]> pere.pagekite.me Git - text-free-culture-lessig.git/blob - freeculture.xml
Add several indexterm entries after comparing with the ones in http://www.jus.uio...
[text-free-culture-lessig.git] / freeculture.xml
1 <?xml version='1.0' encoding='UTF-8' ?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href="docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type="text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012 with input from Martin Borg. -->
5 <!--
6 TODO
7 * indexterm primary
8 -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC "-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
11 [
12 <!ENTITY copy "©">
13 <!ENTITY translationblock "">
14 ]>
15 <book id="index" lang="en">
16 <bookinfo>
17 <title>Free Culture</title>
18
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
20
21 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
22 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY</subtitle>
23
24 <pubdate>2004-03-25</pubdate>
25
26 <releaseinfo>Version 2004-02-10</releaseinfo>
27
28 <authorgroup>
29 <author>
30 <firstname>Lawrence</firstname>
31 <surname>Lessig</surname>
32 </author>
33 </authorgroup>
34
35 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
36 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
37 -->
38 <subjectset scheme="libraryofcongress">
39 <subject>
40 <subjectterm>Intellectual property&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
41 </subject>
42 <subject>
43 <subjectterm>Mass media&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
44 </subject>
45 <subject>
46 <subjectterm>Technological innovations&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
47 </subject>
48 <subject>
49 <subjectterm>Art&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
50 </subject>
51 </subjectset>
52
53
54 <publisher>
55 <publishername>The Penguin Press</publishername>
56 <address><city>New York</city></address>
57 </publisher>
58
59 <copyright>
60 <year>2004</year>
61 <holder>Lawrence Lessig</holder>
62 </copyright>
63 <legalnotice>
64 <para>
65 <inlinemediaobject>
66 <imageobject>
67 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.png" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
68 </imageobject>
69 <imageobject>
70 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.svg" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
71 </imageobject>
72 <textobject>
73 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved</phrase>
74 </textobject>
75 </inlinemediaobject>
76 </para>
77
78 <para>
79 This version of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is licensed under
80 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
81 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
82 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
83 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/</ulink>
84 </para>
85 </legalnotice>
86
87 <abstract>
88 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR</title>
89 <para>
90 LAWRENCE LESSIG
91 (<ulink url="http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org</ulink>),
92 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
93 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
94 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
95 (<ulink url="http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org</ulink>).
96 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) and Code: And
97 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), Lessig is a member of
98 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
99 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
100 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
101 twice listed in BusinessWeek's <quote>e.biz 25,</quote> and named one of Scientific
102 American's <quote>50 visionaries.</quote> A graduate of the University of
103 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
104 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
105 Appeals.
106 </para>
107 </abstract>
108
109 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
110 <mediaobject role="cover">
111 <imageobject remap="lrg" role="front-large">
112 <imagedata fileref="images/cover.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
113 </imageobject>
114 <!--
115 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
116 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
117 </imageobject>
118 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
119 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
120 </imageobject>
121 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
122 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
123 </imageobject>
124 -->
125 </mediaobject>
126
127 <biblioid class="isbn">1-59420-006-8</biblioid>
128
129 <!-- LCCN from
130 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
131 -->
132 <biblioid class="libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
133
134 </bookinfo>
135 <!--PAGE BREAK 1-->
136 <dedication id="salespoints">
137 <title></title>
138 <para>
139 You can buy a copy of this book by clicking on one of the links below:
140 </para>
141 <itemizedlist mark="number" spacing="compact">
142 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.amazon.com/">Amazon</ulink></para></listitem>
143 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.barnesandnoble.com/">B&amp;N</ulink></para></listitem>
144 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.penguin.com/">Penguin</ulink></para></listitem>
145 <!-- <ulink url="">Local Bookstore</ulink> -->
146 </itemizedlist>
147 </dedication>
148 <!-- PAGE BREAK 2 -->
149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
150 <dedication id="alsobylessig">
151 <title></title>
152 <para>
153 ALSO BY LAWRENCE LESSIG
154 </para>
155 <para>
156 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
157 </para>
158 <para>
159 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
160 </para>
161 </dedication>
162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
163 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
164 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
165 <colophon>
166 <para>
167 THE PENGUIN PRESS, a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc. 375 Hudson Street New
168 York, New York
169 </para>
170 <para>
171 Copyright &copy; Lawrence Lessig. All rights reserved.
172 </para>
173 <para>
174 Excerpt from an editorial titled <quote>The Coming of Copyright Perpetuity,</quote>
175 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, January 16, 2003. Copyright
176 &copy; 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted with permission.
177 </para>
178 <para>
179 Cartoon in <xref linkend="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/> by Paul Conrad, copyright Tribune
180 Media Services, Inc. All rights reserved. Reprinted with permission.
181 </para>
182 <para>
183 Diagram in <xref linkend="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership"/> courtesy of the office of FCC
184 Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
185 </para>
186 <para>
187 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
188 </para>
189 <para>
190 Lessig, Lawrence.
191 Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law to lock down
192 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
193 </para>
194 <para>
195 p. cm.
196 </para>
197 <para>
198 Includes index.
199 </para>
200 <para>
201 ISBN 1-59420-006-8 (hardcover)
202 </para>
203
204 <para>
205 1. Intellectual property&mdash;United States. 2. Mass media&mdash;United States.
206 </para>
207 <para>
208 3. Technological innovations&mdash;United States. 4. Art&mdash;United States. I. Title.
209 </para>
210 <para>
211 KF2979.L47
212 </para>
213 <para>
214 343.7309'9&mdash;dc22
215 </para>
216 <para>
217 This book is printed on acid-free paper.
218 </para>
219 <para>
220 Printed in the United States of America
221 </para>
222 <para>
223 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4
224 </para>
225 <para>
226 Designed by Marysarah Quinn
227 </para>
228
229 <para>
230 &translationblock;
231 </para>
232
233 <para>
234 Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of
235 this publication may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a
236 retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means
237 (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise),
238 without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and
239 the above publisher of this book.
240 </para>
241 <para>
242 The scanning, uploading, and distribution of this book via the
243 Internet or via any other means without the permission of the
244 publisher is illegal and punishable by law. Please purchase only
245 authorized electronic editions and do not participate in or encourage
246 electronic piracy of copyrighted materials. Your support of the
247 author's rights is appreciated.
248 </para>
249 </colophon>
250
251 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
252 <dedication><title></title>
253 <para>
254 To Eric Eldred&mdash;whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
255 it continues still.
256 </para>
257 </dedication>
258
259 <toc id="toc"></toc>
260
261 <lot>
262 <title>List of figures</title>
263 </lot>
264
265 <!--
266 c PREFACE xiii
267 c INTRODUCTION
268 c "PIRACY"
269 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
270 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
271 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
272 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
273 2 Film
274 2 Recorded Music
275 2 Radio
276 2 Cable TV
277 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
278 2 Piracy I
279 2 Piracy II
280 c "PROPERTY"
281 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
282 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
283 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
284 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
285 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
286 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
287 2 Beginnings
288 2 Law: Duration
289 2 Law: Scope
290 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
291 2 Architecture and Law: Force
292 2 Market: Concentration
293 2 Together
294 c PUZZLES
295 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
296 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
297 2 Constraining Creators
298 2 Constraining Innovators
299 2 Corrupting Citizens
300 c BALANCES
301 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
302 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
303 c CONCLUSION
304 c AFTERWORD
305 1 Us, Now
306 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
307 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
308 1 Them, Soon
309 2 1. More Formalities
310 3 Registration and Renewal
311 3 Marking
312 2 2. Shorter Terms
313 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
314 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
315 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
316 c NOTES
317 c ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
318 c INDEX
319 -->
320
321 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
322
323 <preface id="preface">
324 <title>PREFACE</title>
325 <indexterm id='idxpoguedavid' class='startofrange'><primary>Pogue, David</primary></indexterm>
326 <para>
327 <emphasis role="bold">At the end</emphasis> of his review of my first
328 book, <citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle>, David
329 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
330 computer-related texts, wrote this:
331 </para>
332 <blockquote>
333 <para>
334 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
335 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
336 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
337 system, you can always flip off the modem.<footnote id="preface01"><para>
338 David Pogue, <quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 30 January 2000.
339 </para></footnote>
340 </para>
341 </blockquote>
342 <para>
343 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book&mdash;that
344 software, or <quote>code,</quote> functioned as a kind of law&mdash;and his review
345 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
346 could always <quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome</quote>-like simply flip a
347 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
348 any troubles that exist in <emphasis>that</emphasis> space wouldn't
349 <quote>affect</quote> us anymore.
350 </para>
351 <para>
352 Pogue might have been right in 1999&mdash;I'm skeptical, but maybe.
353 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
354 <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
355 causes even after the modem is turned
356 <!--PAGE BREAK 12-->
357 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
358 on-line have fundamentally affected <quote>people who aren't online.</quote> There
359 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
360 </para>
361 <indexterm startref='idxpoguedavid' class='endofrange'/>
362 <para>
363 But unlike <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
364 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
365 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
366 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
367 important.
368 </para>
369 <para>
370 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
371 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of <quote>free culture</quote>&mdash;not
372 <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free beer</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
373 free software movement<footnote>
374 <para>
375 Richard M. Stallman, <citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed. 2002).
376 </para></footnote>), but <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free speech,</quote> <quote>free markets,</quote>
377 <quote>free trade,</quote> <quote>free enterprise,</quote> <quote>free will,</quote> and <quote>free elections.</quote> A
378 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
379 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
380 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
381 follow-on creators and innovators remain <emphasis>as free as
382 possible</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
383 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
384 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
385 <quote>permission culture</quote>&mdash;a culture in which creators get to create
386 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
387 past.
388 </para>
389 <para>
390 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not <quote>we</quote>
391 on the Left or <quote>you</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
392 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
393 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
394 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
395 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
396 culture deem fundamental.
397 </para>
398 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
399 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
400 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
401 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted</primary></indexterm>
402 <para>
403 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
404 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
405 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
406 generated more than 700,000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
407 As William Safire described marching <quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
408 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
409 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,</quote> he formulated perhaps
410 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
411 he asked,
412 </para>
413 <blockquote>
414 <para>
415 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
416 power&mdash;political, corporate, media, cultural&mdash;should be anathema to
417 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
418 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
419 the greatest expression of democracy.<footnote><para> William Safire,
420 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 May 2003.
421 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
422 </para></footnote>
423 </para>
424 </blockquote>
425 <para>
426 This idea is an element of the argument of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle>, though my
427 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
428 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
429 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
430 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
431 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
432 you&mdash;whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
433 Safire's left or on his right.
434 </para>
435 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'/>
436 <para>
437 <emphasis role="strong">The inspiration</emphasis> for the title and for
438 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
439 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
440 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in <citetitle>Free Software, Free
441 Society</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
442 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
443 that this work is <quote>merely</quote> derivative.
444 </para>
445 <para>
446 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
447 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
448 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
449 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
450 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
451 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
452 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
453 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
454
455 <!--PAGE BREAK 14-->
456 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
457 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
458 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
459 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
460 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
461 what I advance here.
462 </para>
463 <para>
464 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
465 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
466 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
467 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
468 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
469 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
470 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
471 book is written.
472 </para>
473
474 </preface>
475 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
476
477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
478 <chapter label="0" id="c-introduction">
479 <title>INTRODUCTION</title>
480 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
481 <para>
482 <emphasis role="strong">On December 17</emphasis>, 1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
483 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
484 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
485 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
486 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
487 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
488 </para>
489 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.</primary></indexterm>
490 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
491 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
492 <para>
493 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
494 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
495 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
496 and all the space above, to <quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.</quote><footnote><para>
497 St. George Tucker, <citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
498 Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18.
499 </para></footnote>
500 For many
501 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
502 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
503 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
504 </para>
505 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
506 <para>
507 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
508 law&mdash;deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
509 by the most important legal thinkers of our past&mdash;mattered. If
510 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
511 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
512 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
513 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
514 </para>
515 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
516 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
517 <para>
518 In 1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
519 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
520 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
521 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
522 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
523 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
524 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to <quote>an indefinite
525 extent, upwards,</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
526 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
527 </para>
528 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
529 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
530 <indexterm id='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='startofrange'><primary>Douglas, William O.</primary></indexterm>
531 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on airspace vs. land rights</secondary></indexterm>
532 <para>
533 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
534 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
535 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
536 <quote>taking</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
537 that <quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
538 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.</quote> But Justice Douglas
539 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
540 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
541 </para>
542 <blockquote>
543 <para>
544 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
545 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
546 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
547 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
548 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
549 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
550 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
551 the public has a just claim.<footnote>
552 <para>
553 United States v. Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. The Court did find
554 that there could be a <quote>taking</quote> if the government's use of its land
555 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
556 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, <quote>(Intellectual)
557 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
558 Authorship,</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review</citetitle> 48 (1996): 1293, 1333. See also Paul
559 Goldstein, <citetitle>Real Property</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press, 1984),
560 1112&ndash;13.
561 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
562 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
563 </para></footnote>
564 </para>
565 </blockquote>
566 <para>
567 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.</quote>
568 </para>
569 <indexterm startref='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='endofrange'/>
570 <para>
571 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
572 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
573 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
574 <!--PAGE BREAK 18-->
575 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: <quote>Common sense revolts
576 at the idea.</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
577 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
578 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
579 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
580 </para>
581 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
582 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
583 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
584 <para>
585 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
586 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
587 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
588 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
589 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
590 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
591 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
592 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
593 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by <quote>what
594 seemed reasonable</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
595 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
596 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
597 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
598 end, the force of what seems <quote>obvious</quote> to everyone else&mdash;the power of
599 <quote>common sense</quote>&mdash;would prevail. Their <quote>private interest</quote> would not be
600 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
601 </para>
602 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'/>
603 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'/>
604 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'/>
605 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='endofrange'/>
606 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
607 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham</primary></indexterm>
608 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
609 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael</primary></indexterm>
610 <indexterm id='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
611 <para>
612 <emphasis role='strong'>Edwin Howard Armstrong</emphasis> is one of
613 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
614 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
615 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
616 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
617 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
618 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in 1831. But
619 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
620 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
621 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
623 </para>
624 <para>
625 On the day after Christmas, 1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
626 for his most significant invention&mdash;FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
627 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
628 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
629 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
630 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
631 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
632 much less transmitter power and static.
633 </para>
634 <para>
635 On November 5, 1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
636 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
637 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
638 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
639 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
640 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
641 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
642 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
643 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.</quote>
644 </para>
645 <para>
646 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
647 </para>
648 <blockquote>
649 <para>
650 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
651 sounded like a glass of water being poured. &hellip; A paper was crumpled
652 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
653 fire. &hellip; Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
654 and guitar number were performed. &hellip; The music was projected with a
655 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio <quote>music
656 box.</quote><footnote><para>
657 Lawrence Lessing, <citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong</citetitle>
658 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209.
659 </para></footnote>
660 </para>
661 </blockquote>
662 <indexterm id='idxrca' class='startofrange'><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
663 <indexterm id='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
664 <para>
665 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
666 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
667 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
668 AM radio market. By 1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
669 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
670 a handful of networks.
671 <!--PAGE BREAK 20-->
672 </para>
673 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
674 <para>
675 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
676 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
677 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
678 that removed static from <quote>radio.</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
679 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
680 </para>
681 <blockquote>
682 <para>
683 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
684 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
685 revolution&mdash; start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
686 RCA.<footnote><para> See <quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
687 Electronic Era,</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
688 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
689
690 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #1</ulink>.
691 </para></footnote>
692 </para>
693 </blockquote>
694 <indexterm id='idxfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
695 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
696 <para>
697 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
698 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
699 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
700 described,
701 </para>
702 <indexterm id='idxlessinglawrence' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessing, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
703 <blockquote>
704 <para>
705 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
706 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
707 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
708 unrestrained, posed &hellip; a complete reordering of radio power
709 &hellip; and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
710 on which RCA had grown to power.<footnote><para>Lessing, 226.
711 </para></footnote>
712 </para>
713 </blockquote>
714 <indexterm id='idxfcconfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FCC</primary><secondary>on FM radio</secondary></indexterm>
715 <para>
716 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
717 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
718 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
719 FM radio's deployment generally. In 1936, RCA hired the former head
720 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
721 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM&mdash;principally by moving FM
722 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
723 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
724 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
725 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
726 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
727 </para>
728 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
729 <blockquote>
730 <para>
731 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
732 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
733 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
734 deviousness.<footnote><para>
735 Lessing, 256.
736 </para></footnote>
737 </para>
738 </blockquote>
739 <indexterm startref='idxlessinglawrence' class='endofrange'/>
740 <indexterm><primary>AT&amp;T</primary></indexterm>
741 <para>
742 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
743 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
744 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
745 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
746 (This change was strongly supported by AT&amp;T, because the loss of
747 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
748 wired links from AT&amp;T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
749 least temporarily.
750 </para>
751 <indexterm startref='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='endofrange'/>
752 <indexterm startref='idxfcconfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
753 <para>
754 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
755 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
756 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
757 invalid&mdash;baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
758 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
759 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
760 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
761 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
762 now broke, in 1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
763 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
764 </para>
765 <indexterm startref='idxfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
766 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'/>
767 <para>
768 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
769 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
770 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
771 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
772 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
773 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
774 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
775 course always public spirited; the reality is something
776 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
777 to themselves, would crumble in
778 <!--PAGE BREAK 22-->
779 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
780 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
781 effect of technological change.
782 </para>
783 <indexterm startref='idxrca' class='endofrange'/>
784 <indexterm startref='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='endofrange'/>
785 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
786 <para>
787 <emphasis role="strong">There's no</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
788 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
789 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
790 Internet and American Life Project, 58 percent of Americans had access
791 to the Internet in 2002, up from 49 percent two years
792 before.<footnote><para>
793 Amanda Lenhart, <quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
794 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,</quote> Pew Internet and American
795 Life Project, 15 April 2003: 6, available at
796 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #2</ulink>.
797 </para></footnote>
798 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
799 of 2004.
800 </para>
801 <para>
802 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
803 changed things. Some of these changes are technical&mdash;the Internet has
804 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
805 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
806 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
807 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
808 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
809 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
810 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
811 </para>
812 <para>
813 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
814 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
815 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
816 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
817 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
818 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
819 has introduced.
820 </para>
821 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
822 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel</primary></indexterm>
823 <indexterm id='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='startofrange'><primary>culture</primary><secondary>commercial vs. noncommercial</secondary></indexterm>
824 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah</primary></indexterm>
825 <para>
826 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
827 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
828 regulation of each. By <quote>commercial culture</quote> I mean that part of our
829 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
830 <quote>noncommercial culture</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
831 parks or on
832 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
833 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
834 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his <quote>Reader,</quote> or
835 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
836 </para>
837 <para>
838 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
839 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
840 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
841 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
842 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
843 left this culture <quote>free.</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
844 individuals shared and transformed their culture&mdash;telling
845 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
846 clubs, sharing music, making tapes&mdash;were left alone by the law.
847 </para>
848 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>commercial creativity as primary purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
849 <para>
850 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
851 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
852 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
853 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
854 marketplace.<footnote>
855 <para>
856 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
857 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
858 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
859 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
860 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
861 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
862 D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote> Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193,
863 198&ndash;200.
864 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
865 </para></footnote>
866 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
867 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
868 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
869 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
870 </para>
871 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
872 <indexterm><primary>permission culture</primary><secondary> free culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
873 <para>
874 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
875 been erased.<footnote><para>
876 See Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
877 2001), ch. 13.
878 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
879 </para></footnote>
880 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
881 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
882 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
883 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
884 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
885 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
886 the balance of our history&mdash;between uses of our culture that were
887 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission&mdash;has
888 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
889 culture, more and more a permission culture.
890 </para>
891 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
892 <indexterm><primary>protection of artists vs. business interests</primary></indexterm>
893 <para>
894 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
895 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
896 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
897 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
898 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
899 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
900 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
901 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
902 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
903 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
904 Causbys.
905 </para>
906 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='endofrange'/>
907 <para>
908 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
909 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
910 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
911 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
912 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
913 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
914 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
915 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
916 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
917 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
918 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
919 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
920 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
921 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
922 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
923 than creators do today&mdash;all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
924 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
925 </para>
926 <para>
927 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
928 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
929 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
930 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
931 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
932 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
933 remakes them.
934 </para>
935 <indexterm startref='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='endofrange'/>
936 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary> on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
937 <para>
938 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
939 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
940 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
941 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions&mdash;whether <quote>piracy</quote> will
942 be permitted, and whether <quote>property</quote> will be protected. The <quote>war</quote> that
943 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet&mdash;what
944 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
945 calls his <quote>own terrorist war</quote><footnote><para>
946 Amy Harmon, <quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
947 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,</quote> <citetitle>New York
948 Times</citetitle>, 17 January 2002.
949 </para></footnote>&mdash;has been framed as a battle about the
950 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
951 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
952 against it.
953 </para>
954 <para>
955 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
956 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
957 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
958 <quote>creative property.</quote> I believe that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that the
959 law, properly tuned, should punish <quote>piracy,</quote> whether on or off the
960 Internet.
961 </para>
962 <para>
963 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
964 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
965 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet <quote>pirates</quote> will also rid our
966 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
967 </para>
968 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
969 <indexterm><primary>Copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
970 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
971 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
972 <para>
973 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first 180 years of
974 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
975 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
976 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
977 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,<footnote>
978 <para>
979 Neil W. Netanel, <quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
980 Journal</citetitle> 106 (1996): 283.
981 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
982 </para></footnote>
983 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
984 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
985 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
986 could cultivate and extend our culture.
987 </para>
988 <para>
989 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
990 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
991 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
992 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist&ndash;like,
993 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
994 granted&mdash;but it is not often granted to the critical or the
995 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
996 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
997 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
998 </para>
999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Should "Is it" be "It is" ? -->
1000 <para>
1001 The story that follows is about this war. Is it not about the
1002 <quote>centrality of technology</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
1003 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
1004 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
1005 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
1006 against an industry.
1007 </para>
1008 <para>
1009 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
1010 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
1011 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
1012 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
1013 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
1014 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
1015 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
1016 </para>
1017 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1018 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1019 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary></indexterm>
1020 <para>
1021 <emphasis role="strong">Like the Causbys'</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about <quote>property.</quote> The
1022 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
1023 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
1024 this <quote>property</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
1025 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
1026 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
1027 of <quote>intellectual property</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
1028 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
1029 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
1030 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
1031 <quote>trespassing</quote> upon legitimate claims of <quote>property.</quote> It is as plain to
1032 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
1033 trespass.
1034 </para>
1035 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1036 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1037 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
1038 <para>
1039 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
1040 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
1041 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
1042 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
1043 war. Unlike
1044 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
1045 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
1046 on its side.
1047 </para>
1048 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
1049 <para>
1050 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
1051 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
1052 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
1053 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
1054 our <quote>culture</quote> was as <quote>owned</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
1055 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
1056 <emphasis>uses</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
1057 accepted as it is now.
1058 </para>
1059 <para>
1060 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
1061 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
1062 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
1063 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1064 </para>
1065 <para>
1066 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1067 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1068 </para>
1069 <para>
1070 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1071 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1072 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1073 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1074 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1075 </para>
1076 <para>
1077 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1078 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1079 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1080 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1081 view?
1082 </para>
1083 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1084 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1085 <para>
1086 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1087 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1088 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1089 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of <quote>intellectual
1090 property.</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1091 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1092 this silliness will be much more profound.
1093 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1094 </para>
1095 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='endofrange'/>
1096 <para>
1097 <emphasis role="strong">The struggle</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas: <quote>piracy</quote> and
1098 <quote>property.</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1099 ideas.
1100 </para>
1101 <para>
1102 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1103 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1104 obscure French theorists&mdash;however natural that is for the weird
1105 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1106 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1107 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1108 </para>
1109 <para>
1110 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1111 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1112 government, pushed by big media to respond to this <quote>something new,</quote> is
1113 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1114 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let <quote>common
1115 sense</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1116 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1117 law&mdash;and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1118 fundamental about who we have always been.
1119 </para>
1120 <para>
1121 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1122 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1123 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1124 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1125 of one more consequence of this form of corruption&mdash;a consequence
1126 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1127 </para>
1128 </chapter>
1129 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1130 <part id="c-piracy">
1131 <title><quote>PIRACY</quote></title>
1132 <partintro>
1133 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1134 <indexterm><primary>Copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
1135 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
1136 <indexterm><primary>music publishing</primary></indexterm>
1137 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
1138 <para>
1139 <emphasis role="strong">Since the inception</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1140 been a war against <quote>piracy.</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1141 <quote>piracy,</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1142 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1143 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1144 </para>
1145 <blockquote>
1146 <para>
1147 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1148 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1149 of them for his own use.<footnote><para>
1150 <!-- f1 -->
1151 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield).
1152 </para></footnote>
1153 </para>
1154 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='endofrange'/>
1155 </blockquote>
1156 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary> efficient content distribution on</secondary></indexterm>
1157 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='startofrange'><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>efficiency of</secondary></indexterm>
1158 <para>
1159 Today we are in the middle of another <quote>war</quote> against <quote>piracy.</quote> The
1160 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1161 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1162 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1163 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1164 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1165 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1166 </para>
1167 <para>
1168 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1169 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1170 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1171 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1172 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will <quote>rob the author of the
1173 profit.</quote>
1174 </para>
1175 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='endofrange'/>
1176 <para>
1177 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1178 increasingly to technology to defend their <quote>property</quote> against this
1179 <quote>piracy.</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1180 raised to believe that <quote>property</quote> should be <quote>free.</quote> Forget tattoos,
1181 never mind body piercing&mdash;our kids are becoming
1182 <emphasis>thieves</emphasis>!
1183 </para>
1184 <para>
1185 There's no doubt that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1186 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1187 notion of <quote>piracy</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1188 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1189 </para>
1190 <para>
1191 The idea goes something like this:
1192 </para>
1193 <blockquote>
1194 <para>
1195 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1196 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1197 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1198 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1199 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1200 piracy.
1201 </para>
1202 </blockquote>
1203 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP</primary></indexterm>
1204 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle</primary></indexterm>
1205 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts</primary></indexterm>
1206 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory of</secondary></indexterm>
1207 <indexterm id='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
1208 <para>
1209 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1210 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1211 theory of creative property<footnote><para>
1212 <!-- f2 -->
1213 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, <quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1214 in the Pepsi Generation,</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review</citetitle> 65 (1990): 397.
1215 </para></footnote>
1216 &mdash;if there is value, then someone must have a
1217 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1218 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1219 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.<footnote><para>
1220 <!-- f3 -->
1221 Lisa Bannon, <quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1222 Up,</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 21 August 1996, available at
1223 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #3</ulink>; Jonathan
1224 Zittrain, <quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1225 Speech, No One Wins,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 24 November 2002.
1226 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
1227 </para></footnote>
1228 There was <quote>value</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1229 <quote>right</quote>&mdash;even against the Girl Scouts.
1230 </para>
1231 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='endofrange'/>
1232 <para>
1233 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1234 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1235 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1236 of law protecting creative property. But the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1237 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1238 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1239 </para>
1240 <indexterm startref='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='endofrange'/>
1241 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
1242 <indexterm id='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>legal restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
1243 <para>
1244 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1245 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1246 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1247 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1248 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1249 </para>
1250 <para>
1251 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1252 takes care to draw&mdash;the distinction between republishing someone's
1253 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1254 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1255 copyright law today regulates both.
1256 </para>
1257 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='endofrange'/>
1258 <para>
1259 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1260 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1261 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1262 entities could bear the burden of the law&mdash;even the burden of the
1263 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1264 more expense of doing business.
1265 </para>
1266 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>creativity impeded by</secondary></indexterm>
1267 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1268 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1269 <para>
1270 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1271 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1272 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1273 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1274 <quote>copying,</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1275 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1276 outweighs any original benefit&mdash;certainly as it affects
1277 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1278 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1279 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1280 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1281 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1282 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1283 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1284 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1285 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1286 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the <quote>Rise of the Creative
1287 Class.</quote><footnote>
1288 <para>
1289 <!-- f4 -->
1290 In <citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class</citetitle> (New York:
1291 Basic Books, 2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1292 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1293 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1294 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1295 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1296 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1297
1298 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1299 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1300 </para></footnote>
1301 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1302 this creative class.
1303 </para>
1304 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='endofrange'/>
1305 <para>
1306 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1307 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1308 context the current battles about behavior labeled <quote>piracy.</quote>
1309 </para>
1310 </partintro>
1311
1312 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1313 <chapter label="1" id="creators">
1314 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators</title>
1315 <indexterm id='idxanimatedcartoons' class='startofrange'><primary>animated cartoons</primary></indexterm>
1316 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'><primary>cartoon films</primary></indexterm>
1317 <para>
1318 <emphasis role="strong">In 1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1319 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called <citetitle>Plane Crazy</citetitle>.
1320 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1321 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle> brought
1322 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1323 </para>
1324 <para>
1325 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1326 movie <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1327 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1328 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1329 Disney ran a test in the summer of 1928, the results were unambiguous.
1330 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1331 </para>
1332 <blockquote>
1333 <para>
1334 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1335 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1336 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1337 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1338 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1339 </para>
1340 <para>
1341 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1342 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1343 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1344 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1345 synchronization was pretty close.
1346 </para>
1347 <para>
1348 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1349 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1350 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1351 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1352 it was something new!<footnote><para>
1353 <!-- f1 -->
1354 Leonard Maltin, <citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1355 Cartoons</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34&ndash;35.
1356 </para></footnote>
1357 </para>
1358 </blockquote>
1359 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub</primary></indexterm>
1360 <para>
1361 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1362 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: <quote>I have never been so thrilled
1363 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.</quote>
1364 </para>
1365 <para>
1366 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1367 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1368 rarely&mdash;except in Disney's hands&mdash;been anything more than
1369 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1370 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1371 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1372 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1373 </para>
1374 <para>
1375 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that 1928 also marks
1376 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1377 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1378 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>.
1379 </para>
1380 <para>
1381 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in 1895. In the era of silent
1382 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1383 uncontrollable laughter from his audience. <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1384 Jr</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1385 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton&mdash;wildly popular
1386 and among the best of its genre.
1387 </para>
1388 <para>
1389 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1390 Willie.
1391 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1392 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1393 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,<footnote><para>
1394 <!-- f2 -->
1395 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1396 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #4</ulink>.
1397 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1398 use the music for five songs in <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>: <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote> <quote>The
1399 Simpleton</quote> (Delille), <quote>Mischief Makers</quote> (Carbonara), <quote>Joyful Hurry No. 1</quote>
1400 (Baron), and <quote>Gawky Rube</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song, <quote>The Turkey in the
1401 Straw,</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1402 Harry Surden, 10 July 2003, on file with author.
1403 </para></footnote>
1404 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1405 the invention of synchronized sound in <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle> that we
1406 get <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1407 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote>
1408 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1409 Mouse.
1410 </para>
1411 <para>
1412 This <quote>borrowing</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1413 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1414 films of his day.<footnote><para>
1415 <!-- f3 -->
1416 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, <quote>The Mouse
1417 that Ate the Public Domain,</quote> Findlaw, 5 March 2002, at
1418 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #5</ulink>.
1419 </para></footnote>
1420 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1421 knockoffs&mdash;slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1422 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1423 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1424 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1425 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1426 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1427 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1428 old.
1429 </para>
1430 <para>
1431 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1432 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1433 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1434 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1435 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1436 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1437 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1438 </para>
1439 <para>
1440 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1441 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1442 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1443 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1444 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1445 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1446 work of others is astonishing when set together: <citetitle>Snow White</citetitle>
1447 (1937), <citetitle>Fantasia</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Pinocchio</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Dumbo</citetitle>
1448 (1941), <citetitle>Bambi</citetitle> (1942), <citetitle>Song of the South</citetitle> (1946),
1449 <citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle> (1950), <citetitle>Alice in Wonderland</citetitle> (1951), <citetitle>Robin
1450 Hood</citetitle> (1952), <citetitle>Peter Pan</citetitle> (1953), <citetitle>Lady and the Tramp</citetitle>
1451 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1452 (1955), <citetitle>Mulan</citetitle> (1998), <citetitle>Sleeping Beauty</citetitle> (1959), <citetitle>101
1453 Dalmatians</citetitle> (1961), <citetitle>The Sword in the Stone</citetitle> (1963), and
1454 <citetitle>The Jungle Book</citetitle> (1967)&mdash;not to mention a recent example
1455 that we should perhaps quickly forget, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>
1456 (2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1457 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1458 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1459 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1460 </para>
1461 <indexterm startref="idxanimatedcartoons" class='endofrange'/>
1462 <para>
1463 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1464 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1465 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1466 its importance. We could call this <quote>Disney creativity,</quote> though that
1467 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, <quote>Walt Disney
1468 creativity</quote>&mdash;a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1469 culture around us and makes it something different.
1470 </para>
1471 <para> In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1472 relatively fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was
1473 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1474 thirty years&mdash;for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1475 copyrighted.<footnote><para>
1476 <!-- f4 -->
1477 Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1478 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the <quote>average</quote> term by
1479 determining
1480 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1481 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in year
1482 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the
1483 average
1484 term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1485 Web site associated with this book, available at
1486 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #6</ulink>.
1487 </para></footnote>
1488 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1489 copyright holders of a creative work had an <quote>exclusive right</quote> to control
1490 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1491 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1492 </para>
1493 <para>
1494 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1495 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1496 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a <quote>lawyer-free
1497 zone.</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1498 for Disney to use and build upon in 1928. It was free for
1499 anyone&mdash; whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1500 approved or not&mdash;to use and build upon.
1501 </para>
1502 <para>
1503 This is the ways things always were&mdash;until quite recently. For most
1504 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1505 until 1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1506 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1507
1508 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1509 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1510 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s
1511 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1512 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1513 content from before the Great Depression.
1514 </para>
1515 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'/>
1516 <para>
1517 <emphasis role="strong">Of course</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on <quote>Walt Disney creativity.</quote>
1518 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1519 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1520 universal.
1521 </para>
1522 <para>
1523 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1524 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: <citetitle>manga</citetitle>, or
1525 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of
1526 publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives
1527 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1528 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1529 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1530 </para>
1531 <para>
1532 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1533 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1534 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1535 the stories that these <quote>graphic novels</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1536 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are <quote>men in tights.</quote>
1537 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1538 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1539 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1540 interestingly different way.
1541 </para>
1542 <para>
1543 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1544 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1545 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1546 </para>
1547 <para>
1548 This is the phenomenon of <citetitle>doujinshi</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1549 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1550 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is <emphasis>just</emphasis> a
1551 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1552 transforming it either subtly or
1553 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1554 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1555 develop it differently&mdash;with a different story line. Or the comic can
1556 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1557 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently <quote>different.</quote> But they
1558 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1559 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1560 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1561 </para>
1562 <para>
1563 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1564 huge. More than 33,000 <quote>circles</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1565 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come
1566 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1567 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1568 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1569 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1570 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1571 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1572 </para>
1573 <para>
1574 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1575 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1576 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1577 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1578 one. Doujinshi are plainly <quote>derivative works.</quote> There is no general
1579 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1580 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1581 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1582 Jr</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that <quote>taking</quote> without
1583 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1584 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1585 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1586 </para>
1587 <indexterm id='idxwinickjudd' class='startofrange'><primary>Winick, Judd</primary></indexterm>
1588 <para>
1589 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1590 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1591 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, <quote>The
1592 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1593 in Japan now. &hellip; American comics were born out of copying each
1594 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1595 other. &hellip; That's how [the artists] learn to draw&mdash;by going into comic
1596 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them</quote>
1597 and building from them.<footnote><para>
1598 <!-- f5 -->
1599 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, <citetitle>Reinventing Comics</citetitle> (New
1600 York: Perennial, 2000).
1601 </para></footnote>
1602 </para>
1603 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics</primary></indexterm>
1604 <para>
1605 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1606 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1607 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, <quote>there are these rules
1608 and you have to stick to them.</quote> There are things Superman <quote>cannot</quote>
1609 do. <quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1610 which are fifty years old.</quote>
1611 </para>
1612 <indexterm startref="idxwinickjudd" class='endofrange'/>
1613 <para>
1614 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1615 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1616 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1617 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1618 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1619 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1620 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.<footnote><para>
1621 <!-- f6 -->
1622 See Salil K. Mehra, <quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1623 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1624 Review</citetitle> 55 (2002): 155, 182. <quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1625 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1626 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1627 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1628 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1629 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.</quote>
1630 </para></footnote>
1631 </para>
1632 <para>
1633 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1634 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1635 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1636 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1637 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1638 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1639 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1640 a more general pattern of blocking this <quote>free taking</quote> by the doujinshi
1641 culture?
1642 </para>
1643 <para>
1644 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1645 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1646 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. <quote>We don't have enough
1647 lawyers,</quote> he told me one afternoon. There <quote>just aren't enough resources
1648 to prosecute cases like this.</quote>
1649 </para>
1650 <para>
1651 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1652 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1653 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1654 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1655 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1656 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1657 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1658 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1659 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1660 their clients or hurt them?
1661 </para>
1662 <para>
1663 <emphasis role='strong'>Let's pause</emphasis> for a moment.
1664 </para>
1665 <para>
1666 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1667 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1668 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1669 </para>
1670 <para>
1671 We live in a world that celebrates <quote>property.</quote> I am one of those
1672 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1673 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1674 <quote>intellectual property.</quote><footnote><para>
1675 <!-- f7 -->
1676 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
1677 The term <citetitle>intellectual property</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1678 Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 11 (New York: New York
1679 University Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
1680 (New York: Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately
1681 describes a set of <quote>property</quote> rights&mdash;copyright, patents,
1682 trademark, and trade-secret&mdash;but the nature of those rights is
1683 very different.
1684 </para></footnote>
1685 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1686 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1687 property.
1688 </para>
1689 <para>
1690 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1691 plenty of value out there that <quote>property</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1692 mean <quote>money can't buy you love,</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1693 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1694 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1695 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1696 condemning that taking as wrong&mdash; even though trivial, even if
1697 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1698 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1699 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1700 Disney's use would have been considered <quote>fair.</quote> There was nothing
1701 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1702 the public domain.
1703 </para>
1704 <para>
1705 Thus, even though the things that Disney took&mdash;or more generally,
1706 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity&mdash;are
1707 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1708
1709 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1710 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1711 freedom is good.
1712 </para>
1713 <para>
1714 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1715 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1716 work&mdash;or even one copy&mdash;without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1717 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1718 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1719 form, whether large or small.
1720 </para>
1721 <para>
1722 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1723 say that the copycat comic artists are <quote>stealing.</quote> This form of Walt
1724 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1725 particular find it hard to say why.
1726 </para>
1727 <para>
1728 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1729 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1730 without asking or paying for the privilege. (<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1731 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1732 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?</quote>) Acting companies
1733 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1734 permission from anyone. (Does <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> believe
1735 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1736 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1737 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1738 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s;
1739 two volcano disaster films in 1997.
