
12891 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
12892 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
12895 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
12896 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
12897 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
12898 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
12899 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system
—
12900 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
12903 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
12904 drug companies would love
—they say, and I believe them
—to
12905 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
12906 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
12907 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
12908 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
12911 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
12912 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
12913 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask,
<quote>How
12914 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $
1 a pill, but the same
12915 drug would cost an American $
1,
500?
</quote> Because there is no
<quote>sound
12916 bite
</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
12917 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
12918 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
12919 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
12920 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
12921 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
12922 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal
—the sanctity of an
12923 idea called
<quote>intellectual property.
</quote>
12926 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
12927 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
12928 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
12929 What is the argument?
12932 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
12933 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
12934 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
12935 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
12936 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
12937 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
12938 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
12939 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
12940 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
12941 were balanced in just this sense.
12944 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
12945 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
12946 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
12947 our tradition, now reigns in this culture
—bizarrely, and with
12948 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
12949 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
12951 <indexterm startref=
"idxafricahivmed" class='endofrange'
/>
12952 <indexterm startref=
"idxhivaidstherapies" class='endofrange'
/>
12953 <indexterm startref=
"idxantiretroviraldrugs" class='endofrange'
/>
12955 <emphasis role='strong'
>A simple idea
</emphasis> blinds us, and under
12956 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
12957 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
12958 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
12959 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
12960 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
12961 control of that property removes our
12962 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
12963 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
12964 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
12965 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
12966 this common sense open its eyes.
12969 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
12970 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
12971 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
12972 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
12973 to fight
<quote>piracy,
</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
12974 the idea of
<quote>creative property,
</quote> while transforming real creators into
12975 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
12976 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
12977 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
12978 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
12979 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
12980 produce the
<quote>perfect storm
</quote> for free culture.
12982 <indexterm><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>public projects in
</secondary></indexterm>
12983 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)
</primary></indexterm>
12984 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust
</primary></indexterm>
12985 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web
</primary></indexterm>
12986 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System
</primary></indexterm>
12987 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
12988 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'
><primary>biomedical research
</primary></indexterm>
12990 <emphasis role='strong'
>In August
2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
12991 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
12992 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.
<footnote><para>
12993 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim,
<quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
12994 August
2003, E1, available at
12995 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
59</ulink>; William New,
<quote>Global Group's
12996 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,
</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
12997 Daily
</citetitle>,
19 August
2003, available at
12998 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
60</ulink>; William New,
<quote>U.S. Official
12999 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,
</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13000 Daily
</citetitle>,
19 August
2003, available at
13001 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
61</ulink>.
13003 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
13004 a meeting to discuss
<quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
13005 goods.
</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
13006 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
13007 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
13008 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
13009 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
13010 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
13011 that I describe in the Afterword. It included a project to develop
13012 single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs), which are thought to have
13013 great significance in biomedical research. (That nonprofit project
13014 comprised a consortium of the Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and
13015 technological companies, including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
13016 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
13017 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
13018 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
13019 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
13020 in the early
1980s. And it included
<quote>open source and free software.
</quote>
13021 <indexterm><primary>academic journals
</primary></indexterm>
13022 <indexterm><primary>IBM
</primary></indexterm>
13023 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)
</primary></indexterm>
13025 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'
/>
13027 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
13028 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
13029 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
13030 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
13031 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
13034 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.
<footnote><para>
13035 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
13038 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
13039 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
13040 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
13041 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
13045 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
13046 about WIPO. In February
2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
13047 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
13048 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
13049 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
13050 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
13051 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
13052 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
13053 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
13054 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
13055 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
13056 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
13057 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
13058 talk about an
<quote>Information Society
</quote> unless one also talked about the
13059 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
13060 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
13061 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
13063 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
13064 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
13065 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
13066 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
13069 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
13070 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
13071 thus the meeting about
<quote>open and collaborative projects to create
13072 public goods
</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
13074 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation
</primary></indexterm>
13076 But there is one project within that list that is highly
13077 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is
<quote>open source
13078 and free software.
</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
13079 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
13080 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
13081 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
13082 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
13083 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
13084 rather than
<quote>proprietary software,
</quote> for their own internal uses.
13086 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft
</quote> licenses
</primary></indexterm>
13087 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
13088 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
13089 <indexterm><primary>IBM
</primary></indexterm>
13091 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
13092 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
13093 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
13094 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
13095 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
13096 operating system, the most famous bit of
<quote>free software
</quote>—and IBM
13097 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support
<quote>open source and
13098 free software
</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
13099 to support a mode of software development that is different from
13100 Microsoft's.
<footnote><para>
13102 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
13103 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
13104 <quote>open source
</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
13105 principal opposition is to
<quote>free software
</quote> licensed under a
<quote>copyleft
</quote>
13106 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
13107 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith,
<quote>The Future
13108 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,
</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
13109 Toward Open Source Software
</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
13110 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
13111 Public Policy Research,
2002),
69, available at
13112 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
62</ulink>. See also
13113 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president,
<citetitle>The Commercial Software
13114 Model
</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (
3
13115 May
2001), available at
13116 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
63</ulink>.