1740 </para>
1741 <para>
1742 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1743 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1744 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1745 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1746 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1747 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1748 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking&mdash;free
1749 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1750 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1751 </para>
1752 <para>
1753 The hard question is therefore not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> a
1754 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1755 question instead is <quote><emphasis>How</emphasis> free is this culture?</quote>
1756 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1757 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1758 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1759 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1760 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1761 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1762 a studio or not?
1763 </para>
1764 <para>
1765 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1766 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1767 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1768 </para>
1769
1770 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1771 </chapter>
1772 <chapter label="2" id="mere-copyists">
1773 <title>CHAPTER TWO: <quote>Mere Copyists</quote></title>
1774 <indexterm id='idxcameratech' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1775 <indexterm id='idxphotography' class='startofrange'><primary>photography</primary></indexterm>
1776 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis</primary></indexterm>
1777 <para>
1778 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1779 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1780 <quote>photographs.</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1781 <quote>daguerreotypes.</quote> The process was complicated and
1782 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1783 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1784 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1785 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1786 </para>
1787 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William</primary></indexterm>
1788 <para>
1789 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1790 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1791 <quote>automatic pictures.</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1792 making <quote>negatives.</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1793 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1794 the 1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1795 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1796 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1797 amateurs.
1798 </para>
1799 <indexterm id='idxeastmangeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Eastman, George</primary></indexterm>
1800 <para>
1801 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1802 didn't happen until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1803 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1804 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1805 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1806 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1807 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1808 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1809 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1810 population of photographers.
1811 </para>
1812 <indexterm><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)</primary></indexterm>
1813 <para>
1814 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1815 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1816 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. <quote>You press the button and we
1817 do the rest.</quote><footnote><para>
1818 <!-- f1 -->
1819 Reese V. Jenkins, <citetitle>Images and Enterprise</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975), 112.
1820 </para></footnote> As he described in <citetitle>The Kodak Primer</citetitle>:
1821 </para>
1822 <blockquote>
1823 <para>
1824 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1825 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1826 that only an expert can do. &hellip; We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1827 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1828 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1829 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1830 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1831 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1832 chemicals.<footnote>
1833 <para>
1834 <!-- f2 -->
1835 Brian Coe, <citetitle>The Birth of Photography</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1836 1977), 53.
1837 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1838 </para></footnote>
1839 </para>
1840 </blockquote>
1841 <para>
1842 For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1843 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1844 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1845 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1846 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1847 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in 1888; one
1848 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1849 From 1888 through 1909, while industrial production was rising by 4.7
1850 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by 11
1851 percent.<footnote><para>
1852 <!-- f3 -->
1853 Jenkins, 177.
1854 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1855 an average annual increase of over 17 percent.<footnote><para>
1856 <!-- f4 -->
1857 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p. 178.
1858 </para></footnote>
1859 </para>
1860 <indexterm startref='idxcameratech' class='endofrange'/>
1861 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1862 <para>
1863
1864 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1865 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1866 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1867 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1868 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1869 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, <quote>For the
1870 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1871 permanent record of his family and its activities. &hellip; For the first
1872 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1873 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1874 interpretation or bias.</quote><footnote><para>
1875 <!-- f5 -->
1876 Coe, 58.
1877 </para></footnote>
1878 </para>
1879 <para>
1880 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1881 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1882 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1883 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1884 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1885 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its <quote>quality</quote>;
1886 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1887 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1888 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1889 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1890 have before.
1891 </para>
1892 <para>
1893 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1894 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1895 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1896 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1897 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1898 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1899 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1900 he wanted. Their answer was no.<footnote><para>
1901 <!-- f6 -->
1902 For illustrative cases, see, for example, <citetitle>Pavesich</citetitle>
1903 v. <citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co</citetitle>., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905);
1904 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Chinn</citetitle>, 123090 S.W. 364, 366
1905 (Ky. 1909); <citetitle>Corliss</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Walker</citetitle>, 64 F. 280 (Mass.
1906 Dist. Ct. 1894).
1907 </para></footnote>
1908 </para>
1909 <para>
1910 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1911 familiar. The photographer was <quote>taking</quote> something from the person or
1912 building whose photograph he shot&mdash;pirating something of
1913 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1914 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1915 draw
1916 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1917 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1918 that they thought valuable.
1919 </para>
1920 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1921 <para>
1922 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1923 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1924 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1925 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1926 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.<footnote>
1927 <para>
1928 <!-- f7 -->
1929 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote>
1930 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review</citetitle> 4 (1890): 193.
1931 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1932 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.</primary></indexterm>
1933 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1934 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1935 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1936 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1937 </para>
1938 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
1939 <para>
1940 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1941 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1942 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1943 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1944 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1945 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1946 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1947 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1948 clearing the rights to do the capturing.<footnote><para>
1949 <!-- f8 -->
1950 See Melville B. Nimmer, <quote>The Right of Publicity,</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
1951 Problems</citetitle> 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, <quote>Privacy,</quote> <citetitle>California Law
1952 Review</citetitle> 48 (1960) 398&ndash;407; <citetitle>White</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
1953 Inc</citetitle>., 971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951
1954 (1993).
1955 </para></footnote>)
1956 </para>
1957 <para>
1958 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1959 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1960 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1961 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1962 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1963 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1964 Kodak would be benefiting from the <quote>theft</quote> committed by the
1965 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1966 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1967 from the <quote>image-right</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
1968 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1969 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1970 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1971 </para>
1972 <para>
1973
1974 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
1975 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
1976 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
1977 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
1978 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
1979 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
1980 technology as they did&mdash;since professionals could have more
1981 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
1982 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
1983 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
1984 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
1985 realized.
1986 </para>
1987 <indexterm><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1988 <para>
1989 <emphasis role='strong'>If you drive</emphasis> through San
1990 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
1991 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
1992 <quote>Just Think!</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
1993 there's little that's <quote>just</quote> cerebral in the projects
1994 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
1995 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
1996 the film of your VCR. Rather the <quote>film</quote> of digital
1997 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
1998 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
1999 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
2000 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
2001 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
2002 think. By tinkering, they learn.
2003 </para>
2004 <indexterm startref="idxeastmangeorge" class='endofrange'/>
2005 <indexterm startref="idxphotography" class='endofrange'/>
2006 <para>
2007 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
2008 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
2009 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, <quote>Five years ago, a good
2010 real-time digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get
2011 professional quality for $595.</quote><footnote><para>
2012 <!-- f9 -->
2013 H. Edward Goldberg, <quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
2014 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,</quote>
2015 cadalyst, February 2002, available at
2016 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #7</ulink>.
2017 </para></footnote>
2018 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
2019 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
2020 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
2021 learning more and more of something teachers call <quote>media literacy.</quote>
2022 </para>
2023 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2024 <para>
2025 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
2026 <quote>Media literacy,</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
2027 Think!, puts it, <quote>is the ability &hellip; to understand, analyze, and
2028 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2029 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2030 the way people access it.</quote>
2031 </para>
2032 <para>
2033 This may seem like an odd way to think about <quote>literacy.</quote> For most
2034 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2035 and noticing split infinitives are the things that <quote>literate</quote> people know
2036 about.
2037 </para>
2038 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2039 <para>
2040 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of
2041 television commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000
2042 commercials generally,<footnote><para>
2043 <!-- f10 -->
2044 Judith Van Evra, <citetitle>Television and Child Development</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2045 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990); <quote>Findings on Family and TV
2046 Study,</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post</citetitle>, 25 May 1997, B6.
2047 </para></footnote>
2048 it is increasingly important to understand the <quote>grammar</quote> of media. For
2049 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2050 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2051 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2052 (at least at first) terrible media.
2053 </para>
2054 <para>
2055 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2056 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2057 has written understands how difficult writing is&mdash;how difficult
2058 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2059 language to be understandable&mdash;few of us have any real sense of
2060 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2061 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2062 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2063 </para>
2064 <para>
2065 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2066 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2067 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2068 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2069 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2070 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2071 </para>
2072 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael</primary></indexterm>
2073 <para>
2074 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2075 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2076 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2077
2078 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2079 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2080 about <quote>the placement of objects, color, &hellip; rhythm, pacing, and
2081 texture.</quote><footnote>
2082 <para>
2083 <!-- f11 -->
2084 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish, 13 December
2085 2002.
2086 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2087 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2088 </para></footnote>
2089 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2090 <quote>played</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2091 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2092 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2093 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2094 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2095 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2096 to a wildly successful author.<footnote><para>
2097 <!-- f12 -->
2098 See Scott Steinberg, <quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,</quote> E!online, 4
2099 November 2000, available at
2100 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #8</ulink>; <quote>Timeline,</quote> 22 November 2000,
2101 available at
2102 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #9</ulink>.
2103 </para></footnote>
2104 </para>
2105 <indexterm><primary>computer games</primary></indexterm>
2106 <para>
2107 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2108 describes, <quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2109 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2110 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2111 led.</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2112 </para>
2113 <para>
2114 Yet the push for an expanded literacy&mdash;one that goes beyond text
2115 to include audio and visual elements&mdash;is not about making better
2116 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2117 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2118 </para>
2119 <blockquote>
2120 <para>
2121 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2122 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2123 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2124 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2125 being read-only.
2126 </para>
2127 </blockquote>
2128 <para>
2129 <quote>Read-only.</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2130 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2131 twentieth century.
2132 </para>
2133 <para>
2134 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2135 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2136 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2137 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2138 literacy,
2139 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2140 and this literacy in particular, is to <quote>empower people to choose the
2141 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2142 express.</quote><footnote>
2143 <para>
2144 <!-- f13 -->
2145 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2146 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2147 </para></footnote> It is to enable students <quote>to communicate in the
2148 language of the twenty-first century.</quote><footnote><para>
2149 <!-- f14 -->
2150 Ibid.
2151 </para></footnote>
2152 </para>
2153 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2154 <para>
2155 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2156 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2157 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2158 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2159 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2160 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2161 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2162 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2163 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2164 students know something about&mdash;gun violence.
2165 </para>
2166 <para>
2167 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2168 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2169 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2170 away. The <quote>kids were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night,</quote>
2171 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2172 what education should be about&mdash;learning how to express themselves.
2173 </para>
2174 <para>
2175 Using whatever <quote>free web stuff they could find,</quote> and relatively simple
2176 tools to enable the kids to mix <quote>image, sound, and text,</quote> Barish said
2177 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2178 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2179 close to the lives of these students. The project <quote>gave them a tool
2180 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2181 it,</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2182 expression&mdash;far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2183 been created using only text. <quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2184 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2185 gone and done something else,</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2186 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2187 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2188 <emphasis>these</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2189 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2190 </para>
2191 <para>
2192
2193 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2194 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?</quote> I asked. In part,
2195 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2196 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of <quote>constructing
2197 meaning.</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2198 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2199 part&mdash;and increasingly, not the most powerful part&mdash;of
2200 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2201 our interview,
2202 </para>
2203 <blockquote>
2204 <para>
2205 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2206 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2207 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2208 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2209 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2210 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2211 you say, <quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.</quote>
2212 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2213 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2214 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, <quote>Well, with all these things that you
2215 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2216 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2217 for me something that reflects that.</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2218 camera and &hellip; saying, <quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2219 make a little movie.</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2220 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2221 about the topic.&hellip;
2222 </para>
2223 <para>
2224 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2225 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2226 bump up against the fact, <quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2227 to write something.</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2228 they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 times, till they got it right.
2229 </para>
2230 <para>
2231 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2232 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2233 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2234 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2235 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2236 had a lot of power with this language.
2237 </para>
2238 <!-- FIXME removed a " from the end of the previous paragraph that did
2239 not match with any start quote. -->
2240 </blockquote>
2241 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center</primary></indexterm>
2242 <para>
2243 <emphasis role='strong'>When two planes</emphasis> crashed into the
2244 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2245 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2246 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2247 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2248 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2249 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2250 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2251 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2252 watching.
2253 </para>
2254 <para>
2255 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2256 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2257 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was <quote>balance,</quote>
2258 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2259 increasingly come to expect it, <quote>news as entertainment,</quote> even if the
2260 entertainment is tragedy.
2261 </para>
2262 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
2263 <indexterm><primary>CBS</primary></indexterm>
2264 <para>
2265 But in addition to this produced news about the <quote>tragedy of September
2266 11,</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2267 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2268 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2269 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2270 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2271 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2272 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2273 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2274 the term in his book <citetitle>Cyber Rights</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2275 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2276 was also the Internet.
2277 </para>
2278 <para>
2279 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet&mdash;though I do think the
2280 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2281 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2282 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2283 movie
2284 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2285 by a student on the <quote>Just Think!</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2286 with sound or text.
2287 </para>
2288 <para>
2289 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2290 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2291 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2292 tradition&mdash;not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2293 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2294 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2295 spread practically instantaneously.
2296 </para>
2297 <para>
2298 September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2299 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2300 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2301 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2302 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2303 cultures, it records private facts in a public way&mdash;it's a kind
2304 of electronic <citetitle>Jerry Springer</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2305 </para>
2306 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2307 <para>
2308 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2309 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2310 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2311 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2312 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2313 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2314 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2315 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2316 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2317 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2318 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2319 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2320 </para>
2321 <para>
2322 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2323 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2324 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2325 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2326 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2327 people vote
2328 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2329 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2330 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2331 </para>
2332 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de</primary></indexterm>
2333 <indexterm><primary>jury system</primary></indexterm>
2334 <para>
2335 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2336 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2337 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2338 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2339 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2340 most important account of early <quote>Democracy in America.</quote> It wasn't
2341 popular elections that fascinated him&mdash;it was the jury, an
2342 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2343 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2344 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2345 deliberated. Members argued about the <quote>right</quote> result; they tried to
2346 persuade each other of the <quote>right</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2347 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2348 come to an end.<footnote><para>
2349 <!-- f15 -->
2350 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, <citetitle>Democracy in America</citetitle>,
2351 bk. 1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16.
2352 </para></footnote>
2353 </para>
2354 <para>
2355 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2356 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2357 are pushing to create just such an institution.<footnote><para>
2358 <!-- f16 -->
2359 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, <quote>Deliberation Day,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2360 Political Philosophy</citetitle> 10 (2) (2002): 129.
2361 </para></footnote>
2362 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2363 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2364 place for <quote>democratic deliberation</quote> to occur.
2365 </para>
2366 <para>
2367 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2368 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2369 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2370 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2371 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2372 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.<footnote><para>
2373 <!-- f17 -->
2374 Cass Sunstein, <citetitle>Republic.com</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001),
2375 65&ndash;80, 175, 182, 183, 192.
2376 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2377 little beyond what our friends say.
2378 </para>
2379 <indexterm id='idxblogs1' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2380 <indexterm><primary>e-mail</primary></indexterm>
2381 <para>
2382 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2383 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2384 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2385 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2386 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2387
2388 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2389 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2390 place.
2391 </para>
2392 <para>
2393 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2394 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2395 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2396 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2397 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2398 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2399 </para>
2400 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard</primary></indexterm>
2401 <para>
2402 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2403 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race
2404 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2405 is having an effect.
2406 </para>
2407 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent</primary></indexterm>
2408 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom</primary></indexterm>
2409 <para>
2410 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2411 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2412 <quote>misspoke</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2413 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2414 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2415 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2416 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2417 more instances of the same <quote>misspeaking</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2418 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2419 resign as senate majority leader.<footnote><para>
2420 <!-- f18 -->
2421 Noah Shachtman, <quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,</quote> New
2422 York Times, 16 January 2003, G5.
2423 </para></footnote>
2424 </para>
2425 <para>
2426 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2427 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2428 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2429 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2430 on.
2431 </para>
2432 <para>
2433 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2434 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2435 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2436 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2437 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2438 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2439 peer-generated rankings.
2440 </para>
2441 <indexterm id='idxwinerdave' class='startofrange'><primary>Winer, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2442 <para>
2443 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2444 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2445 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2446 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2447 difference is the absence of a financial <quote>conflict of interest.</quote> <quote>I think you
2448 have to take the conflict of interest</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2449 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2450 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2451 get it out of the way.</quote>
2452 </para>
2453 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2454 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2455 <para>
2456 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2457 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2458 from the public than an unconcentrated media can&mdash;as CNN admitted
2459 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2460 its own employees.<footnote><para>
2461 <!-- f19 -->
2462 Telephone interview with David Winer, 16 April 2003.
2463 </para></footnote>
2464 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2465 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2466 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2467 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2468 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2469 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2470 told her that <emphasis>they</emphasis> were writing <quote>the story.</quote>)
2471 </para>
2472 <para> Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2473 debate&mdash;<quote>amateur</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced, but in the
2474 sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to give their
2475 reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a story, as
2476 reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds from across
2477 the southwest United States turned to the Internet to retell what they
2478 had seen.<footnote><para>
2479 <!-- f20 -->
2480 John Schwartz, <quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2481 Information Online,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci
2482 D. Kramer, <quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,</quote>
2483 Online Journalism Review, 2 February 2003, available at
2484 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #10</ulink>.
2485 </para></footnote>
2486 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2487 <quote>triangulate,</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2488 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2489 out of it</quote>&mdash;with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2490 </para>
2491 <para>
2492 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2493 with blogs. <quote>It's going to become an essential skill,</quote> Winer predicts,
2494 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2495 not clear that <quote>journalism</quote> is happy about this&mdash;some journalists
2496 have been told to curtail their blogging.<footnote>
2497 <para>
2498 <!-- f21 -->
2499 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2500 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2501 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve</primary></indexterm>
2502 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2503 See Michael Falcone, <quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?</quote> <citetitle>New
2504 York Times</citetitle>, 29 September 2003, C4. (<quote>Not all news organizations have
2505 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2506 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2507 war on March 9, stopped posting 12 days later at his bosses'
2508 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a <citetitle>Houston Chronicle</citetitle> reporter, was
2509 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2510 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.</quote>)
2511 </para></footnote>
2512 But it is clear that we are still in transition. <quote>A
2513
2514 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2515 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,</quote> Winer told me.
2516 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2517 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2518 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, <quote>we will
2519 be the last thing that gets shut down.</quote>
2520 </para>
2521 <para>
2522 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because <quote>you
2523 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.</quote>
2524 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2525 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2526 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2527 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2528 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2529 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2530 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2531 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2532 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2533 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2534 extraordinary to report.
2535 </para>
2536 <indexterm startref='idxblogs1' class='endofrange'/>
2537 <indexterm startref="idxwinerdave" class='endofrange'/>
2538 <indexterm id='idxbrownjohnseely' class='startofrange'><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
2539 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2540 <para>
2541 <emphasis role='strong'>John Seely Brown</emphasis> is the chief
2542 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2543 describes it, is <quote>human learning and &hellip; the creation of
2544 knowledge ecologies for creating &hellip; innovation.</quote>
2545 </para>
2546 <para>
2547 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2548 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2549 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2550 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2551 affect learning.
2552 </para>
2553 <para>
2554 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When <quote>a lot of us grew up,</quote>
2555 he explains, that tinkering was done <quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2556 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.</quote> But digital technologies
2557 enable a different kind of tinkering&mdash;with abstract ideas though
2558 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2559 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2560 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2561 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2562 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2563 or <quote>free collage,</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2564 the tinkering of many others.
2565 </para>
2566 <para>
2567 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2568 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2569 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2570 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2571 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2572 </para>
2573 <para>
2574 This opportunity creates a <quote>completely new kind of learning platform,</quote>
2575 as Brown describes. <quote>As soon as you start doing that, you &hellip;
2576 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2577 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2578 if they can improve it.</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2579 apprenticeship. <quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.</quote>
2580 </para>
2581 <para>
2582 In this process, <quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2583 They are code.</quote> Kids are <quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2584 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2585 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2586 platform. &hellip; You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2587 you tinker the more you improve.</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2588 learn.
2589 </para>
2590 <para>
2591 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2592 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2593 it, <quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2594 intelligence.</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2595 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2596 text. <quote>The Web &hellip; says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2597 you are visual, if you are interested in film &hellip; [then] there is a
2598 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2599 these multiple forms of intelligence.</quote>
2600 </para>
2601 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'/>
2602 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2603 <para>
2604 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2605 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2606
2607 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2608 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2609 kind of recognition.
2610 </para>
2611 <para>
2612 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2613 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2614 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2615 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2616 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2617 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2618 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2619 </para>
2620 <para>
2621 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2622 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2623 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>)
2624 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the <quote>right to
2625 tinker</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2626 general.<footnote><para>
2627 <!-- f22 -->
2628 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, <quote>Technological Access
2629 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2630 of the Association for Computer Machinery</citetitle> 43 (2000): 9.
2631 </para></footnote>
2632 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2633 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2634 </para>
2635 <para>
2636 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,</quote> Brown
2637 explains. We need to <quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2638 and want to learn.</quote>
2639 </para>
2640 <para>
2641 <quote>Yet,</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2642 evince, <quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2643 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. &hellip; We're building an
2644 architecture that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2645 system that closes down that part of the brain.</quote>
2646 </para>
2647 <indexterm startref="idxbrownjohnseely" class='endofrange'/>
2648 <para>
2649 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2650 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2651 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2652 the law to close down that technology.
2653 </para>
2654 <para>
2655 <quote>No way to run a culture,</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2656 chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="collectors"/>,
2657 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2658 </para>
2659 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2660 </chapter>
2661 <chapter label="3" id="catalogs">
2662 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs</title>
2663 <indexterm><primary>RPI</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</see></indexterm>
2664 <indexterm id='idxrensselaer' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary></indexterm>
2665 <para>
2666 <emphasis role='strong'>In the fall</emphasis> of 2002, Jesse Jordan
2667 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2668 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2669 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2670 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2671 was available on the RPI network.
2672 </para>
2673 <para>
2674 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2675 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2676 to information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand
2677 undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school
2678 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2679 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2680 </para>
2681 <para>
2682 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2683 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2684 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2685 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2686 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2687 </para>
2688 <para>
2689 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2690 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2691 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2692 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2693 engines can do this even better. The idea of <quote>intranet</quote> search
2694 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2695 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2696 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2697 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2698 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2699 </para>
2700 <para>
2701 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2702 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2703 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2704 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2705 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2706 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2707 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2708 </para>
2709 <para>
2710 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2711 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2712 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2713 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2714 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2715 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2716 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2717 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2718 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2719 on-line.
2720 </para>
2721 <para>
2722 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2723 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2724 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2725 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2726 be on users' computers.
2727 </para>
2728 <para>
2729 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2730 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2731 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2732 might have created; university brochures&mdash;basically anything that
2733 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2734 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2735 computer.
2736 </para>
2737 <para>
2738 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2739 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2740 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and&mdash;so that this
2741 point is absolutely clear&mdash;Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2742 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2743 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2744 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2745 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2746 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2747 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2748 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2749 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2750 supposed to do.
2751 </para>
2752 <para>
2753 On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2754 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2755 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2756 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2757 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2758 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2759 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2760 </para>
2761 <para>
2762 <quote>It was absurd,</quote> he told me. <quote>I don't think I did anything
2763 wrong. &hellip; I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2764 engine that I ran or &hellip; what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2765 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2766 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2767 easier to use</quote>&mdash;again, a <emphasis>search engine</emphasis>,
2768 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2769 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2770 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2771 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2772 with music.
2773 </para>
2774 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages</primary></indexterm>
2775 <para>
2776 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2777 network and had therefore <quote>willfully</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2778 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2779 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2780 <quote>willful infringement,</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2781 call <quote>statutory damages.</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2782 claim $150,000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2783 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2784 Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000.
2785 </para>
2786 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University</primary></indexterm>
2787 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University</primary></indexterm>
2788 <para>
2789 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2790 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2791 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2792 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2793 huge demands for <quote>damages</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2794 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2795 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $100
2796 <emphasis>billion</emphasis>&mdash;six times the
2797 <emphasis>total</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2798 2001.<footnote><para>
2799
2800 <!-- f1 -->
2801 Tim Goral, <quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks:
2802 Suit Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages,</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC</citetitle> 6
2803 (2003): 5, available at 2003 WL 55179443.
2804 </para></footnote>
2805 </para>
2806 <indexterm startref="idxrensselaer" class='endofrange'/>
2807 <para>
2808 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2809 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2810 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2811 $12,000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2812 $12,000 to dismiss the case.
2813 </para>
2814 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt</primary></indexterm>
2815 <para>
2816 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2817 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2818 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2819 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2820 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2821 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2822 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, <quote>You don't want to pay another
2823 visit to a dentist like me.</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2824 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2825 </para>
2826 <para>
2827 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2828 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2829 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2830 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2831 at least $250,000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2832 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2833 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2834 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2835 </para>
2836 <para>
2837 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $250,000 and a chance at winning,
2838 or $12,000 and a settlement.
2839 </para>
2840 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
2841 <para>
2842 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2843 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2844 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2845 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2846 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $1 million a year.
2847 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2848 artist makes $45,900.<footnote><para>
2849 <!-- f2 -->
2850 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001)
2851 (27&ndash;2042&mdash;Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2852 the Arts, <citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon</citetitle> (2000).
2853 </para></footnote>
2854 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2855 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2856 student for running a search engine?<footnote><para>
2857 <!-- f3 -->
2858 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in <quote>KaZaA and Punishment,</quote>
2859 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, A24.
2860 </para></footnote>
2861 </para>
2862 <para>
2863 On June 23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2864 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2865 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $15 million lawsuit became an
2866 activist:
2867 </para>
2868 <blockquote>
2869 <para>
2870 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2871 an activist. &hellip; [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2872 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2873 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2874 </para>
2875 </blockquote>
2876 <para>
2877 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2878 his father told me, Jesse <quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
2879 I. &hellip; He's not a tree hugger. &hellip; I think it's bizarre that they would
2880 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2881 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.</quote>
2882 </para>
2883 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
2884 </chapter>
2885 <chapter label="4" id="pirates">
2886 <title>CHAPTER FOUR: <quote>Pirates</quote></title>
2887 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
2888 <para>
2889 <emphasis role='strong'>If <quote>piracy</quote> means</emphasis>
2890 using the creative property of others without their
2891 permission&mdash;if <quote>if value, then right</quote> is
2892 true&mdash;then the history of the content industry is a history of
2893 piracy. Every important sector of <quote>big media</quote>
2894 today&mdash;film, records, radio, and cable TV&mdash;was born of a
2895 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
2896 generation's pirates join this generation's country club&mdash;until
2897 now.
2898 </para>
2899 <section id="film">
2900 <title>Film</title>
2901 <para>
2902 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.<footnote><para>
2903 <!-- f1 -->
2904 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
2905 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
2906 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 87&ndash;93,
2907 which details Edison's <quote>adventures</quote> with copyright and patent.
2908 </para></footnote>
2909 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
2910 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
2911 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
2912 exercised through a monopoly <quote>trust,</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
2913 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
2914 property&mdash;patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
2915 this creative property
2916 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
2917 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
2918 </para>
2919 <para>
2920 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
2921 </para>
2922 <blockquote>
2923 <para>
2924 A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
2925 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
2926 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
2927 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
2928 summer of 1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
2929 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
2930 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
2931 </para>
2932 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William</primary></indexterm>
2933 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company</primary></indexterm>
2934 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
2935 <para>
2936 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
2937 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
2938 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
2939 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
2940 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
2941 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
2942 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
2943 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
2944 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
2945 license was revoked.<footnote><para>
2946 <!-- f2 -->
2947 J. A. Aberdeen, <citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
2948 Picture Producers</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts
2949 posted at <quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
2950 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,</quote> available at
2951 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #11</ulink>. For a
2952 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
2953 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, <quote>From
2954 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
2955 the Propertization of Copyright</quote> (September 2002), University of
2956 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
2957 Working Paper No. 159.
2958 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
2959 </para></footnote>
2960 </para>
2961 </blockquote>
2962 <para>
2963 The Napsters of those days, the <quote>independents,</quote> were companies like
2964 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
2965 resisted. <quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
2966 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
2967 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.</quote><footnote><para>
2968 <!-- f3 -->
2969 Marc Wanamaker, <quote>The First Studios,</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority</citetitle>, archived at
2970 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #12</ulink>.
2971 </para></footnote>
2972 That led the independents to flee the East
2973 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
2974 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
2975 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
2976 did just that.
2977 </para>
2978 <para>
2979 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
2980 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
2981 patent holder a truly <quote>limited</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
2982
2983 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
2984 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
2985 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
2986 Edison's creative property.
2987 </para>
2988 </section>
2989 <section id="recordedmusic">
2990 <title>Recorded Music</title>
2991 <para>
2992 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
2993 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
2994 </para>
2995 <indexterm id="idxfourneauxhenri" class='startofrange'><primary>Fourneaux, Henri</primary></indexterm>
2996 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil</primary></indexterm>
2997 <para>
2998 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
2999 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
3000 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
3001 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
3002 their music. In other words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
3003 1899 hit <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
3004 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
3005 right to perform it publicly.
3006 </para>
3007 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3008 <para>
3009 But what if I wanted to record <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> using Edison's phonograph
3010 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
3011 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
3012 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
3013 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
3014 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
3015 <quote>public performance</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
3016 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
3017 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
3018 brain are not&mdash;yet&mdash; regulated by copyright law). So if I
3019 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
3020 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
3021 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
3022 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
3023 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
3024 its composer anything.
3025 </para>
3026 <indexterm startref="idxfourneauxhenri" class='endofrange'/>
3027 <para>
3028 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
3029 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
3030 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
3031 put it,
3032 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3033 </para>
3034 <blockquote>
3035 <para>
3036 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3037 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3038 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3039 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3040 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3041 rights.<footnote><para>
3042 <!-- f4 -->
3043 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3044 S. 6330 and H.R. 19853 Before the ( Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th
3045 Cong. 59, 1st sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3046 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in <citetitle>Legislative History of the
3047 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3048 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3049 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3050 </para></footnote>
3051 </para>
3052 </blockquote>
3053 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip</primary></indexterm>
3054 <para>
3055 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3056 people's works were <quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3057 genius of American composers,</quote><footnote><para>
3058 <!-- f5 -->
3059 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223
3060 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3061 </para></footnote>
3062 and the <quote>music publishing industry</quote>
3063 was thereby <quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.</quote><footnote><para>
3064 <!-- f6 -->
3065 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226
3066 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3067 </para></footnote>
3068 As John Philip
3069 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, <quote>When they make money
3070 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.</quote><footnote><para>
3071 <!-- f7 -->
3072 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23
3073 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3074 </para></footnote>
3075 </para>
3076 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company</primary></indexterm>
3077 <indexterm><primary>player pianos</primary></indexterm>
3078 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
3079 <para>
3080 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3081 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3082 player piano argued that <quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3083 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3084 of anything he had before their introduction.</quote> Rather, the machines
3085 increased the sales of sheet music.<footnote><para>
3086 <!-- f8 -->
3087
3088 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283&ndash;84
3089 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3090 Perforating Company of New York).
3091 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3092 Congress was <quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3093 they represent, and whose servants they are.</quote> <quote>All talk about
3094 `theft,'</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3095 wrote, <quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3096 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3097 statute.</quote><footnote><para>
3098 <!-- f9 -->
3099 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared
3100 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3101 Graphophone Company Association).
3102 </para></footnote>
3103 </para>
3104 <para>
3105 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3106 <emphasis>and</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3107 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the <quote>mechanical
3108 reproductions</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3109 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3110 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3111 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3112 recorded once. This is the part of
3113
3114 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3115 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3116 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3117 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3118 </para>
3119 <para>
3120 American law ordinarily calls this a <quote>compulsory license,</quote> but I will
3121 refer to it as a <quote>statutory license.</quote> A statutory license is a license
3122 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3123 Copyright Act in 1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3124 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3125 the fee set by the statute.
3126 </para>
3127 <para>
3128 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3129 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3130 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3131 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3132 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3133 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3134 Grisham.
3135 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
3136 </para>
3137 <para>
3138 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3139 thus, in effect, the law <emphasis>subsidizes</emphasis> the recording
3140 industry through a kind of piracy&mdash;by giving recording artists a
3141 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3142 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3143 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3144 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3145 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3146 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3147 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3148 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3149 creativity.<footnote><para>
3150
3151 <!-- f10 -->
3152 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and
3153 H.R. 11794 Before the ( Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st
3154 sess., 217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3155 in <citetitle>Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3156 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3157 </para></footnote>
3158 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3159 </para>
3160 <para>
3161 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3162 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3163 records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3164 relates,
3165 </para>
3166 <blockquote>
3167 <para>
3168 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3169 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3170 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3171 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3172 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3173 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3174 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3175 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3176 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before 1909 and
3177 the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3178 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3179 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3180 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3181 choice.<footnote><para>
3182 <!-- f11 -->
3183 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee
3184 on the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8
3185 March 1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3186 this report.</para></footnote>
3187 </para>
3188 </blockquote>
3189 <para>
3190 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3191 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3192 </para>
3193 </section>
3194 <section id="radio">
3195 <title>Radio</title>
3196 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments1' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
3197 <para>
3198 Radio was also born of piracy.
3199 </para>
3200 <para>
3201 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3202 <quote>public performance</quote> of the composer's work.<footnote><para>
3203 <!-- f12 -->
3204 See 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning,
3205 record companies printed <quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast</quote> and other
3206 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3207 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3208 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3209 station. See <citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Whiteman</citetitle>, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd
3210 Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3211 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3212 Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 281.
3213 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned</primary></indexterm>
3214 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3215 </para></footnote>
3216 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3217 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3218 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3219 </para>
3220 <para>
3221 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3222 copy of the <emphasis>composer's</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3223 also performing a copy of the <emphasis>recording artist's</emphasis>
3224 work. It's one thing to have <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> sung on the radio by the
3225 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3226 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3227 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3228 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3229 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3230 music for his work.
3231 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
3232
3233 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3234 </para>
3235 <para>
3236 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3237 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3238 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3239 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3240 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3241 of playing the song.
3242 </para>
3243 <indexterm id="idxmadonna" class='startofrange'><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3244 <para>
3245 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3246 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3247 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3248 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3249 </para>
3250 <para>
3251 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3252 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3253 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3254 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3255 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3256 <quote>protected</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3257 <emphasis>pirate</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3258 her anything.
3259 </para>
3260 <indexterm startref="idxmadonna" class='endofrange'/>
3261 <para>
3262 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3263 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3264 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3265 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3266 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3267 to take something for nothing.
3268 </para>
3269 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments1' class='endofrange'/>
3270 </section>
3271 <section id="cabletv">
3272 <title>Cable TV</title>
3273 <indexterm id='idxcabletv1' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
3274 <para>
3275 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3276 </para>
3277 <para>
3278 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3279 television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3280 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3281 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3282 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3283 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3284 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3285 did&mdash; Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3286 give away.
3287 </para>
3288 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas</primary></indexterm>
3289 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin</primary></indexterm>
3290 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3291 <para>
3292 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3293 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3294 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.</quote><footnote><para>
3295 <!-- f13 -->
3296 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the
3297 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3298 Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966)
3299 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3300 Commission).
3301 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3302 </para></footnote>
3303 There may have been a <quote>public interest</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3304 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3305 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, <quote>Does public
3306 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?</quote><footnote><para>
3307 <!-- f14 -->
3308 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3309 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3310 </para></footnote>
3311 As another broadcaster put it,
3312 </para>
3313 <blockquote>
3314 <para>
3315 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3316 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3317 paid for.<footnote><para>
3318 <!-- f15 -->
3319 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3320 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3321 </para></footnote>
3322 </para>
3323 </blockquote>
3324 <para>
3325 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3326 </para>
3327 <blockquote>
3328 <para>
3329 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3330 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3331 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3332 think there are harsher words which would fit it.<footnote><para>
3333 <!-- f16 -->
3334 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3335 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3336 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3337 </para></footnote>
3338 </para>
3339 </blockquote>
3340 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3341 <para>
3342 These were <quote>free-ride[rs],</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3343 Heston said, who were <quote>depriving actors of
3344 compensation.</quote><footnote><para>
3345 <!-- f17 -->
3346 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3347 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3348 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3349 </para>
3350 </footnote>
3351 </para>
3352 <para>
3353 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3354 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3355 </para>
3356 <blockquote>
3357 <para>
3358 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3359 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3360 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3361 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. &hellip; The
3362
3363 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3364 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3365 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.<footnote><para>
3366 <!-- f18 -->
3367 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M.
3368 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3369 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3370 </para></footnote>
3371 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3372 </para>
3373 </blockquote>
3374 <para>
3375 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3376 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3377 </para>
3378 <para>
3379 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3380 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they <quote>pirated.</quote>
3381 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3382 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3383 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3384 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3385 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3386 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3387 companies thus built their empire in part upon a <quote>piracy</quote> of the value
3388 created by broadcasters' content.
3389 </para>
3390 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv1' class='endofrange'/>
3391 <para>
3392 <emphasis role='strong'>These separate stories</emphasis> sing a
3393 common theme. If <quote>piracy</quote> means using value from someone
3394 else's creative property without permission from that creator&mdash;as
3395 it is increasingly described today<footnote><para>
3396 <!-- f19 -->
3397 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, <citetitle>The Engine
3398 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet&mdash;The Myth of Free
3399 Information</citetitle>, available at
3400 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #13</ulink>. <quote>The
3401 threat of piracy&mdash;the use of someone else's creative work without
3402 permission or compensation&mdash;has grown with the Internet.</quote>
3403 </para></footnote>
3404 &mdash; then <emphasis>every</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3405 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3406 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV. &hellip; The list is long and
3407 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3408 last. Every generation&mdash;until now.
3409 </para>
3410 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3411 </section>
3412 </chapter>
3413 <chapter label="5" id="piracy">
3414 <title>CHAPTER FIVE: <quote>Piracy</quote></title>
3415 <para>
3416 <emphasis role='strong'>There is piracy</emphasis> of copyrighted
3417 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3418 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3419 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3420 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3421 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3422 </para>
3423 <para>
3424 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of <quote>taking</quote>
3425 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3426 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3427 taking <quote>piracy,</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3428 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3429 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3430 has so often done in the past.
3431 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3432 </para>
3433 <section id="piracy-i">
3434 <title>Piracy I</title>
3435 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3436 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3437 <para>
3438 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3439 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3440 content, copy it, and sell it&mdash;all without the permission of a copyright
3441 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion
3442 every year to physical piracy<footnote><para>
3443 <!-- f1 -->
3444 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), <citetitle>The
3445 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003</citetitle>, July 2003, available
3446 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #14</ulink>. See
3447 also Ben Hunt, <quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3448 Times</citetitle>, 14 February 2003, 11.
3449 </para></footnote>
3450 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3451 estimates that it loses $3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3452 </para>
3453 <para>
3454 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3455 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3456 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3457 This piracy is wrong.
3458 </para>
3459 <para>
3460 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3461 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3462 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3463 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3464 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3465 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3466 of our existence, treated as right.
3467 </para>
3468 <para>
3469 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3470 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3471 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3472 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3473 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3474 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3475 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3476 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3477 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3478 </para>
3479 <para>
3480 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3481 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3482 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3483 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3484 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3485 similar childhood.
3486 </para>
3487 <para>
3488 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3489 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3490 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3491 of intellectual property law.<footnote><para>
3492 <!-- f2 -->
3493 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3494 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The
3495 New Press, 2003), 10&ndash;13, 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3496 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3497 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3498 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3499 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3500 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3501 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3502 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3503 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3504 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3505 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3506 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3507 TRIPS framework.
3508 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents</primary></indexterm>
3509 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
3510 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3511 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3512 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3513 is wrong.
3514 </para>
3515 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3516 <para>
3517 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3518 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3519 to American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3520 bought those American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any
3521 less money than they otherwise would have had.<footnote><para>
3522 <!-- f3 -->
3523 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3524 Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002),
3525 144&ndash;90. <quote>In some instances &hellip; the impact of piracy on the
3526 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3527 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3528 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3529 pirating were not an option.</quote> Ibid., 149.
3530 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3531 </para></footnote>
3532 </para>
3533 <para>
3534 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3535 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3536 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3537 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3538 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes &amp; Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3539 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?</quote>
3540 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes &amp;
3541 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3542 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3543 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3544 piracy of the tangible.
3545 </para>
3546 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'/>
3547 <para>
3548 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3549 property right of a very special sort, it <emphasis>is</emphasis> a
3550 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3551 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3552 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3553 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3554 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3555 give people the right to <quote>take</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3556 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3557
3558 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3559 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3560 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3561 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3562 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3563 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what <quote>property</quote> means.
3564 </para>
3565 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3566 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
3567 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
3568 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3569 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3570 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of</secondary></indexterm>
3571 <indexterm><primary>Windows</primary></indexterm>
3572 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>international software piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3573 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of</secondary></indexterm>
3574 <para>
3575 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3576 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese <quote>steal</quote>
3577 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3578 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3579 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3580 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3581 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3582 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3583 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3584 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3585 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3586 </para>
3587 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
3588 <para>
3589 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3590 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3591 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3592 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3593 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3594 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3595 </para>
3596 <indexterm><primary>Netscape</primary></indexterm>
3597 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer</primary></indexterm>
3598 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3599 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3600 <para>
3601 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3602 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3603 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3604 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3605 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3606 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3607 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3608 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3609 what&mdash;at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3610 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3611 violating the law is still wrong.
3612 </para>
3613 <para>
3614 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3615 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3616 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3617 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3618 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3619 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3620 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3621 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3622 is flat out wrong.
3623 </para>
3624 <para>
3625 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3626 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is. Or
3627 at least, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3628 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of <quote>piracy</quote> are useful
3629 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3630 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3631 <quote>piracy</quote> in that sense of the term.
3632 </para>
3633 <para>
3634 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3635 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3636 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3637 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3638 </para>
3639 <para>
3640 For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3641 controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it
3642 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable
3643 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3644 </para>
3645 <para>
3646 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3647 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3648 sharing to survive.
3649 </para>
3650 </section>
3651 <section id="piracy-ii">
3652 <title>Piracy II</title>
3653 <para>
3654 The key to the <quote>piracy</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that <quote>rob[s]
3655 the author of [his] profit.</quote><footnote><para>
3656 <!-- f4 -->
3657 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777).
3658 </para></footnote>
3659 This means we must determine whether
3660 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3661 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3662 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3663 author of his profit.
3664 </para>
3665 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3666 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn</primary></indexterm>
3667 <para>
3668 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3669 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3670 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3671 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well<footnote><para>
3672 <!-- f5 -->
3673 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3674 See Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3675 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle> (New York:
3676 HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3677 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3678 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3679 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3680 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3681 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 89&ndash;92, 139.
3682
3683 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
3684 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3685 put together components that had been developed independently.
3686 </para>
3687 <para>
3688 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999,
3689 Napster amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After
3690 eighteen months, there were close to 80 million registered users of the
3691 system.<footnote><para>
3692 <!-- f6 -->
3693 See Carolyn Lochhead, <quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,</quote> <citetitle>San
3694 Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24 September 2002, A1; <quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,</quote>
3695 <citetitle>New Scientist</citetitle>, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Napster Names CEO,
3696 Secures New Financing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 23 May 2003, C1;
3697 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton,
3698 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet</quote> (London) <citetitle>Times</citetitle>, 26 July 2002, 18.
3699 </para></footnote>
3700 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3701 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3702 boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3703 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3704 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3705 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend&mdash;
3706 or your 20,000 best friends.
3707 </para>
3708 <para>
3709 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3710 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3711 September 2002 estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded
3712 music&mdash;28 percent of Americans older than 12.<footnote><para>
3713
3714 <!-- f7 -->
3715 See Ipsos-Insight, <citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution</citetitle>
3716 (September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3717 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have
3718 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3719 </para></footnote>
3720 A survey by the NPD group quoted in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>
3721 estimated that 43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3722 exchange content in May 2003.<footnote><para>
3723 <!-- f8 -->
3724 Amy Harmon, <quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,</quote> <citetitle>New
3725 York Times</citetitle>, 6 June 2003, A1.
3726 </para></footnote>
3727 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3728 massive quantity of content is being <quote>taken</quote> on these networks. The
3729 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3730 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3731 </para>
3732 <para>
3733 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3734 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3735 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3736 complicated than one might think. So consider&mdash;a bit more
3737 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3738 do&mdash;the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3739 of harm it entails.
3740 </para>
3741 <para>
3742 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3743 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3744 different kinds into four types.
3745 </para>
3746 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
3747 <listitem>
3748 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3749 <para>
3750 <!-- A. -->
3751 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3752 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3753 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3754 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3755 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3756 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3757 users who download instead of purchasing.
3758 </para></listitem>
3759 <listitem><para>
3760 <!-- B. -->
3761 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3762 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3763 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3764 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3765 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3766 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3767 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3768 music purchased.
3769 </para></listitem>
3770 <listitem><para>
3771 <!-- C. -->
3772 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3773 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3774 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3775 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3776 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3777 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3778 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend <quote>recalling</quote> old
3779 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3780 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3781 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3782 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero&mdash;the same
3783 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to
3784 a local collector.
3785 </para></listitem>
3786 <listitem><para>
3787 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3788 <!-- D. -->
3789 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3790 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3791 wants to give away.
3792 </para></listitem>
3793 </orderedlist>
3794 <para>
3795 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3796 </para>
3797 <para>
3798 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3799 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3800 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3801 harmful.<footnote><para>
3802 <!-- f9 -->
3803 See Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle>, 148&ndash;49.
3804 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3805 </para></footnote>
3806 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3807 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3808 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3809 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3810 answer&mdash;and certainly much more difficult than the current
3811 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3812 </para>
3813 <para>
3814 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3815 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3816 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3817 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3818 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of <quote>theft</quote> that is
3819 <quote>devastating</quote> the industry.
3820 </para>
3821 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
3822 <para>
3823 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3824 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3825 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3826 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3827 &amp; Young put it, <quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3828 technology, the labels fought it.</quote><footnote><para>
3829 <!-- f10 -->
3830 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary></indexterm>
3831 See Cap Gemini Ernst &amp; Young, <citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
3832 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis</citetitle> (2003), 3. This report
3833 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3834 practice of cassette taping in the 1970s, including an advertising
3835 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption <quote>Home taping
3836 is killing music.</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3837 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3838 behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3839 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3840 Assessment, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law</citetitle>,
3841 OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3842 October 1989), 145&ndash;56. </para></footnote>
3843 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3844 when record sales fell by 11.4 percent in 1981, the industry claimed
3845 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3846 regulating technology was the answer.
3847 </para>
3848 <indexterm><primary>MTV</primary></indexterm>
3849 <para>
3850 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3851 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3852 turnaround. <quote>In the end,</quote> Cap Gemini concludes, <quote>the `crisis' &hellip; was
3853 not the fault of the tapers&mdash;who did not [stop after MTV came into
3854 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
3855 being]&mdash;but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
3856 innovation at the major labels.</quote><footnote><para>
3857 <!-- f11 -->
3858 U.S. Congress, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying</citetitle>, 4.
3859 </para></footnote>
3860 </para>
3861 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'/>
3862 <para>
3863 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
3864 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
3865 the industry in particular, and society in general&mdash;or at least
3866 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
3867 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
3868 VCR&mdash;the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
3869 harmful. The question is also <emphasis>how</emphasis> harmful type A
3870 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
3871 </para>
3872 <para>
3873 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
3874 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
3875 The <quote>net harm</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
3876 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
3877 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
3878 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
3879 therefore have little <emphasis>static</emphasis> reason to resist
3880 them.
3881
3882 </para>
3883 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>sales levels of</secondary></indexterm>
3884 <para>
3885 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
3886 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
3887 actually suggest it might be close.
3888 </para>
3889 <para>
3890 In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9 percent,
3891 from 882 million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7
3892 percent.<footnote><para>
3893 <!-- f12 -->
3894 See Recording Industry Association of America, <citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics</citetitle>,
3895 available at
3896 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #15</ulink>. A later
3897 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
3898 Association of America, <citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy</citetitle>, 25 June 2003,
3899 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
3900 #16</ulink>: <quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
3901 have fallen by 26 percent from 1.16 billion units in to 860 million
3902 units in 2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
3903 of sales, revenues are down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in to $12.6
3904 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
3905 industry worldwide has gone from a $39 billion industry in 2000 down
3906 to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
3907 shipments).</quote>
3908 </para></footnote>
3909 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
3910 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
3911 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
3912 than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That no
3913 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
3914 account for at least some of the loss. <quote>From 1999 to 2001, the average
3915 price of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19.</quote><footnote>
3916 <!-- f13 -->
3917 <para>
3918 Jane Black, <quote>Big Music's Broken Record,</quote> BusinessWeek online, 13
3919 February 2003, available at
3920 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #17</ulink>.
3921 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane</primary></indexterm>
3922 </para>
3923 </footnote>
3924 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
3925 the decline. As Jane Black of <citetitle>BusinessWeek</citetitle> notes, <quote>The
3926 soundtrack to the film <citetitle>High Fidelity</citetitle> has a list price of
3927 $18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
3928 $19.99.</quote><footnote><para>
3929 <!-- f14 -->
3930 Ibid.
3931 </para></footnote>
3932 </para>
3933 <para>
3934
3935 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
3936 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
3937 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
3938 that the RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
3939 estimates that 2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
3940 although 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
3941 free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 percent.
3942 </para>
3943 <para>
3944 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
3945 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
3946 The recording industry constantly asks, <quote>What's the difference between
3947 downloading a song and stealing a CD?</quote>&mdash;but their own numbers
3948 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
3949 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
3950 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
3951 downloads. If every download were a lost sale&mdash;if every use of
3952 Kazaa <quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit</quote>&mdash;then the industry
3953 would have suffered a 100 percent drop in sales last year, not a 7
3954 percent drop. If 2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
3955 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, then there is
3956 a huge difference between <quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.</quote>
3957 </para>
3958 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'/>
3959 <para>
3960 These are the harms&mdash;alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
3961 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
3962 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
3963 these costs?
3964 </para>
3965 <para>
3966 One benefit is type C sharing&mdash;making available content that
3967 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
3968 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
3969 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
3970 available.<footnote><para>
3971 <!-- f15 -->
3972 By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels
3973 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
3974 Law&mdash;Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
3975 Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April
3976 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
3977 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #18</ulink>.
3978 </para></footnote>
3979 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
3980 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
3981 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
3982 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
3983 sense <emphasis>to the company</emphasis> to make it available.
3984 </para>
3985 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
3986 <para>
3987 In real space&mdash;long before the Internet&mdash;the market had a simple
3988 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
3989 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
3990 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
3991 today.<footnote><para>
3992 <!-- f16 -->
3993 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
3994 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
3995 in existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the
3996 United States, an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter
3997 Press, <citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
3998 Market</citetitle> (2002), available at
3999 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #19</ulink>. Used
4000 records accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See National
4001 Association of Recording Merchandisers, <quote>2002 Annual Survey
4002 Results,</quote> available at
4003 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #20</ulink>.
4004 </para></footnote>
4005 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
4006 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
4007 content, <emphasis>even if the content is still under
4008 copyright</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
4009 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
4010 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
4011 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
4012 the content they sell.
4013 </para>
4014 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard</primary></indexterm>
4015 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
4016 <para>
4017 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
4018 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
4019 the content available isn't making money from making the content
4020 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
4021 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
4022 when someone shares my 1949 recording of Bernstein's <quote>Two Love Songs,</quote>
4023 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
4024 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
4025 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
4026 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
4027 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
4028 </para>
4029 <para>
4030 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
4031 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
4032 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
4033 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
4034 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
4035 shut as well?
4036 </para>
4037 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
4038 <para>
4039 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4040 type D sharing to occur&mdash;the sharing of content that copyright owners
4041 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4042 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4043 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
4044 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4045
4046 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4047 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4048 would be a great advertisement for the <quote>real</quote> book. People would read
4049 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4050 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4051 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4052 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4053 great book!)
4054 </para>
4055 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'/>
4056 <para>
4057 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4058 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4059 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4060 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4061 </para>
4062 <para>
4063 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4064 understandably says, <quote>This is how much we've lost,</quote> we must also ask,
4065 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4066 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4067 unavailable?</quote>
4068 </para>
4069 <para>
4070 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4071 chapter, much of the <quote>piracy</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4072 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4073 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="pirates"/>, much of
4074 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4075 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4076 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4077 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4078 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4079 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4080 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4081 found only with time.
4082 </para>
4083 <para>
4084 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4085 just what you call type A sharing?</quote>
4086 </para>
4087 <para>
4088 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The
4089 effect
4090 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4091 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4092 Napster
4093 case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4094 developed
4095 a technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of identified
4096 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4097 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4
4098 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4099 <quote>down to zero.</quote><footnote><para>
4100 <!-- f17 -->
4101 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34-
4102 35 (N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183
4103 MHP, available at
4104
4105 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #21</ulink>. For an
4106 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4107 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster</citetitle> (New
4108 York: Crown Business, 2003), 269&ndash;82.
4109 </para></footnote>
4110 </para>
4111 <para>
4112 If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4113 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4114 assure that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance
4115 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of
4116 VCRs or 100 percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns
4117 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4118 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4119 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4120 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4121 </para>
4122 <para>
4123 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4124 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4125 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4126 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4127 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4128 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4129 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4130 </para>
4131 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
4132 <para>
4133 So, as we've seen, when <quote>mechanical reproduction</quote> threatened the
4134 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4135 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4136 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4137 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4138 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4139 complained to Congress that their <quote>creative property</quote> was not being
4140 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4141 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4142 benefit was enough.
4143 </para>
4144 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
4145 <para>
4146 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4147 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4148 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4149 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4150 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4151 price.
4152 </para>
4153 <para>
4154
4155 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4156 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4157 pianos, served two important goals&mdash;indeed, the two central goals
4158 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4159 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4160 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4161 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4162 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4163 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4164 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4165 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4166 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4167 Congress chose a path that would assure
4168 <emphasis>compensation</emphasis> without giving the past
4169 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4170 </para>
4171 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'/>
4172 <indexterm><primary>Betamax</primary></indexterm>
4173 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
4174 <para>
4175 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4176 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4177 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4178 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4179 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4180 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4181 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4182 <quote>record</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4183 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4184 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4185 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4186 </para>
4187 <para>
4188 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4189 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4190 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4191 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4192 machine to copy only if there were a special <quote>copy me</quote> signal on the
4193 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4194 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4195 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4196 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4197 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4198 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4199 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4200 for the architecture it chose.
4201 </para>
4202 <para>
4203 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4204 champion. Valenti called VCRs <quote>tapeworms.</quote> He warned, <quote>When there are
4205 20, 30, 40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4206 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4207 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4208 copyright.</quote><footnote><para>
4209 <!-- f18 -->
4210 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4211 S. 1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st
4212 and 2nd sess., 459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4213 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4214 </para></footnote>
4215 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4216 creative judgment,</quote> he told Congress, <quote>to understand the devastation
4217 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4218 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4219 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4220 and plain common sense.</quote><footnote><para>
4221 <!-- f19 -->
4222 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475.
4223 </para></footnote>
4224 Indeed, as surveys would later show,
4225 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more<footnote><para>
4226 <!-- f20 -->
4227 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 480 F. Supp. 429,
4228 (C.D. Cal., 1979).
4229 </para></footnote>
4230 &mdash; a use the Court would later hold was not <quote>fair.</quote> By
4231 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4232 copyright infringementwithout creating a mechanism to compensate
4233 copyrightowners,</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would <quote>take from the
4234 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4235 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4236 profit from its reproduction.</quote><footnote><para>
4237 <!-- f21 -->
4238 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony
4239 of Jack Valenti).
4240 </para></footnote>
4241 </para>
4242 <para>
4243 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4244 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4245 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction&mdash;leading Judge Alex
4246 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the <quote>Hollywood
4247 Circuit</quote>&mdash;held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4248 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4249 rule, this totally familiar technology&mdash;which Jack Valenti had
4250 called <quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry</quote> (worse
4251 yet, it was a <emphasis>Japanese</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4252 American film industry)&mdash;was an illegal
4253 technology.<footnote><para>
4254 <!-- f22 -->
4255 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th Cir.
4256 1981).
4257 </para></footnote>
4258 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex</primary></indexterm>
4259 </para>
4260 <para>
4261 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4262
4263 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4264 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4265 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4266 Court wrote,
4267 </para>
4268 <blockquote>
4269 <para>
4270 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4271 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4272 market
4273 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4274 authority
4275 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4276 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4277 implicated
4278 by such new technology.<footnote><para>
4279 <!-- f23 -->
4280 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417, 431 (1984).
4281 </para></footnote>
4282 </para>
4283 </blockquote>
4284 <para>
4285 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4286 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4287 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4288 enough, this <quote>taking</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4289 together, a pattern is clear:
4290 </para>
4291
4292 <informaltable id="t1">
4293 <tgroup cols="4" align="left">
4294 <thead>
4295 <row>
4296 <entry>CASE</entry>
4297 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS <quote>PIRATED</quote></entry>
4298 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS</entry>
4299 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS</entry>
4300 </row>
4301 </thead>
4302 <tbody>
4303 <row>
4304 <entry>Recordings</entry>
4305 <entry>Composers</entry>
4306 <entry>No protection</entry>
4307 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4308 </row>
4309 <row>
4310 <entry>Radio</entry>
4311 <entry>Recording artists</entry>
4312 <entry>N/A</entry>
4313 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4314 </row>
4315 <row>
4316 <entry>Cable TV</entry>
4317 <entry>Broadcasters</entry>
4318 <entry>No protection</entry>
4319 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4320 </row>
4321 <row>
4322 <entry>VCR</entry>
4323 <entry>Film creators</entry>
4324 <entry>No protection</entry>
4325 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4326 </row>
4327 </tbody>
4328 </tgroup>
4329 </informaltable>
4330 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'/>
4331 <para>
4332 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4333 way content was distributed.<footnote><para>
4334 <!-- f24 -->
4335 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4336 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4337 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4338 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4339 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4340 1992 (Title 17 of the <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat.
4341 4237, codified at 17 U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4342 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4343 Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 71. See also Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,</quote>
4344 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 293&ndash;96.
4345 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
4346 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
4347 </para></footnote>
4348 In each case, throughout our history,
4349 that change meant that someone got a <quote>free ride</quote> on someone else's
4350 work.
4351 </para>
4352 <para>
4353 In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4354 Congress eliminate all free riding. In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of
4355 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4356 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4357 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of <quote>piracy.</quote>
4358 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4359 the behavior of the <quote>pirates.</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4360 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4361 interests at stake.
4362 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4363 </para>
4364 <para>
4365 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4366 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4367 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4368 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4369 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4370 regulated?
4371 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4372 to $15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4373 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4374 permission to record a song?
4375 </para>
4376 <para>
4377 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4378 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4379 copyright <quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4380 over all possible uses of his work.</quote><footnote><para>
4381 <!-- f25 -->
4382 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
4383 (1984).
4384 </para></footnote>
4385 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4386 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4387 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4388 balancing has historically been done <emphasis>after</emphasis> a
4389 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4390 facilitate the distribution of content.
4391 </para>
4392 <para>
4393 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4394 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4395 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4396 should not become a tool for <quote>stealing</quote> from artists. But neither
4397 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4398 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4399 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4400 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4401 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4402 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4403 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4404 public interest that innovation continue.
4405 </para>
4406 <para>
4407
4408 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4409 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4410 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4411 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4412 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4413 efficient. Yet these <quote>potential public benefits,</quote> as John Schwartz
4414 writes in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, <quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4415 fight.</quote><footnote><para>
4416 <!-- f26 -->
4417 John Schwartz, <quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4418 Echoes Past Efforts,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 September 2003, C3.
4419 </para></footnote>
4420 </para>
4421 <para>
4422 <emphasis role='strong'>Yet when anyone</emphasis> begins to talk
4423 about <quote>balance,</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4424 argument. <quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4425 incentives,</quote> they say, <quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4426 content,</quote> the warriors insist, <quote>is our
4427 <emphasis>property</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4428 `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4429 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4430 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether
4431 the car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?</quote>
4432 </para>
4433 <para>
4434 <quote>It is <emphasis>our property</emphasis>,</quote> the warriors
4435 insist. <quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4436 is protected.</quote>
4437 </para>
4438 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4439 </section>
4440 </chapter>
4441 </part>
4442 <part id="c-property">
4443 <title><quote>PROPERTY</quote></title>
4444 <partintro>
4445 <para>
4446
4447 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4448 <emphasis role='strong'>The copyright warriors</emphasis> are right: A
4449 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4450 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4451 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4452 that partially determine the price she can get.
4453 </para>
4454 <para>
4455 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a <quote>property</quote> right is a
4456 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4457 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4458 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4459 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4460 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4461 when I take the good <emphasis>idea</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4462 table in the backyard&mdash;by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4463 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4464 then?
4465 </para>
4466 <para>
4467 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4468 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4469 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4470 in the ordinary case&mdash;indeed, in practically every case except for a
4471 narrow
4472 range of exceptions&mdash;ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4473 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress&mdash;though I
4474 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4475 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4476 when I copy the way someone else dresses), <quote>He who receives an idea
4477 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4478 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.</quote><footnote><para>
4479 <!-- f1 -->
4480 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in
4481 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson</citetitle>, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4482 Ellery Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333&ndash;34.
4483 </para></footnote>
4484 </para>
4485 <para>
4486 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4487 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4488 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4489 expression
4490 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4491 property.
4492 </para>
4493 <para>
4494 But how, and to what extent, and in what form&mdash;the details,
4495 in other words&mdash;matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4496 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4497 <quote>property</quote> in its proper context.<footnote><para>
4498 <!-- f2 -->
4499 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4500 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4501 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4502 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4503 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4504 Adam Mossoff, <quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,</quote>
4505 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review</citetitle> 45 (2003): 373, 429 n. 241.
4506 </para></footnote>
4507 </para>
4508 <para>
4509 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4510 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4511 <quote>copyright material is property</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4512 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4513 these stories, the significance of this true
4514 statement&mdash;<quote>copyright material is property</quote>&mdash; will be a bit
4515 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4516 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4517 </para>
4518 </partintro>
4519
4520 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4521 <chapter label="6" id="founders">
4522 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders</title>
4523 <indexterm><primary>Henry V</primary></indexterm>
4524 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4525 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for</secondary></indexterm>
4526 <para>
4527 <emphasis role='strong'>William Shakespeare</emphasis> wrote
4528 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> in 1595. The play was first
4529 published in 1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4530 written. He would continue to write plays through 1613, and the plays
4531 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4532 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4533 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4534 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4535 Henry V: <quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4536 clichés.</quote>
4537 </para>
4538 <para>
4539 In 1774, almost 180 years after <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> was written, the
4540 <quote>copy-right</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4541 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.<footnote><para>
4542 <!-- f1 -->
4543 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben</primary></indexterm>
4544 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John</primary></indexterm>
4545 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4546 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4547 handsome <quote>definitive editions</quote> of classic works. In addition to <citetitle>Romeo and
4548 Juliet</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4549 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4550 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, <quote>Jacob Tonson,
4551 Bookseller,</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar</citetitle> 61:3 (1992): 424&ndash;31.
4552 </para></footnote>
4553 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4554 the Conger<footnote><para>
4555 <!-- f2 -->
4556 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle> (Nashville:
4557 Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 151&ndash;52.
4558 </para></footnote>
4559 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4560 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the <quote>copy</quote> of
4561 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4562 that no
4563 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4564 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4565 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4566 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4567 </para>
4568 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4569 <para>
4570 Now, there's something puzzling about the year 1774 to anyone who
4571 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4572 history of copyright is 1710, the year that the British Parliament
4573 adopted the first <quote>copyright</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4574 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4575 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4576 works already published by 1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4577 additional years.<footnote><para>
4578 <!-- f3 -->
4579 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4580 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4581 <quote>copyright law.</quote> See Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 40.
4582 </para></footnote> Under this law, <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> should have been
4583 free in 1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4584 Tonson's control in 1774?
4585 </para>
4586 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (1662)</primary></indexterm>
4587 <para>
4588 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a <quote>copyright</quote>
4589 was&mdash;indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4590 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4591 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of 1662, had
4592 expired in 1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4593 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4594 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4595 that the publishers, or <quote>Stationers,</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4596 books.
4597 </para>
4598 <para>
4599 There was no <emphasis>positive</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4600 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4601 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4602 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4603 from legislatures <quote>positive law.</quote> We call the words from judges
4604 <quote>common law.</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4605 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4606 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4607 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4608 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4609 </para>
4610 <para>
4611 This question was important to the publishers, or <quote>booksellers,</quote> as
4612 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4613 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4614 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4615
4616 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4617 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4618 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4619 ultimately
4620 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4621 </para>
4622 <para>
4623 The Statute of Anne granted the author or <quote>proprietor</quote> of a book an
4624 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4625 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4626 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4627 copyright <quote>expired,</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4628 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4629 believed.
4630 </para>
4631 <para>
4632 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4633 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4634 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4635 <emphasis>at all?</emphasis>
4636 </para>
4637 <para>
4638 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4639 strong claim. Take <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> as an example: That play
4640 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4641 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4642 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4643 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4644 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4645 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4646 reason is there to allow someone else to <quote>steal</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4647 </para>
4648 <para>
4649 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4650 about the notion of <quote>copyright</quote> that existed at the time of the
4651 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4652 <quote>booksellers.</quote>
4653 </para>
4654 <para>
4655 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4656 to apply the concept of <quote>copyright</quote> ever more broadly. But in 1710, it
4657 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4658 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4659 others from reprinting a book. In 1710, the <quote>copy-right</quote> was a right
4660 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4661 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4662 generally how
4663 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4664 a work could be <emphasis>used</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4665 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4666 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4667 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4668 </para>
4669 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4670 <para>
4671 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4672 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4673 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4674 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4675 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4676 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4677 allowed to make his films. The <quote>copy-right</quote> was only an exclusive
4678 right to print&mdash;no less, of course, but also no more.
4679 </para>
4680 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England</primary></indexterm>
4681 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (1656)</primary></indexterm>
4682 <para>
4683 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4684 They had had a long and ugly experience with <quote>exclusive rights,</quote>
4685 especially <quote>exclusive rights</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4686 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4687 monopolies&mdash;especially monopolies for works that already
4688 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4689 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4690 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In 1656, it passed the
4691 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4692 inventions. And by 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4693 monopoly in publishing.
4694 </para>
4695 <para>
4696 Thus the <quote>copy-right,</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4697 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4698 claim that <quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,</quote> try
4699 sounding convincing when uttering, <quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4700 have it forever.</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4701 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4702 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4703 </para>
4704 <indexterm id='idxbooksellers' class='startofrange'><primary>booksellers, English</primary></indexterm>
4705 <para>
4706 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4707 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4708 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4709 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4710 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4711
4712 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4713 kind&mdash;tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4714 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4715 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as <quote>old patentees
4716 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling</quote>; they were <quote>men who do
4717 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4718 indetted.</quote><footnote><para>
4719
4720 <!-- f4 -->
4721 Philip Wittenberg, <citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4722 Property</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31.
4723 </para></footnote>
4724 </para>
4725 <para>
4726 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4727 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4728 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4729 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4730 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4731 with that idea.
4732 </para>
4733 <para>
4734 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4735 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4736 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4737 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4738 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4739 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4740 compromise
4741 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4742 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4743 construction and spread of culture.
4744 </para>
4745 <para>
4746 When 1731 (1710 + 21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4747 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4748 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4749 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4750 to control publication. But in 1735 and 1737, they tried to persuade
4751 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4752 they said; they needed more time.
4753 </para>
4754 <para>
4755 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4756 words that echo today,
4757 </para>
4758 <blockquote>
4759 <para>
4760 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4761 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4762 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4763 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4764 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4765 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4766 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4767 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4768 Booksellers.<footnote><para>
4769 <!-- f5 -->
4770 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4771 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4772 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4773 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4774 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4775 mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4776 al., 8, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618).
4777 </para></footnote>
4778 </para>
4779 </blockquote>
4780 <para>
4781 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4782 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4783 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
4784 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
4785 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
4786 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
4787 creative <quote>property</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
4788 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
4789 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
4790 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
4791 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
4792 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
4793 way to protect authors.
4794 </para>
4795 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
4796 <para>
4797 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
4798 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
4799 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
4800 <quote>The publishers &hellip; had as much concern for authors as a cattle
4801 rancher has for cattle.</quote><footnote><para>
4802 <!-- f6 -->
4803 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
4804 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4805 Lyman Ray Patterson, <quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
4806 Law Review</citetitle> 40 (1987): 28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
4807 Vaidhyanathan, 37&ndash;48.
4808 </para></footnote>
4809 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
4810 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
4811 </para>
4812 <para>
4813 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
4814 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
4815 Donaldson.<footnote><para>
4816 <!-- f7 -->
4817 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, <citetitle>Authorship and Copyright</citetitle>
4818 (London: Routledge, 1992), 62&ndash;69.
4819 </para></footnote>
4820 </para>
4821 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James</primary></indexterm>
4822 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew</primary></indexterm>
4823 <para>
4824 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
4825 career in Edinburgh in 1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
4826 reprints <quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,</quote> at least
4827 under the Statute of Anne.<footnote><para>
4828 <!-- f8 -->
4829 Mark Rose, <citetitle>Authors and Owners</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
4830 1993), 92.
4831 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
4832 </para></footnote>
4833 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
4834 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
4835 and became <quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.</quote> <quote>[A]mong
4836 them,</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was <quote>the young James Boswell
4837 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
4838 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.</quote><footnote><para>
4839 <!-- f9 -->
4840 Ibid., 93.
4841 </para></footnote>
4842 </para>
4843 <para>
4844 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
4845 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
4846 inexpensive editions <quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
4847 of the supposed common law right of Literary
4848 Property.</quote><footnote><para>
4849 <!-- f10 -->
4850 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
4851 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle>, 167 (quoting
4852 Borwell).
4853 </para></footnote>
4854 His books undercut the Conger prices by 30 to 50 percent, and he
4855 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
4856 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
4857 </para>
4858 <para>
4859 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block <quote>piracy</quote> like
4860 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the <quote>pirates,</quote>
4861 the most important early victory being <citetitle>Millar</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Taylor</citetitle>.
4862 </para>
4863 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)</primary></indexterm>
4864 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert</primary></indexterm>
4865 <para>
4866 Millar was a bookseller who in 1729 had purchased the rights to James
4867 Thomson's poem <quote>The Seasons.</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
4868 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
4869 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
4870 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
4871 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.<footnote><para>
4872 <!-- f11 -->
4873 Howard B. Abrams, <quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
4874 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review</citetitle> 29
4875 (1983): 1152.
4876 </para></footnote>
4877 </para>
4878 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
4879 <para>
4880 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
4881 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
4882 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
4883 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
4884 law would protect the author against subsequent <quote>pirates.</quote>
4885 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
4886 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
4887 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
4888 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
4889 </para>
4890 <para>
4891 Considered as a matter of abstract justice&mdash;reasoning as if
4892 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
4893 principles&mdash;Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
4894 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
4895 with in 1710: How best to limit
4896 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
4897 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
4898 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in 1710, but
4899 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
4900 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
4901 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
4902 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
4903 </para>
4904 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='endofrange'/>
4905 <para>
4906 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
4907 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
4908 </para>
4909 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
4910 <para>
4911 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
4912 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
4913 Thomas Beckett.<footnote><para>
4914 <!-- f12 -->
4915 Ibid., 1156.
4916 </para></footnote>
4917 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
4918 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in <citetitle>Millar</citetitle>,
4919 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
4920 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
4921 Court. In February of 1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
4922 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
4923 </para>
4924 <para>
4925 As few legal cases ever do, <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle> drew an
4926 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
4927 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
4928 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
4929 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
4930 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
4931 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
4932 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
4933 </para>
4934 <para>
4935 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
4936 presented to the House and voted upon first by the <quote>law lords,</quote>
4937 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
4938 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
4939 House of Lords generally voted.
4940 </para>
4941 <para>
4942 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
4943 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
4944 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
4945 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
4946 (22 to 11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
4947 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
4948 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
4949 passed into the public domain.
4950 </para>
4951 <para>
4952 <quote>The public domain.</quote> Before the case of <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle>
4953 v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
4954 England. Before 1774, there was a strong argument that common law
4955 copyrights were perpetual. After 1774, the public domain was
4956 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
4957 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
4958 history&mdash;including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
4959 and Bunyan&mdash;were free of legal restraint.
4960 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis</primary></indexterm>
4961 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John</primary></indexterm>
4962 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel</primary></indexterm>
4963 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
4964 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4965 </para>
4966 <para>
4967 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
4968 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
4969 where most of the <quote>pirate publishers</quote> did their work, people
4970 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the <citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser</citetitle>
4971 reported, <quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
4972 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
4973 decision of which so many individuals were interested.</quote> <quote>Great
4974 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
4975 and illuminations.</quote><footnote><para>
4976 <!-- f13 -->
4977 Rose, 97.
4978 </para></footnote>
4979 </para>
4980 <para>
4981 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
4982 equally strong in the opposite direction. The <citetitle>Morning Chronicle</citetitle>
4983 reported:
4984 </para>
4985 <blockquote>
4986 <para>
4987 By the above decision &hellip; near 200,000 pounds worth of what was
4988 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
4989 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
4990 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
4991 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
4992 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
4993 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
4994 successors.<footnote><para>
4995 <!-- f14 -->
4996 Ibid.
4997 </para></footnote>
4998 </para>
4999 </blockquote>
5000 <para>
5001 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
5002 <quote>Ruined</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
5003 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
5004 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
5005 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
5006 <emphasis>free</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
5007 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
5008 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
5009 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
5010 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
5011 book from someone. But <emphasis>free</emphasis> in the sense that the
5012 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
5013 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
5014 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
5015 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
5016 develop&mdash; chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
5017 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a <emphasis>competitive
5018 context</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
5019 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
5020 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
5021 </para>
5022 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellers' class='endofrange'/>
5023 <para>
5024 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
5025 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
5026 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
5027 protected.
5028 </para>
5029 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'/>
5030 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishlaw' class='endofrange'/>
5031 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
5032 </chapter>
5033 <chapter label="7" id="recorders">
5034 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders</title>
5035 <para>
5036 <emphasis role='strong'>Jon Else</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5037 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5038 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5039 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5040 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5041 </para>
5042 <para>
5043 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5044 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5045 today.
5046 </para>
5047 <para>
5048 In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5049 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5050 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5051 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5052 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5053 stage.
5054 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5055 </para>
5056 <para>
5057 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5058 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5059 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5060 and the opera company played Wagner, was <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. As Else judged
5061 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5062 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5063 about the scene.
5064 </para>
5065 <para>
5066 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5067 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>.
5068 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5069 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5070 unless <quote>fair use</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5071 </para>
5072 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5073 <para>
5074 Else called <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5075 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5076 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5077 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5078 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5079 </para>
5080 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5081 <para>
5082 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5083 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5084 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5085 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5086 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5087 </para>
5088 <para>
5089 Then, as Else told me, <quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5090 &hellip; that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation&mdash;or at
5091 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.</quote>
5092 And second, Fox <quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5093 to use this four-point-five seconds of &hellip; entirely unsolicited
5094 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.</quote>
5095 </para>
5096 <indexterm><primary>Herrera, Rebecca</primary></indexterm>
5097 <para>
5098 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5099 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5100 explained to her, <quote>There must be some mistake here. &hellip; We're
5101 asking for your educational rate on this.</quote> That was the educational
5102 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5103 confirm what he had been told.
5104 </para>
5105 <para>
5106 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,</quote> he told me. <quote>Yes, you
5107 have your facts straight,</quote> she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the
5108 clip of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5109 about
5110
5111 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5112 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, <quote>And
5113 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.</quote> As an assistant
5114 to Herrera told Else later on, <quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5115 the money.</quote>
5116 </para>
5117 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5118 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The</primary></indexterm>
5119 <para>
5120 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5121 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5122 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5123 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5124 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5125 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5126 </para>
5127 <para>
5128 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5129 copyright to <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5130 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5131 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5132 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5133 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5134 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5135 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5136 says the owner gets to control.
5137 </para>
5138 <para>
5139 For example, <quote>public performance</quote> is a use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> that the
5140 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5141 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see <quote>My
5142 Favorite <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>,</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5143 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5144 whatever she wants&mdash;$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set
5145 by the law.
5146 </para>
5147 <para>
5148 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5149 thought is <quote>fair use.</quote><footnote><para>
5150 <!-- f1 -->
5151 For an excellent argument that such use is <quote>fair use,</quote> but that
5152 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is <quote>fair use,</quote> see Richard
5153 A. Posner with William F. Patry, <quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5154 Wake of <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5155 Law School, 5 August 2003.
5156 </para></footnote>
5157 Else's use of just 4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>
5158 episode is clearly a fair use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>&mdash;and fair use does
5159 not require the permission of anyone.
5160 </para>
5161 <para>
5162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5163 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon <quote>fair use.</quote> Here's his reply:
5164 </para>
5165 <blockquote>
5166 <para>
5167 The <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5168 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5169 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5170 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was <quote>clearly
5171 fair use</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5172 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5173 </para>
5174 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
5175 <listitem><para>
5176 <!-- 1. -->
5177 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5178 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5179 <quote>visual cue sheet</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5180 shot in the film. They take a dim view of <quote>fair use,</quote> and a claim of
5181 <quote>fair use</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5182 </para></listitem>
5183 <listitem>
5184 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5185 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George</primary></indexterm>
5186 <para>
5187 <!-- 2. -->
5188 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5189 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5190 tracking down and stopping unlicensed <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> usage, just as George
5191 Lucas had a very high profile litigating <citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5192 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5193 license to four seconds of <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5194 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5195 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5196 principle.
5197 </para></listitem>
5198 <listitem><para>
5199 <!-- 3. -->
5200 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5201 School &hellip; who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5202 that Fox would <quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5203 life,</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5204 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5205 pockets, me or them.
5206 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5207 </para></listitem>
5208 <listitem><para>
5209 <!-- 4. -->
5210 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5211 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5212 money.
5213 </para></listitem>
5214 </orderedlist>
5215 </blockquote>
5216 <para>
5217 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5218 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5219 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5220 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5221 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5222 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5223 </para>
5224 <para>
5225 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5226 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5227 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5228 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5229 not.