13119 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)
</primary></indexterm>
13120 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)
</primary></indexterm>
13122 More important for our purposes, to support
<quote>open source and free
13123 software
</quote> is not to oppose copyright.
<quote>Open source and free software
</quote>
13124 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
13125 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
13126 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
13128 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
13129 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
13130 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
13131 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
13132 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
13133 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
13134 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
13135 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
13136 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
13137 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
13139 <indexterm><primary>Krim, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
13140 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by
</secondary></indexterm>
13142 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
13143 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
13144 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
13145 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
13146 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
13147 <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
13148 States government to veto the meeting.
<footnote><para>
13150 Krim,
<quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,
</quote> available at
<ulink
13151 url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
64</ulink>.
13153 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
13156 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
13157 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
13158 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
13159 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
13160 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
13161 its lobbying efforts.
13163 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois
</primary></indexterm>
13165 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
13166 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
13167 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
13168 Office, explained that
<quote>open-source software runs counter to the
13169 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.
</quote>
13170 She is quoted as saying,
<quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
13171 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
13172 goals of WIPO.
</quote>
13175 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
13177 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
13179 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
13180 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
13181 right called
<quote>copyright
</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
13182 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it
<quote>runs counter
</quote> to the mission
13183 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
13184 in understanding
—the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
13185 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
13186 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
13188 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs
</primary></indexterm>
13190 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to
<quote>promote
</quote>
13191 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
13192 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
13193 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
13194 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
13195 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
13196 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
13197 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
13198 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
13199 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
13200 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
13202 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
13204 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
13205 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
13206 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13207 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13208 <emphasis>their
</emphasis> rights. If they want to
<quote>waive
</quote> or
13209 <quote>disclaim
</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13210 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $
20 billion to do
13211 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13212 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13213 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13214 to do with
<emphasis>their
</emphasis> property.
13216 <indexterm id='idxboland' class='startofrange'
><primary>Boland, Lois
</primary></indexterm>
13218 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13219 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,
</quote> she's
13220 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13221 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13222 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13223 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from
<quote>waiving
</quote> or
13224 <quote>disclaiming
</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13225 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13226 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13230 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13231 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called
<quote>feudalism.
</quote> Under
13232 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13233 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13234 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13235 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13236 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13237 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13238 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13241 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
13242 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John
</primary></indexterm>
13244 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13245 choice we are now making about intellectual property.
<footnote><para>
13247 See Drahos with Braithwaite,
<citetitle>Information Feudalism
</citetitle>,
210–20.
13248 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
13250 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13251 choice now is whether that information society will be
13252 <emphasis>free
</emphasis> or
<emphasis>feudal
</emphasis>. The trend is
13256 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13257 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13258 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13259 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13263 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13264 it should be (
<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13265 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13266 not simply to promote intellectual property rights
</quote>), not as it is. If
13267 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13268 say anything wrong. But in the world
13269 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13270 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13271 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13275 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13276 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13277 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13278 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13279 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13280 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13281 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13282 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13284 <indexterm startref='idxboland' class='endofrange'
/>
13286 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13287 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13288 <quote>goal
</quote> of a government should be
<quote>to promote the right balance
</quote> of
13289 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13290 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism.
<quote>Typical for
13291 an academic,
</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13294 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13295 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13296 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13297 our own country's history).
13300 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13301 government should be to
<quote>seek balance,
</quote> then count me with the silly,
13302 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13303 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13304 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13305 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13306 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13307 not lies is just na
ïve, then who have we, the most powerful
13308 democracy in the world, become?
13311 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13312 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13313 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13314 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13315 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13316 been part of our tradition for most of our history
—free culture.
13319 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13321 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace
</primary></indexterm>
13322 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
13323 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted
</primary></indexterm>
13325 <emphasis role='strong'
>There are moments
</emphasis> of hope in this
13326 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13327 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13328 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13329 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13330 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13331 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13332 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing
700,
000 letters were
13333 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13336 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13337 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13338 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13339 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13340 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13341 concentration in the media.
13344 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13345 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13346 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13347 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13348 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13351 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13352 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13353 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13354 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13355 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13356 range of rights
—property rights of a historically extreme
13357 form
—that makes their bigness bad.
13359 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13361 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13362 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13363 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13364 Americans have a long history of fighting
<quote>big,
</quote> wisely or not. That
13365 we could be motivated to fight
<quote>big
</quote> again is not something new.
13368 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13369 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13370 the idea of
<quote>intellectual property.
</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13371 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13372 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13373 called
<quote>property
</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13376 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13379 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob
</primary></indexterm>
13381 <emphasis role='strong'
>As I write
</emphasis> these final words, the
13382 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
13383 three hundred individuals.