5230 </para>
5231 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5232 </chapter>
5233 <chapter label="8" id="transformers">
5234 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers</title>
5235 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul</primary></indexterm>
5236 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5237 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary></indexterm>
5238 <para>
5239 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5240 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5241 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5242 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5243 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5244 anticipation of the power of networks.
5245 </para>
5246 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on</secondary></indexterm>
5247 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in</primary></indexterm>
5248 <para>
5249 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5250 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology&mdash;not to distribute
5251 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5252 difficult. In 1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5253 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5254 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5255 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5256 important to his career.
5257 </para>
5258 <para>
5259 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5260 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5261 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5262 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5263 </para>
5264 <para>
5265 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5266 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5267 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5268 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5269 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5270 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5271 </para>
5272 <para>
5273 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. <quote>Our
5274 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5275 Eastwood's films,</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5276 arose. <quote>No one had ever really done this before,</quote> Alben explained. <quote>No
5277 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5278 actor's career.</quote>
5279 </para>
5280 <para>
5281 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5282 Slade asked, <quote>Well, what will it take?</quote>
5283 </para>
5284 <para>
5285 Alben replied, <quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5286 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5287 else that we want to use in these film clips.</quote> Slade said, <quote>Great! Go
5288 for it.</quote><footnote>
5289 <para>
5290 <!-- f1 -->
5291 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5292 publicity&mdash;rights an artist has to control the commercial
5293 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden <quote>Rip, Mix,
5294 Burn</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5295 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of</secondary></indexterm>
5296 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5297 </para></footnote>
5298 </para>
5299 <para>
5300 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5301 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5302 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5303 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5304 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5305 </para>
5306 <para>
5307 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5308 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5309 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5310 </para>
5311 <blockquote>
5312 <para>
5313 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5314 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include&mdash;of
5315 course we were going to use the <quote>Make my day</quote> clip from <citetitle>Dirty
5316 Harry</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5317 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5318 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5319 </para>
5320 <para>
5321 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5322 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5323 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5324 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5325 rate at the time was about $600. So we had to identify the
5326 people&mdash;some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5327 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5328 glass&mdash;is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5329 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5330 started calling people.
5331 </para>
5332 </blockquote>
5333 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald</primary></indexterm>
5334 <para>
5335 Some actors were glad to help&mdash;Donald Sutherland, for example,
5336 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5337 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5338 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5339 know, $1,200?</quote> And they would say, <quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5340 to get $1,200.</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5341 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5342 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5343 career.
5344 </para>
5345 <para>
5346 It was one <emphasis>year</emphasis> later&mdash;<quote>and even then we
5347 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.</quote>
5348 </para>
5349 <para>
5350 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5351 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5352 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5353 </para>
5354 <blockquote>
5355 <para>
5356 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5357 hands and said, <quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5358 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5359 actors.</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5360 constituent parts and said, <quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5361 directors, &hellip; this many musicians,</quote> and we just went at it very
5362 systematically and cleared the rights.
5363 </para>
5364 </blockquote>
5365 <para>
5366
5367 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5368 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5369 loved it, and it sold very well.
5370 </para>
5371 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter</primary></indexterm>
5372 <para>
5373 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5374 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5375 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, <quote>There is
5376 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5377 at all.</quote><footnote><para>
5378 <!-- f2 -->
5379 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, <citetitle>Seven
5380 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition</citetitle>, available at
5381 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #22</ulink>.
5382 </para></footnote>
5383 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5384 has to be made?
5385 </para>
5386 <para>
5387 For, as he acknowledged, <quote>very few &hellip; have the time and resources,
5388 and the will to do this,</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5389 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5390 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5391 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5392 </para>
5393 <blockquote>
5394 <para>
5395 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5396 he or she gets paid very well. &hellip; And then when 30 seconds of
5397 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5398 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person &hellip; should be
5399 compensated for that.
5400 </para>
5401 </blockquote>
5402 <para>
5403 Or at least, is this <emphasis>how</emphasis> the artist should be
5404 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5405 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5406 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5407 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5408 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5409 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5410 made to be more clean?
5411 </para>
5412 <blockquote>
5413 <para>
5414 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5415 mechanism&mdash;where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5416 subject to estranged former spouses&mdash;you'd see a lot more of this
5417 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5418 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5419 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5420 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5421 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5422 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5423 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5424 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5425 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5426 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5427 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, <quote>Oh, I
5428 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5429 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5430 money,</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5431 </para>
5432 </blockquote>
5433 <para>
5434 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5435 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5436 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5437 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5438 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5439 </para>
5440 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'/>
5441 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'/>
5442 <para>
5443 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5444 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5445 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5446 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5447 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5448 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5449 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5450 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5451 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5452 <quote>Does this still make sense?</quote>
5453 </para>
5454 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'/>
5455 <para>
5456 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5457 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5458 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5459 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5460
5461 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5462 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5463 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5464 </para>
5465 <para>
5466 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5467 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode.
5468 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5469 judges loved every minute of it.
5470 </para>
5471 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David</primary></indexterm>
5472 <para>
5473 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5474 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5475 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5476 room of over 250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5477 began his talk with a question: <quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5478 were just violated in this room?</quote>
5479 </para>
5480 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David</primary></indexterm>
5481 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5482 <para>
5483 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5484 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5485 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5486 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5487 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle
5488 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5489 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5490 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5491 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5492 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5493 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5494 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5495 couldn't easily do them legally.
5496 </para>
5497 <para>
5498 We live in a <quote>cut and paste</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5499 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5500 and paste architecture of the Internet created&mdash;in a second you can
5501 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5502 planted in your presentation.
5503 </para>
5504 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos</primary></indexterm>
5505 <para>
5506 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5507 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5508 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5509 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5510 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5511 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5512 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5513 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5514 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5515 </para>
5516 <para>
5517 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5518 wanted to be <quote>legal,</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5519 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5520 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5521 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5522 </para>
5523 <para>
5524 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5525 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5526 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5527 necessarily requiring that the <quote>free</quote> use be free as in <quote>free beer.</quote>
5528 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5529 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5530 along: a rule, for example, that says <quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5531 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5532 will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5533 copyright owner.</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5534 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5535 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5536 registers the work.
5537 </para>
5538 <para>
5539 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5540 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5541 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5542 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5543 </para>
5544 <para>
5545 <emphasis role='strong'>In February 2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5546 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5547 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live</citetitle> and
5548 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5549 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5550 would work together to form a <quote>unique filmmaking pact.</quote> Under the
5551 agreement, DreamWorks <quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5552 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and&mdash;with the use
5553 of stateof-the-art digital technology&mdash;insert Myers and other
5554 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5555 entertainment.</quote>
5556 </para>
5557 <para>
5558 The announcement called this <quote>film sampling.</quote> As Myers explained,
5559 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5560 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5561 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5562 to take that same concept and apply it to film.</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5563 quoted as saying, <quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5564 new audiences, it is Mike.</quote>
5565 </para>
5566 <para>
5567 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5568 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5569 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5570 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5571 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5572 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5573 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5574 privilege reserved for the funny and famous&mdash;and presumably rich.
5575 </para>
5576 <para>
5577 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5578 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of <quote>fair use.</quote>
5579 Much of <quote>sampling</quote> should be considered <quote>fair use.</quote> But few would
5580 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5581 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5582 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5583 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5584 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5585 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5586 process is a process of paying lawyers&mdash;again a privilege, or perhaps a
5587 curse, reserved for the few.
5588 </para>
5589 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5590 </chapter>
5591 <chapter label="9" id="collectors">
5592 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors</title>
5593 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
5594 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
5595 <para>
5596 <emphasis role='strong'>In April 1996</emphasis>, millions of
5597 <quote>bots</quote>&mdash;computer codes designed to
5598 <quote>spider,</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5599 content&mdash;began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5600 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5601 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5602 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5603 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5604 Internet and stored them.
5605 </para>
5606 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5607 <para>
5608 By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5609 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5610 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5611 the world. Using a technology called <quote>the Way Back Machine,</quote> you could
5612 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to 1996, as
5613 well as when those pages changed.
5614 </para>
5615 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Orwell, George</primary></indexterm>
5616 <para>
5617 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5618 appreciated. In the dystopia described in <citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5619 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5620 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5621 reports.
5622 </para>
5623 <para>
5624 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5625 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5626 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5627 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5628 </para>
5629 <para>
5630 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5631 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5632 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5633 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5634 library&mdash;constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5635 </para>
5636 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'/>
5637 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5638 <para>
5639 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5640 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5641 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5642 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5643 what others might prefer you forget.<footnote><para>
5644 <!-- f1 -->
5645 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
5646 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases</primary></indexterm>
5647 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5648 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003,
5649 press release stated, <quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.</quote> That was
5650 later changed, without notice, to <quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5651 Have Ended.</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003.
5652 </para></footnote>
5653 </para>
5654 <indexterm><primary>history, records of</primary></indexterm>
5655 <para>
5656 <emphasis role='strong'>We take it</emphasis> for granted that we can
5657 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5658 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5659 race riots in Watts in 1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in 1963,
5660 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5661 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5662 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
5663 remember&mdash;not just what it is convenient to remember, but
5664 remember something close to the truth.
5665 </para>
5666 <para>
5667 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5668 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We <emphasis>all</emphasis>
5669 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
5670 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
5671 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
5672 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
5673 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
5674 </para>
5675 <para>
5676 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5677 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5678 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5679 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5680 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5681 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5682 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5683 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet&mdash;the
5684 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5685 </para>
5686 <para>
5687 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5688 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5689 researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5690 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5691 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5692 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5693 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10
5694 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5695 </para>
5696 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
5697 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive</primary></indexterm>
5698 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University</primary></indexterm>
5699 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5700 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>archival function of</secondary></indexterm>
5701 <para>
5702 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
5703 human history. At the end of 2002, it held <quote>two hundred and thirty
5704 terabytes of material</quote>&mdash;and was <quote>ten times larger than the
5705 Library of Congress.</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
5706 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
5707 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
5708 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
5709 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
5710 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
5711 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University&mdash;thanks to a
5712 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
5713 is available to scholars for a very low fee. <quote>But other than that,
5714 [television] is almost unavailable,</quote> Kahle told me. <quote>If you were
5715 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
5716 just a graduate student?</quote> As Kahle put it,
5717 </para>
5718 <blockquote>
5719 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan</primary></indexterm>
5720 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes</primary></indexterm>
5721 <para>
5722 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
5723 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
5724 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
5725 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
5726 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
5727
5728 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
5729 <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode that came out after it &hellip; it would be almost
5730 impossible. &hellip; Those materials are almost unfindable. &hellip;
5731 </para>
5732 </blockquote>
5733 <indexterm><primary>newspapers</primary><secondary>archives of</secondary></indexterm>
5734 <para>
5735 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
5736 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
5737 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
5738 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
5739 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
5740 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
5741 </para>
5742 <para>
5743 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
5744 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
5745 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
5746 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
5747 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
5748 work.
5749 </para>
5750 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
5751 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
5752 <para>
5753 These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library
5754 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
5755 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
5756 borrow back the deposits&mdash;for an unlimited time at no cost. In
5757 1915 alone, there were more than 5,475 films deposited and <quote>borrowed
5758 back.</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
5759 held by any library. The copy exists&mdash;if it exists at
5760 all&mdash;in the library archive of the film company.<footnote><para>
5761 <!-- f2 -->
5762 Doug Herrick, <quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
5763 the Library of Congress,</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly</citetitle> 13 nos. 2&ndash;3
5764 (1980): 5; Anthony Slide, <citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
5765 Preservation in the United States</citetitle> ( Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland &amp;
5766 Co., 1992), 36.
5767 </para></footnote>
5768 </para>
5769 <para>
5770 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
5771 were originally not copyrighted&mdash;there was no way to capture the
5772 broadcasts, so there was no fear of <quote>theft.</quote> But as technology enabled
5773 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
5774 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
5775 <quote>copyrighted.</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
5776 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
5777 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
5778 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
5779 </para>
5780 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
5781 <para>
5782 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and
5783 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
5784 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
5785 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
5786 September 11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
5787 stations from around the world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made
5788 their coverage during the week of September 11 available free on-line.
5789 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
5790 events of that day.
5791 </para>
5792 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive</primary></indexterm>
5793 <indexterm><primary>archive.org</primary><seealso>Internet Archive</seealso></indexterm>
5794 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
5795 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive</primary></indexterm>
5796 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film</primary></indexterm>
5797 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films</primary></indexterm>
5798 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick</primary></indexterm>
5799 <para>
5800 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
5801 archive of film includes close to 45,000 <quote>ephemeral films</quote> (meaning
5802 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
5803 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
5804 1,300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
5805 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
5806 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
5807 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
5808 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
5809 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
5810 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
5811 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
5812 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the <quote>Duck and Cover</quote> film
5813 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
5814 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
5815 few minutes&mdash;for free.
5816 </para>
5817 <para>
5818 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
5819 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
5820 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
5821 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
5822 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
5823 to find them.
5824 </para>
5825 <para>
5826 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
5827 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
5828 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
5829 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
5830 property, but during a second life that all creative property
5831 has&mdash;a noncommercial life.
5832 </para>
5833 <para>
5834 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
5835 of creative property goes through different <quote>lives.</quote> In its first
5836 life, if the
5837
5838 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
5839 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
5840 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
5841 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
5842 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
5843 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
5844 </para>
5845 <para>
5846 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
5847 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
5848 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
5849 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
5850 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
5851 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
5852 longer sold.
5853 </para>
5854 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
5855 <para>
5856 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
5857 very quickly (the average today is after about a year<footnote><para>
5858 <!-- f3 -->
5859 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
5860 Dave Barns, <quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
5861 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>,
5862 5 September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927
5863 and 1946, only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese,
5864 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,</quote> <citetitle>Boston
5865 College Law Review</citetitle> 44 (2003): 593 n. 51.
5866 </para></footnote>). After
5867 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
5868 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
5869 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
5870 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
5871 important to the spread and stability of culture.
5872 </para>
5873 <para>
5874 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
5875 creative property does not hold true with the most important
5876 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
5877 centuries. For these&mdash;television, movies, music, radio, the
5878 Internet&mdash;there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
5879 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes &amp;
5880 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
5881 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
5882 disappears.
5883 </para>
5884 <para>
5885 <emphasis role='strong'>For most of</emphasis> the twentieth century,
5886 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
5887 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
5888 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
5889 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
5890 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
5891 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
5892 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
5893 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
5894 little practical effect.
5895 </para>
5896 <para>
5897 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
5898 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
5899 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
5900 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
5901 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
5902 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
5903 </para>
5904 <para>
5905 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
5906 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
5907 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
5908 Kahle describes,
5909 </para>
5910 <blockquote>
5911 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>total number of</secondary></indexterm>
5912 <para>
5913 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
5914 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
5915 movies, &hellip; and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
5916 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
5917 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
5918 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
5919 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
5920 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
5921 &hellip; thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
5922 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
5923 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
5924 </para>
5925 </blockquote>
5926 <para>
5927 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
5928 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
5929 libraries or archives could be. <emphasis>When</emphasis> the
5930 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
5931 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
5932 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
5933 will draw upon it to understand it;
5934 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
5935 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
5936 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
5937 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past&mdash;a
5938 future <emphasis>for</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
5939 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
5940 </para>
5941 <para>
5942 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
5943 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
5944 call these <quote>archives,</quote> as warm as the idea of a <quote>library</quote> might seem,
5945 the <quote>content</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
5946 someone's <quote>property.</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
5947 that Kahle and others would exercise.
5948 </para>
5949 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'/>
5950 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
5951 </chapter>
5952 <chapter label="10" id="property-i">
5953 <title>CHAPTER TEN: <quote>Property</quote></title>
5954 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon</primary></indexterm>
5955 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
5956 <para>
5957 <emphasis role='strong'>Jack Valenti</emphasis> has been the president
5958 of the Motion Picture Association of America since 1966. He first came
5959 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
5960 administration&mdash;literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
5961 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
5962 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
5963 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
5964 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
5965 </para>
5966 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
5967 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment</primary></indexterm>
5968 <indexterm><primary>MGM</primary></indexterm>
5969 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures</primary></indexterm>
5970 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox</primary></indexterm>
5971 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures</primary></indexterm>
5972 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
5973 <para>
5974 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
5975 Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal
5976 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
5977 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
5978 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
5979 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
5980 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
5981 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
5982 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
5983 Warner Brothers.
5984 </para>
5985 <para>
5986 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
5987 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
5988 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
5989 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
5990 political skill of a Southerner&mdash;the ability to appear simple and
5991 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
5992 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
5993 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
5994 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
5995 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
5996 Washingtonian way.
5997 </para>
5998 <para>
5999 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
6000 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
6001 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
6002 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
6003 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
6004 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
6005 redefine the meaning of <quote>creative property.</quote>
6006 </para>
6007 <para>
6008 In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
6009 perfectly:
6010 </para>
6011 <blockquote>
6012 <para>
6013 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
6014 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
6015 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
6016 theme which animates this entire debate: <emphasis>Creative property
6017 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
6018 other property owners in the nation</emphasis>. That is the issue.
6019 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
6020 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.<footnote><para>
6021 <!-- f1 -->
6022 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R.
6023 4794, H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the
6024 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
6025 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
6026 Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack
6027 Valenti).
6028 </para></footnote>
6029 </para>
6030 </blockquote>
6031 <para>
6032 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
6033 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
6034 <quote>central theme</quote> to which <quote>reasonable men and women</quote> will return is
6035 this:
6036 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6037 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6038 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.</quote>
6039 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6040 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6041 </para>
6042 <para>
6043 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6044 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6045 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6046 extreme a claim made by <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> who is serious in
6047 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6048 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6049 it comes to the nature and scope of <quote>creative property.</quote> His views
6050 have <emphasis>no</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6051 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6052 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6053 </para>
6054 <para>
6055 While <quote>creative property</quote> is certainly <quote>property</quote> in a nerdy and
6056 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,<footnote><para>
6057 <!-- f2 -->
6058 Lawyers speak of <quote>property</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6059 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6060 object. Thus, my <quote>property right</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6061 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For
6062 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of <quote>property</quote> to
6063 <quote>lawyer talk,</quote> see Bruce Ackerman, <citetitle>Private Property and the
6064 Constitution</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 26&ndash;27.
6065 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6066 <quote>creative property owners</quote> have been <quote>accorded the same rights and
6067 protection resident in all other property owners.</quote> Indeed, if creative
6068 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6069 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6070 in our tradition.
6071 </para>
6072 <para>
6073 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6074 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6075 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6076 overturned in 1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6077 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6078 culture would develop.
6079 </para>
6080 <para>
6081 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6082 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6083 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6084 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6085 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6086 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6087 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6088 the same would be to
6089
6090 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6091 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6092 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6093 perfect control.
6094 </para>
6095 <para>
6096 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6097 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6098 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6099 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6100 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6101 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6102 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6103 </para>
6104 <para>
6105 <emphasis role='strong'>To get</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6106 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6107 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6108 </para>
6109 <para>
6110 The framers of our Constitution loved <quote>property.</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6111 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6112 important requirement. If the government takes your property&mdash;if
6113 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6114 farm&mdash;it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's <quote>Takings
6115 Clause,</quote> to pay you <quote>just compensation</quote> for that taking. The
6116 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6117 sacred. It cannot <emphasis>ever</emphasis> be taken from the property
6118 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6119 </para>
6120 <para>
6121 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6122 Valenti calls <quote>creative property.</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6123 power to create <quote>creative property,</quote> the Constitution
6124 <emphasis>requires</emphasis> that after a <quote>limited time,</quote> Congress
6125 take back the rights that it has granted and set the <quote>creative
6126 property</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6127 the expiration of a copyright term <quote>takes</quote> your copyright and turns it
6128 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6129 pay <quote>just compensation</quote> for this <quote>taking.</quote> Instead, the same
6130 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6131 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6132 requires that you lose your <quote>creative property</quote> right without any
6133 compensation at all.
6134 </para>
6135 <para>
6136 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6137 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6138 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6139 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6140 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6141 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6142 itself.
6143 </para>
6144 <para>
6145 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6146 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6147 The Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6148 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6149 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6150 president (as it did in 1800). The framers were no doubt
6151 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6152 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6153 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6154 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6155 </para>
6156 <para>
6157 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6158 least try to understand <emphasis>why</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6159 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6160 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6161 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6162 domain?
6163 </para>
6164 <para>
6165 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6166 history of these <quote>creative property</quote> rights, and the control that they
6167 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6168 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6169 should be at the core of this war: Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis>
6170 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6171 <emphasis>whether</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6172 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6173 ought to be. Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6174 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6175 also control how culture develops.
6176 </para>
6177 <para>
6178
6179 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6180 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6181 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6182 than the narrow language of the law allows. In <citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6183 Cyberspace</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6184 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6185 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6186 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6187 </para>
6188 <figure id="fig-1331">
6189 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.</title>
6190 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6191 </figure>
6192 <para>
6193 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6194 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6195 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6196 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6197 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6198 be regulated&mdash; either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6199 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6200 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6201 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6202 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6203 Web, you can be punished
6204 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6205 with a $150,000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6206 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6207 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6208 </para>
6209 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6210 <para>
6211 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6212 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6213 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6214 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6215 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6216 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6217 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6218 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6219 the source of the enforcement.
6220 </para>
6221 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6222 <para>
6223 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6224 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6225 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6226 norms&mdash;it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6227 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6228 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6229 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6230 individual or group might behave.
6231 </para>
6232 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6233 <para>
6234 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6235 <quote>architecture</quote>&mdash;the physical world as one finds it&mdash;is a
6236 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6237 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6238 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6239 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6240 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6241 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6242 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6243 theft, but by nature, by <quote>architecture.</quote> If a 500-pound boulder
6244 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6245 constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6246 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6247 </para>
6248 <para>
6249
6250 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6251 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6252 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6253 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6254 undermined by another.
6255 </para>
6256 <para>
6257 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6258 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6259 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6260 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6261 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6262 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6263 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6264 </para>
6265 <indexterm id="idxdrivespeed" class='startofrange'><primary>driving speed, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6266 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6267 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6268 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6269 <para>
6270 So, for example, consider the <quote>freedom</quote> to drive a car at a high
6271 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6272 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6273 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6274 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6275 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6276 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6277 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6278 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6279 the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own
6280 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6281 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6282 </para>
6283 <para>
6284 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6285 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6286 special role in affecting the three.<footnote><para>
6287 <!-- f3 -->
6288 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6289 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6290 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6291 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6292 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Code: And
6293 Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90&ndash;95;
6294 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>The New Chicago School,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies</citetitle>,
6295 June 1998.
6296 </para></footnote>
6297 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6298 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6299 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6300 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6301 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6302 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6303 used to require that other laws be more
6304 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6305 strict&mdash;a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6306 limit, for example&mdash;so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6307 driving.
6308 </para>
6309 <indexterm startref="idxdrivespeed" class='endofrange'/>
6310
6311 <figure id="fig-1361">
6312 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.</title>
6313 <graphic fileref="images/1361.png"></graphic>
6314 </figure>
6315 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6316 <para>
6317 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6318 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6319 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6320 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6321 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6322 another.<footnote>
6323 <para>
6324 <!-- f4 -->
6325 Some people object to this way of talking about <quote>liberty.</quote> They object
6326 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6327 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6328 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6329 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6330 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6331 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6332 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6333 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6334 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6335 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6336 of liberty. As I argued in <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, we come from a
6337 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6338 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6339 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6340 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6341 <citetitle>On Liberty</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6342 1978), 19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6343 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons, <quote>The
6344 Right to Work,</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6345 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays</citetitle> (London:
6346 Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6347 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6348 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6349 places easier; 42 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
6350 12101 (2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6351 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6352 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6353 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6354 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (1990)</primary></indexterm>
6355 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.</primary></indexterm>
6356 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6357 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6358 </para></footnote>
6359 </para>
6360 <section id="hollywood">
6361 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right</title>
6362 <para>
6363 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6364 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6365 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6366 rallying makes sense.
6367 </para>
6368 <para>
6369 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6370 Internet:
6371 </para>
6372 <figure id="fig-1371">
6373 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6374 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6375 </figure>
6376 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6377 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6378 <para>
6379 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6380 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6381 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6382 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6383 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6384 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6385 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6386 recognize&mdash;kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6387 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6388 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6389 this form of infringement.
6390 </para>
6391 <para>
6392 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6393 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6394 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6395 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6396 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6397 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6398 </para>
6399 <para>
6400 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6401 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6402 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6403 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6404 Iraq
6405 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6406 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6407 looting that results.
6408 </para>
6409 <figure id="fig-1381">
6410 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.</title>
6411 <graphic fileref="images/1381.png"></graphic>
6412 </figure>
6413 <para>
6414 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6415 warriors. Indeed, in a <quote>White Paper</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6416 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995,
6417 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6418 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6419 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should
6420 strengthen intellectual property law, (2) businesses should adopt
6421 innovative marketing techniques, (3) technologists should push to
6422 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (4) educators should
6423 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6424 </para>
6425 <indexterm><primary>steel industry</primary></indexterm>
6426 <para>
6427 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed&mdash;if it was to
6428 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6429 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6430 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6431 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6432 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6433 life. Homeowners living in a
6434
6435 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6436 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6437 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6438 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6439 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6440 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6441 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6442 </para>
6443 <para>
6444 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6445 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6446 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6447 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6448 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6449 Brown describes it, its <quote>architecture of revenue.</quote>
6450 </para>
6451 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry</primary></indexterm>
6452 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
6453 <indexterm><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
6454 <para>
6455 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6456 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6457 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6458 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6459 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20
6460 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6461 of digital cameras.<footnote><para>
6462 <!-- f5 -->
6463 See Geoffrey Smith, <quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?</quote>
6464 BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at
6465 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #23</ulink>. For a more
6466 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6467 R. Schoenberger, <quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?</quote> Forbes.com, 6
6468 October 2003, available at
6469 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #24</ulink>.
6470 </para></footnote>
6471
6472 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6473 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6474 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6475 <emphasis>for the purpose of</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6476 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6477 weakened the <quote>stickiness</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6478 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf ), and it
6479 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6480 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6481 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6482 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6483 </para>
6484 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
6485 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
6486 <para>
6487 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6488 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6489 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6490 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6491 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6492 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6493 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6494 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, <quote>established companies
6495 have an interest in excluding future competitors.</quote><footnote><para>
6496 <!-- f6 -->
6497 Fred Warshofsky, <citetitle>The Patent Wars</citetitle> (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170&ndash;71.
6498 </para></footnote>
6499 And relative to a
6500 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6501 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6502 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6503 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6504 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6505 Brezhnev.
6506 </para>
6507 <para>
6508 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6509 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6510 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6511 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6512 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6513 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6514 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6515 opportunities for innovation and change.
6516 </para>
6517 <para>
6518 In the context of laws regulating speech&mdash;which include,
6519 obviously, copyright law&mdash;that duty is even stronger. When the
6520 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6521 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6522 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6523 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6524 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6525 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: <quote>Congress
6526 shall make no law &hellip; abridging the freedom of speech.</quote> So when
6527 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would <quote>abridge</quote> the freedom
6528 of speech, it should ask&mdash; carefully&mdash;whether such
6529 regulation is justified.
6530 </para>
6531 <para>
6532 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6533 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6534 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6535 <quote>justified.</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6536 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6537 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6538 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6539 </para>
6540 <para>
6541 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6542 </para>
6543 <indexterm id="idxddt" class='startofrange'><primary>DDT</primary></indexterm>
6544 <indexterm><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann</primary></indexterm>
6545 <para>
6546 In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss
6547 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6548 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the
6549 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6550 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6551 </para>
6552 <para>
6553 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6554 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6555 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6556 </para>
6557 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6558 <indexterm><primary>Silent Sprint (Carson)</primary></indexterm>
6559 <para>
6560 But in 1962, Rachel Carson published <citetitle>Silent Spring</citetitle>, which argued that
6561 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6562 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6563 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6564 </para>
6565 <para>
6566 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6567 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6568 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6569 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6570 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6571 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6572 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6573 </para>
6574 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James</primary></indexterm>
6575 <para>
6576 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6577 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an <quote>environmentalism</quote> for
6578 culture.<footnote><para>
6579 <!-- f7 -->
6580 See, for example, James Boyle, <quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6581 Environmentalism for the Net?</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal</citetitle> 47 (1997): 87.
6582 </para></footnote>
6583 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6584 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6585 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6586 <quote>for free.</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6587 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6588 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6589 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6590 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6591 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6592 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6593 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6594 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6595 </para>
6596 <para>
6597 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6598 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6599 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6600 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6601 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6602 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6603 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6604 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6605 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6606 </para>
6607 <para>
6608 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6609 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6610 be lost.
6611 </para>
6612 <indexterm startref="idxddt" class='endofrange'/>
6613 </section>
6614 <section id="beginnings">
6615 <title>Beginnings</title>
6616 <para>
6617 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6618 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of <quote>creative
6619 property</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6620 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6621 </para>
6622 <para>
6623 The power to establish <quote>creative property</quote> rights is granted to
6624 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6625 odd. Article I, section 8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that:
6626 </para>
6627 <para>
6628 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6629 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6630 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
6631
6632 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
6633 We can call this the <quote>Progress Clause,</quote> for notice what this clause
6634 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
6635 <quote>creative property rights.</quote> It says that Congress has the power
6636 <emphasis>to promote progress</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
6637 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
6638 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
6639 </para>
6640 <para>
6641 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
6642 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="founders"/>,
6643 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
6644 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
6645 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
6646 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
6647 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
6648 copyrights extend <quote>to Authors</quote> only.
6649 </para>
6650 <para>
6651 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
6652 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
6653 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
6654 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
6655 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
6656 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
6657 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
6658 to reinforce the power of the states&mdash;including the Senate, whose
6659 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
6660 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
6661 case, a <emphasis>structure</emphasis> built checks and balances into
6662 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
6663 concentrations of power.
6664 </para>
6665 <para>
6666 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call <quote>copyright</quote>
6667 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
6668 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
6669 <quote>copyright</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210
6670 years since they first struck its design.
6671 </para>
6672 <para>
6673 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
6674 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
6675 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
6676 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
6677 started here:
6678 </para>
6679 <figure id="fig-1441">
6680 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6681 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6682 </figure>
6683 <para>
6684 We will end here:
6685 </para>
6686 <figure id="fig-1442">
6687 <title><quote>Copyright</quote> today.</title>
6688 <graphic fileref="images/1442.png"></graphic>
6689 </figure>
6690 <para>
6691 Let me explain how.
6692 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
6693 </para>
6694 </section>
6695 <section id="lawduration">
6696 <title>Law: Duration</title>
6697 <para>
6698 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
6699 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
6700 the English had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws
6701 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
6702 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
6703 authorship.<footnote>
6704 <para>
6705 <!-- f8 -->
6706 William W. Crosskey, <citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
6707 the United States</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press, 1953), vol. 1,
6708 485&ndash;86: <quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
6709 Law of the Land,' <emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
6710 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law</emphasis></quote>
6711 (emphasis added).
6712 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.</primary></indexterm>
6713 </para></footnote>
6714 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
6715 States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
6716 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
6717 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
6718 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
6719 domain to reprint and distribute works.
6720 </para>
6721 <para>
6722 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
6723 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
6724 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
6725 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
6726 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
6727 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
6728 </para>
6729 <para>
6730 In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
6731 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
6732 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
6733 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
6734 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
6735 </para>
6736 <para>
6737 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
6738 ten years of the Republic, only 5 percent of the works were actually
6739 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
6740 in the United States both before 1790 and from 1790 through 1800, 95
6741 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
6742 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
6743 likely within fourteen years.<footnote><para>
6744 <!-- f9 -->
6745 Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790
6746 to 1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, <citetitle>A
6747 History of Book Publishing in the United States</citetitle>, vol. 1, <citetitle>The Creation
6748 of an Industry, 1630&ndash;1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000
6749 imprints recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
6750 1790 act; William J. Maher, <citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
6751 and the Copyright Law of 1790 in Historical Context</citetitle>, 7&ndash;10 (2002),
6752 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
6753 #25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
6754 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
6755 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
6756 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
6757 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
6758 Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124. </para></footnote>
6759 </para>
6760 <para>
6761 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
6762 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
6763 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
6764 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
6765 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
6766 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
6767 copyright, either.
6768 </para>
6769 <para>
6770 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
6771 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
6772 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
6773 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
6774 domain.<footnote><para>
6775 <!-- f10 -->
6776 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
6777 instance, of the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were
6778 renewed in 1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
6779 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, <quote>Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright,</quote>
6780 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright</citetitle>, vol. 1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
6781 1963), 618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
6782 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote>
6783 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 471, 498&ndash;501, and
6784 accompanying figures. </para></footnote>
6785 </para>
6786 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6787 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
6788 <para>
6789 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
6790 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
6791 out of print after one year.<footnote><para>
6792 <!-- f11 -->
6793 See Ringer, ch. 9, n. 2. </para></footnote> When that happens, the
6794 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
6795 no longer <emphasis>effectively</emphasis> controlled by
6796 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
6797 is to sell the books as used books; that use&mdash;because it does not
6798 involve publication&mdash;is effectively free.
6799 </para>
6800 <para>
6801 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
6802 changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28
6803 years to a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
6804 from 14 years to 28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
6805 the term increased once again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal
6806 term of 14 years to 28 years, setting a maximum term of 56 years.
6807 </para>
6808 <para>
6809 Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
6810 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
6811 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
6812 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
6813 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
6814 In 1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
6815 And in 1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
6816 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
6817 </para>
6818 <para>
6819 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
6820 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
6821 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
6822 years, or 70 percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years
6823
6824 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
6825 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
6826 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
6827 of the expiration of a copyright term.
6828 </para>
6829 <para>
6830 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
6831 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
6832 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
6833 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
6834 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
6835 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
6836 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
6837 value.
6838 </para>
6839 <para>
6840 The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For
6841 all works created after 1978, there was only one copyright term&mdash;the
6842 maximum term. For <quote>natural</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
6843 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992,
6844 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
6845 before 1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
6846 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
6847 was ninety-five years.
6848 </para>
6849 <para>
6850 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
6851 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
6852 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
6853 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
6854 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
6855 that terms be <quote>limited,</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
6856 them.
6857 </para>
6858 <para>
6859 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
6860 dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to
6861 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
6862 in 1973 was just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
6863 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
6864 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95
6865 years.<footnote><para>
6866 <!-- f12 -->
6867 These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the
6868 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
6869 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
6870 Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote> loc. cit.
6871 </para></footnote>
6872 </para>
6873 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
6874 </section>
6875 <section id="lawscope">
6876 <title>Law: Scope</title>
6877 <para>
6878 The <quote>scope</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
6879 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
6880 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
6881 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
6882 </para>
6883 <para>
6884 In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only <quote>maps,
6885 charts, and books.</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
6886 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
6887 the author the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> copyrighted works. That
6888 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
6889 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
6890 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
6891 did not extend to what lawyers call <quote>derivative works.</quote> It would not,
6892 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
6893 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
6894 (such as a drama based on a published book).
6895 </para>
6896 <para>
6897 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
6898 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
6899 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
6900 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
6901 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
6902 work not only the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> the work, but also the
6903 exclusive right of control over any <quote>copies</quote> of that work. And most
6904 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
6905 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
6906 <quote>derivative work</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
6907 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
6908 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
6909 on the initial creative work.
6910 </para>
6911 <para>
6912 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
6913 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
6914 complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition
6915 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
6916 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
6917 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
6918 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
6919 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
6920 famous &copy; or the word <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>. And for most
6921 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
6922 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
6923 secured.
6924 </para>
6925 <para>
6926 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
6927 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
6928 in the first ten years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible
6929 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
6930 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
6931 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
6932 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
6933 copyrighted&mdash;that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
6934 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
6935 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
6936 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
6937 original author.
6938 </para>
6939 <para>
6940 All of these <quote>formalities</quote> were abolished in the American system when
6941 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
6942 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
6943 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
6944 a &copy;; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
6945 copy available for others to copy.
6946 </para>
6947 <para>
6948 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
6949 differences.
6950 </para>
6951 <para>
6952 If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who
6953 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
6954 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
6955 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
6956 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were
6957 174 publishers in the United States.<footnote><para>
6958 <!-- f13 -->
6959 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, <quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
6960 Creation of American Literature,</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
6961 International Law and Politics</citetitle> 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
6962 Federal Copyright Records, 1790&ndash;1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987).
6963
6964 </para></footnote>
6965 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
6966 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
6967 the United States&mdash;publishers.
6968 </para>
6969 <para>
6970 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
6971 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
6972 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
6973 was totally unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and made
6974 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
6975 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
6976 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
6977 were restrained.
6978 </para>
6979 <para>
6980 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
6981 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
6982 every note to your spouse, every doodle, <emphasis>every</emphasis>
6983 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form&mdash;all of this is
6984 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
6985 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
6986 protect it.
6987 </para>
6988 <para>
6989 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
6990 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
6991 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
6992 </para>
6993 <para>
6994 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
6995 control
6996 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
6997 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of <quote>derivative
6998 rights.</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
6999 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
7000 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
7001 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
7002 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
7003 exclusive
7004 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
7005 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
7006 </para>
7007 <para>
7008 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
7009 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
7010 expansion
7011 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
7012 copyright.
7013 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
7014 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
7015 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
7016 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
7017 </para>
7018 <para>
7019 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
7020 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
7021 within a free culture&mdash;at least, it's astonishing when you
7022 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
7023 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
7024 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
7025 <emphasis>that</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
7026 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
7027 all&mdash;they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
7028 not protect derivative rights at all.<footnote><para>
7029 <!-- f14 -->
7030 Jonathan Zittrain, <quote>The Copyright Cage,</quote> <citetitle>Legal
7031 Affairs</citetitle>, July/August 2003, available at
7032 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #26</ulink>.
7033 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
7034 </para></footnote>
7035 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
7036 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7037 the wrong of direct piracy.
7038 </para>
7039 <para>
7040 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7041 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7042 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7043 of my book.<footnote><para>
7044 <!-- f15 -->
7045 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7046 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7047 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere <quote>copies</quote> and
7048 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld, <quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7049 Copyright's Constitutionality,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7050 Journal</citetitle> 112 (2002): 1&ndash;60 (see especially
7051 pp. 53&ndash;59).
7052 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb</primary></indexterm>
7053 </para></footnote>
7054 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7055 </para>
7056 <para>
7057 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7058 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7059 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7060 called <quote>Mickey Mouse,</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7061 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7062 created?
7063 </para>
7064 <para>
7065 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7066 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7067 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7068 the rights originally granted.
7069 </para>
7070 </section>
7071 <section id="lawreach">
7072 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach</title>
7073 <para>
7074 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7075 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7076 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7077 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.<footnote><para>
7078 <!-- f16 -->
7079 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7080 certainly regulates more than <quote>copies</quote>&mdash;a public performance of a
7081 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7082 per se doesn't make a copy; 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7083 106(4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a <quote>copy</quote>; 17
7084 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section 112(a). But the presumption under the
7085 existing law (which regulates <quote>copies;</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7086 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7087 </para></footnote>
7088 </para>
7089 <para>
7090 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7091 <quote>Copies.</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7092 <emphasis>copy</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7093 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that <quote>creative
7094 property</quote> deserves the <quote>same rights</quote> as all other property, it is the
7095 <emphasis>obvious</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7096 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7097 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7098 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7099 copies should <emphasis>not</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7100 law. More precisely, they should not <emphasis>always</emphasis> be
7101 the trigger for copyright law.
7102 </para>
7103 <para>
7104 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7105 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7106 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7107 the law of copyright automatically applies,<footnote><para>
7108 <!-- f17 -->
7109 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7110 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7111 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7112 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7113 technology.
7114 </para></footnote>
7115 because it is clear that the
7116 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7117 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7118 </para>
7119 <para>
7120 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7121 empty circle.
7122 </para>
7123 <figure id="fig-1521">
7124 <title>All potential uses of a book.</title>
7125 <graphic fileref="images/1521.png"></graphic>
7126 </figure>
7127 <indexterm id='idxbooksusetypes' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>three types of uses of</secondary></indexterm>
7128 <para>
7129 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7130 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7131 all its potential <emphasis>uses</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7132 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7133 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7134 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7135 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7136 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7137 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7138 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7139 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7140 acts do not make a copy.
7141 </para>
7142 <figure id="fig-1531">
7143 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.</title>
7144 <graphic fileref="images/1531.png"></graphic>
7145 </figure>
7146 <para>
7147 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7148 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7149 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7150 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7151 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see first
7152 diagram on next page).
7153 </para>
7154 <para>
7155 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7156 that remain unregulated because the law considers these <quote>fair uses.</quote>
7157 </para>
7158 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7159 <figure id="fig-1541">
7160 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.</title>
7161 <graphic fileref="images/1541.png"></graphic>
7162 </figure>
7163 <para>
7164 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7165 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7166 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7167 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7168 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7169 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7170 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such <quote>fair uses</quote>
7171 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7172 </para>
7173 <figure id="fig-1542">
7174 <title>Unregulated copying considered <quote>fair uses.</quote></title>
7175 <graphic fileref="images/1542.png"></graphic>
7176 </figure>
7177 <para> </para>
7178 <figure id="fig-1551">
7179 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.</title>
7180 <graphic fileref="images/1551.png"></graphic>
7181 </figure>
7182 <para>
7183 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7184 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7185 sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that
7186 are nonetheless deemed <quote>fair</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7187 </para>
7188 <indexterm startref='idxbooksusetypes' class='endofrange'/>
7189 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7190 <para>
7191 Enter the Internet&mdash;a distributed, digital network where every use
7192 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.<footnote><para>
7193 <!-- f18 -->
7194 I don't mean <quote>nature</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7195 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7196 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7197 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7198 of copies remain.
7199 </para></footnote>
7200 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7201 digital network, the scope of category 1 changes dramatically. Uses
7202 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7203 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7204 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7205 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7206 a copy&mdash;category 1 gets sucked into category 2. And those who
7207 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7208 exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7209 shift.
7210 </para>
7211 <para>
7212 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7213 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7214 be no plausible <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>-related argument that
7215 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7216 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7217 the book once, ten times, or every
7218 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7219 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7220 use&mdash;reading&mdash; could be regulated by copyright law because
7221 none of those uses produced a copy.
7222 </para>
7223 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7224 <para>
7225 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7226 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7227 only once or only once a month, then <emphasis>copyright
7228 law</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7229 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7230 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7231 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7232 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7233 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7234 copyright owner's wish.
7235 </para>
7236 <para>
7237 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7238 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7239 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7240 points also become clear:
7241 </para>
7242 <para>
7243 First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7244 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7245 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7246 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7247 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7248 part of free culture before the Internet.
7249 </para>
7250 <para>
7251 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7252 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7253 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7254 <emphasis>any</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7255 using a machine. <quote>Copy and paste</quote> and <quote>cut and paste</quote> become
7256 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7257 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7258 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7259 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7260 creative work.
7261 </para>
7262 <para>
7263 Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary
7264
7265 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7266 burden on category 3 (<quote>fair use</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7267 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7268 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7269 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7270 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7271 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7272 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7273 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7274 regulated.
7275 </para>
7276 <para>
7277 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7278 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7279 depend upon fair use&mdash;never even addressing the earlier question
7280 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7281 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7282 <emphasis>unregulated</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7283 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7284 enough.
7285 </para>
7286 <indexterm id='idxadvertising2' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
7287 <para>
7288 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7289 in the business of making <quote>trailer</quote> advertisements for movies available
7290 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7291 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7292 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7293 </para>
7294 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7295 <para>
7296 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it began
7297 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7298 previews. The idea was to expand their <quote>selling by sampling</quote>
7299 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7300 <quote>browsing.</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7301 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7302 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7303 </para>
7304 <para>
7305 In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7306 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7307 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7308 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7309 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7310 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter&mdash;he had built a
7311 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7312 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7313 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7314 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7315 <quote>fair use</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7316 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7317 their rights.
7318 </para>
7319 <para>
7320 Disney countersued&mdash;for $100 million in damages. Those damages
7321 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had <quote>willfully
7322 infringed</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7323 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7324 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7325 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7326 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7327 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $100 million.
7328 </para>
7329 <para>
7330 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7331 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7332 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7333 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7334 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7335 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7336 Disney's permission.
7337 </para>
7338 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising2' class='endofrange'/>
7339 <para>
7340 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7341 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7342 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7343 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7344 was in the marketplace, the <quote>first-sale doctrine</quote> would free the
7345 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7346 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7347 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7348 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7349 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7350 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7351 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7352 </para>
7353 <indexterm><primary>Barnes &amp; Noble</primary></indexterm>
7354 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7355 <para>
7356 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7357 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7358 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes &amp; Noble has the
7359 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7360 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7361 abuse. If Barnes &amp; Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7362 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7363 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7364 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7365 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7366 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7367 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7368 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7369 happening are quite slight.
7370 </para>
7371 <para>
7372 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7373 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7374 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7375 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7376 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7377 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7378 </para>
7379 </section>
7380 <section id="lawforce">
7381 <title>Architecture and Law: Force</title>
7382 <para>
7383 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7384 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7385 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7386 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7387 </para>
7388 <para>
7389 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7390 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7391 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7392 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7393 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7394 your freedom.
7395 </para>
7396 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca</primary></indexterm>
7397 <indexterm id="idxmarxbrothers" class='startofrange'><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7398 <indexterm id="idxwarnerbrothers" class='startofrange'><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7399 <para>
7400 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7401 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7402 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7403 <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7404 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7405 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7406 plan.<footnote><para>
7407 <!-- f19 -->
7408 See David Lange, <quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7409 Contemporary Problems</citetitle> 44 (1981): 172&ndash;73.
7410 </para></footnote>
7411 </para>
7412 <para>
7413 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7414 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers <quote>were brothers long before
7415 you were.</quote><footnote><para>
7416 <!-- f20 -->
7417 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
7418 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and
7419 Copywrongs</citetitle>, 1&ndash;3.
7420 </para></footnote>
7421 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7422 <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7423 trying to control <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>, then the Marx
7424 Brothers would insist on control over <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>.
7425 </para>
7426 <para>
7427 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7428 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7429 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7430 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7431 </para>
7432 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7433 <para>
7434 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7435 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7436 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7437 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7438 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7439 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7440 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7441 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7442 </para>
7443 <indexterm startref="idxwarnerbrothers" class='endofrange'/>
7444 <indexterm startref="idxmarxbrothers" class='endofrange'/>
7445
7446 <indexterm id="idxadobeebookreader" class='startofrange'><primary>Adobe eBook Reader</primary></indexterm>
7447 <para>
7448 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7449 </para>
7450 <para>
7451 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7452 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7453 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7454 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7455 technology.
7456 </para>
7457 <para>
7458 On the next page is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook
7459 Reader.
7460 </para>
7461 <para>
7462 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7463 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7464 public domain: <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, for example, is in
7465 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7466 public domain: My own book <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
7467 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7468 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7469 copy of
7470 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7471 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7472 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
7473 </para>
7474 <figure id="fig-1611">
7475 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader</title>
7476 <graphic fileref="images/1611.png"></graphic>
7477 </figure>
7478 <para>
7479 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7480 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7481 </para>
7482 <figure id="fig-1612">
7483 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.</title>
7484 <graphic fileref="images/1612.png"></graphic>
7485 </figure>
7486 <para>
7487 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7488 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
7489 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
7490 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
7491 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
7492 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>
7493 read aloud through the computer.
7494 </para>
7495 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle</primary></indexterm>
7496 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics</citetitle>, (Aristotle)</primary></indexterm>
7497 <para>
7498 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7499 translation): Aristotle's <citetitle>Politics</citetitle>.
7500 </para>
7501 <figure id="fig-1621">
7502 <title>E-book of Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote></title>
7503 <graphic fileref="images/1621.png"></graphic>
7504 </figure>
7505 <para>
7506 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7507 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
7508 the book.
7509 </para>
7510 <figure id="fig-1622">
7511 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote>.</title>
7512 <graphic fileref="images/1622.png"></graphic>
7513 </figure>
7514 <para>
7515 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
7516 original e-book version of my last book, <citetitle>The Future of
7517 Ideas</citetitle>:
7518 </para>
7519 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
7520 <figure id="fig-1631">
7521 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>The Future of Ideas</quote>.</title>
7522 <graphic fileref="images/1631.png"></graphic>
7523 </figure>
7524 <para>
7525 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
7526 </para>
7527 <para>
7528 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
7529 <quote>permissions</quote>&mdash; as if the publisher has the power to control how
7530 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
7531 certainly does have the power&mdash;up to the limits of the copyright
7532 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
7533 power.<footnote><para>
7534 <!-- f21 -->
7535 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
7536 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
7537 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
7538 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
7539 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
7540 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
7541 subsequently acquired the book.
7542 </para></footnote>
7543 When my e-book of <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> says I have the
7544 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
7545 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
7546 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
7547 control that the law would enable.
7548 </para>
7549 <para>
7550 The control comes instead from the code&mdash;from the technology
7551 within which the e-book <quote>lives.</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
7552 permissions, they are not the sort of <quote>permissions</quote> that most of us
7553 deal with. When a teenager gets <quote>permission</quote> to stay out till
7554 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
7555 till 2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
7556 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
7557 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
7558 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
7559 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
7560 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
7561 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
7562 aloud&mdash;it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
7563 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
7564 won't read aloud.
7565 </para>
7566 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7567 <para>
7568 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
7569 These are <emphasis>controls</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
7570 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
7571 you tried to type <quote>Warner Brothers,</quote> erased <quote>Brothers</quote> from the
7572 sentence.
7573 </para>
7574 <para>
7575 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
7576 <emphasis>law</emphasis> as copyright <emphasis>code</emphasis>. The
7577 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
7578 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
7579 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
7580 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
7581 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
7582 </para>
7583 <para>
7584 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
7585 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
7586 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
7587 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
7588 to defeat these protections as well?
7589 </para>
7590 <para>
7591 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
7592 eBook Reader.
7593 </para>
7594 <indexterm><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)</primary></indexterm>
7595 <para>
7596 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
7597 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
7598 on the Adobe site was a copy of <citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
7599 Wonderland</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
7600 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
7601 following report:
7602 </para>
7603 <figure id="fig-1641">
7604 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>Alice's Adventures in
7605 Wonderland</quote>.</title>
7606 <graphic fileref="images/1641.png"></graphic>
7607 </figure>
7608 <beginpage pagenum="164"/>
7609 <para>
7610 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
7611 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
7612 <quote>permissions</quote> indicated, not allowed to <quote>read aloud</quote>!
7613 </para>
7614 <para>
7615 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
7616 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
7617 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
7618 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
7619 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
7620 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
7621 </para>
7622 <para>
7623 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
7624 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
7625 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
7626 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
7627 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
7628 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
7629 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
7630 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
7631 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
7632 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
7633 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
7634 </para>
7635 <para>
7636 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
7637 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
7638 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
7639 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
7640 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
7641 often crazy.
7642 </para>
7643 <indexterm startref="idxadobeebookreader" class='endofrange'/>
7644 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'/>
7645 <para>
7646 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
7647 story of mine that makes the same point.
7648 </para>
7649 <indexterm id="idxaibo1" class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7650 <indexterm id="idxroboticdog1" class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7651 <indexterm id="idxsonyaibo1" class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
7652 <para>
7653 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named <quote>Aibo.</quote> The Aibo
7654 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
7655 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
7656 </para>
7657 <para>
7658 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
7659 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
7660 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
7661 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
7662 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
7663 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
7664 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
7665 </para>
7666 <para>
7667 <quote>Teach</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
7668 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
7669 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
7670 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
7671 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
7672 their computer <quote>dog</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
7673 </para>
7674 <indexterm><primary>hacks</primary></indexterm>
7675 <para>
7676 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
7677 <citetitle>hack</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
7678 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
7679 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
7680 them, <citetitle>hack</citetitle> is a much more positive
7681 term. <citetitle>Hack</citetitle> just means code that enables the
7682 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
7683 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
7684 old computer doesn't run, or <quote>drive,</quote> the printer. If you discovered
7685 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
7686 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
7687 you just bought.
7688 </para>
7689 <para>
7690 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
7691 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
7692 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
7693 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
7694 ethically.
7695 </para>
7696 <para>
7697 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
7698 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
7699 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
7700 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
7701 than Sony had built.
7702 </para>
7703 <indexterm startref="idxsonyaibo1" class='endofrange'/>
7704 <indexterm startref="idxroboticdog1" class='endofrange'/>
7705 <indexterm startref="idxaibo1" class='endofrange'/>
7706 <para>
7707 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
7708 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
7709 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
7710 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
7711 the
7712
7713 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
7714 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
7715 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
7716 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
7717 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
7718 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
7719 thought, <emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
7720 a robot dog to dance?</emphasis>
7721 </para>
7722 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>government case against</secondary></indexterm>
7723 <para>
7724 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show&mdash;
7725 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
7726 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
7727 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
7728 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
7729 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
7730 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
7731 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
7732 into being silent about something he knew very well.
7733 </para>
7734 <para>
7735 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.<footnote><para>
7736 <!-- f22 -->
7737 See Pamela Samuelson, <quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,</quote>
7738 <citetitle>Science</citetitle> 293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, <quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
7739 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect</citetitle>,
7740 January 2002; <quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
7741 DMCA,</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter</citetitle>, 11 December 2001; Bill
7742 Holland, <quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,</quote> <citetitle>Billboard</citetitle>,
7743 May 2001; Janelle Brown, <quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?</quote> Salon.com,
7744 April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, <quote>Frequently Asked
7745 Questions about <citetitle>Felten and USENIX</citetitle> v. <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> Legal Case,</quote> available at
7746 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #27</ulink>.
7747 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
7748 </para></footnote>
7749 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
7750 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
7751 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
7752 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
7753 </para>
7754 <para>
7755 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
7756 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
7757 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
7758 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
7759 <quote>this music cannot be copied,</quote> and have a computer respect that
7760 command. The technology was to be part of a <quote>trusted system</quote> of
7761 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
7762 Internet much more.
7763 </para>
7764 <para>
7765 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
7766 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
7767 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
7768 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
7769 </para>
7770 <para>
7771 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
7772 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
7773 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
7774 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
7775 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
7776 </para>
7777 <para>
7778 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
7779 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
7780 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
7781 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
7782 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
7783 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
7784 </para>
7785 <para>
7786 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
7787 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
7788 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
7789 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
7790 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
7791 constituted, succeed.
7792 </para>
7793 <indexterm id="idxaibo2" class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7794 <indexterm id="idxroboticdog2" class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7795 <indexterm id="idxsonyaibo2" class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
7796 <para>
7797 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
7798 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
7799 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
7800 wrote:
7801 </para>
7802 <blockquote>
7803 <para>
7804 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
7805 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
7806 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
7807 </para>
7808 </blockquote>
7809 <indexterm startref="idxsonyaibo2" class='endofrange'/>
7810 <indexterm startref="idxroboticdog2" class='endofrange'/>
7811 <indexterm startref="idxaibo2" class='endofrange'/>
7812 <para>
7813 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
7814 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
7815 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
7816 </para>
7817 <blockquote>
7818 <para>
7819 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
7820 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
7821 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
7822 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
7823 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (<quote>DMCA</quote>).
7824 </para>
7825 </blockquote>
7826 <para>
7827 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
7828 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
7829 spreading such information an offense.
7830 </para>
7831 <para>
7832 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
7833 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
7834 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
7835 These new technologies would be copyright protection
7836 technologies&mdash; technologies to control the replication and
7837 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
7838 <emphasis>code</emphasis> to modify the original
7839 <emphasis>code</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
7840 protection for copyright owners.
7841 </para>
7842 <para>
7843 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
7844 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
7845 <emphasis>legal code</emphasis> intended to buttress
7846 <emphasis>software code</emphasis> which itself was intended to
7847 support the <emphasis>legal code of copyright</emphasis>.
7848 </para>
7849 <para>
7850 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
7851 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
7852 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
7853 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
7854 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
7855 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
7856 have been a copyright violation.
7857 </para>
7858 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7859 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7860 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
7861 <para>
7862 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
7863 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
7864 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
7865 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
7866 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
7867 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
7868 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
7869 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
7870 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
7871 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
7872 </para>
7873 <para>
7874 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
7875 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
7876 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
7877 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
7878 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
7879 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
7880 </para>
7881 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
7882 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
7883 <para>
7884 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
7885 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
7886 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
7887 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
7888 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
7889 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka <quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers</citetitle>,</quote>
7890 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
7891 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
7892 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
7893 </para>
7894 <blockquote>
7895 <para>
7896 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
7897 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
7898 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
7899 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
7900 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
7901 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the <quote>Neighborhood</quote>
7902 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
7903 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
7904 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
7905 broadcasting has always been <quote>You are an important person just the way
7906 you are. You can make healthy decisions.</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
7907 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
7908 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
7909 important.<footnote><para>
7910 <!-- f23 -->
7911 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
7912 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
7913 455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
7914 James Lardner, <citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
7915 the VCR</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270&ndash;71.
7916 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
7917 </para></footnote>
7918 </para>
7919 </blockquote>
7920 <para>
7921 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
7922 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
7923 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
7924 the VCR responsible.
7925 </para>
7926 <para>
7927 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
7928 the DMCA.
7929 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
7930 </para>
7931 <para>
7932 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
7933 </para>
7934 <para>
7935 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
7936 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
7937 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
7938 pirating of copyrighted material&mdash;a bad end. Or they can be used
7939 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
7940 would be considered fair use&mdash;a good end.
7941 </para>
7942 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'><primary>handguns</primary></indexterm>
7943 <para>
7944 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
7945 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
7946 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
7947 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
7948 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
7949 and bad uses.
7950 </para>
7951 <figure id="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig">
7952 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.</title>
7953 <graphic fileref="images/1711.png"></graphic>
7954 </figure>
7955 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
7956 <para>
7957 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
7958 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
7959 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: <emphasis>No one ever
7960 died from copyright circumvention</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
7961 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
7962 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
7963 </para>
7964 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'/>
7965 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'/>
7966 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7967 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7968 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
7969 <para>
7970 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
7971 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
7972 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
7973 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
7974 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
7975 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
7976 </para>
7977 <para>
7978 This is how <emphasis>code</emphasis> becomes
7979 <emphasis>law</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
7980 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
7981 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
7982 law&mdash;increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
7983 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
7984 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
7985 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect&mdash;at
7986 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
7987 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
7988 </para>
7989 <para>
7990 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
7991 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
7992 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
7993 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
7994 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
7995 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
7996 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
7997 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
7998 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
7999 </para>
8000 <para>
8001
8002 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
8003 For example, imagine you were part of a <citetitle>Star Trek</citetitle> fan club. You
8004 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
8005 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
8006 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
8007 simply continue it.<footnote><para>
8008 <!-- f24 -->
8009 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, <quote>Legal Fictions,
8010 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
8011 Entertainment Law Journal</citetitle> 17 (1997): 651.
8012 </para></footnote>
8013 </para>
8014 <para>
8015 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
8016 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
8017 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
8018 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
8019 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
8020 </para>
8021 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
8022 <para>
8023 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
8024 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
8025 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
8026 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
8027 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
8028 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
8029 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
8030 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
8031 </para>
8032 <para>
8033 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
8034 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
8035 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
8036 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8037 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8038 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8039 </para>
8040 </section>
8041 <section id="marketconcentration">
8042 <title>Market: Concentration</title>
8043 <para>
8044 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically&mdash;tripled in
8045 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8046 well&mdash;from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8047 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8048 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8049 find better ways
8050 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8051 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8052 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8053 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8054 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8055 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8056 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8057 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8058 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8059 control.
8060 </para>
8061 <para>
8062 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8063 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8064 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8065 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8066 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8067 </para>
8068 <para>
8069 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8070 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8071 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8072 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8073 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8074 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8075 announced in June 2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8076 live in a world where just three companies control more than percent
8077 of the media.
8078 </para>
8079 <para>
8080 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8081 nature.
8082 </para>
8083 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8084 <indexterm><primary>BMG</primary></indexterm>
8085 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
8086 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John</primary></indexterm>
8087 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8088 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8089 <para>
8090 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8091 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8092 ownership, <quote>five companies control 85 percent of our media sources.</quote><footnote><para>
8093 <!-- f25 -->
8094 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8095 Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003)
8096 (statement of Senator John McCain). </para></footnote>
8097 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8098 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 percent of the
8099 U.S. music market.<footnote><para>
8100 <!-- f26 -->
8101 Lynette Holloway, <quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8102 Slide,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 23 December 2002.
8103 </para></footnote>
8104 The <quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8105 programming to 74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.</quote><footnote><para>
8106 <!-- f27 -->
8107 Molly Ivins, <quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette</citetitle>,
8108 31 May 2003.
8109 </para></footnote>
8110 </para>
8111 <para>
8112 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8113 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8114 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8115 seventy-five stations. Today <emphasis>one</emphasis> company owns
8116 more than 1,200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8117 total number of radio owners dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most
8118 markets, the two largest broadcasters control 74 percent of that
8119 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control 90 percent of
8120 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8121 </para>
8122 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8123 <para>
8124 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8125 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8126 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8127 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8128 the United States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all
8129 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent
8130 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8131 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8132 protected&mdash; by the market.
8133 </para>
8134 <para>
8135 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8136 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8137 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8138 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8139 </para>
8140 <blockquote>
8141 <para>
8142 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8143 unmatched in its integration. They supply content&mdash;Fox movies
8144 &hellip; Fox TV shows &hellip; Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8145 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8146 advertisers&mdash;in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8147 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8148 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8149 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8150 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8151 the same function in the United States.<footnote><para>
8152 <!-- f28 -->
8153 James Fallows, <quote>The Age of Murdoch,</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly</citetitle> (September
8154 2003): 89.
8155 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8156 </para></footnote>
8157 </para>
8158 </blockquote>
8159 <para>
8160 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8161 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8162 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8163 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8164 </para>
8165 <figure id="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership">
8166 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.</title>
8167 <graphic fileref="images/1761.png"></graphic>
8168 </figure>
8169 <para>
8170 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8171 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8172 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8173 distribute content?
8174 </para>
8175 <para>
8176 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8177 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8178 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8179 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8180 </para>
8181 <para>
8182 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8183 integration may matter.
8184 </para>
8185 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman</primary></indexterm>
8186 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8187 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8188 <para>
8189 In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle>. He took
8190 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8191 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8192 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8193 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8194 </para>
8195 <para>
8196 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8197 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8198 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8199 control.<footnote><para>
8200 <!-- f29 -->
8201 Leonard Hill, <quote>The Axis of Access,</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8202 Forum, <quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,</quote> St. Louis,
8203 Missouri, 3 April 2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8204 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #28</ulink>;
8205 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8206 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #29</ulink>).
8207 </para></footnote>
8208 </para>
8209 <para>
8210
8211 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8212 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8213 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8214 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8215 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992,
8216 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8217 television&mdash;75 percent of it&mdash;was <quote>independent</quote> of the
8218 networks.
8219 </para>
8220 <para>
8221 In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8222 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985,
8223 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8224 2002, only five independent television studios remained. <quote>In 1992,
8225 only 15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8226 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8227 controlled companies more than quintupled to 77 percent.</quote> <quote>In 1992, 16
8228 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8229 year there was one.</quote><footnote><para>
8230 <!-- f30 -->
8231 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8232 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st
8233 sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8234 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8235 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8236 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8237 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February
8238 2003.
8239 </para></footnote>
8240 In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8241 that ran it. <quote>In the ten-year period between 1992 and 2002, the number
8242 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8243 increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8244 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8245 63%.</quote><footnote><para>
8246 <!-- f31 -->
8247 Ibid.
8248 </para></footnote>
8249 </para>
8250 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8251 <para>
8252 Today, another Norman Lear with another <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle> would
8253 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8254 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8255 owned by the network.
8256 </para>
8257 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry</primary></indexterm>
8258 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill</primary></indexterm>
8259 <para>
8260 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8261 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8262 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8263 </para>
8264 <blockquote>
8265 <para>
8266 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8267 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8268 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8269 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8270 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8271 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8272 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8273 handful.<footnote><para>
8274 <!-- f32 -->
8275 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers</citetitle>, Bill
8276 Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at
8277 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #31</ulink>.
8278 </para></footnote>
8279 </para>
8280 </blockquote>
8281 <para>
8282 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8283 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8284 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8285 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8286 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8287 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8288 question without risk of consequence&mdash;not necessarily banishment
8289 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8290 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8291 democracy.
8292 </para>
8293 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.</primary></indexterm>
8294 <para>
8295 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8296 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the <quote>Innovator's
8297 Dilemma</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8298 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8299 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8300 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.<footnote><para>
8301 <!-- f33 -->
8302 Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8303 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle>
8304 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press, 1997). Christensen
8305 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8306 Kim B. Clark, <quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8307 Concepts in Technological Evolution,</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy</citetitle> 14 (1985):
8308 235&ndash;51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8309 Kaplan, <citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8310 Underperform the Market&mdash;and How to Successfully Transform Them</citetitle>
8311 (New York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001). </para></footnote>
8312
8313 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8314 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8315 sprinting.
8316 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
8317 </para>
8318 <para>
8319 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8320 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8321 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8322 measure.
8323 </para>
8324 <para>
8325 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8326 suggest the concern.
8327 </para>
8328 <para>
8329 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8330 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8331 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8332 </para>
8333 <para>
8334 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8335 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8336 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8337
8338 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8339 wrecked by drugs&mdash;though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8340 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8341 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8342 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8343 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8344 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8345 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8346 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8347 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8348 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8349 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8350 outweigh these costs.
8351 </para>
8352 <para>
8353 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8354 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8355 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8356 these issues.
8357 </para>
8358 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8359 <para>
8360 Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8361 a media campaign as part of the <quote>war on drugs.</quote> The campaign produced
8362 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8363 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8364 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8365 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8366 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8367 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8368 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8369 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8370 </para>
8371 <para>
8372 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8373 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8374 </para>
8375 <para>
8376 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8377 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8378 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8379 war. Can you do it?
8380 </para>
8381 <para>
8382 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8383 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8384 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8385 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8386 message will be heard then?
8387 </para>
8388 <para>
8389 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8390 <quote>controversial</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8391 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8392 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8393 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8394 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8395 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8396 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8397 rights of the stations to be this biased.<footnote><para>
8398 <!-- f34 -->
8399 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads
8400 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8401 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as <quote>against
8402 [their] policy.</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8403 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8404 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8405 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8406 Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8407 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, <quote>On the Issue of
8408 an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV Networks,</quote> <citetitle>New
8409 York Times</citetitle>, 13 March 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time
8410 there is very little that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to
8411 even the playing field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, <quote>Ad
8412 Hoc Access: The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8413 Radio,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review</citetitle> 6 (1988): 449&ndash;79, and for a
8414 more recent summary of the stance of the FCC and the courts, see
8415 <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors Association</citetitle> v. <citetitle>FCC</citetitle>, 184 F. 3d 872
8416 (D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8417 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8418 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8419 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, <quote>Antidiesel Group Fuming
8420 After Muni Rejects Ad,</quote> SFGate.com, 16 June 2003, available at
8421 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #32</ulink>. The ground
8422 was that the criticism was <quote>too controversial.</quote>
8423 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8424 <indexterm><primary>Comcast</primary></indexterm>
8425 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project</primary></indexterm>
8426 <indexterm><primary>NBC</primary></indexterm>
8427 <indexterm><primary>WJOA</primary></indexterm>
8428 <indexterm><primary>WRC</primary></indexterm>
8429 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8430 </para></footnote>
8431 </para>
8432 <para>
8433 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well&mdash;if we lived
8434 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8435 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8436 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8437 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8438 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8439 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8440 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8441 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8442 </para>
8443 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'/>
8444 </section>
8445 <section id="together">
8446 <title>Together</title>
8447 <para>
8448 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8449 copyright warriors that the government should <quote>protect my property.</quote>
8450 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8451 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8452 </para>
8453 <para>
8454 But when we see how dramatically this <quote>property</quote> has changed&mdash;
8455 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8456 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8457 cultivate our culture is dramatically different&mdash;the claim begins
8458 to seem
8459
8460 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8461 less innocent and obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to
8462 supplement the law's control, and (2) the power of concentrated
8463 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8464 the massively expanded <quote>property</quote> rights granted by copyright
8465 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8466 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8467 be redefined.
8468 </para>
8469 <para>
8470 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8471 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8472 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8473 our culture today.
8474 </para>
8475 <para>
8476 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8477 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8478 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8479 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8480 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8481 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8482 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8483 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8484 traditionally defined copyright's regulation&mdash;a weakening of that
8485 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
8486 </para>
8487 <para>
8488 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
8489 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
8490 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
8491 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
8492 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
8493 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
8494 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
8495 future. And these changes have to be <emphasis>reductions</emphasis>
8496 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
8497 in control that technology and the market enable.
8498 </para>
8499 <para>
8500 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
8501 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
8502 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
8503 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
8504 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
8505 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
8506 more of the development of our culture than now</emphasis>.
8507 </para>
8508 <para>
8509 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
8510 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
8511 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
8512 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
8513 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
8514 were independent of the networks. <emphasis>Never</emphasis> has
8515 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
8516 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
8517 regulation&mdash;a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
8518 energy of a nation at the founding&mdash;is now a massive regulation
8519 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
8520 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
8521 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
8522 known.<footnote><para>
8523 <!-- f35 -->
8524 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
8525 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his <quote>four surrenders</quote> of
8526 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan, 159&ndash;60.
8527 </para></footnote>
8528 </para>
8529 <para>
8530 <emphasis role='strong'>This has been</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
8531 point can now be briefly stated.
8532 </para>
8533 <para>
8534 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
8535 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
8536 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
8537 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
8538 that copyright law has undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this:
8539 </para>
8540
8541 <informaltable id="t2">
8542 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
8543 <thead>
8544 <row>
8545 <entry></entry>
8546 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
8547 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8548 </row>
8549 </thead>
8550 <tbody>
8551 <row>
8552 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8553 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8554 <entry>Free</entry>
8555 </row>
8556 <row>
8557 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8558 <entry>Free</entry>
8559 <entry>Free</entry>
8560 </row>
8561 </tbody>
8562 </tgroup>
8563 </informaltable>
8564
8565 <para>
8566 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
8567 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
8568 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
8569
8570 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
8571 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
8572 noncommercial work was also free.
8573 </para>
8574 <para>
8575 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
8576 </para>
8577
8578 <informaltable id="t3">
8579 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
8580 <thead>
8581 <row>
8582 <entry></entry>
8583 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
8584 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8585 </row>
8586 </thead>
8587 <tbody>
8588 <row>
8589 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8590 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8591 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8592 </row>
8593 <row>
8594 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8595 <entry>Free</entry>
8596 <entry>Free</entry>
8597 </row>
8598 </tbody>
8599 </tgroup>
8600 </informaltable>
8601
8602 <para>
8603 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law&mdash;if
8604 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
8605 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
8606 transformation were still essentially free.
8607 </para>
8608 <para>
8609 In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
8610 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
8611 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
8612 expanded. Thus by 1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
8613 we could say the law began to look like this:
8614 </para>
8615
8616 <informaltable id="t4">
8617 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
8618 <thead>
8619 <row>
8620 <entry></entry>
8621 <entry>COPY</entry>
8622 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8623 </row>
8624 </thead>
8625 <tbody>
8626 <row>
8627 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8628 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8629 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8630 </row>
8631 <row>
8632 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8633 <entry>&copy;/Free</entry>
8634 <entry>Free</entry>
8635 </row>
8636 </tbody>
8637 </tgroup>
8638 </informaltable>
8639
8640 <para>
8641 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
8642 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
8643 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
8644 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
8645 that the law now looks like this:
8646 </para>
8647
8648 <informaltable id="t5">
8649 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
8650 <thead>
8651 <row>
8652 <entry></entry>
8653 <entry>COPY</entry>
8654 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8655 </row>
8656 </thead>
8657 <tbody>
8658 <row>
8659 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8660 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8661 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8662 </row>
8663 <row>
8664 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8665 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8666 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8667 </row>
8668 </tbody>
8669 </tgroup>
8670 </informaltable>
8671
8672 <para>
8673 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
8674 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
8675 creativity&mdash;
8676 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
8677 commercial or not, transformative or not&mdash;with the same rules
8678 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
8679 </para>
8680 <para>
8681 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
8682 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
8683 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
8684 these domains actually does any good.
8685 </para>
8686 <para>
8687 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
8688 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
8689 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
8690 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
8691 reasons sketched especially in chapters
8692 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/> and
8693 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>, one
8694 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
8695 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
8696 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
8697 </para>
8698 <para>
8699 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
8700 course copyright is a kind of <quote>property,</quote> and of course, as with any
8701 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
8702 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
8703 property rights<footnote><para>
8704 <!-- f36 -->
8705 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
8706 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
8707 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, <quote>The
8708 Disintegration of Property,</quote> in <citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property</citetitle>, J. Roland
8709 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
8710 Press, 1980).
8711 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement</primary></indexterm>
8712 </para></footnote>)
8713 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
8714 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
8715 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
8716 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the <quote>copyright</quote>
8717 did not control <emphasis>at all</emphasis> the freedom of others to
8718 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
8719 free, and for almost 180 years our country consistently protected a
8720 vibrant and rich free culture.
8721 </para>
8722 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
8723 <para>
8724 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
8725 limits on the scope of the interests protected by <quote>property.</quote> The very
8726 birth of <quote>copyright</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
8727 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
8728 story of chapter 6). The tradition of <quote>fair use</quote> is animated by a
8729 similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the costs of
8730 exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the story of
8731 chapter 7). Adding
8732 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
8733 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
8734 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter
8735 8). And granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect,
8736 claims of property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing
8737 the soul of a culture (chapter 9). Free cultures, like free markets,
8738 are built with property. But the nature of the property that builds a
8739 free culture is very different from the extremist vision that
8740 dominates the debate today.
8741 </para>
8742 <para>
8743 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
8744 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
8745 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
8746 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
8747 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
8748 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
8749 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
8750 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
8751 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
8752 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
8753 lawyer.
8754 </para>
8755 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
8756 </section>
8757 </chapter>
8758 </part>
8759 <part id="c-puzzles">
8760 <title>PUZZLES</title>
8761
8762 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
8763 <chapter label="11" id="chimera">
8764 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera</title>
8765 <indexterm id="idxchimera" class='startofrange'><primary>chimeras</primary></indexterm>
8766 <indexterm id="idxwells" class='startofrange'><primary>Wells, H. G.</primary></indexterm>
8767 <indexterm id="idxtcotb" class='startofrange'><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The</quote> (Wells)</primary></indexterm>
8768
8769 <para>
8770 <emphasis role='strong'>In a well-known</emphasis> short story by
8771 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
8772 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
8773 Andes.<footnote><para>
8774 <!-- f1. -->
8775 H. G. Wells, <quote>The Country of the Blind</quote> (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells,
8776 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
8777 York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
8778 </para></footnote>
8779 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with <quote>sweet water, pasture,
8780 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
8781 that bore an excellent fruit.</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
8782 takes this as an opportunity. <quote>In the Country of the Blind,</quote> he tells
8783 himself, <quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.</quote> So he resolves to live with the
8784 villagers to explore life as a king.
8785 </para>
8786 <para>
8787 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
8788 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
8789 <quote>blind.</quote> They don't have the word <citetitle>blind</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
8790 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
8791 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
8792 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. <quote>`You
8793 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
8794 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
8795 alone!'</quote>
8796 </para>
8797 <para>
8798 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
8799 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
8800 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
8801 affection, a young woman who to him seems <quote>the most beautiful thing in
8802 the whole of creation,</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
8803 description of what he sees <quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
8804 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
8805 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
8806 indulgence.</quote> <quote>She did not believe,</quote> Wells tells us, and <quote>she could
8807 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.</quote>
8808 </para>
8809 <para>
8810 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his <quote>mysteriously delighted</quote>
8811 love, the father and the village object. <quote>You see, my dear,</quote> her
8812 father instructs, <quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
8813 anything right.</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
8814 </para>
8815 <para>
8816 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. <quote>His brain
8817 is affected,</quote> he reports.
8818 </para>
8819 <para>
8820 <quote>What affects it?</quote> the father asks. <quote>Those queer things that are
8821 called the eyes &hellip; are diseased &hellip; in such a way as to affect
8822 his brain.</quote>
8823 </para>
8824 <para>
8825 The doctor continues: <quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
8826 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
8827 simple and easy surgical operation&mdash;namely, to remove these
8828 irritant bodies [the eyes].</quote>
8829 </para>
8830 <para>
8831 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
8832 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
8833 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
8834 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
8835 </para>
8836 <para>
8837 <emphasis role='strong'>It sometimes</emphasis> happens that the eggs
8838 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
8839 <quote>chimera.</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
8840 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
8841 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
8842
8843 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
8844 plot for murder mysteries. <quote>But the DNA shows with 100 percent
8845 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
8846 scene. &hellip;</quote>
8847 </para>
8848 <indexterm startref="idxtcotb" class='endofrange'/>
8849 <indexterm startref="idxwells" class="endofrange"/>
8850 <para>
8851 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
8852 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
8853 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
8854 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
8855 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
8856 understanding of a <quote>person</quote> should reflect this reality.
8857 </para>
8858 <para>
8859 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
8860 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
8861 unfairly enough, <quote>the copyright wars,</quote> the more I think we're dealing
8862 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question <quote>What is
8863 p2p file sharing?</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
8864 wrong. One side says, <quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
8865 others' records&mdash;the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
8866 thirty years without any question at all.</quote> That's true, at least in
8867 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
8868 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
8869 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
8870 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
8871 </para>
8872 <para>
8873 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
8874 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
8875 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
8876 <quote>friends</quote> beyond recognition to say <quote>my ten thousand best friends</quote> can
8877 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
8878 what <quote>we have always been allowed to do,</quote> we have not always been
8879 allowed to share music with <quote>our ten thousand best friends.</quote>
8880 </para>
8881 <para>
8882 Likewise, when the other side says, <quote>File sharing is just like walking
8883 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
8884 with it,</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
8885 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
8886 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
8887 from Tower.