<footnote><para>
13385 John Borland,
<quote>RIAA Sues
261 File Swappers,
</quote> CNET News.com, September
13387 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
65</ulink>; Paul
13388 R. La Monica,
<quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,
</quote> CNN/Money,
8 September
13390 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
66</ulink>; Soni
13391 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty,
<quote>Sued for a Song,
13392 N.Y.C.
12-Yr-Old Among
261 Cited as Sharers,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News
</citetitle>,
9
13393 September
2003,
3; Frank Ahrens,
<quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13394 Targets; Single Mother in Calif.,
12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13395 Defendants,
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13396 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,
</quote> <citetitle>Wired News
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003,
13398 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
67</ulink>.
13400 Eminem has just been sued for
<quote>sampling
</quote> someone else's
13401 music.
<footnote><para>
13403 Jon Wiederhorn,
<quote>Eminem Gets Sued
… by a Little Old Lady,
</quote>
13404 mtv.com,
17 September
2003, available at
13405 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
68</ulink>.
13407 The story about Bob Dylan
<quote>stealing
</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13408 finished making the rounds.
<footnote><para>
13410 Kenji Hall, Associated Press,
<quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13411 Dylan Songs,
</quote> Kansascity.com,
9 July
2003, available at
13412 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
69</ulink>.
13413 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13415 An insider from Hollywood
—who insists he must remain
13416 anonymous
—reports
<quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13417 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13418 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13419 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13420 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.
</quote> Congressmen are
13421 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13422 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13423 kids who use a computer to share content.
13425 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
13426 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
13427 <indexterm><primary>BBC
</primary></indexterm>
13428 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in
</primary></indexterm>
13429 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons
</primary></indexterm>
13430 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto
</primary></indexterm>
13431 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom
</primary><secondary>public creative archive in
</secondary></indexterm>
13433 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13434 that it will build a
<quote>Creative Archive,
</quote> from which British citizens can
13435 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.
<footnote><para>
13436 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,
</quote> BBC press release,
13437 24 August
2003, available at
13438 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
70</ulink>.
13440 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13441 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13442 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13443 country.
<footnote><para>
13445 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,
</quote> Creative Commons Weblog,
6 August
2003,
13447 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
71</ulink>.
13449 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13450 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13451 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13452 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13453 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13454 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13455 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13456 day into the Causbys.
13459 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
13460 potential is ever to be realized.
13462 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
13466 <chapter label=
"16" id=
"c-afterword">
13467 <title>AFTERWORD
</title>
13470 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
13471 <emphasis role='strong'
>At least some
</emphasis> who have read this
13472 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
13473 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
13476 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
13477 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
13478 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
13479 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
13482 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
13483 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
13484 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists
—all to tell this
13485 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
13489 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
13490 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
13491 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
13492 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
13493 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
13495 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
13497 <section id=
"usnow">
13498 <title>US, NOW
</title>
13500 <emphasis role='strong'
>Common sense
</emphasis> is with the copyright
13501 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
13502 extremes
—as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
13503 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
13504 choice, then the warriors should win.
13507 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
13508 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
13509 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright
—<quote>All Rights
13510 Reserved
</quote>— and those who reject copyright
—<quote>No Rights
13511 Reserved.
</quote> The
<quote>All Rights Reserved
</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
13512 permission before you
<quote>use
</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The
<quote>No
13513 Rights Reserved
</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
13514 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
13517 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
13518 tilted in the
<quote>no rights reserved
</quote> direction. Content could be copied
13519 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
13520 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
13523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
13524 original design of the Internet was
<quote>no rights reserved.
</quote> Content was
13525 <quote>taken
</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
13529 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
13530 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
13531 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
13532 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
13533 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
13534 architecture made the effective default
<quote>no rights reserved,
</quote> the
13535 future architecture will make the effective default
<quote>all rights
13536 reserved.
</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
13537 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
13538 content requires permission. The
<quote>cut and paste
</quote> world that defines
13539 the Internet today will become a
<quote>get permission to cut and paste
</quote>
13540 world that is a creator's nightmare.
13543 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle
—neither
13544 <quote>all rights reserved
</quote> nor
<quote>no rights reserved
</quote> but
<quote>some rights
13545 reserved
</quote>— and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
13546 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
13547 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
13551 <section id=
"examples">
13552 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
</title>
13553 <indexterm id='browsing' class='startofrange'
><primary>browsing
</primary></indexterm>
13555 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
13556 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
13557 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
13558 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
13559 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
13560 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
13561 to your neighbors or boss. The
<quote>privacy
</quote> of your browsing habits was
13565 What made it assured?
13567 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
13569 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
13570 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>, your
13571 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
13572 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
13573 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
13574 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
13575 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
13576 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
13577 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
13578 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
13579 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
13580 (there is no law protecting
<quote>privacy
</quote> in public places), and in many
13581 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
13582 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
13584 <indexterm><primary>Amazon
</primary></indexterm>
13585 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet
</primary></indexterm>
13587 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
13588 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
13589 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
13590 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
13591 <quote>recently viewed
</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
13592 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
13593 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any
<quote>privacy
</quote>
13594 protected by the friction disappears, too.