8888 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
8889 </para>
8890 <para>
8891
8892 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
8893 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
8894 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
8895 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
8896 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
8897 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
8898 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
8899 $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
8900 CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.)
8901 </para>
8902 <para>
8903 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
8904 that it is both&mdash;both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
8905 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
8906 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
8907 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
8908 </para>
8909 <para>
8910 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
8911 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
8912 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
8913 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
8914 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
8915 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
8916 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
8917 implemented.<footnote><para>
8918 <!-- f2. -->
8919 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
8920 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
8921 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
8922 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003,
8923 available at
8924 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
8925 #33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
8926 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
8927 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
8928 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, <quote>House Bill Aims to Up
8929 Stakes on Piracy,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 17 July 2003, available at
8930 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #34</ulink>. Civil
8931 penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied song. For a recent
8932 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
8933 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 songs
8934 through a family computer, see <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
8935 re. Verizon Internet Services)</citetitle>, 240 F. Supp. 2d 24
8936 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $90
8937 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
8938 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
8939 $12,000 to $17,500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
8940 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $98
8941 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
8942 Elizabeth Young, <quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,</quote> redandblack.com,
8943 August 2003, available at
8944 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #35</ulink>. For an
8945 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
8946 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
8947 identities, see James Collins, <quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
8948 Name Students,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 8 August 2003, D3, available at
8949 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #36</ulink>.
8950 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
8951 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
8952 </para></footnote>
8953
8954 </para>
8955 <indexterm startref="idxchimera" class='endofrange'/>
8956 <para>
8957 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
8958 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
8959 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
8960 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
8961 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
8962 </para>
8963 <para>
8964 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
8965 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
8966 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
8967 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
8968 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
8969 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe <emphasis>either</emphasis> extreme
8970 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
8971 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
8972 </para>
8973 <para>
8974
8975 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
8976 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
8977 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
8978 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
8979 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
8980 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
8981 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
8982 </para>
8983 <para>
8984 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to <quote>steal</quote> music. My
8985 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
8986 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
8987 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
8988 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
8989 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
8990 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
8991 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
8992 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
8993 protection for copyrighted material,
8994 </para>
8995 <blockquote>
8996 <para>
8997 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
8998 material, and we want to protect those rights.
8999 </para>
9000 <para>
9001 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
9002 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
9003 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
9004 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
9005 produce a totally different industry model.
9006 </para>
9007 <para>
9008 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
9009 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
9010 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
9011 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
9012 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
9013 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
9014 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
9015 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
9016 interests.<footnote><para>
9017 <!-- f3. -->
9018 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
9019 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
9020 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
9021 House Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement of Peter
9022 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
9023 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
9024 Congressional Testimony File. </para></footnote>
9025 </para>
9026 </blockquote>
9027 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
9028 <para>
9029 In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
9030 one of <quote>the major labels.</quote> Its position on these matters has now
9031 changed.
9032 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9033 </para>
9034 <para>
9035 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
9036 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9037 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9038 </para>
9039
9040 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9041 </chapter>
9042 <chapter label="12" id="harms">
9043 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms</title>
9044 <para>
9045 <emphasis role='strong'>To fight</emphasis> <quote>piracy,</quote> to
9046 protect <quote>property,</quote> the content industry has launched a
9047 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9048 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9049 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9050 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9051 </para>
9052 <para>
9053 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9054 particular, the consequences for <quote>free culture.</quote> But my aim now is to
9055 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9056 justified?
9057 </para>
9058 <para>
9059 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9060 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9061 power of the property called <quote>intellectual property</quote> is at its greatest in
9062 our history.
9063 </para>
9064 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
9065 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
9066 <para>
9067 Yet <quote>common sense</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9068 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9069 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9070 rejection of <quote>piracy</quote> still has play.
9071 </para>
9072 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9073 <para>
9074 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9075 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9076 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9077 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9078 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9079 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9080 </para>
9081 <section id="constrain">
9082 <title>Constraining Creators</title>
9083 <para>
9084 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9085 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9086 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9087 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9088 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9089 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9090 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9091 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9092 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9093 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9094 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9095 weave together a string&mdash;a mash-up&mdash; of songs from your
9096 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9097 </para>
9098 <para>
9099 This digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> is in part an extension of the
9100 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9101 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9102 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9103 of digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9104 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9105 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9106 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9107 the culture all around.
9108 </para>
9109 <para>
9110 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9111 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9112
9113 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9114
9115 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9116 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9117 storytelling extended across the globe.
9118 </para>
9119 <para>
9120 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9121 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9122 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9123 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9124 that catalog cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9125 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9126 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9127 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9128 work is presumptively illegal.
9129 </para>
9130 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom</primary></indexterm>
9131 <para>
9132 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9133 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9134 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9135 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9136 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9137 by the RIAA ( Jesse Jordan of chapter 3 was just one) were threatened
9138 with a $98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted
9139 songs to be copied. Yet World-Com&mdash;which defrauded investors of
9140 $11 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization
9141 of over $200 billion&mdash;received a fine of a mere $750
9142 million.<footnote><para>
9143 <!-- f1. -->
9144 See Lynne W. Jeter, <citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom</citetitle>
9145 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley &amp; Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of
9146 the settlement, see MCI press release, <quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9147 Approval for SEC Settlement</quote> (7 July 2003), available at
9148 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #37</ulink>.
9149 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom</primary></indexterm>
9150 </para></footnote>
9151 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9152 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9153 no more than $250,000 in damages for pain and
9154 suffering.<footnote>
9155 <para>
9156 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9157 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For
9158 an overview, see Tanya Albert, <quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9159 Say Tort Reformers,</quote> amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at
9160 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #38</ulink>,
9161 and <quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,</quote> CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003,
9162 available at
9163 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9164 recent months.
9165 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.</primary></indexterm>
9166 </para></footnote>
9167 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9168 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9169 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9170 </para>
9171 <indexterm><primary>art, underground</primary></indexterm>
9172 <para>
9173 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9174 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9175 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9176 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9177 Disneys <quote>pirates.</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9178 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9179 designed to
9180
9181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9182 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9183 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9184 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9185 we will begin to see a world of underground art&mdash;not because the
9186 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9187 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9188 fraught. Already, exhibits of <quote>illegal art</quote> tour the United
9189 States.<footnote><para>
9190 <!-- f3. -->
9191
9192 See Danit Lidor, <quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,</quote> <citetitle>Wired</citetitle>, 7 July
9193 2003, available at
9194 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9195 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #41</ulink>.
9196 </para></footnote>
9197 In what does their <quote>illegality</quote> consist?
9198 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9199 critical or reflective.
9200 </para>
9201 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9202 <para>
9203 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9204 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9205 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. But an
9206 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9207 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9208 discovered in 2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9209 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9210 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9211 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9212 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9213 </para>
9214 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
9215 <para>
9216 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9217 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9218 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9219 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9220 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9221 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9222 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9223 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9224 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9225 </para>
9226 <para>
9227 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9228 described in chapter
9229 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/>, in
9230 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9231 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9232 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9233 use.
9234 </para>
9235 <para>
9236
9237 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9238 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9239 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9240 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad&mdash;in
9241 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9242 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9243 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9244 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9245 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9246 </para>
9247 <para>
9248 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9249 <quote>breathing room</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9250 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9251 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9252 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9253 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9254 journalists&mdash; these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9255 these rules have little relationship to the <quote>law</quote> with which judges
9256 comfort themselves.
9257 </para>
9258 <para>
9259 For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful
9260 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9261 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9262 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9263 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak&mdash;in that
9264 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9265 <quote>copyright</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9266 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9267 culture that is free.
9268 </para>
9269 <para>
9270 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9271 </para>
9272 <blockquote>
9273 <para>
9274 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9275 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9276 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9277 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made &hellip; you're not
9278 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9279 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9280 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, <quote>This has been
9281 cleared.</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9282 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9283 </para>
9284 </blockquote>
9285 </section>
9286 <section id="innovators">
9287 <title>Constraining Innovators</title>
9288 <para>
9289 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9290 story&mdash;creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9291 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9292 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9293 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9294 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9295 </para>
9296 <para>
9297 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9298 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9299 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9300 one at that, 188 pages into a book like this), then you can see this
9301 other aspect by substituting <quote>free market</quote> every place I've spoken of
9302 <quote>free culture.</quote> The point is the same, even if the interests
9303 affecting culture are more fundamental.
9304 </para>
9305 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9306 <para>
9307 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9308 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9309 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary&mdash;at
9310 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9311 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9312 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9313 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9314 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9315 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9316 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9317 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9318 </para>
9319 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9320 <para>
9321 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9322 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9323 strategy that I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9324 labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9325 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9326 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9327 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9328 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9329 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9330 lesson. That lesson&mdash;what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9331 <quote>nuclear pall</quote> that has fallen over the Valley&mdash;has been learned.
9332 </para>
9333 <para>
9334 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9335 I told in <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9336 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9337 </para>
9338 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael</primary></indexterm>
9339 <para>
9340 In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9341 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9342 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9343 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9344 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9345 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9346 </para>
9347 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9348 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>preference data on</secondary></indexterm>
9349 <para>
9350 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9351 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9352 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9353 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9354 Raitt. And so on.
9355 </para>
9356 <para>
9357 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9358 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9359 preference data. In January 2000, the company launched a service
9360 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9361 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9362 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9363 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9364 wherever you were&mdash;at work or at home&mdash;you could get access
9365 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9366 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9367 </para>
9368 <para>
9369 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9370 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9371
9372 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9373 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9374 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9375 the kind of content the users liked.
9376 </para>
9377 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'/>
9378 <para>
9379 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000
9380 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9381 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9382 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9383 therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9384 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9385 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9386 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was 50,000
9387 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers something
9388 they had already bought.
9389 </para>
9390 <indexterm id="idxvivendiuniversal" class='startofrange'><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9391 <para>
9392 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9393 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9394 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9395 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9396 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9397 MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9398 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $54 million. Vivendi
9399 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9400 </para>
9401 <para>
9402 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9403 </para>
9404 <para>
9405 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9406 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9407 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9408 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9409 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9410 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9411 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9412 demanded.
9413 </para>
9414 <para>
9415 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9416 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9417 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9418 clients in this
9419 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9420 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9421 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9422 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9423 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9424 </para>
9425 <indexterm startref="idxvivendiuniversal" class='endofrange'/>
9426 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John</primary></indexterm>
9427 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9428 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad</primary></indexterm>
9429 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
9430 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
9431 <para>
9432 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003,
9433 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9434 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9435 its development, its cofounder ( John Hummer), and general partner
9436 (Hank Barry).<footnote><para>
9437 <!-- f4. -->
9438 See Joseph Menn, <quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9439 Times</citetitle>, 23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9440 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, <quote>The Music
9441 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,</quote> Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available
9442 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #42</ulink>.
9443 See also Jon Healey, <quote>Online Music Services Besieged,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9444 Times</citetitle>, 28 May 2001.
9445 </para></footnote>
9446 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
9447 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
9448 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
9449 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
9450 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
9451 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
9452 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
9453 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
9454 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
9455 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
9456 <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
9457 discussion with BMW:
9458 </para>
9459 <blockquote>
9460 <indexterm><primary>BMW</primary></indexterm>
9461 <indexterm><primary>cars, MP3 sound system in</primary></indexterm>
9462 <para>
9463 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
9464 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
9465 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
9466 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
9467 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
9468 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
9469 United States with bona fide MP3 players. &hellip; <footnote>
9470 <para>
9471 <!-- f5. -->
9472 Rafe Needleman, <quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,</quote> <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, 16 June
9473 2003, available at
9474 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #43</ulink>. I am grateful
9475 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
9476 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
9477 </para></footnote>
9478 </para>
9479 </blockquote>
9480 <para>
9481 This is the world of the mafia&mdash;filled with <quote>your money or your
9482 life</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
9483 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
9484 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
9485 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
9486 constantly threatened by litigation.
9487 </para>
9488 <para>
9489
9490 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
9491 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
9492 enterprises. The point is the definition of <quote>illegal.</quote> The law is a
9493 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
9494 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
9495 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
9496 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
9497 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
9498 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
9499 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
9500 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
9501 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
9502 much less creativity.
9503 </para>
9504 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9505 <para>
9506 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
9507 use. Whatever the <quote>real</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
9508 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
9509 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
9510 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
9511 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
9512 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
9513 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
9514 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
9515 produce an overregulatedregulated market.
9516 </para>
9517 <para>
9518 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
9519 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
9520 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
9521 culture&mdash;a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
9522 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
9523 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
9524 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
9525 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
9526 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
9527 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
9528 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
9529 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
9530 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
9531 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
9532 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
9533 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
9534 result.
9535 </para>
9536 <para>
9537 <emphasis role='strong'>The uncertainty</emphasis> of the law is one
9538 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
9539 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
9540 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
9541 better protects their content.
9542 </para>
9543 <para>
9544 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
9545 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
9546 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
9547 this feature is a <quote>bug.</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
9548 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
9549 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
9550 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables <quote>piracy,</quote> then,
9551 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
9552 </para>
9553 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
9554 <para>
9555 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
9556 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
9557 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
9558 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.<footnote><para>
9559 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> GartnerG2 and
9560 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
9561 (2003), 33&ndash;35, available at
9562 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
9563 </para></footnote>
9564 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
9565 <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
9566 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
9567 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
9568 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
9569 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
9570 copyright violators and disable their machines.<footnote><para>
9571 <!-- f7. -->
9572 GartnerG2, 26&ndash;27.
9573 </para></footnote>
9574 </para>
9575 <para>
9576 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
9577 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
9578 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
9579 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
9580 and costs on
9581 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
9582 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
9583 those requirements.
9584 </para>
9585 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
9586 <para>
9587 In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
9588 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
9589 would impose.<footnote><para>
9590 <!-- f8. -->
9591 See David McGuire, <quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,</quote> Newsbytes,
9592 February 2002 (Entertainment).
9593 </para></footnote>
9594 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
9595 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
9596 harm than good.
9597 </para>
9598 <para>
9599 <emphasis role='strong'>There is one</emphasis> more obvious way in
9600 which this war has harmed innovation&mdash;again, a story that will be
9601 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
9602 </para>
9603 <para>
9604 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
9605 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
9606 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
9607 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
9608 </para>
9609 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
9610 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
9611 <para>
9612 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9613 linkend="property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
9614 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
9615 Jessica Litman in her book <citetitle>Digital
9616 Copyright</citetitle>,<footnote><para>
9617 <!-- f9. -->
9618 Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (Amherst,
9619 N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 2001).
9620 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
9621 </para></footnote>
9622 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter 10 details,
9623 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
9624 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
9625 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
9626 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
9627 </para>
9628 <para>
9629 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
9630 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
9631 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
9632 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
9633 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
9634 </para>
9635 <para>
9636 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.<footnote><para>
9637 <!-- f10. -->
9638 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.</primary></indexterm>
9639 The only circuit court exception is found in <citetitle>Recording Industry
9640 Association of America (RIAA)</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems</citetitle>, 180 F. 3d
9641 1072 (9th Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
9642 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
9643 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
9644 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
9645 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
9646 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
9647 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Grokster, Ltd</citetitle>., 259 F. Supp. 2d
9648 1029 (C.D. Cal., 2003), where the court found the link between the
9649 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
9650 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
9651 liability.
9652 </para></footnote>
9653 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
9654 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
9655 here.<footnote><para>
9656 <!-- f11. -->
9657 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy</primary></indexterm>
9658 For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
9659 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize
9660 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
9661 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
9662 August 2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
9663 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
9664 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that
9665 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
9666 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
9667 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
9668 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, <quote>Copyright and
9669 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003, 33&ndash;34,
9670 available at
9671 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
9672 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
9673 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz</primary></indexterm>
9674 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
9675 </para></footnote>
9676 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
9677 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
9678 </para>
9679 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
9680 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
9681 <para>
9682
9683 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
9684 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9685 linkend="pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
9686 artist doesn't get paid for that <quote>radio performance</quote> unless he or she
9687 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
9688 version of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote>&mdash;to memorialize her famous
9689 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden&mdash;
9690 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
9691 copyright owners of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> would get some money, whereas
9692 Marilyn Monroe would not.
9693 </para>
9694 <para>
9695 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
9696 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
9697 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
9698 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
9699 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
9700 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
9701 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
9702 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
9703 recording artists.
9704 </para>
9705 <para>
9706 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
9707 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
9708 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
9709 spectrum. Thus, I can <quote>tune in</quote> to an Internet radio station in
9710 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
9711 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
9712 metropolitan area.
9713 </para>
9714 <para>
9715 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
9716 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
9717 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
9718 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
9719 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
9720 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
9721 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
9722 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
9723 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
9724 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
9725 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
9726 </para>
9727 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9728 <para>
9729
9730 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
9731 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
9732 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
9733 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
9734 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
9735 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
9736 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
9737 FM radio,
9738 </para>
9739 <blockquote>
9740 <para>
9741 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
9742 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
9743 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
9744 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
9745 than by technical restrictions. &hellip; Armstrong likened the situation
9746 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
9747 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
9748 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
9749 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
9750 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
9751 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
9752 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
9753 shackles.<footnote><para>
9754 <!-- f12. -->
9755 Lessing, 239.
9756 </para></footnote>
9757 </para>
9758 </blockquote>
9759 <para>
9760 This potential for FM radio was never realized&mdash;not
9761 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
9762 underestimated the power of <quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
9763 legislation</quote><footnote><para>
9764 <!-- f13. -->
9765 Ibid., 229.
9766 </para></footnote>
9767 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
9768 </para>
9769 <para>
9770 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
9771 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
9772 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
9773 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
9774 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
9775 radio?
9776 </para>
9777 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments2' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
9778 <para>
9779 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
9780 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
9781
9782 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
9783 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
9784 of Internet radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
9785 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
9786 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
9787 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
9788 of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> on the air, <emphasis>Internet radio
9789 does</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
9790 radio&mdash;the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
9791 burdens terrestrial radio.
9792 </para>
9793 <para>
9794 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
9795 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
9796 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
9797 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
9798 over $1 million a year.<footnote>
9799 <para>
9800 <!-- f14. -->
9801 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
9802 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
9803 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
9804 iLaw (Stanford), 3 July 2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
9805 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
9806 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
9807 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP
9808 DTRA 1 and 2, available at
9809 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #45</ulink>.
9810 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
9811 C. Picker, <quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
9812 Distribution,</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin</citetitle> (Summer/Fall 2002): 461: <quote>This was
9813 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
9814 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
9815 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
9816 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
9817 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.</quote>
9818 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)</primary></indexterm>
9819 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
9820 </para></footnote>
9821 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
9822 equivalent fee.
9823 </para>
9824 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments2' class='endofrange'/>
9825 <para>
9826 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
9827 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
9828 station) would have to collect the following data from <emphasis>every
9829 listening transaction</emphasis>:
9830 </para>
9831 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
9832 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
9833 <listitem><para>
9834 name of the service;
9835 </para></listitem>
9836 <listitem><para>
9837 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
9838 </para></listitem>
9839 <listitem><para>
9840 type of program (archived/looped/live);
9841 </para></listitem>
9842 <listitem><para>
9843 date of transmission;
9844 </para></listitem>
9845 <listitem><para>
9846 time of transmission;
9847 </para></listitem>
9848 <listitem><para>
9849 time zone of origination of transmission;
9850 </para></listitem>
9851 <listitem><para>
9852 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
9853 </para></listitem>
9854 <listitem><para>
9855 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
9856 </para></listitem>
9857 <listitem><para>
9858 sound recording title;
9859 </para></listitem>
9860 <listitem><para>
9861 ISRC code of the recording;
9862 </para></listitem>
9863 <listitem><para>
9864 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
9865 </para></listitem>
9866 <listitem><para>
9867 featured recording artist;
9868 </para></listitem>
9869 <listitem><para>
9870 retail album title;
9871 </para></listitem>
9872 <listitem><para>
9873 recording label;
9874 </para></listitem>
9875 <listitem><para>
9876 UPC code of the retail album;
9877 </para></listitem>
9878 <listitem><para>
9879 catalog number;
9880 </para></listitem>
9881 <listitem><para>
9882 copyright owner information;
9883 </para></listitem>
9884 <listitem><para>
9885 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
9886 </para></listitem>
9887 <listitem><para>
9888 name of the service or entity;
9889 </para></listitem>
9890 <listitem><para>
9891 channel or program;
9892 </para></listitem>
9893 <listitem><para>
9894 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
9895 </para></listitem>
9896 <listitem><para>
9897 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
9898 </para></listitem>
9899 <listitem><para>
9900 time zone where the signal was received (user);
9901 </para></listitem>
9902 <listitem><para>
9903 unique user identifier;
9904 </para></listitem>
9905 <listitem><para>
9906 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
9907 </para></listitem>
9908 </orderedlist>
9909
9910 <para>
9911 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
9912 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
9913 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
9914 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
9915 Internet radio has to pay a <emphasis>type of copyright fee</emphasis>
9916 that terrestrial radio does not.
9917 </para>
9918 <para>
9919 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
9920 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
9921 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
9922 </para>
9923 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
9924 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
9925 <para>
9926 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
9927 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
9928 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
9929 </para>
9930 <blockquote>
9931 <para>
9932 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
9933 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
9934 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
9935 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
9936 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
9937 webcasters asked the RIAA, &hellip; <quote>How do you come up with a
9938
9939 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
9940 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
9941 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
9942 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
9943 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
9944 business. &hellip;</quote>
9945 </para>
9946 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
9947 <para>
9948 And the RIAA experts said, <quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
9949 industry with thousands of webcasters, <emphasis>we think it should be
9950 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
9951 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market</emphasis>.</quote> (Emphasis
9952 added.)
9953 </para>
9954 </blockquote>
9955 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'/>
9956 <para>
9957 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
9958 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
9959 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
9960 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
9961 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
9962 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
9963 effective to prevent it.
9964 </para>
9965 </section>
9966 <section id="corruptingcitizens">
9967 <title>Corrupting Citizens</title>
9968 <para>
9969 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
9970 dinosaurs
9971 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
9972 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
9973 </para>
9974 <para>
9975 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
9976 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
9977 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
9978 </para>
9979 <para>
9980 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
9981 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
9982 large number of citizens. According to <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, 43 million
9983 Americans downloaded music in May 2002.<footnote><para>
9984 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, <quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,</quote> Pew
9985 Internet and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at
9986 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #46</ulink>.
9987 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that 37 million
9988 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early 2001.
9989 </para></footnote>
9990 According to the RIAA,
9991 the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
9992 set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As the
9993
9994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
9995 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
9996 the world, but against students building search engines, and
9997 increasingly
9998 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
9999 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
10000 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
10001 extreme
10002 response by the other.
10003 </para>
10004 <para>
10005 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
10006 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
10007 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
10008 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
10009 ($15,000,000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
10010 paying all the money in the world in damages ($250,000 in legal fees)
10011 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
10012 ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
10013 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September 2003, the RIAA
10014 sued 261 individuals&mdash;including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
10015 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
10016 was.<footnote><para>
10017 <!-- f16. -->
10018 Alex Pham, <quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,</quote> <citetitle>Los
10019 Angeles Times</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, Business.
10020 </para></footnote>
10021 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
10022 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
10023 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000
10024 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
10025 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
10026 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
10027 they oppose.
10028 </para>
10029 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition</primary></indexterm>
10030 <para>
10031 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
10032 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
10033 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
10034 consumption of alcohol was 1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
10035 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just 30 percent
10036 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10037 consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition
10038 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10039 number were criminals.<footnote><para>
10040 <!-- f17. -->
10041 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, <quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10042 Prohibition,</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review</citetitle> 81, no. 2 (1991): 242.
10043 </para></footnote>
10044 We have
10045 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10046 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10047 narcotics that 7 percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.<footnote><para>
10048 <!-- f18. -->
10049 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10050 Reform Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of
10051 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10052 </para></footnote>
10053 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of
10054 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10055 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10056 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10057 cheat.<footnote><para>
10058 <!-- f19. -->
10059 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, <quote>Tax
10060 Compliance,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature</citetitle> 36 (1998): 818 (survey of
10061 compliance literature).
10062 </para></footnote>
10063 We pride ourselves on our <quote>free society,</quote> but an endless array of
10064 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10065 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10066 </para>
10067 <indexterm><primary>law schools</primary></indexterm>
10068 <para>
10069 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10070 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10071 students about the importance of <quote>ethics.</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10072 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10073 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10074 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10075 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10076 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10077 teach them how to behave ethically&mdash;how to say no to bribes, or
10078 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10079 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10080 Americans&mdash;more significantly in some parts of America than in
10081 others, but still, everywhere in America today&mdash;can't live their
10082 lives both normally and legally, since <quote>normally</quote> entails a certain
10083 degree of illegality.
10084 </para>
10085 <para>
10086 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10087 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10088 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10089 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10090 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10091 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10092 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10093 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10094 to consider the alternative.
10095 </para>
10096 <para>
10097
10098 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10099 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10100 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10101 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10102 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10103 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10104 </para>
10105 <para>
10106 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10107 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10108 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10109 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10110 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10111 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10112 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10113 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10114 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10115 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10116 introduced this different idea of <quote>sharing.</quote> We need to be able to
10117 call these twenty million Americans <quote>citizens,</quote> not <quote>felons.</quote>
10118 </para>
10119 <para>
10120 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10121 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10122 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10123 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10124 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10125 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10126 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10127 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10128 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10129 a nation of felons?
10130 </para>
10131 <para>
10132 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10133 </para>
10134 <para>
10135 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10136 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10137 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10138 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10139 used
10140
10141 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10142 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That <quote>use</quote> of the
10143 recordings is free.
10144 </para>
10145 <para>
10146 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10147 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10148 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am <quote>free</quote> to copy,
10149 or <quote>rip,</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10150 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that <quote>freedom</quote> was a
10151 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the <quote>Rip, Mix, Burn</quote>
10152 capacities of digital technologies.
10153 </para>
10154 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda</primary></indexterm>
10155 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>mix technology and</secondary></indexterm>
10156 <para>
10157 This <quote>use</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10158 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10159 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10160 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10161 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10162 Others&mdash;the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10163 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10164 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10165 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10166 </para>
10167 <para>
10168 This use is enabled by unprotected media&mdash;either CDs or records.
10169 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10170 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10171 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10172 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10173 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10174 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10175 on people's machines.
10176 </para>
10177 <para>
10178 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10179 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10180 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10181 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10182 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10183 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10184
10185 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10186 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10187 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10188 plastic or were part of a massively complex <quote>digital rights
10189 management</quote> system.
10190 </para>
10191 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'/>
10192 <para>
10193 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10194 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10195 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10196 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10197 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10198 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10199 freedom to move content easily?
10200 </para>
10201 <para>
10202 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10203 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10204 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10205 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10206 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10207 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10208 alternative&mdash;namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10209 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10210 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10211 </para>
10212 <para>
10213 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10214 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10215 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10216 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10217 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10218 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10219 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10220 </para>
10221 <para>
10222 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10223 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10224 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10225 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10226 </para>
10227 <para>
10228 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10229 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10230
10231 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10232
10233 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10234 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10235 </para>
10236 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
10237 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
10238 <para>
10239 <emphasis role='strong'>There's one more</emphasis> aspect to this
10240 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10241 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10242 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10243 <quote>collateral damage</quote> that <quote>arises whenever you turn
10244 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.</quote> This
10245 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10246 </para>
10247 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10248 <para>
10249 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,</quote> von Lohmann
10250 explains,
10251 </para>
10252 <blockquote>
10253 <para>
10254 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10255 evaporate to one degree or another. &hellip; If you're a copyright
10256 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10257 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10258 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10259 access? &hellip; Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, <quote>Oh, well,
10260 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.</quote> Well, what this campaign
10261 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10262 American Internet-using population into <quote>lawbreakers.</quote>
10263 </para>
10264 </blockquote>
10265 <para>
10266 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10267 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10268 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10269 </para>
10270 <para>
10271 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA
10272 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10273 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10274 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10275 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10276 an Internet user is revealed.
10277 </para>
10278 <para>
10279 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10280 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10281 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10282 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10283 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10284 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10285 the family could be liable for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10286 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10287 Jesse Jordan.<footnote><para>
10288 <!-- f20. -->
10289 See Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10290 Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,</quote>
10291 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, <quote>Worried Parents
10292 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10293 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10294 Being Sued,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson
10295 Graham, <quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 15 September
10296 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, <quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10297 Fan, Either,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 25 September 2003, C1; Margo Varadi, <quote>Is
10298 Brianna a Criminal?</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star</citetitle>, 18 September 2003, P7.
10299 </para></footnote>
10300
10301 </para>
10302 <para>
10303 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10304 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10305 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.<footnote><para>
10306 <!-- f21. -->
10307 See <quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10308 Some Methods Used,</quote> CNN.com, available at
10309 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #47</ulink>.
10310 </para></footnote>
10311 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10312 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10313 one of those MP3s will have the same <quote>fingerprint.</quote>
10314 </para>
10315 <para>
10316 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10317 friend gives a CD to your daughter&mdash;a collection of songs just
10318 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10319 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10320 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10321 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10322 network is <quote>cooperating</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10323 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10324 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10325 as a <quote>criminal.</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10326 to deploy,<footnote><para>
10327 <!-- f22. -->
10328 See Jeff Adler, <quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,</quote>
10329 <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, <quote>Four
10330 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10331 Colleges,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10332 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10333 Monitor</citetitle>, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, <quote>Music
10334 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10335 Lawsuit Possible,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 16 July 2003, 1C; Beth Cox, <quote>RIAA
10336 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,</quote> <citetitle>Internet News</citetitle>, 30 January
10337 2003, available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10338 #48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Download Warning 101: Freshman
10339 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10340 Sharing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 11 August 2003, E11; <quote>Raid, Letters
10341 Are Weapons at Universities,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 26 September 2000, 3D.
10342 </para></footnote>
10343 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10344 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10345 </para>
10346 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'/>
10347 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10348 <para>
10349 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10350 a lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10351 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10352 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10353 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10354 this <quote>contraband</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10355 college students
10356
10357 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10358 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10359 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10360 Says von Lohmann,
10361 </para>
10362 <blockquote>
10363 <para>
10364 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10365 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10366 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10367 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10368 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10369 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10370 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10371 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10372 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10373 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10374 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10375 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10376 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10377 larger number of Americans than drug use. &hellip; If forty to sixty
10378 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10379 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10380 million of them.
10381 </para>
10382 </blockquote>
10383 <para>
10384 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered <quote>criminals</quote> under
10385 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective&mdash;
10386 securing rights to authors&mdash;without these millions being
10387 considered <quote>criminals,</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10388 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10389 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10390 </para>
10391
10392 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10393 </section>
10394 </chapter>
10395 </part>
10396 <part id="c-balances">
10397 <title>BALANCES</title>
10398 <partintro>
10399
10400 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10401 <para>
10402 <emphasis role='strong'>So here's</emphasis> the picture: You're
10403 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
10404 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
10405 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
10406 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10407 </para>
10408 <para>
10409 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10410 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10411 stop&mdash;or before she understands just why she should
10412 stop&mdash;the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10413 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10414 everything around.
10415 </para>
10416 <para>
10417 <emphasis role='strong'>A war</emphasis> about copyright rages all
10418 around&mdash;and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
10419 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
10420 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
10421 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
10422 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
10423 that if let alone would burn itself out.
10424 </para>
10425 <para>
10426 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
10427 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
10428 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
10429 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
10430 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
10431 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
10432 made that is happening all around.
10433 </para>
10434 <para>
10435 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
10436 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
10437 gasoline onto this fire.
10438 </para>
10439 <para>
10440 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
10441 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
10442 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
10443 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
10444 </para>
10445 <para>
10446 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
10447 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
10448 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
10449 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
10450 success will require.
10451 </para>
10452 </partintro>
10453
10454 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
10455 <chapter label="13" id="eldred">
10456 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred</title>
10457 <indexterm id="idxhawthornenathaniel" class='startofrange'><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel</primary></indexterm>
10458 <para>
10459 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
10460 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
10461 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
10462 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
10463 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
10464 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
10465 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
10466 </para>
10467 <para>
10468 It didn't work&mdash;at least for his daughters. They didn't find
10469 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
10470 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
10471 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
10472 them available for free.
10473 </para>
10474 <para>
10475 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
10476 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
10477 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
10478 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
10479 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
10480 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
10481 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
10482 many others, into a form more accessible&mdash;technically
10483 accessible&mdash;today.
10484 </para>
10485 <para>
10486 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
10487 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's <citetitle>Scarlet Letter</citetitle> had passed into the
10488 public domain in 1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
10489 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
10490 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
10491 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
10492 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
10493 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (<citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle>), sometimes not
10494 (<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame</citetitle>, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>). These are all
10495 commercial publications of public domain works.
10496 </para>
10497 <indexterm startref="idxhawthornenathaniel" class='endofrange'/>
10498 <para>
10499 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
10500 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
10501 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
10502 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
10503 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
10504 call the <quote>noncommercial publishing industry,</quote> which before the
10505 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
10506 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
10507 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
10508 generally.<footnote><para>
10509 <!-- f1. -->
10510 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
10511 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
10512 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers&mdash;people who
10513 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
10514 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
10515 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
10516 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
10517 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
10518 Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on
10519 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
10520 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
10521 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
10522 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
10523 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
10524 protect noncommercial pornographers.</para></footnote>
10525 </para>
10526 <para>
10527 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's
10528 collection of poems <citetitle>New Hampshire</citetitle> was slated to
10529 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
10530 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
10531 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10532 linkend="property-i"/>, in 1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
10533 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights&mdash;this time by
10534 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
10535 than 1923 to his collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
10536 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
10537 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
10538 more than 1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
10539 </para>
10540 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
10541 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
10542 <para>
10543
10544 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
10545 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
10546 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
10547 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
10548 <quote>copyrights should be forever.</quote><footnote><para>
10549 <!-- f2. -->
10550 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
10551 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
10552 The full text is: <quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
10553 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
10554 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
10555 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
10556 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
10557 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
10558 Congress,</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998).
10559 </para></footnote>
10560
10561 </para>
10562 <para>
10563 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
10564 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
10565 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
10566 second law passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
10567 of publishing would make Eldred a felon&mdash;whether or not anyone
10568 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
10569 to undertake.
10570 </para>
10571 <para>
10572 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
10573 constitutional
10574 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
10575 interpretation.
10576 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
10577 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
10578 importantly
10579 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
10580 </para>
10581 <blockquote>
10582 <para>
10583 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science &hellip;
10584 by securing for limited Times to Authors &hellip; exclusive Right to
10585 their &hellip; Writings. &hellip;
10586 </para>
10587 </blockquote>
10588 <para>
10589 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
10590 clause of Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
10591 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
10592 something&mdash;for example, to regulate <quote>commerce among the several
10593 states</quote> or <quote>declare War.</quote> But here, the <quote>something</quote> is something quite
10594 specific&mdash;to <quote>promote &hellip; Progress</quote>&mdash;through means that
10595 are also specific&mdash; by <quote>securing</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights</quote> (i.e.,
10596 copyrights) <quote>for limited Times.</quote>
10597 </para>
10598 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
10599 <para>
10600 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
10601 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
10602 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
10603 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be <quote>limited</quote> will have
10604 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
10605 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
10606 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
10607 what the Constitution plainly forbids&mdash;perpetual terms <quote>on the
10608 installment plan,</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
10609 </para>
10610 <para>
10611 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
10612 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
10613 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
10614 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
10615 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
10616 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
10617 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
10618 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
10619 this gravy train going.
10620 </para>
10621 <para>
10622 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
10623 government. <quote>Corruption</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
10624 bribed. Rather, <quote>corruption</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
10625 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
10626 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
10627 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
10628 do&mdash;and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
10629 </para>
10630 <para>
10631 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
10632 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
10633 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
10634 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry
10635 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
10636 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
10637 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
10638 published by anyone for free.
10639 </para>
10640 <para>
10641 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from
10642 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
10643 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
10644 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
10645 report:
10646 </para>
10647 <para>
10648 <quote>Next year,</quote> the adviser announces, <quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
10649
10650 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
10651 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
10652 receiving the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of
10653 those works.</quote>
10654 </para>
10655 <para>
10656 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,</quote> she continues, <quote>that
10657 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
10658 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
10659 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.</quote>
10660 </para>
10661 <para>
10662 <quote>Hope?</quote> a fellow board member says. <quote>Can't we be doing something
10663 about it?</quote>
10664 </para>
10665 <para>
10666 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>We could contribute
10667 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
10668 they support the bill.</quote>
10669 </para>
10670 <para>
10671 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
10672 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. <quote>How much
10673 would we get if this extension were passed?</quote> you ask the adviser. <quote>How
10674 much is it worth?</quote>
10675 </para>
10676 <para>
10677 <quote>Well,</quote> the adviser says, <quote>if you're confident that you will continue
10678 to get at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
10679 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent),
10680 then this law would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate.</quote>
10681 </para>
10682 <para>
10683 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
10684 correct conclusion:
10685 </para>
10686 <para>
10687 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
10688 $1,000,000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
10689 contributions
10690 would assure that the bill was passed?</quote>
10691 </para>
10692 <para>
10693 <quote>Absolutely,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>It is worth it to you to
10694 contribute
10695 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
10696 copyrights. Which for us means over $1,000,000.</quote>
10697 </para>
10698 <para>
10699 You quickly get the point&mdash;you as the member of the board and, I
10700 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
10701 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
10702 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
10703 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
10704 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
10705 copyrights
10706 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
10707 the copyright term extended.
10708 </para>
10709 <para>
10710 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
10711 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
10712 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
10713 </para>
10714 <para>
10715 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
10716 Copyright
10717 Term Extension Act, this <quote>theory</quote> about incentives was proved
10718 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
10719 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
10720 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
10721 contributions.<footnote><para>
10722 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, <quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
10723 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years,</quote>
10724 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 17 October 1998, 22.
10725 </para></footnote>
10726 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
10727 $1.5 million lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more
10728 than $200,000 in campaign contributions.<footnote><para>
10729 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, <quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
10730 Age,</quote> available at
10731 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #49</ulink>.
10732 </para></footnote>
10733 Disney is estimated to have
10734 contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in the
10735 cycle.<footnote><para>
10736 <!-- f5. -->
10737 Alan K. Ota, <quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,</quote>
10738 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week</citetitle>, 8 August 1990, available at
10739 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #50</ulink>.
10740 </para></footnote>
10741
10742 </para>
10743 <para>
10744 <emphasis role='strong'>Constitutional law</emphasis> is not oblivious
10745 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
10746 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
10747 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
10748 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
10749 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
10750 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
10751 constitutional requirement that terms be <quote>limited.</quote> If
10752 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
10753 again.
10754 </para>
10755 <para>
10756 It was also my judgment that <emphasis>this</emphasis> Supreme Court
10757 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
10758 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
10759 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
10760 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
10761 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
10762 Supreme Court's
10763
10764 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
10765 decision in 1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
10766 guns near schools.
10767 </para>
10768 <para>
10769 Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
10770 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
10771 power to regulate only <quote>commerce among the several states</quote> (aka
10772 <quote>interstate
10773 commerce</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
10774 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
10775 interstate
10776 commerce.
10777 </para>
10778 <para>
10779 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
10780 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
10781 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
10782 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
10783 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
10784 </para>
10785 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
10786 <para>
10787 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
10788 that in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The government had
10789 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
10790 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
10791 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
10792 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
10793 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
10794 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
10795 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
10796 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
10797 position to second-guess Congress.
10798 </para>
10799 <para>
10800 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,</quote>
10801 the Chief Justice wrote.<footnote><para>
10802 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995).
10803 </para></footnote>
10804 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
10805 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
10806 Congress's power. The decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
10807 later in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>.<footnote><para>
10808 <!-- f7. -->
10809 <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>, 529 U.S. 598 (2000).
10810 </para></footnote>
10811 </para>
10812 <para>
10813 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
10814 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.<footnote><para>
10815 <!-- f8. -->
10816 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
10817 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
10818 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
10819 by the government would allow the government unending power to
10820 regulate commerce&mdash;the limitation to interstate commerce
10821 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
10822 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
10823 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights&mdash;the
10824 limitation to <quote>limited times</quote> notwithstanding.
10825 </para></footnote>
10826 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
10827 yield the conclusion that Congress
10828 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
10829 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
10830 term, then there would be no <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power over
10831 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
10832 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
10833 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
10834 term of existing copyrights.
10835 </para>
10836 <para>
10837 <emphasis>If</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
10838 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> stood for
10839 politics&mdash;a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
10840 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
10841 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
10842 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
10843 demonstrating the <quote>fidelity</quote> in such an interpretation of the
10844 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
10845 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
10846 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
10847 were going to be petty politicians.
10848 </para>
10849 <para>
10850 <emphasis role='strong'>Now let's pause</emphasis> for a moment to
10851 make sure we understand what the argument in
10852 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
10853 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
10854 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
10855 piracy&mdash;piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
10856 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
10857 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
10858 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
10859 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
10860 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
10861 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
10862 power&mdash;expressed through the power of lobbyists' money&mdash;to
10863 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
10864 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
10865 piracy that affects us all.
10866 </para>
10867 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association</primary></indexterm>
10868 <para>
10869 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
10870
10871 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
10872 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
10873 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than <quote>legal piracy.</quote><footnote><para>
10874 <!-- f9. -->
10875 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
10876 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available
10877 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #51</ulink>.
10878 </para></footnote>
10879 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
10880 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
10881 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
10882 charter.
10883 </para>
10884 <para>
10885 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
10886 copyright
10887 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
10888 influence
10889 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
10890 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
10891 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
10892 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
10893 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
10894 bought to extend them again.
10895 </para>
10896 <para>
10897 <emphasis role='strong'>It is valuable</emphasis> copyrights that are
10898 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
10899 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.</quote> These works are too valuable for
10900 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
10901 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
10902 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
10903 the 1920s and 1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
10904 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
10905 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
10906 and no longer available as a result.
10907 </para>
10908 <para>
10909 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to
10910 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
10911 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
10912 copyright holders for that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
10913 But the law and its effect were not limited to that 2 percent. The law
10914 extended the terms of copyright generally.<footnote><para>
10915 <!-- f10. --> The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
10916 Congressional
10917 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
10918 of Petitioners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 7, available at
10919 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #52</ulink>.
10920 </para></footnote>
10921
10922 </para>
10923 <para>
10924 Think practically about the consequence of this
10925 extension&mdash;practically,
10926 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
10927
10928 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
10929 work. In 1930, 10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those
10930 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
10931 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
10932 remaining
10933 9,873. What would you have to do?
10934 </para>
10935 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
10936 <para>
10937 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were
10938 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
10939 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
10940 titles and authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration
10941 and renewal records for works published in 1930. That will produce a
10942 list of books still under copyright.
10943 </para>
10944 <para>
10945 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
10946 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
10947 </para>
10948 <para>
10949 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
10950 owners
10951 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
10952 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
10953 being at least a list?
10954 </para>
10955 <para>
10956 But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in
10957 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
10958 practically
10959 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
10960 thousands
10961 of such records&mdash;especially since the person who registered is
10962 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930!
10963 </para>
10964 <para>
10965 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,</quote> the
10966 apologists for the system respond. <quote>Why should there be a list of
10967 copyright owners?</quote>
10968 </para>
10969 <para>
10970 Well, actually, if you think about it, there <emphasis>are</emphasis>
10971 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
10972 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
10973 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
10974 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
10975 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
10976 what tangible property.
10977 </para>
10978 <para>
10979 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
10980 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
10981 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
10982
10983 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
10984 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
10985 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
10986 happen
10987 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
10988 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
10989 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
10990 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
10991 know quite well who owns what property.
10992 </para>
10993 <para>
10994 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
10995 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
10996 already
10997 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
10998 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
10999 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
11000 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
11001 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
11002 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
11003 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
11004 </para>
11005 <para>
11006 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
11007 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
11008 consequence
11009 for other creative works is much more dire.
11010 </para>
11011 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'><primary>Agee, Michael</primary></indexterm>
11012 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
11013 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films</primary></indexterm>
11014 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The</primary></indexterm>
11015 <para>
11016 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
11017 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
11018 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
11019 made between 1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, <citetitle>The Lucky Dog</citetitle>, is
11020 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923
11021 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
11022 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
11023 money. According to one estimate, <quote>Roach has sold about 60,000
11024 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's silent
11025 films.</quote><footnote><para>
11026 <!-- f11. -->
11027 See David G. Savage, <quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,</quote>
11028 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, <quote>Classic Movies,
11029 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
11030 Down Copyright Extension,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 9 October 2002.
11031 </para></footnote>
11032 </para>
11033 <para>
11034 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
11035 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
11036 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11037 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11038 </para>
11039 <para>
11040 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11041
11042 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11043 any continuing commercial value. The rest&mdash;to the extent it
11044 survives at all&mdash;sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11045 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11046 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11047 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11048 work available for distribution.
11049 </para>
11050 <para>
11051 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11052 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11053 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11054 it cost more than $10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11055 film in 1993, it can now cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of
11056 mm film.<footnote><para>
11057 <!-- f12. -->
11058 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11059 Supporting the Petitoners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11060 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01- 618), 12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11061 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11062 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, available at
11063 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #53</ulink>.
11064 </para></footnote>
11065
11066 </para>
11067 <para>
11068 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11069 important.
11070 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11071 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11072 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11073 locate the copyright owner.
11074 </para>
11075 <para>
11076 Or more accurately, <emphasis>owners</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11077 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11078 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11079 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11080 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11081 to these films is exceptionally high.
11082 </para>
11083 <para>
11084 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11085 copyright owner when she shows up?</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11086 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11087 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11088 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11089 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11090 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11091 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11092 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11093 </para>
11094 <para>
11095 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11096
11097 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11098 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11099 benefit
11100 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11101 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11102 the copyright expires.
11103 </para>
11104 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'/>
11105 <para>
11106 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11107 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11108 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11109 canisters
11110 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11111 than dust.
11112 </para>
11113 <para>
11114 <emphasis role='strong'>Of all the</emphasis> creative work produced
11115 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11116 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11117 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11118 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11119 the copyright acts as an <quote>engine of free expression.</quote>
11120 </para>
11121 <para>
11122 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11123 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11124 indicated,
11125 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11126 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11127 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11128 distributors,
11129 the commercial life ends.
11130 </para>
11131 <para>
11132 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11133 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes &amp; Noble, and
11134 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11135 between
11136 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11137 Friday
11138 night watching a 1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11139 of culture is important and valuable&mdash;for entertainment but also, and
11140 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11141 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11142 have, we need to have access to this history.
11143 </para>
11144 <para>
11145 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11146
11147 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11148 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11149 this context do no good.
11150 </para>
11151 <para>
11152 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11153 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11154 <emphasis>copyright-related use</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11155 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11156 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11157 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11158 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11159 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11160 was independent of copyright law.
11161 </para>
11162 <para>
11163 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11164 a film&mdash;the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs&mdash;were
11165 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11166 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11167 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11168 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11169 market didn't have more to offer.
11170 </para>
11171 <para>
11172 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11173 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11174 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11175 would not have interfered with anything.
11176 </para>
11177 <para>
11178 But this situation has now changed.
11179 </para>
11180 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11181 <para>
11182 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11183 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11184 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11185 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11186 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11187 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11188 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11189 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11190 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11191 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11192 </para>
11193 <para>
11194 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11195 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11196 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11197 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11198 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11199 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11200 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11201 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11202 written for a radically different context.
11203 </para>
11204 <para>
11205 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11206 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11207 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11208 <emphasis>copyright</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11209 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11210 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11211 context, copyright is serving no purpose <emphasis>at all</emphasis>
11212 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11213 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11214 </para>
11215 <para>
11216 You may well ask, <quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11217 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11218 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11219 culture widely?</quote>
11220 </para>
11221 <para>
11222 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11223 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes &amp; Noble
11224 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11225 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11226 of a library is to serve what <quote>the market</quote> would demand. But if you
11227 think the role of a library is bigger than this&mdash;if you think its
11228 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11229 particular bit of that culture or not&mdash;then we can't count on the
11230 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11231 </para>
11232 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'/>
11233 <para>
11234 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11235 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11236 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11237 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11238
11239 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11240 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11241 culture, 94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11242 and 1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11243 commercial market, if access is a value, then 6 percent is a failure
11244 to provide that value.<footnote><para>
11245 <!-- f13. -->
11246 Jason Schultz, <quote>The Myth of the 1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,</quote> 20
11247 December 2002, available at
11248 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #54</ulink>.
11249 </para></footnote>
11250
11251 </para>
11252 <para>
11253 <emphasis role='strong'>In January 1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11254 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11255 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11256 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (1)
11257 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11258 <quote>limited Times</quote> requirement, and (2) that extending terms
11259 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11260 </para>
11261 <para>
11262 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11263 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11264 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11265 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11266 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11267 </para>
11268 <para>
11269 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11270 copyrights be for <quote>limited Times</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11271 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11272 <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11273 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11274 terms that are <quote>limited.</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11275 to interpret the term <quote>limited Times</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11276 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11277 power to extend existing terms.
11278 </para>
11279 <para>
11280 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11281 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11282 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11283 whole, where the court will sit <quote>en banc</quote> to hear the case.
11284 </para>
11285 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David</primary></indexterm>
11286 <para>
11287 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11288 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11289
11290 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11291 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11292 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11293 overstepped its bounds.
11294 </para>
11295 <para>
11296 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11297 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11298 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11299 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11300 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11301 </para>
11302 <para>
11303 But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11304 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11305 was set for October of 2002. The summer would be spent writing
11306 briefs and preparing for argument.
11307 </para>
11308 <para>
11309 <emphasis role='strong'>It is over</emphasis> a year later as I write
11310 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
11311 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
11312 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
11313 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
11314 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
11315 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
11316 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
11317 client, Eric Eldred.
11318 </para>
11319 <para>
11320 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11321 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11322 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11323 mistake lost it.
11324 </para>
11325 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11326 <para>
11327 <emphasis role='strong'>The mistake</emphasis> was made early, though
11328 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
11329 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
11330 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
11331 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
11332 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11333 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11334 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11335 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11336 </para>
11337 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11338 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan</primary></indexterm>
11339 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11340 <para>
11341 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11342 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11343 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11344 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11345 told me, if we could make the issue seem <quote>important</quote> to the Supreme
11346 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11347 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against <quote>the
11348 most powerful media companies in the world.</quote>
11349 </para>
11350 <para>
11351 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
11352 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
11353 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
11354 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
11355 <quote>right</quote> as in <quote>true,</quote> I thought, but it is <quote>wrong</quote> as in <quote>it just shouldn't be
11356 that way.</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
11357 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
11358 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
11359 interpretation
11360 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
11361 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
11362 unconstitutional,
11363 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
11364 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
11365 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
11366 Constitution,
11367 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
11368 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
11369 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
11370 </para>
11371 <para>
11372 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
11373 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
11374 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
11375 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
11376 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
11377 why it was unconstitutional.
11378 </para>
11379 <para>
11380 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
11381
11382 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
11383 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
11384 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
11385 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
11386 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
11387 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
11388 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
11389 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
11390 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
11391 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
11392 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
11393 <emphasis>law</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
11394 the widest range of credible critics&mdash;credible not because they
11395 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
11396 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
11397 </para>
11398 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11399 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis</primary></indexterm>
11400 <para>
11401 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
11402 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
11403 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
11404 Congress. In November 1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
11405 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
11406 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
11407 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
11408 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
11409 to get bogged down?</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
11410 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
11411 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
11412 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
11413 </para>
11414 <para>
11415 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
11416 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
11417 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
11418 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
11419 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
11420 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
11421 </para>
11422 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
11423 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
11424 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
11425 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11426 <para>
11427 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
11428 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
11429
11430 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
11431 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/ Linux
11432 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
11433 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
11434 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
11435 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
11436 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
11437 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
11438 </para>
11439 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries</primary></indexterm>
11440 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union</primary></indexterm>
11441 <para>
11442 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
11443 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
11444 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
11445 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
11446 </para>
11447 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
11448 <para>
11449 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
11450 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
11451 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
11452 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
11453 clear.
11454 </para>
11455 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George</primary></indexterm>
11456 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
11457 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James</primary></indexterm>
11458 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11459 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton</primary></indexterm>
11460 <para>
11461 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
11462 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
11463 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
11464 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
11465 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
11466 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
11467 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
11468 nothing more than <quote>rent-seeking</quote>&mdash;the fancy term economists use
11469 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
11470 </para>
11471 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11472 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan</primary></indexterm>
11473 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen</primary></indexterm>
11474 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11475 <para>
11476 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
11477 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
11478 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
11479 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
11480 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
11481 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
11482 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
11483 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
11484
11485 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
11486 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
11487 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
11488 </para>
11489 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11490 <para>
11491 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
11492 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
11493 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
11494 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
11495 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
11496 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
11497 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
11498 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
11499 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
11500 confidence in our argument.
11501 </para>
11502 <para>
11503 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
11504 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these <quote>friends</quote> included
11505 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
11506 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
11507 copyright holders.
11508 </para>
11509 <para>
11510 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
11511 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either&mdash;they
11512 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
11513 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
11514 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
11515 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
11516 wanted to control.
11517 </para>
11518 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George</primary></indexterm>
11519 <para>
11520 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
11521 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
11522 Dr. Seuss's work&mdash; better than allowing it to fall into the
11523 public domain&mdash;because if this creativity were in the public
11524 domain, then people could use it to <quote>glorify drugs or to create
11525 pornography.</quote><footnote><para>
11526 <!-- f14. -->
11527 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11528 U.S. (2003) (No. 01-618), 19.
11529 </para></footnote>
11530 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
11531 <quote>protection</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
11532 to license <citetitle>Porgy and Bess</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
11533 Americans in the cast.<footnote><para>
11534 <!-- f15. -->
11535 Dinitia Smith, <quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
11536 Mouse Joins the Fray,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 28 March 1998, B7.
11537 </para></footnote>
11538 That's
11539 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
11540 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
11541 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
11542 </para>
11543 <para>
11544 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
11545 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
11546 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
11547 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
11548 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, <quote>Give us twenty years
11549 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
11550 better with them than anyone else.</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
11551 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
11552 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
11553 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
11554 </para>
11555 <para>
11556 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
11557 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
11558 copyrights&mdash;extensions that would further concentrate the market;
11559 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
11560 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
11561 </para>
11562 <para>
11563 <emphasis role='strong'>Between February</emphasis> and October, there
11564 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
11565 I set the strategy.
11566 </para>
11567 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
11568 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
11569 <para>
11570 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
11571 called <quote>the Conservatives.</quote> The other we called <quote>the Rest.</quote> The
11572 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
11573 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
11574 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
11575 five who had supported the <citetitle>Lopez/Morrison</citetitle> line
11576 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
11577 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
11578 </para>
11579 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11580 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
11581 <para>
11582 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
11583 Congress's power. These four&mdash;Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
11584 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer&mdash;had repeatedly argued that
11585 the Constitution
11586 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
11587 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
11588 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
11589 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
11590 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
11591 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
11592 </para>
11593 <para>
11594 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
11595 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
11596 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
11597 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
11598 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
11599 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
11600 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
11601 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
11602 sense.
11603 </para>
11604 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11605 <para>
11606 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
11607 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
11608 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
11609 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
11610 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
11611 these retrospective extensions.
11612 </para>
11613 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'/>
11614 <para>
11615 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
11616 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
11617 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
11618 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
11619 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
11620 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
11621 </para>
11622 <para>
11623 This analysis of <quote>the Rest</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
11624 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
11625 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
11626 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
11627 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation&mdash;the
11628 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
11629 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
11630 powers have limits.
11631 </para>
11632 <para>
11633 This then was the core of our strategy&mdash;a strategy for which I am
11634 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
11635 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
11636 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
11637 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
11638 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
11639 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
11640 supposed to be <quote>limited.</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
11641 reconcile <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> with
11642 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
11643 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
11644 be limited.
11645 </para>
11646 <para>
11647 <emphasis role='strong'>The argument</emphasis> on the government's
11648 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
11649 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
11650 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
11651 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
11652 that practice is unconstitutional.
11653 </para>
11654 <para>
11655 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
11656 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in 1831
11657 and in 1909. And of course, in 1962, Congress began extending
11658 existing
11659 terms regularly&mdash;eleven times in forty years.
11660 </para>
11661 <para>
11662 But this <quote>consistency</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
11663 extended
11664 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
11665 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
11666 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
11667 existing
11668 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
11669 restraint
11670 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
11671 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
11672 hesitated
11673 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
11674 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
11675 </para>
11676 <para>
11677 <emphasis role='strong'>Oral argument</emphasis> was scheduled for the
11678 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
11679 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
11680 <quote>mooted</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
11681
11682 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
11683 help in the case. Such <quote>moots</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
11684 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
11685 </para>
11686 <para>
11687 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
11688 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
11689 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
11690 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
11691 Congress
11692 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
11693 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
11694 this central idea.
11695 </para>
11696 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11697 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11698 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11699 <para>
11700 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
11701 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
11702 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
11703 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
11704 </para>
11705 <para>
11706 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
11707 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
11708 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
11709 the harm&mdash;passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
11710 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.</quote>
11711 </para>
11712 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11713 <para>
11714 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
11715 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
11716 right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
11717 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
11718 does the right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it is right. As
11719 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
11720 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
11721 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
11722 </para>
11723 <para>
11724 <emphasis role='strong'>The night before</emphasis> the argument, a
11725 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
11726 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
11727 culture. Hundreds stood in line
11728
11729 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
11730 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
11731 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
11732 </para>
11733 <para>
11734 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
11735 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
11736 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
11737 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
11738 congressmen
11739 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
11740 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
11741 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
11742 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
11743 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
11744 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
11745 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
11746 family of the Justices.
11747 </para>
11748 <para>
11749 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
11750 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
11751 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
11752 those enumerated powers had any limit.
11753 </para>
11754 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
11755 <para>
11756 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
11757 The history was bothering her.
11758 </para>
11759 <blockquote>
11760 <para>
11761 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
11762 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
11763 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
11764 practice that began with the very first act.
11765 </para>
11766 </blockquote>
11767 <para>
11768 She was quite willing to concede <quote>that this flies directly in the face
11769 of what the framers had in mind.</quote> But my response again and again
11770 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
11771 </para>
11772 <blockquote>
11773 <para>
11774 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
11775 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
11776 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
11777 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
11778 is yes.
11779 </para>
11780 </blockquote>
11781 <para>
11782 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
11783 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
11784 Kennedy, who observed,
11785 </para>
11786 <blockquote>
11787 <para>
11788 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
11789 the '76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
11790 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
11791 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
11792 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
11793 </para>
11794 </blockquote>
11795 <para>
11796 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
11797 student,
11798 I answered,
11799 </para>
11800 <blockquote>
11801 <para>
11802 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
11803 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
11804 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
11805 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
11806 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
11807 </para>
11808 </blockquote>
11809 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11810 <para>
11811 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
11812 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
11813 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
11814 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
11815 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
11816 </para>
11817 <para>
11818 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
11819 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> ruling,
11820 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
11821 </para>
11822 <para>
11823 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
11824 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
11825
11826 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
11827 </para>
11828 <blockquote>
11829 <para>
11830 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
11831 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
11832 </para>
11833 <para>
11834 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
11835 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
11836 domain
11837 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
11838 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
11839 into the Copyright Clause.
11840 </para>
11841 </blockquote>
11842 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.</primary></indexterm>
11843 <para>
11844 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
11845 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
11846 asked Solicitor General Olson,
11847 </para>
11848 <blockquote>
11849 <para>
11850 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11851 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
11852 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
11853 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11854 time.
11855 </para>
11856 </blockquote>
11857 <para>
11858 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
11859 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
11860 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
11861 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
11862 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
11863 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
11864 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
11865 Patent Clause&mdash; indeed, the very first case striking a law of
11866 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
11867 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
11868 Court to my side.
11869 </para>
11870 <para>
11871 <emphasis role='strong'>As I left</emphasis> the court that day, I
11872 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
11873 hundred questions I wished I had
11874
11875 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
11876 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
11877 optimistic.
11878 </para>
11879 <para>
11880 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
11881 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
11882 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
11883 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
11884 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
11885 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
11886 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
11887 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
11888 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
11889 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
11890 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court&mdash;in particular,
11891 the Conservatives&mdash;would feel itself constrained by the rule of
11892 law that it had established elsewhere.
11893 </para>
11894 <para>
11895 <emphasis role='strong'>The morning</emphasis> of January 15, 2003, I
11896 was five minutes late to the office and missed the 7:00 A.M. call from
11897 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
11898 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
11899 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
11900 majority. There were two dissents.
11901 </para>
11902 <para>
11903 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
11904 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
11905 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
11906 </para>
11907 <para>
11908 My <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
11909 money in the world against <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. And here
11910 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
11911 reasoning.
11912 </para>
11913 <para>
11914 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
11915 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
11916 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
11917 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
11918 even appear in the Court's opinion.
11919 </para>
11920 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
11921 <para>
11922
11923 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
11924 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
11925 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
11926 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
11927 </para>
11928 <para>
11929 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable&mdash;for her, and for Justice
11930 Souter. Neither believes in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
11931 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
11932 they had worked so hard to defeat.
11933 </para>
11934 <para>
11935 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
11936 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
11937 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
11938 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
11939 reconcile the two simply <emphasis>by not addressing the
11940 argument</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
11941 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
11942 followed from the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
11943 be limited, but in this context it would not.
11944 </para>
11945 <para>
11946 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
11947 they would respect? By what right did they&mdash;the silent
11948 five&mdash;get to select the part of the Constitution they would
11949 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
11950 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
11951 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
11952 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
11953 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
11954 the system we have.
11955 </para>
11956 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11957 <para>
11958 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
11959 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
11960 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
11961 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
11962 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
11963 the Court discounted the parallel&mdash;without explaining how the
11964 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
11965 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
11966 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
11967 </para>
11968 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11969 <para>
11970 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
11971 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
11972 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
11973 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
11974 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8
11975 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
11976 that the actual number was 99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
11977 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
11978 <quote>limited,</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
11979 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
11980 </para>
11981 <para>
11982 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
11983 because neither believed in the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
11984 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
11985 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
11986 Sentelle. It was <citetitle>Hamlet</citetitle> without the Prince.
11987 </para>
11988 <para>
11989 <emphasis role='strong'>Defeat brings depression</emphasis>. They say
11990 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
11991 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
11992 sorts.
11993 </para>
11994 <indexterm><primary>originalism</primary></indexterm>
11995 <para>
11996 It was first anger with the five <quote>Conservatives.</quote> It would have been
11997 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> didn't
11998 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
11999 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
12000 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
12001 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
12002 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is <quote>originalism</quote>&mdash;to
12003 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
12004 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
12005 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> and many other <quote>originalist</quote> rulings. Where was their
12006 <quote>originalism</quote> now?
12007 </para>
12008 <para>
12009 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
12010 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
12011 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
12012 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
12013
12014 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
12015 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
12016 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
12017 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
12018 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
12019 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
12020 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
12021 own principles.
12022 </para>
12023 <para>
12024 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
12025 myself.
12026 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
12027 the law as it is.
12028 </para>
12029 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12030 <para>
12031 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
12032 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
12033 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
12034 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
12035 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
12036 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12037 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12038 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12039 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12040 </para>
12041 <para>
12042 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12043 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12044 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12045 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12046 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12047 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12048 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12049 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12050 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12051 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12052 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12053 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12054 effort to persuade; but I
12055 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12056 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12057 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12058 should decide the issue.
12059 </para>
12060 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12061 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12062 <para>
12063 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12064 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12065 Kathleen Sullivan?
12066 </para>
12067 <para>
12068 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12069 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12070 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12071 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12072 </para>
12073 <para>
12074 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12075 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12076 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12077 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12078 have persuaded.
12079 </para>
12080 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12081 <para>
12082 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12083 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12084 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12085 case was a mistake. <quote>The Court is not ready,</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12086 issue should not be raised until it is.
12087 </para>
12088 <para>
12089 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12090 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12091 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12092 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12093 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12094 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12095 this case&mdash;a decision I had made four years before&mdash;was wrong.
12096 </para>
12097 <para>
12098 <emphasis role='strong'>While the reaction</emphasis> to the Sonny
12099 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12100 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12101 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12102 that battle over ideas. Where
12103
12104 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12105 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12106 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12107 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12108 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12109 harmful law. <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12110 </para>
12111 <blockquote>
12112 <para>
12113 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12114 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12115 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12116 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12117 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12118 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12119 </para>
12120 </blockquote>
12121 <para>
12122 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12123 hilarious images&mdash;of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12124 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced on the next page
12125 (<xref linkend="fig-18"/>). The <quote>powerful and wealthy</quote> line is a bit
12126 unfair. But the punch in the face felt exactly like that.
12127 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12128 </para>
12129 <figure id="fig-18">
12130 <title>Tom the Dancing Bug cartoon</title>
12131 <graphic fileref="images/18.png"></graphic>
12132 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12133 </figure>
12134 <para>
12135 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12136 quote from <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>. That <quote>grand experiment</quote> we call the
12137 <quote>public domain</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think, <quote>Honey,
12138 I shrunk the Constitution.</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12139 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12140 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12141 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12142 </para>
12143 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12144 </chapter>
12145 <chapter label="14" id="eldred-ii">
12146 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II</title>
12147 <para>
12148 <emphasis role='strong'>The day</emphasis>
12149 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12150 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12151 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was denied&mdash;meaning the case was
12152 really finally over&mdash;fate would have it that I was giving a
12153 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12154 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12155 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12156 wrote an op-ed piece.
12157 </para>
12158 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12159 <para>
12160 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12161 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12162 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12163 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12164 Justice Kennedy: <quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12165 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12166 that.</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12167 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12168 </para>
12169 <para>
12170 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12171 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12172 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12173 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12174 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12175 the work passed into the public domain.
12176 </para>
12177 <para>
12178 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12179 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12180 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12181 </para>
12182 <para>
12183 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12184 is either the <quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act</quote> or the <quote>Copyright
12185 Term Deregulation Act.</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12186 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12187 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12188 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $1. But for
12189 everything else, let the content go.
12190 </para>
12191 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12192 <para>
12193 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12194 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12195 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12196 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12197 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12198 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12199 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12200 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12201 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12202 the stupid harm of the present system.
12203 </para>
12204 <para>
12205 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12206 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12207 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12208 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12209 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12210 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12211 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12212 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12213 where copyright owners could be identified.
12214 </para>
12215 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12216 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12217 <para>
12218 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12219 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
12220 linkend="property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12221 removed in 1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12222 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.<footnote><para>
12223 <!-- f1. -->
12224 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law</primary></indexterm>
12225 Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12226 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12227 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12228 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act,
12229 every text of the Convention has provided that <quote>the enjoyment and the
12230 exercise</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention <quote>shall not be subject
12231 to any formality.</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12232 embodied in Article 5(2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12233 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12234 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12235 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12236 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12237 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12238 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12239 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12240 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>International
12241 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12242 Press, 2001), 153&ndash;54. </para></footnote>
12243 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a <quote>natural right.</quote> Natural
12244 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12245 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12246 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12247 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12248 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12249 </para>
12250 <para>
12251 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12252 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12253 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12254 <quote>Walt Disney creativity</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12255 know what's protected and what's not.
12256 </para>
12257 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12258 <para>
12259 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12260 Berlin in 1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12261 Convention in 1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12262 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12263 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12264 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12265 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an <citetitle>i</citetitle> or cross a
12266 <citetitle>t</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12267 </para>
12268 <para>
12269 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12270 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12271 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12272 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12273 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12274 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12275 </para>
12276 <para>
12277 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12278 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12279 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12280 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12281 burden
12282 imposed upon creators.
12283 </para>
12284 <para>
12285 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was
12286 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12287
12288 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12289 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12290 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12291 the government. He has a property right over the table <quote>naturally,</quote>
12292 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12293 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12294 table.
12295 </para>
12296 <para>
12297 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12298 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12299 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12300 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12301 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12302 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12303 spread.
12304 </para>
12305 <para>
12306 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12307 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12308 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12309 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12310 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12311 important reason to secure registration&mdash;both because it makes
12312 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12313 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12314 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12315 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12316 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12317 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12318 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12319 system of protection for property generally.
12320 </para>
12321 <para>
12322 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12323 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12324 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12325 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12326 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12327 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12328 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12329 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12330
12331 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12332 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12333 <emphasis>lawyer</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12334 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
12335 </para>
12336 <para>
12337 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12338 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12339 didn't <quote>get.</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
12340 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
12341 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, <quote>short,</quote> then this
12342 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
12343 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
12344 be presumptively uncontrolled.
12345 </para>
12346 <para>
12347 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
12348 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
12349 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
12350 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
12351 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
12352 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
12353 seen before <emphasis>because there are no formalities</emphasis>.
12354 </para>
12355 <para>
12356 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
12357 it is worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
12358 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
12359 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
12360 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
12361 </para>
12362 <para>
12363 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
12364 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
12365 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
12366 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
12367 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you.
12368 </para>
12369 <para>
12370 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
12371 registering the work mean that the $1 is really misleading? Isn't the
12372 hassle worth more than $1? Isn't that the real problem with
12373 registration?
12374 </para>
12375 <para>
12376 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
12377 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
12378 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
12379
12380 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
12381 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
12382 address the real problem of <emphasis>governments</emphasis> standing
12383 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
12384 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
12385 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
12386 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
12387 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
12388 upon historical data, that system would move up to 98 percent of
12389 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
12390 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
12391 </para>
12392 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12393 <para>
12394 <emphasis role='strong'>When Steve Forbes</emphasis> endorsed the
12395 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
12396 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
12397 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
12398 willing to take the first step.
12399 </para>
12400 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe</primary></indexterm>
12401 <para>
12402 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
12403 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
12404 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
12405 possible. In May 2003, it looked as if the bill would be
12406 introduced. On May 16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, <quote>we are
12407 close.</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
12408 something good might happen here.
12409 </para>
12410 <para>
12411 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
12412 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
12413 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
12414 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
12415 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
12416 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
12417 </para>
12418 <para>
12419 The MPAA argued first that Congress had <quote>firmly rejected the central
12420 concept in the proposed bill</quote>&mdash;that copyrights be renewed. That
12421 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's <quote>firm rejection</quote> had occurred
12422 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
12423 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
12424 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
12425 owners&mdash;apparently those who could not afford the $1 fee. Third,
12426 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
12427 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
12428 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
12429 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
12430 off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
12431 argued that the bill would impose <quote>enormous</quote> costs, since a
12432 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
12433 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
12434 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
12435 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
12436 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
12437 film is a valid derivative use.
12438 </para>
12439 <para>
12440 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
12441 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
12442 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
12443 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
12444 or not&mdash;a controversial claim in any case&mdash;unless they know
12445 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
12446 </para>
12447 <para>
12448 <emphasis role='strong'>At the beginning</emphasis> of this book, I
12449 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
12450 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
12451 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
12452 opposition&mdash;the power of the side that fought to defend the
12453 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
12454 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
12455 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
12456 </para>
12457 <para>
12458 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
12459 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
12460 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
12461 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
12462 sense?
12463 </para>
12464 <para>
12465
12466 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
12467 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
12468 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
12469 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
12470 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
12471 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
12472 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
12473 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
12474 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
12475 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
12476 </para>
12477 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin</primary></indexterm>
12478 <para>
12479 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
12480 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
12481 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
12482 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
12483 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
12484 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the <quote>Dark
12485 Content</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
12486 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
12487 </para>
12488 <para>
12489 What does this industry really want?
12490 </para>
12491 <para>
12492 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
12493 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
12494 protecting <emphasis>their</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
12495 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
12496 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
12497 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
12498 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
12499 content that doesn't require <emphasis>their</emphasis> permission
12500 first.
12501 </para>
12502 <para>
12503 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
12504 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
12505 its aim not the protection of <quote>property</quote> but the rejection of a
12506 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
12507 theirs. <emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
12508 theirs</emphasis>.
12509 </para>
12510 <para>
12511 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
12512 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
12513
12514 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
12515 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
12516 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
12517 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
12518 and to share its own creation.
12519 </para>
12520 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
12521 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
12522 <para>
12523 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
12524 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
12525 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
12526 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
12527 block the progress of others.
12528 </para>
12529 <para>
12530 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
12531 <quote>property</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
12532 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
12533 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing <quote>permission
12534 society.</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
12535 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
12536 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
12537 </para>
12538 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
12539 </chapter>
12540 </part>
12541 <chapter label="15" id="c-conclusion">
12542 <title>CONCLUSION</title>
12543 <indexterm id="idxantiretroviraldrugs" class='startofrange'><primary>antiretroviral drugs</primary></indexterm>
12544 <indexterm id="idxhivaidstherapies" class='startofrange'><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies</primary></indexterm>
12545 <indexterm id="idxafricahivmed" class='startofrange'><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in</primary></indexterm>
12546 <para>
12547 <emphasis role='strong'>There are more</emphasis> than 35 million
12548 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
12549 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
12550 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
12551 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
12552 </para>
12553 <para>
12554 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
12555 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
12556 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
12557 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
12558 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
12559 the disease almost invisible.
12560 </para>
12561 <para>
12562 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
12563 United States, they cost between $10,000 and $15,000 per person per
12564 year. Today, some cost $25,000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
12565 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
12566 population:
12567 $15,000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
12568 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.<footnote><para>
12569 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, <quote>Final Report: Integrating
12570 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy</quote> (London, 2002),
12571 available at
12572 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
12573 release
12574 issued 9 July 2002, only 230,000 of the 6 million who need drugs in
12575 the developing world receive them&mdash;and half of them are in Brazil.
12576 </para></footnote>
12577 </para>
12578 <para>
12579 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
12580 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
12581 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
12582 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
12583 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
12584 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
12585 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
12586 </para>
12587 <para>
12588 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
12589 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
12590 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
12591 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
12592 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
12593 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
12594 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
12595 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
12596 changes.
12597 </para>
12598 <para>
12599 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
12600 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
12601 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
12602 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
12603 costs significantly below the market price.
12604 </para>
12605 <para>
12606 In 1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
12607 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
12608 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
12609 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
12610 Africa from India. This is called <quote>parallel importation,</quote> and it is
12611 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
12612 permitted within the European Union.<footnote>
12613 <para>
12614 <!-- f2. -->
12615 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
12616 Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37.
12617 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
12618 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12619 </para></footnote>
12620 </para>
12621 <para>
12622 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
12623 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
12624 characterized it, <quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa &hellip;
12625 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
12626 imports.</quote><footnote><para>
12627 <!-- f3. -->
12628 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
12629 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12630 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12631 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 14, available at
12632 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #56</ulink>. For a
12633 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
12634 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
12635 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess.,
12636 Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150&ndash;57 (statement of James
12637 Love).
12638 </para></footnote>
12639 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
12640 government asked South Africa to change the law&mdash;and to add
12641 pressure to that request, in 1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
12642 possible trade sanctions.
12643 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
12644 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
12645 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
12646 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
12647 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
12648 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
12649 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
12650 patent&mdash; pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
12651 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
12652 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
12653 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.<footnote><para>
12654 <!-- f4. -->
12655 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
12656 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12657 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12658 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 15. </para></footnote>
12659 </para>
12660 <para>
12661 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
12662 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
12663 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
12664 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
12665 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
12666 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
12667 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
12668 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
12669 </para>
12670 <para>
12671 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
12672 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
12673 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
12674 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
12675 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
12676 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save 15 to 30 million lives.
12677 </para>
12678 <para>
12679 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
12680 profits of United States drug companies&mdash;at least, not substantially. It
12681 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
12682 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
12683 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
12684 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
12685 by U.S. companies.
12686 </para>
12687 <para>
12688 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
12689 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
12690 argument
12691 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
12692 about the sanctity of property.<footnote><para>
12693 <!-- f5. -->
12694 See Sabin Russell, <quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
12695 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24
12696 May 1999, A1, available at
12697 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #57</ulink>
12698 (<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
12699 system of intellectual property protection</quote>); Robert Weissman, <quote>AIDS
12700 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
12701 Medicines,</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus</citetitle> 4:23 (August 1999), available at
12702 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #58</ulink>
12703 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, <quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
12704 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
12705 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
12706 Symposium Journal</citetitle> (Spring 2001): 175.
12707 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
12708 </para></footnote>
12709 It was because <quote>intellectual property</quote> would be violated that these
12710 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
12711 importance of <quote>intellectual property</quote> that led these government actors
12712 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
12713 </para>
12714 <para>
12715 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
12716 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
12717 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
12718 direct cost would be to speed the death of 15 to 30 million Africans,
12719 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the <quote>sanctity</quote> of an
12720 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
12721 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
12722 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
12723 </para>
12724 <para>
12725 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
12726 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
12727 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
12728 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
12729 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system&mdash;
12730 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
12731 </para>
12732 <para>
12733 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
12734 drug companies would love&mdash;they say, and I believe them&mdash;to
12735 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
12736 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
12737 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
12738 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
12739 </para>
12740 <para>
12741 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
12742 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
12743 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, <quote>How
12744 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $1 a pill, but the same
12745 drug would cost an American $1,500?</quote> Because there is no <quote>sound
12746 bite</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
12747 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
12748 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
12749 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
12750 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
12751 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
12752 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal&mdash;the sanctity of an
12753 idea called <quote>intellectual property.</quote>
12754 </para>
12755 <para>
12756 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
12757 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
12758 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
12759 What is the argument?
12760 </para>
12761 <para>
12762 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
12763 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
12764 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
12765 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
12766 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
12767 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
12768 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
12769 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
12770 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
12771 were balanced in just this sense.