13597 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
13598 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
13599 people should have the
<quote>right
</quote> to browse in a library without the
13600 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
13601 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
13602 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
13603 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
13606 <indexterm startref='browsing' class='endofrange'
/>
13608 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define
<quote>privacy
</quote>
13609 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
13610 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
13611 friction did.
<footnote><para>
13614 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg,
<quote>Fair Information Practices and the
13615 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),
</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
13616 Law Review
</citetitle> 1 (
2001): par.
6–18, available at
13618 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
72</ulink>
13619 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
13620 also Jeffrey Rosen,
<citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
13621 in an Anxious Age
</citetitle> (New York: Random House,
2004) (mapping tradeoffs
13622 between technology and privacy).
</para></footnote>
13623 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
13624 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
13626 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
13627 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
13628 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
13629 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
13632 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
13633 movement. When computers with software were first made available
13634 commercially, the software
—both the source code and the
13635 binaries
— was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
13636 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
13637 care much about controlling their software.
13638 <indexterm><primary>IBM
</primary></indexterm>
13640 <indexterm><primary>Stallman, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
13642 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
13643 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
13644 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
13645 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
13646 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
13650 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
13651 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
13652 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
13653 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
13654 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
13655 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
13656 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
13657 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
13658 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
13662 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
13663 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
13664 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
13665 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
13666 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
13667 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
13668 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
13671 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
13672 early
1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
13673 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
13674 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
13675 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
13676 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
13677 fundamentally weakened.
13679 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus
</primary></indexterm>
13681 Therefore, in
1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
13682 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
13683 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's
<quote>Linux
</quote>
13684 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
13685 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
13686 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
13689 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
13690 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
13691 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
13692 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
13693 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
13694 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
13695 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
13696 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
13700 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
13701 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
13702 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
13703 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
13704 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
13705 what before had been passively guaranteed.
13708 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
13709 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
13710 scientific journals are produced.
13712 <indexterm id=
"idxacademocjournals" class='startofrange'
><primary>academic journals
</primary></indexterm>
13714 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
13715 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
13716 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
13717 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
13718 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
13719 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
13720 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
13721 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
13722 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
13723 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
13724 and Westlaw are also free
13725 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
13726 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
13727 Court opinion through their respective services.
13730 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
13731 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
13732 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
13733 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
13734 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
13735 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
13736 access to material that is not in the public domain.
13739 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
13740 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
13741 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
13744 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
13745 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
13746 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
13747 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
13748 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
13749 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
13750 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
13751 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
13752 the technology of paper journals (architecture)
—namely, that it
13753 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
13756 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
13757 that libraries not give the general public access to the
13758 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
13759 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
13760 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
13764 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
13765 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
13766 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
13767 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
13768 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
13769 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
13770 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
13771 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
13772 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
13773 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
13774 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
13775 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)
</primary></indexterm>
13778 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
13779 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
13780 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
13781 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
13782 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
13783 presumptively a good
—especially when it helps spread knowledge
13786 <indexterm startref=
"idxacademocjournals" class='endofrange'
/>
13789 <section id=
"oneidea">
13790 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
</title>
13791 <indexterm id=
"idxcc" class='startofrange'
><primary>Creative Commons
</primary></indexterm>
13793 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
13794 increasing control effected through law and technology.
13796 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University
</primary></indexterm>
13798 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
13799 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
13800 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
13801 <emphasis>reasonable
</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
13802 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
13803 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
13804 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
13805 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
13806 make this possible.
13809 <emphasis>Simple
</emphasis>—which means without a middleman, or
13810 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
13811 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
13812 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
13813 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
13814 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
13815 shared. These three expressions together
—a legal license, a
13816 human-readable description, and
13817 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
13818 machine-readable tags
—constitute a Creative Commons license. A
13819 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
13820 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
13821 that the person associated with the license believes in something
13822 different than the
<quote>All
</quote> or
<quote>No
</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
13823 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
13824 certain freedoms are given.
13827 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
13828 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
13829 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
13830 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
13831 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
13832 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (
<quote>share and share
13833 alike
</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
13834 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
13835 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
13838 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
13839 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
13840 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
13841 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
13842 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
13843 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
13844 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
13845 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
13848 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia
</primary></indexterm>
13850 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
13851 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
13852 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
13853 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
13854 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
13855 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
13856 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
13857 of content (
<quote>content conducers,
</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
13858 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
13859 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
13862 The aim is not to fight the
<quote>All Rights Reserved
</quote> sorts. The aim is to
13863 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
13864 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
13865 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
13866 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
13867 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
13868 the background of digital technologies. New rules
—with different
13869 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
13870 them
—are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
13871 to begin to build those rules.
13873 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of
</secondary></indexterm>
13875 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
13876 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
13877 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel,
<citetitle>Down and Out in
13878 the Magic Kingdom
</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
13879 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
13882 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
13883 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (
1)
13884 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
13885 and (
2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
13886 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (
1) will download
13887 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(
1)s. Some part of (
2)
13888 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
13889 them (
2)-goods. If there are more (
2)-goods than bad-(
1)s, the
13890 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
13891 <emphasis>increase
</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
13894 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
13895 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
13896 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
13897 was a total success.
13899 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)
</primary></indexterm>
13900 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
13902 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
13903 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
13904 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
13905 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled
<citetitle>Free for All
</citetitle>,
13906 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
13907 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
13908 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
13909 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
13912 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'
/>
13913 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy
</primary></indexterm>
13914 <indexterm><primary>rap music
</primary></indexterm>
13915 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter
</primary></indexterm>
13917 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
13918 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
13919 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
13920 reasons. Many who use the
<quote>sampling license
</quote> do so because anything
13921 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
13922 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
13923 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
13924 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
13925 art
—they, too, sample from others. Because the
13926 <emphasis>legal
</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
13927 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
13928 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not
<quote>allow
</quote>
13929 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
13930 high
<footnote><para>
13932 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
13933 Culture Wars
</citetitle> (
2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
13934 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
13935 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
72</ulink>.
13936 </para></footnote>),
13937 these artists release into the creative environment content
13938 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
13941 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
13942 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
13943 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
13944 you are effectively saying you believe in the
<quote>All Rights Reserved
</quote>
13945 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
13946 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
13947 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
13948 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
13949 this notion of
<quote>Some Rights Reserved,
</quote> and gives many the chance to
13953 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
13954 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
13955 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
13956 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
13958 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
13959 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
13960 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
13963 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
13964 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
13965 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
13966 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
13967 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
13968 steps are possible.
13971 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
13972 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
13973 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
13974 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
13975 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
13976 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
13977 creativity to spread more easily.
13979 <indexterm startref=
"idxcc" class='endofrange'
/>
13981 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
13984 <section id=
"themsoon">
13985 <title>THEM, SOON
</title>
13987 <emphasis role='strong'
>We will
</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
13988 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
13989 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
13990 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
13991 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
13994 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
13995 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
13996 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
14000 <section id=
"formalities">
14001 <title>1. More Formalities
</title>
14003 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
14004 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
14005 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
14006 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
14009 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
14010 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
14011 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
14015 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
14016 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
14017 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
14018 default is control, and
<quote>formalities
</quote> are banished.
14024 As I suggested in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
14025 linkend=
"property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
14026 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
14027 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
14028 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
14029 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
14030 formalities were getting in the way.
14033 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
14034 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
14035 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
14036 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
14037 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
14038 trace
— there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
14039 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
14040 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
14041 past. And thus, the
<emphasis>lack
</emphasis> of formalities forces
14042 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
14045 The law should therefore change this requirement
<footnote><para>
14047 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
14048 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
14049 adopted by other countries as well.
</para></footnote>—but it
14050 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
14051 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
14052 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
14055 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
14056 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
14057 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
14058 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
14059 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
14060 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
14061 developed by others.
14064 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
14066 <section id=
"registration">
14067 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL
</title>
14069 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
14070 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
14071 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
14072 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
14073 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
14074 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
14075 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
14076 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
14077 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
14078 panic
—nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
14079 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
14082 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
14083 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
14084 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
14085 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
14086 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
14087 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
14088 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
14091 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
14092 There are at least
32 million Web sites registered around the world.
14093 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
14094 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
14095 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
14096 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
14097 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
14098 with which registration occurs up.
14101 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
14102 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
14103 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
14104 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
14105 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
14106 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
14107 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
14108 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
14109 formality
—while producing a database
14110 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
14111 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
14115 <section id=
"marking">
14116 <title>MARKING
</title>
14118 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
14119 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
14120 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule
—akin to
14121 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
14122 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
14123 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
14124 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
14125 uniformly across all media.
14128 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
14129 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
14130 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
14134 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
14135 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
14136 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
14137 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
14138 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
14139 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
14140 signal from the failure to mark
—not the loss of the copyright, but the
14141 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
14144 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
14145 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
14146 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
14147 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
14148 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
14149 doesn't give permission.
<footnote><para>
14151 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
14152 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
14153 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
14155 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be
<quote>use unless someone
14156 complains.
</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
14157 stop using the work in any new
14158 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
14159 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
14160 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
14164 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
14165 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
14166 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
14167 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
14168 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
14170 <indexterm><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>copyright marking of
</secondary></indexterm>
14172 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
14173 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
14174 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
14175 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
14176 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
14177 <emphasis>solely
</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
14178 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
14179 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
14180 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
14181 other important functions.
14184 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
14185 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
14186 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
14187 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
14188 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
14189 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
14192 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
14193 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
14194 make things unclear.
14197 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
14198 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
14199 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
14200 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
14201 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
14202 that assertion at the appropriate time.
14205 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
14208 <section id=
"shortterms">
14209 <title>2. Shorter Terms
</title>
14211 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14212 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14216 In
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14217 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14218 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14219 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14220 radical.
<citetitle>The Economist
</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14221 copyright term.
<footnote><para>
14224 <quote>A Radical Rethink,
</quote> <citetitle>Economist
</citetitle>,
366:
8308 (
25 January
2003):
15,
14226 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
74</ulink>.
14228 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14231 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14232 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14233 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14236 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
14239 <emphasis>Keep it short:
</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14240 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14241 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14242 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14243 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14244 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14248 <emphasis>Keep it simple:
</emphasis> The line between the public
14249 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14250 fuzziness of
<quote>fair use,
</quote> and the distinction between
<quote>ideas
</quote> and
14251 <quote>expression.
</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14252 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14253 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14254 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14255 <quote>lawyer-free zone
</quote> makes the complexities of
<quote>fair use
</quote> and
14256 <quote>idea/expression
</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14257 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14260 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions
</primary></indexterm>
14263 <emphasis>Keep it alive:
</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14264 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14265 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14266 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14267 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14268 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14269 pension.
<footnote><para>
14271 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14272 and/or Pension, VA Form
21-
526 (OMB Approved No.
2900-
0001),
14274 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
75</ulink>.
14276 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14277 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14282 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:
</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14283 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14284 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14285 in
1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14286 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14287 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in
1923 than we
14288 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14289 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14290 the number of authors who wrote in
1923. Of course, we can increase
14291 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14292 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14293 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14294 creativity in
1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14295 we can do about that now.
</para></listitem>
14298 These changes together should produce an
<emphasis>average
</emphasis>
14299 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until
1976,
14300 the average term was just
32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14304 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas
<quote>radical.
</quote> (After all, I
14305 call them
<quote>extremists.
</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14306 than the term under Richard Nixon. How
<quote>radical
</quote> can it be to ask for
14307 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14310 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14313 <section id=
"freefairuse">
14314 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
</title>
14315 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and
</primary></indexterm>
14316 <indexterm><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
14318 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14319 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14320 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14321 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14322 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14323 the emergence of that new technology.
14326 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors
<quote>exclusive
14327 right
</quote> to
<quote>their writings.
</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14328 right to
<quote>their writings
</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14329 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14330 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14331 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14332 though that movie is not
<quote>my writing.
</quote>
14334 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin
</primary></indexterm>
14336 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in
1870, when it
14337 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14338 control translations and dramatizations of a work.
<footnote><para>
14340 Benjamin Kaplan,
<citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright
</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14341 University Press,
1967),
32.
14343 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14344 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14345 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14349 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14350 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14351 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14352 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.
<footnote><para>
14353 <!-- f6. --> Ibid.,
56.
14358 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14359 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14360 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14361 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14362 Consider each limitation in turn.
14365 <emphasis>Term:
</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14366 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14367 sense to protect John
14369 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14370 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14371 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14372 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14373 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14374 after the creative work is done.
14375 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John
</primary></indexterm>
14378 <emphasis>Scope:
</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14379 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14380 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14381 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14382 material. When all
<quote>reuse
</quote> of creative material was within the control
14383 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14384 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14385 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14386 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14387 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14388 the creative process. Smothers it.
14390 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
14392 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14393 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14394 foreseeable derivative rights
—turning a book into a movie, or a
14395 poem into a musical score
—it doesn't make sense to require
14396 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14400 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14401 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14402 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14403 Paul Goldstein.
<footnote>
14406 Paul Goldstein,
<citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14407 Jukebox
</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
2003),
187–216.
14408 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
14410 His view is that the law should be written so that
14411 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14414 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14415 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14416 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14417 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14418 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14421 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14422 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
14423 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
14424 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
14425 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
14426 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
14430 <section id=
"liberatemusic">
14431 <title>4. Liberate the Music
—Again
</title>
14433 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
14434 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
14435 is, to most people, most pressing
—music. There is no other
14436 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
14437 battles around the sharing of music.
14440 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
14441 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
14442 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
14443 killer app
—possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
14444 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
14445 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
14446 innovation on the network.
14449 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
14450 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
14451 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
14452 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
14453 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
14456 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
14457 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
14458 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
14459 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"piracy"/>, they enable
14460 four different kinds of sharing:
14462 <orderedlist numeration=
"upperalpha">
14465 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
14466 for purchasing CDs.
14470 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
14471 on the way to purchasing CDs.
14474 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
14476 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14477 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
14478 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
14482 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14483 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
14484 owner plainly endorses.
14487 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
14488 <indexterm><primary>VCRs
</primary></indexterm>
14490 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
14491 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
14492 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
14493 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
14494 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
14495 significantly weakened.
14498 As I said in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
14499 linkend=
"piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
14500 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
14501 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
14502 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
14506 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
14507 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
14511 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
14512 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
14513 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
14514 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
14515 is cumbersome and slow
—we in the United States are lucky to have
14516 broadband service at
1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
14517 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
14518 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
14519 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
14520 Internet is mainly just an idea.
14523 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
14524 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
14525 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
14526 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
14527 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
14528 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
14529 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
14530 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
14531 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
14532 where everywhere you are
—except maybe the desert or the
14533 Rockies
—you can instantaneously be connected to the
14534 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
14535 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
14537 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over
</primary></indexterm>
14539 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
14540 give you access to content on the fly
—such as Internet radio,
14541 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
14542 then, is the critical point: When it is
<emphasis>extremely
</emphasis>
14543 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
14544 <emphasis>easier
</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
14545 access to content than it will be to download and store content
14546 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
14547 content
</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
14548 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
14549 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
14550 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
14551 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
14552 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
14553 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
14554 paying for this content even though
<quote>free
</quote> content is available in the
14555 form of MP3s across the Web.
<footnote><para>
14557 See, for example,
<quote>Music Media Watch,
</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter,
3
14558 April
2002, available at
14559 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
76</ulink>.
14564 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
14565 present: It is emphatically temporary. The
<quote>problem
</quote> with file
14566 sharing
—to the extent there is a real problem
—is a problem
14567 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
14568 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
14569 makers today to be
<quote>solving
</quote> this problem in light of a technology
14570 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
14571 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
14572 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
14573 artists get paid, during
14575 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
14576 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
14577 and twenty-first-century technologies.
14580 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different
<quote>problems
</quote>
14581 here to solve. Let's start with type D content
—uncopyrighted
14582 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
14583 <quote>problem
</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
14584 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
14585 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
14586 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
14587 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
14588 order to eliminate kidnapping.
14591 Type C content raises a different
<quote>problem.
</quote> This is content that was,
14592 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
14593 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
14594 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
14595 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
14596 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
14597 way that returns something to the artist.
14599 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
14600 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
14602 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
14603 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
14604 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
14605 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
14606 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
14607 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
14608 from the author's perspective, this
<quote>sharing
</quote> of his content without
14609 his being compensated is less than ideal.
14612 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
14613 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
14614 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
14615 providers would be free, under this rule, to
<quote>share
</quote> that content,
14616 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
14617 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
14618 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
14622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
14623 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
14624 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
14625 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
14626 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
14627 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
14628 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
14629 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
14633 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
14634 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
14635 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
14636 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
14637 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
14638 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
14639 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
14640 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
14643 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
14644 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
14645 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
14646 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
14647 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
14648 delivering and accessing content.
14651 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
14652 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
14655 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
14656 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
14657 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
14658 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
14659 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
14660 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
14661 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
14662 harmed the interests of the content industry.
14665 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
14666 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
14667 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
14668 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
14669 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
14670 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
14671 way to compensate those who are harmed.
14673 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'
><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)
</primary></indexterm>
14675 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
14676 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.
<footnote>
14679 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
14680 William Fisher,
<citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities
</citetitle> (last
14681 revised:
10 October
2000), available at
14682 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
77</ulink>; William
14683 Fisher,
<citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
14684 Entertainment
</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
14685 2004), ch.
6, available at
14686 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
78</ulink>. Professor
14687 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
14688 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
14689 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel,
<quote>Impose a
14690 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,
</quote> available at
14691 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig,
<quote>Who's Holding Back
14692 Broadband?
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
8 January
2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
14693 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
14694 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee,
26 February
2002,
14696 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine,
<citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
14697 Use Fee (IPUF)
</citetitle>,
3 March
2002, available at
14698 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
14699 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,
</quote> <citetitle>USA Today
</citetitle>,
13 May
14701 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry,
<quote>Getting Copyright Right,
</quote>
14702 IEEE Spectrum Online,
1 July
2002, available at
14703 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
83</ulink>; Declan
14704 McCullagh,
<quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,
</quote> CNET News.com,
27 August
14706 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
84</ulink>.
14707 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
14708 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
14709 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
14710 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
14711 debate by about a decade. See
14712 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
85</ulink>.
14713 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William
</primary></indexterm>
14714 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
14715 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)
</primary></indexterm>
14716 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'
/>
14718 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
14719 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
14720 would (
1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
14721 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
14722 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
14723 develop (
2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
14724 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (
3) artists would be
14725 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (
4) an appropriate
14729 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
14730 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
14731 <citetitle>Promises to Keep
</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
14732 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
14733 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
14734 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
14735 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
14736 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
14737 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
14738 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
14739 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
14740 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
14741 controlling access.
14743 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'
/>
14744 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
14746 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
14747 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
14748 the system supports the widest range of
<quote>semiotic democracy
</quote>
14749 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
14750 other changes I described were accomplished
—in particular, the
14751 limits on derivative
14753 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
14754 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
14755 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
14756 allowed to do with the content itself.
14758 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation
</primary></indexterm>
14759 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore
</primary></indexterm>
14760 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks
</primary></indexterm>
14761 <indexterm><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>prices of
</secondary></indexterm>
14763 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
14764 <quote>harm
</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
14765 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
14766 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
14767 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
14768 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat
<quote>free
</quote> by being
14769 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
14770 of songs at even the very high price of
99 cents a song. (At
99 cents,
14771 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
14772 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
14773 Real Networks, offering music at just
79 cents a song. And no doubt
14774 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
14777 <indexterm><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
14778 <indexterm><primary>television
</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast
</secondary></indexterm>
14779 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
14780 <indexterm><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>in Asia
</secondary></indexterm>
14781 <indexterm><primary>film industry
</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in
</secondary></indexterm>
14783 This competition has already occurred against the background of
<quote>free
</quote>
14784 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
14785 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
14786 that, there is nothing impossible at all about
<quote>competing with free.
</quote>
14787 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
14788 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
14789 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
14790 theaters are often luxurious
—with
<quote>first class
</quote> seats, and meals
14791 served while you watch a movie
—as they struggle and succeed in
14792 finding ways to compete with
<quote>free.
</quote>
14795 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
14796 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
14797 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
14798 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
14799 innovators
—ones who would have a right to the content, and would
14800 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
14804 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
14808 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
14809 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
14810 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
14811 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
14812 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
14816 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
14819 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
14822 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
14826 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
14827 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
14832 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
14833 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
14837 But what if
<quote>piracy
</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
14838 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
14839 consumers continue to
<quote>take
</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
14843 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
14844 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
14845 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
14846 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
14847 technology that is
95 percent secure and produces a market of size
<citetitle>x
</citetitle>,
14848 or (b) to have a technology that is
50 percent secure but produces a
14849 market of five times
<citetitle>x
</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
14850 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
14851 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
14852 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
14853 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
14857 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
14858 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
14859 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
14861 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
14862 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
14863 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
14867 <section id=
"firelawyers">
14868 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers
</title>
14870 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
14871 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
14872 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
14873 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
14876 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
14877 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
14878 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
14879 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
14880 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
14881 strong view queers the law.
14883 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville
</primary></indexterm>
14884 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (
1998)
</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of
</secondary></indexterm>
14886 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
14887 <quote>radical
</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
14888 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
14889 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
14890 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
14891 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
14892 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
14893 Nimmer, thought it obvious.
<footnote><para>
14895 Lawrence Lessig,
<quote>Copyright's First Amendment
</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
14896 Memorial Lecture),
<citetitle>UCLA Law Review
</citetitle> 48 (
2001):
1057,
1069–70.
14901 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
14902 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
14903 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
14906 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
14907 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
14908 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
14909 the legal system are slight.
<footnote><para>
14911 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
14912 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
14913 leading him to question his own publicly stated
14914 position
—twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
14915 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
14916 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
14917 J. Liebowitz,
<citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
14918 Drive the Digital Marketplace
</citetitle> (New York: Amacom,
2002), (reviewing his
14919 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
14920 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?
</quote> working paper, June
2003,
14922 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
86</ulink>.
14923 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
14924 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
14925 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
14926 <citetitle>Rethinking
</citetitle>,
174–76.
14927 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
14929 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
14930 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
14934 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
14935 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
14936 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
14937 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
14938 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
14939 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
14940 practically never be done.
14943 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
14944 billed at the largest firms at more than $
400 per hour. How much time
14945 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
14946 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
14947 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
14948 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
14949 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
14950 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
14953 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
14954 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
14955 their duty to change the way the law works
—or better, to change the
14956 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
14957 top
1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
14958 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
14961 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
14962 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
14963 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
14966 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid
</primary></indexterm>
14968 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
14969 technology
—the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
14970 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
14971 technology
—a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
14972 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
14973 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
14974 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
14977 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture
—but it should
14978 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
14980 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311-->
14981 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
14982 simple pragmatic question:
<quote>Will it do good?
</quote> When challenged about
14983 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers,
<quote>Why not?
</quote>
14986 We should ask,
<quote>Why?
</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
14987 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
14988 keep your lawyers away.
14990 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
14994 <chapter label=
"17" id=
"c-notes">
14995 <title>NOTES
</title>
14997 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
14998 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
14999 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
15000 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
15001 this book. For each link below, you can go to
15002 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
15003 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
15004 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
15005 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
15009 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
15010 <?latex \theendnotes
?>
15012 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
15015 <chapter label=
"18" id=
"c-acknowledgments">
15016 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
</title>
15018 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
15019 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
15020 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
15021 to him that this book is dedicated.
15023 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark
</primary></indexterm>
15025 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
15026 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
15027 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
15028 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
15029 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
15030 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
15031 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
15032 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
15033 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
15034 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
15035 critical eye on much of this.
15038 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
15039 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
15040 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
15041 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
15042 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
15043 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
15044 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
15045 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
15046 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
15049 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
15050 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
15051 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
15052 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
15053 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
15054 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
15055 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
15056 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
15057 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
15058 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
15059 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
15060 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
15061 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
15062 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
15063 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams,
<quote>Wink,
</quote> Roger Wood,
<quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,
</quote>
15064 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
15065 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
15066 a bunch of great replies.)
15069 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
15070 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
15071 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
15072 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
15073 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
15074 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
15075 throughout this book.
15078 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
15079 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
15080 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
15081 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
15083 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->