12772 </para>
12773 <para>
12774 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
12775 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
12776 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
12777 our tradition, now reigns in this culture&mdash;bizarrely, and with
12778 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
12779 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
12780 </para>
12781 <indexterm startref="idxafricahivmed" class='endofrange'/>
12782 <indexterm startref="idxhivaidstherapies" class='endofrange'/>
12783 <indexterm startref="idxantiretroviraldrugs" class='endofrange'/>
12784 <para>
12785 <emphasis role='strong'>A simple idea</emphasis> blinds us, and under
12786 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
12787 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
12788 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
12789 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
12790 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
12791 control of that property removes our
12792 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
12793 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
12794 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
12795 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
12796 this common sense open its eyes.
12797 </para>
12798 <para>
12799 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
12800 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
12801 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
12802 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
12803 to fight <quote>piracy,</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
12804 the idea of <quote>creative property,</quote> while transforming real creators into
12805 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
12806 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
12807 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
12808 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
12809 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
12810 produce the <quote>perfect storm</quote> for free culture.
12811 </para>
12812 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>public projects in</secondary></indexterm>
12813 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)</primary></indexterm>
12814 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust</primary></indexterm>
12815 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web</primary></indexterm>
12816 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System</primary></indexterm>
12817 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12818 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
12819 <para>
12820 <emphasis role='strong'>In August 2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
12821 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
12822 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.<footnote><para>
12823 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>,
12824 August 2003, E1, available at
12825 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #59</ulink>; William New, <quote>Global Group's
12826 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
12827 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
12828 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #60</ulink>; William New, <quote>U.S. Official
12829 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
12830 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
12831 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #61</ulink>.
12832 </para></footnote>
12833 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
12834 a meeting to discuss <quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
12835 goods.</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
12836 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
12837 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
12838 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
12839 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
12840 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
12841 that I describe in the Afterword. It included a project to develop
12842 single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs), which are thought to have
12843 great significance in biomedical research. (That nonprofit project
12844 comprised a consortium of the Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and
12845 technological companies, including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
12846 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
12847 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
12848 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
12849 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
12850 in the early 1980s. And it included <quote>open source and free software.</quote>
12851 <indexterm><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
12852 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
12853 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
12854 </para>
12855 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'/>
12856 <para>
12857 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
12858 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
12859 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
12860 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
12861 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
12862 </para>
12863 <para>
12864 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.<footnote><para>
12865 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
12866 meeting.
12867 </para></footnote>
12868 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
12869 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
12870 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
12871 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
12872 property issues.
12873 </para>
12874 <para>
12875 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
12876 about WIPO. In February 2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
12877 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
12878 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
12879 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
12880 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
12881 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
12882 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
12883 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
12884 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
12885 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
12886 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
12887 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
12888 talk about an <quote>Information Society</quote> unless one also talked about the
12889 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
12890 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
12891 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
12892 stuff of
12893 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
12894 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
12895 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
12896 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
12897 </para>
12898 <para>
12899 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
12900 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
12901 thus the meeting about <quote>open and collaborative projects to create
12902 public goods</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
12903 </para>
12904 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
12905 <para>
12906 But there is one project within that list that is highly
12907 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is <quote>open source
12908 and free software.</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
12909 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
12910 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
12911 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
12912 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
12913 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
12914 rather than <quote>proprietary software,</quote> for their own internal uses.
12915 </para>
12916 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft</quote> licenses</primary></indexterm>
12917 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12918 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12919 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
12920 <para>
12921 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
12922 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
12923 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
12924 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
12925 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
12926 operating system, the most famous bit of <quote>free software</quote>&mdash;and IBM
12927 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support <quote>open source and
12928 free software</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
12929 to support a mode of software development that is different from
12930 Microsoft's.<footnote><para>
12931 <!-- f8. -->
12932 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
12933 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
12934 <quote>open source</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
12935 principal opposition is to <quote>free software</quote> licensed under a <quote>copyleft</quote>
12936 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
12937 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, <quote>The Future
12938 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
12939 Toward Open Source Software</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
12940 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
12941 Public Policy Research, 2002), 69, available at
12942 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #62</ulink>. See also
12943 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, <citetitle>The Commercial Software
12944 Model</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (3
12945 May 2001), available at
12946 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #63</ulink>.
12947 </para></footnote>
12948 </para>
12949 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)</primary></indexterm>
12950 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)</primary></indexterm>
12951 <para>
12952 More important for our purposes, to support <quote>open source and free
12953 software</quote> is not to oppose copyright. <quote>Open source and free software</quote>
12954 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
12955 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
12956 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
12957 by
12958 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
12959 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
12960 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
12961 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
12962 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
12963 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
12964 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
12965 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
12966 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
12967 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
12968 </para>
12969 <indexterm><primary>Krim, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
12970 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by</secondary></indexterm>
12971 <para>
12972 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
12973 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
12974 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
12975 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
12976 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
12977 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
12978 States government to veto the meeting.<footnote><para>
12979 <!-- f9. -->
12980 Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> available at <ulink
12981 url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #64</ulink>.
12982 </para></footnote>
12983 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
12984 </para>
12985 <para>
12986 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
12987 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
12988 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
12989 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
12990 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
12991 its lobbying efforts.
12992 </para>
12993 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
12994 <para>
12995 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
12996 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
12997 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
12998 Office, explained that <quote>open-source software runs counter to the
12999 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.</quote>
13000 She is quoted as saying, <quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
13001 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
13002 goals of WIPO.</quote>
13003 </para>
13004 <para>
13005 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
13006 </para>
13007 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
13008 <para>
13009 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
13010 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
13011 right called <quote>copyright</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
13012 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it <quote>runs counter</quote> to the mission
13013 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
13014 in understanding&mdash;the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
13015 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
13016 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
13017 </para>
13018 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs</primary></indexterm>
13019 <para>
13020 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to <quote>promote</quote>
13021 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
13022 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
13023 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
13024 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
13025 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
13026 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
13027 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
13028 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
13029 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
13030 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
13031 </para>
13032 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
13033 <para>
13034 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
13035 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
13036 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13037 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13038 <emphasis>their</emphasis> rights. If they want to <quote>waive</quote> or
13039 <quote>disclaim</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13040 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $20 billion to do
13041 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13042 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13043 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13044 to do with <emphasis>their</emphasis> property.
13045 </para>
13046 <indexterm id='idxboland' class='startofrange'><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13047 <para>
13048 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13049 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,</quote> she's
13050 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13051 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13052 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13053 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from <quote>waiving</quote> or
13054 <quote>disclaiming</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13055 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13056 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13057 way possible.
13058 </para>
13059 <para>
13060 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13061 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called <quote>feudalism.</quote> Under
13062 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13063 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13064 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13065 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13066 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13067 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13068 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13069 that control.
13070 </para>
13071 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13072 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13073 <para>
13074 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13075 choice we are now making about intellectual property.<footnote><para>
13076 <!-- f10. -->
13077 See Drahos with Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism</citetitle>, 210&ndash;20.
13078 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13079 </para></footnote>
13080 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13081 choice now is whether that information society will be
13082 <emphasis>free</emphasis> or <emphasis>feudal</emphasis>. The trend is
13083 toward the feudal.
13084 </para>
13085 <para>
13086 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13087 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13088 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13089 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13090 </para>
13091 <blockquote>
13092 <para>
13093 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13094 it should be (<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13095 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13096 not simply to promote intellectual property rights</quote>), not as it is. If
13097 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13098 say anything wrong. But in the world
13099 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13100 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13101 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13102 </para>
13103 </blockquote>
13104 <para>
13105 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13106 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13107 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13108 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13109 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13110 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13111 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13112 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13113 </para>
13114 <indexterm startref='idxboland' class='endofrange'/>
13115 <para>
13116 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13117 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13118 <quote>goal</quote> of a government should be <quote>to promote the right balance</quote> of
13119 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13120 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. <quote>Typical for
13121 an academic,</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13122 </para>
13123 <para>
13124 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13125 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13126 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13127 our own country's history).
13128 </para>
13129 <para>
13130 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13131 government should be to <quote>seek balance,</quote> then count me with the silly,
13132 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13133 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13134 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13135 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13136 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13137 not lies is just na&iuml;ve, then who have we, the most powerful
13138 democracy in the world, become?
13139 </para>
13140 <para>
13141 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13142 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13143 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13144 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13145 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13146 been part of our tradition for most of our history&mdash;free culture.
13147 </para>
13148 <para>
13149 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13150 </para>
13151 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
13152 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
13153 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted</primary></indexterm>
13154 <para>
13155 <emphasis role='strong'>There are moments</emphasis> of hope in this
13156 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13157 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13158 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13159 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13160 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13161 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13162 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing 700,000 letters were
13163 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13164 </para>
13165 <para>
13166 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13167 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13168 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13169 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13170 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13171 concentration in the media.
13172 </para>
13173 <para>
13174 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13175 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13176 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13177 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13178 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13179 </para>
13180 <para>
13181 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13182 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13183 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13184 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13185 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13186 range of rights&mdash;property rights of a historically extreme
13187 form&mdash;that makes their bigness bad.
13188 </para>
13189 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13190 <para>
13191 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13192 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13193 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13194 Americans have a long history of fighting <quote>big,</quote> wisely or not. That
13195 we could be motivated to fight <quote>big</quote> again is not something new.
13196 </para>
13197 <para>
13198 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13199 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13200 the idea of <quote>intellectual property.</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13201 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13202 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13203 called <quote>property</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13204 </para>
13205 <para>
13206 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13207 of our tragedy.
13208 </para>
13209 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob</primary></indexterm>
13210 <para>
13211 <emphasis role='strong'>As I write</emphasis> these final words, the
13212 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
13213 three hundred individuals.<footnote><para>
13214 <!-- f11. -->
13215 John Borland, <quote>RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers,</quote> CNET News.com, September
13216 2003, available at
13217 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #65</ulink>; Paul
13218 R. La Monica, <quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,</quote> CNN/Money, 8 September
13219 2003, available at
13220 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #66</ulink>; Soni
13221 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, <quote>Sued for a Song,
13222 N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among 261 Cited as Sharers,</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News</citetitle>, 9
13223 September 2003, 3; Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13224 Targets; Single Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13225 Defendants,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13226 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,</quote> <citetitle>Wired News</citetitle>, 10 September 2003,
13227 available at
13228 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #67</ulink>.
13229 </para></footnote>
13230 Eminem has just been sued for <quote>sampling</quote> someone else's
13231 music.<footnote><para>
13232 <!-- f12. -->
13233 Jon Wiederhorn, <quote>Eminem Gets Sued &hellip; by a Little Old Lady,</quote>
13234 mtv.com, 17 September 2003, available at
13235 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #68</ulink>.
13236 </para></footnote>
13237 The story about Bob Dylan <quote>stealing</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13238 finished making the rounds.<footnote><para>
13239 <!-- f13. -->
13240 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, <quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13241 Dylan Songs,</quote> Kansascity.com, 9 July 2003, available at
13242 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #69</ulink>.
13243 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13244 </para></footnote>
13245 An insider from Hollywood&mdash;who insists he must remain
13246 anonymous&mdash;reports <quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13247 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13248 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13249 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13250 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.</quote> Congressmen are
13251 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13252 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13253 kids who use a computer to share content.
13254 </para>
13255 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13256 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13257 <indexterm><primary>BBC</primary></indexterm>
13258 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in</primary></indexterm>
13259 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
13260 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto</primary></indexterm>
13261 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>public creative archive in</secondary></indexterm>
13262 <para>
13263 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13264 that it will build a <quote>Creative Archive,</quote> from which British citizens can
13265 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.<footnote><para>
13266 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,</quote> BBC press release,
13267 24 August 2003, available at
13268 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #70</ulink>.
13269 </para></footnote>
13270 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13271 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13272 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13273 country.<footnote><para>
13274 <!-- f15. -->
13275 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,</quote> Creative Commons Weblog, 6 August 2003,
13276 available at
13277 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #71</ulink>.
13278 </para></footnote>
13279 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13280 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13281 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13282 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13283 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13284 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13285 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13286 day into the Causbys.
13287 </para>
13288 <para>
13289 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
13290 potential is ever to be realized.
13291
13292 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
13293
13294 </para>
13295 </chapter>
13296 <chapter label="16" id="c-afterword">
13297 <title>AFTERWORD</title>
13298 <para>
13299
13300 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
13301 <emphasis role='strong'>At least some</emphasis> who have read this
13302 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
13303 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
13304 </para>
13305 <para>
13306 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
13307 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
13308 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
13309 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
13310 </para>
13311 <para>
13312 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
13313 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
13314 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists&mdash;all to tell this
13315 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
13316 is so important.
13317 </para>
13318 <para>
13319 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
13320 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
13321 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
13322 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
13323 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
13324 </para>
13325 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
13326
13327 <section id="usnow">
13328 <title>US, NOW</title>
13329 <para>
13330 <emphasis role='strong'>Common sense</emphasis> is with the copyright
13331 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
13332 extremes&mdash;as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
13333 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
13334 choice, then the warriors should win.
13335 </para>
13336 <para>
13337 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
13338 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
13339 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright&mdash;<quote>All Rights
13340 Reserved</quote>&mdash; and those who reject copyright&mdash;<quote>No Rights
13341 Reserved.</quote> The <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
13342 permission before you <quote>use</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The <quote>No
13343 Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
13344 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
13345 </para>
13346 <para>
13347 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
13348 tilted in the <quote>no rights reserved</quote> direction. Content could be copied
13349 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
13350 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
13351 the
13352
13353 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
13354 original design of the Internet was <quote>no rights reserved.</quote> Content was
13355 <quote>taken</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
13356 unprotected.
13357 </para>
13358 <para>
13359 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
13360 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
13361 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
13362 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
13363 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
13364 architecture made the effective default <quote>no rights reserved,</quote> the
13365 future architecture will make the effective default <quote>all rights
13366 reserved.</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
13367 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
13368 content requires permission. The <quote>cut and paste</quote> world that defines
13369 the Internet today will become a <quote>get permission to cut and paste</quote>
13370 world that is a creator's nightmare.
13371 </para>
13372 <para>
13373 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle&mdash;neither
13374 <quote>all rights reserved</quote> nor <quote>no rights reserved</quote> but <quote>some rights
13375 reserved</quote>&mdash; and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
13376 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
13377 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
13378 before.
13379 </para>
13380
13381 <section id="examples">
13382 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples</title>
13383 <indexterm id='browsing' class='startofrange'><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
13384 <para>
13385 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
13386 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
13387 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
13388 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
13389 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
13390 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
13391 to your neighbors or boss. The <quote>privacy</quote> of your browsing habits was
13392 assured.
13393 </para>
13394 <para>
13395 What made it assured?
13396 </para>
13397 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
13398 <para>
13399 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
13400 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>, your
13401 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
13402 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
13403 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
13404 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
13405 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
13406 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
13407 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
13408 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
13409 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
13410 (there is no law protecting <quote>privacy</quote> in public places), and in many
13411 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
13412 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
13413 </para>
13414 <indexterm><primary>Amazon</primary></indexterm>
13415 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet</primary></indexterm>
13416 <para>
13417 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
13418 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
13419 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
13420 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
13421 <quote>recently viewed</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
13422 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
13423 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any <quote>privacy</quote>
13424 protected by the friction disappears, too.
13425 </para>
13426 <para>
13427 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
13428 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
13429 people should have the <quote>right</quote> to browse in a library without the
13430 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
13431 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
13432 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
13433 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
13434 disappears.
13435 </para>
13436 <indexterm startref='browsing' class='endofrange'/>
13437 <para>
13438 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define <quote>privacy</quote>
13439 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
13440 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
13441 friction did.<footnote><para>
13442 <!-- f1. -->
13443
13444 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, <quote>Fair Information Practices and the
13445 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
13446 Law Review</citetitle> 1 (2001): par. 6&ndash;18, available at
13447
13448 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>
13449 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
13450 also Jeffrey Rosen, <citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
13451 in an Anxious Age</citetitle> (New York: Random House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs
13452 between technology and privacy).</para></footnote>
13453 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
13454 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
13455
13456 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
13457 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
13458 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
13459 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
13460 </para>
13461 <para>
13462 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
13463 movement. When computers with software were first made available
13464 commercially, the software&mdash;both the source code and the
13465 binaries&mdash; was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
13466 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
13467 care much about controlling their software.
13468 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13469 </para>
13470 <indexterm><primary>Stallman, Richard</primary></indexterm>
13471 <para>
13472 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
13473 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
13474 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
13475 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
13476 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
13477 people's work.
13478 </para>
13479 <para>
13480 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
13481 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
13482 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
13483 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
13484 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
13485 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
13486 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
13487 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
13488 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
13489 anything else?
13490 </para>
13491 <para>
13492 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
13493 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
13494 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
13495 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
13496 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
13497 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
13498 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
13499 </para>
13500 <para>
13501 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
13502 early 1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
13503 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
13504 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
13505 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
13506 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
13507 fundamentally weakened.
13508 </para>
13509 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus</primary></indexterm>
13510 <para>
13511 Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
13512 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
13513 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's <quote>Linux</quote>
13514 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
13515 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13516 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13517 </para>
13518 <para>
13519 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
13520 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
13521 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
13522 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
13523 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
13524 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
13525 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
13526 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
13527 byproduct.
13528 </para>
13529 <para>
13530 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
13531 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
13532 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
13533 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
13534 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
13535 what before had been passively guaranteed.
13536 </para>
13537 <para>
13538 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
13539 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
13540 scientific journals are produced.
13541 </para>
13542 <indexterm id="idxacademocjournals" class='startofrange'><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
13543 <para>
13544 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
13545 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
13546 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
13547 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
13548 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
13549 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
13550 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
13551 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
13552 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
13553 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
13554 and Westlaw are also free
13555 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
13556 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
13557 Court opinion through their respective services.
13558 </para>
13559 <para>
13560 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
13561 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
13562 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
13563 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
13564 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
13565 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
13566 access to material that is not in the public domain.
13567 </para>
13568 <para>
13569 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
13570 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
13571 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
13572 </para>
13573 <para>
13574 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
13575 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
13576 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
13577 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
13578 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
13579 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
13580 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
13581 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
13582 the technology of paper journals (architecture)&mdash;namely, that it
13583 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
13584 </para>
13585 <para>
13586 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
13587 that libraries not give the general public access to the
13588 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
13589 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
13590 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
13591 granted before.
13592 </para>
13593 <para>
13594 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
13595 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
13596 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
13597 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
13598 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
13599 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
13600 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
13601 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
13602 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
13603 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
13604 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
13605 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
13606 </para>
13607 <para>
13608 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
13609 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
13610 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
13611 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
13612 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
13613 presumptively a good&mdash;especially when it helps spread knowledge
13614 and science.
13615 </para>
13616 <indexterm startref="idxacademocjournals" class='endofrange'/>
13617
13618 </section>
13619 <section id="oneidea">
13620 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea</title>
13621 <indexterm id="idxcc" class='startofrange'><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
13622 <para>
13623 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
13624 increasing control effected through law and technology.
13625 </para>
13626 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University</primary></indexterm>
13627 <para>
13628 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
13629 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
13630 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
13631 <emphasis>reasonable</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
13632 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
13633 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
13634 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
13635 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
13636 make this possible.
13637 </para>
13638 <para>
13639 <emphasis>Simple</emphasis>&mdash;which means without a middleman, or
13640 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
13641 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
13642 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
13643 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
13644 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
13645 shared. These three expressions together&mdash;a legal license, a
13646 human-readable description, and
13647 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
13648 machine-readable tags&mdash;constitute a Creative Commons license. A
13649 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
13650 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
13651 that the person associated with the license believes in something
13652 different than the <quote>All</quote> or <quote>No</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
13653 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
13654 certain freedoms are given.
13655 </para>
13656 <para>
13657 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
13658 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
13659 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
13660 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
13661 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
13662 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (<quote>share and share
13663 alike</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
13664 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
13665 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
13666 </para>
13667 <para>
13668 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
13669 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
13670 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
13671 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
13672 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
13673 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
13674 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
13675 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
13676 a public domain.
13677 </para>
13678 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia</primary></indexterm>
13679 <para>
13680 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
13681 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
13682 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
13683 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
13684 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
13685 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
13686 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
13687 of content (<quote>content conducers,</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
13688 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
13689 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
13690 </para>
13691 <para>
13692 The aim is not to fight the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts. The aim is to
13693 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
13694 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
13695 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
13696 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
13697 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
13698 the background of digital technologies. New rules&mdash;with different
13699 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
13700 them&mdash;are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
13701 to begin to build those rules.
13702 </para>
13703 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
13704 <para>
13705 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
13706 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
13707 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
13708 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
13709 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
13710 </para>
13711 <para>
13712 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
13713 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1)
13714 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
13715 and (2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
13716 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (1) will download
13717 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2)
13718 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
13719 them (2)-goods. If there are more (2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the
13720 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
13721 <emphasis>increase</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
13722 </para>
13723 <para>
13724 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
13725 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
13726 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
13727 was a total success.
13728 </para>
13729 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)</primary></indexterm>
13730 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13731 <para>
13732 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
13733 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
13734 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
13735 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled <citetitle>Free for All</citetitle>,
13736 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
13737 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
13738 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
13739 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
13740 well.
13741 </para>
13742 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'/>
13743 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy</primary></indexterm>
13744 <indexterm><primary>rap music</primary></indexterm>
13745 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter</primary></indexterm>
13746 <para>
13747 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
13748 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
13749 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
13750 reasons. Many who use the <quote>sampling license</quote> do so because anything
13751 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
13752 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
13753 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
13754 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
13755 art&mdash;they, too, sample from others. Because the
13756 <emphasis>legal</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
13757 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
13758 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not <quote>allow</quote>
13759 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
13760 high<footnote><para>
13761 <!-- f2. -->
13762 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
13763 Culture Wars</citetitle> (2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
13764 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
13765 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>.
13766 </para></footnote>),
13767 these artists release into the creative environment content
13768 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
13769 </para>
13770 <para>
13771 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
13772 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
13773 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
13774 you are effectively saying you believe in the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote>
13775 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
13776 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
13777 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
13778 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
13779 this notion of <quote>Some Rights Reserved,</quote> and gives many the chance to
13780 say it to others.
13781 </para>
13782 <para>
13783 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
13784 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
13785 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
13786 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
13787
13788 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
13789 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
13790 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
13791 </para>
13792 <para>
13793 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
13794 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
13795 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
13796 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
13797 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
13798 steps are possible.
13799 </para>
13800 <para>
13801 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
13802 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
13803 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
13804 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
13805 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
13806 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
13807 creativity to spread more easily.
13808 </para>
13809 <indexterm startref="idxcc" class='endofrange'/>
13810
13811 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
13812 </section>
13813 </section>
13814 <section id="themsoon">
13815 <title>THEM, SOON</title>
13816 <para>
13817 <emphasis role='strong'>We will</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
13818 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
13819 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
13820 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
13821 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
13822 </para>
13823 <para>
13824 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
13825 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
13826 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
13827 to our end.
13828 </para>
13829
13830 <section id="formalities">
13831 <title>1. More Formalities</title>
13832 <para>
13833 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
13834 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
13835 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
13836 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
13837 </para>
13838 <para>
13839 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
13840 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
13841 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
13842 protected.
13843 </para>
13844 <para>
13845 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
13846 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
13847 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
13848 default is control, and <quote>formalities</quote> are banished.
13849 </para>
13850 <para>
13851 Why?
13852 </para>
13853 <para>
13854 As I suggested in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
13855 linkend="property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
13856 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
13857 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
13858 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
13859 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
13860 formalities were getting in the way.
13861 </para>
13862 <para>
13863 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
13864 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
13865 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
13866 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
13867 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
13868 trace&mdash; there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
13869 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
13870 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
13871 past. And thus, the <emphasis>lack</emphasis> of formalities forces
13872 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
13873 </para>
13874 <para>
13875 The law should therefore change this requirement<footnote><para>
13876 <!-- f1. -->
13877 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
13878 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
13879 adopted by other countries as well.</para></footnote>&mdash;but it
13880 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
13881 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
13882 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
13883 </para>
13884 <para>
13885 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
13886 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
13887 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
13888 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
13889 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
13890 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
13891 developed by others.
13892 </para>
13893
13894 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
13895
13896 <section id="registration">
13897 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL</title>
13898 <para>
13899 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
13900 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
13901 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
13902 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
13903 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
13904 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
13905 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
13906 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
13907 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
13908 panic&mdash;nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
13909 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
13910 </para>
13911 <para>
13912 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
13913 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
13914 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
13915 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
13916 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
13917 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
13918 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
13919 </para>
13920 <para>
13921 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
13922 There are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world.
13923 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
13924 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
13925 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
13926 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
13927 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
13928 with which registration occurs up.
13929 </para>
13930 <para>
13931 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
13932 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
13933 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
13934 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
13935 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
13936 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
13937 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
13938 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
13939 formality&mdash;while producing a database
13940 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
13941 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
13942 </para>
13943
13944 </section>
13945 <section id="marking">
13946 <title>MARKING</title>
13947 <para>
13948 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
13949 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
13950 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule&mdash;akin to
13951 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
13952 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
13953 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
13954 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
13955 uniformly across all media.
13956 </para>
13957 <para>
13958 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
13959 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
13960 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
13961 use the work.
13962 </para>
13963 <para>
13964 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
13965 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
13966 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
13967 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
13968 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
13969 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
13970 signal from the failure to mark&mdash;not the loss of the copyright, but the
13971 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
13972 </para>
13973 <para>
13974 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
13975 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
13976 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
13977 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
13978 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
13979 doesn't give permission.<footnote><para>
13980 <!-- f2. -->
13981 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
13982 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
13983 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
13984 </para></footnote>
13985 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be <quote>use unless someone
13986 complains.</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
13987 stop using the work in any new
13988 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
13989 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
13990 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
13991 their work.
13992 </para>
13993 <para>
13994 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
13995 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
13996 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
13997 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
13998 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
13999 </para>
14000 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>copyright marking of</secondary></indexterm>
14001 <para>
14002 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
14003 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
14004 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
14005 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
14006 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
14007 <emphasis>solely</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
14008 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
14009 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
14010 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
14011 other important functions.
14012 </para>
14013 <para>
14014 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
14015 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
14016 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
14017 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
14018 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
14019 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
14020 </para>
14021 <para>
14022 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
14023 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
14024 make things unclear.
14025 </para>
14026 <para>
14027 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
14028 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
14029 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
14030 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
14031 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
14032 that assertion at the appropriate time.
14033 </para>
14034
14035 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
14036 </section>
14037 </section>
14038 <section id="shortterms">
14039 <title>2. Shorter Terms</title>
14040 <para>
14041 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14042 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14043 natural authors.
14044 </para>
14045 <para>
14046 In <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14047 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14048 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14049 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14050 radical. <citetitle>The Economist</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14051 copyright term.<footnote><para>
14052
14053 <!-- f3. -->
14054 <quote>A Radical Rethink,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 366:8308 (25 January 2003): 15,
14055 available at
14056 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #74</ulink>.
14057 </para></footnote>
14058 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14059 </para>
14060 <para>
14061 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14062 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14063 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14064 terms.
14065 </para>
14066 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14067 <listitem><para>
14068 <!-- (1) -->
14069 <emphasis>Keep it short:</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14070 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14071 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14072 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14073 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14074 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14075 </para></listitem>
14076 <listitem><para>
14077 <!-- (2) -->
14078 <emphasis>Keep it simple:</emphasis> The line between the public
14079 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14080 fuzziness of <quote>fair use,</quote> and the distinction between <quote>ideas</quote> and
14081 <quote>expression.</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14082 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14083 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14084 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14085 <quote>lawyer-free zone</quote> makes the complexities of <quote>fair use</quote> and
14086 <quote>idea/expression</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14087 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14088 </para></listitem>
14089 <listitem>
14090 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions</primary></indexterm>
14091 <para>
14092 <!-- (3) -->
14093 <emphasis>Keep it alive:</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14094 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14095 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14096 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14097 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14098 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14099 pension.<footnote><para>
14100 <!-- f4. -->
14101 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14102 and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001),
14103 available at
14104 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #75</ulink>.
14105 </para></footnote>
14106 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14107 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14108 single form.
14109 </para></listitem>
14110 <listitem><para>
14111 <!-- (4) -->
14112 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14113 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14114 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14115 in 1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14116 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14117 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in 1923 than we
14118 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14119 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14120 the number of authors who wrote in 1923. Of course, we can increase
14121 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14122 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14123 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14124 creativity in 1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14125 we can do about that now. </para></listitem>
14126 </orderedlist>
14127 <para>
14128 These changes together should produce an <emphasis>average</emphasis>
14129 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until 1976,
14130 the average term was just 32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14131 same.
14132 </para>
14133 <para>
14134 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas <quote>radical.</quote> (After all, I
14135 call them <quote>extremists.</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14136 than the term under Richard Nixon. How <quote>radical</quote> can it be to ask for
14137 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14138 </para>
14139
14140 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14141
14142 </section>
14143 <section id="freefairuse">
14144 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use</title>
14145 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
14146 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
14147 <para>
14148 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14149 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14150 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14151 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14152 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14153 the emergence of that new technology.
14154 </para>
14155 <para>
14156 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors <quote>exclusive
14157 right</quote> to <quote>their writings.</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14158 right to <quote>their writings</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14159 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14160 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14161 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14162 though that movie is not <quote>my writing.</quote>
14163 </para>
14164 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin</primary></indexterm>
14165 <para>
14166 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it
14167 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14168 control translations and dramatizations of a work.<footnote><para>
14169 <!-- f5. -->
14170 Benjamin Kaplan, <citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14171 University Press, 1967), 32.
14172 </para></footnote>
14173 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14174 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14175 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14176 </para>
14177 <blockquote>
14178 <para>
14179 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14180 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14181 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14182 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.<footnote><para>
14183 <!-- f6. --> Ibid., 56.
14184 </para></footnote>
14185 </para>
14186 </blockquote>
14187 <para>
14188 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14189 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14190 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14191 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14192 Consider each limitation in turn.
14193 </para>
14194 <para>
14195 <emphasis>Term:</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14196 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14197 sense to protect John
14198
14199 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14200 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14201 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14202 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14203 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14204 after the creative work is done.
14205 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
14206 </para>
14207 <para>
14208 <emphasis>Scope:</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14209 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14210 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14211 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14212 material. When all <quote>reuse</quote> of creative material was within the control
14213 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14214 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14215 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14216 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14217 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14218 the creative process. Smothers it.
14219 </para>
14220 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
14221 <para>
14222 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14223 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14224 foreseeable derivative rights&mdash;turning a book into a movie, or a
14225 poem into a musical score&mdash;it doesn't make sense to require
14226 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14227 much more sense.
14228 </para>
14229 <para>
14230 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14231 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14232 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14233 Paul Goldstein.<footnote>
14234 <para>
14235 <!-- f7. -->
14236 Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14237 Jukebox</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187&ndash;216.
14238 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul</primary></indexterm>
14239 </para></footnote>
14240 His view is that the law should be written so that
14241 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14242 </para>
14243 <para>
14244 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14245 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14246 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14247 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14248 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14249 </para>
14250 <para>
14251 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14252 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
14253 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
14254 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
14255 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
14256 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
14257 </para>
14258 </section>
14259
14260 <section id="liberatemusic">
14261 <title>4. Liberate the Music&mdash;Again</title>
14262 <para>
14263 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
14264 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
14265 is, to most people, most pressing&mdash;music. There is no other
14266 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
14267 battles around the sharing of music.
14268 </para>
14269 <para>
14270 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
14271 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
14272 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
14273 killer app&mdash;possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
14274 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
14275 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
14276 innovation on the network.
14277 </para>
14278 <para>
14279 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
14280 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
14281 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
14282 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
14283 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
14284 </para>
14285 <para>
14286 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
14287 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
14288 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
14289 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="piracy"/>, they enable
14290 four different kinds of sharing:
14291 </para>
14292 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
14293 <listitem><para>
14294 <!-- A. -->
14295 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
14296 for purchasing CDs.
14297 </para></listitem>
14298 <listitem><para>
14299 <!-- B. -->
14300 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
14301 on the way to purchasing CDs.
14302 </para></listitem>
14303 <listitem><para>
14304 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
14305 <!-- C. -->
14306 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14307 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
14308 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
14309 </para></listitem>
14310 <listitem><para>
14311 <!-- D. -->
14312 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14313 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
14314 owner plainly endorses.
14315 </para></listitem>
14316 </orderedlist>
14317 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
14318 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
14319 <para>
14320 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
14321 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
14322 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
14323 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
14324 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
14325 significantly weakened.
14326 </para>
14327 <para>
14328 As I said in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
14329 linkend="piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
14330 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
14331 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
14332 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
14333 networks.
14334 </para>
14335 <para>
14336 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
14337 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
14338 should respond.
14339 </para>
14340 <para>
14341 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
14342 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
14343 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
14344 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
14345 is cumbersome and slow&mdash;we in the United States are lucky to have
14346 broadband service at 1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
14347 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
14348 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
14349 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
14350 Internet is mainly just an idea.
14351 </para>
14352 <para>
14353 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
14354 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
14355 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
14356 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
14357 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
14358 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
14359 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
14360 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
14361 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
14362 where everywhere you are&mdash;except maybe the desert or the
14363 Rockies&mdash;you can instantaneously be connected to the
14364 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
14365 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
14366 </para>
14367 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over</primary></indexterm>
14368 <para>
14369 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
14370 give you access to content on the fly&mdash;such as Internet radio,
14371 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
14372 then, is the critical point: When it is <emphasis>extremely</emphasis>
14373 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
14374 <emphasis>easier</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
14375 access to content than it will be to download and store content
14376 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
14377 content</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
14378 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
14379 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
14380 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
14381 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
14382 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
14383 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
14384 paying for this content even though <quote>free</quote> content is available in the
14385 form of MP3s across the Web.<footnote><para>
14386 <!-- f8. -->
14387 See, for example, <quote>Music Media Watch,</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3
14388 April 2002, available at
14389 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #76</ulink>.
14390 </para></footnote>
14391
14392 </para>
14393 <para>
14394 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
14395 present: It is emphatically temporary. The <quote>problem</quote> with file
14396 sharing&mdash;to the extent there is a real problem&mdash;is a problem
14397 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
14398 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
14399 makers today to be <quote>solving</quote> this problem in light of a technology
14400 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
14401 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
14402 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
14403 artists get paid, during
14404
14405 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
14406 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
14407 and twenty-first-century technologies.
14408 </para>
14409 <para>
14410 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different <quote>problems</quote>
14411 here to solve. Let's start with type D content&mdash;uncopyrighted
14412 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
14413 <quote>problem</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
14414 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
14415 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
14416 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
14417 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
14418 order to eliminate kidnapping.
14419 </para>
14420 <para>
14421 Type C content raises a different <quote>problem.</quote> This is content that was,
14422 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
14423 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
14424 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
14425 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
14426 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
14427 way that returns something to the artist.
14428 </para>
14429 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
14430 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
14431 <para>
14432 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
14433 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
14434 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
14435 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
14436 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
14437 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
14438 from the author's perspective, this <quote>sharing</quote> of his content without
14439 his being compensated is less than ideal.
14440 </para>
14441 <para>
14442 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
14443 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
14444 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
14445 providers would be free, under this rule, to <quote>share</quote> that content,
14446 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
14447 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
14448 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
14449 </para>
14450 <para>
14451
14452 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
14453 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
14454 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
14455 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
14456 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
14457 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
14458 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
14459 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
14460 trade.
14461 </para>
14462 <para>
14463 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
14464 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
14465 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
14466 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
14467 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
14468 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
14469 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
14470 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
14471 </para>
14472 <para>
14473 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
14474 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
14475 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
14476 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
14477 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
14478 delivering and accessing content.
14479 </para>
14480 <para>
14481 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
14482 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
14483 </para>
14484 <para>
14485 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
14486 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
14487 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
14488 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
14489 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
14490 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
14491 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
14492 harmed the interests of the content industry.
14493 </para>
14494 <para>
14495 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
14496 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
14497 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
14498 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
14499 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
14500 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
14501 way to compensate those who are harmed.
14502 </para>
14503 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
14504 <para>
14505 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
14506 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.<footnote>
14507 <para>
14508 <!-- f9. -->
14509 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
14510 William Fisher, <citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities</citetitle> (last
14511 revised: 10 October 2000), available at
14512 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #77</ulink>; William
14513 Fisher, <citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
14514 Entertainment</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
14515 2004), ch. 6, available at
14516 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #78</ulink>. Professor
14517 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
14518 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
14519 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, <quote>Impose a
14520 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,</quote> available at
14521 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Who's Holding Back
14522 Broadband?</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
14523 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
14524 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, 26 February 2002,
14525 available at
14526 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, <citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
14527 Use Fee (IPUF)</citetitle>, 3 March 2002, available at
14528 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
14529 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 13 May
14530 2002, available at
14531 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, <quote>Getting Copyright Right,</quote>
14532 IEEE Spectrum Online, 1 July 2002, available at
14533 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #83</ulink>; Declan
14534 McCullagh, <quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,</quote> CNET News.com, 27 August
14535 2002, available at
14536 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #84</ulink>.
14537 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
14538 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
14539 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
14540 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
14541 debate by about a decade. See
14542 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #85</ulink>.
14543 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William</primary></indexterm>
14544 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
14545 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
14546 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'/>
14547 </para></footnote>
14548 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
14549 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
14550 would (1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
14551 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
14552 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
14553 develop (2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
14554 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (3) artists would be
14555 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (4) an appropriate
14556 tax.
14557 </para>
14558 <para>
14559 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
14560 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
14561 <citetitle>Promises to Keep</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
14562 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
14563 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
14564 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
14565 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
14566 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
14567 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
14568 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
14569 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
14570 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
14571 controlling access.
14572 </para>
14573 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'/>
14574 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
14575 <para>
14576 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
14577 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
14578 the system supports the widest range of <quote>semiotic democracy</quote>
14579 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
14580 other changes I described were accomplished&mdash;in particular, the
14581 limits on derivative
14582
14583 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
14584 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
14585 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
14586 allowed to do with the content itself.
14587 </para>
14588 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
14589 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore</primary></indexterm>
14590 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
14591 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>prices of</secondary></indexterm>
14592 <para>
14593 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
14594 <quote>harm</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
14595 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
14596 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
14597 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
14598 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat <quote>free</quote> by being
14599 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
14600 of songs at even the very high price of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents,
14601 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
14602 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
14603 Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a song. And no doubt
14604 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
14605 on-line.
14606 </para>
14607 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
14608 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast</secondary></indexterm>
14609 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
14610 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
14611 <indexterm><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in</secondary></indexterm>
14612 <para>
14613 This competition has already occurred against the background of <quote>free</quote>
14614 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
14615 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
14616 that, there is nothing impossible at all about <quote>competing with free.</quote>
14617 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
14618 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
14619 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
14620 theaters are often luxurious&mdash;with <quote>first class</quote> seats, and meals
14621 served while you watch a movie&mdash;as they struggle and succeed in
14622 finding ways to compete with <quote>free.</quote>
14623 </para>
14624 <para>
14625 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
14626 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
14627 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
14628 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
14629 innovators&mdash;ones who would have a right to the content, and would
14630 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
14631 the law.
14632 </para>
14633 <para>
14634 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
14635 </para>
14636 <para>
14637
14638 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
14639 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
14640 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
14641 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
14642 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
14643 create.
14644 </para>
14645 <para>
14646 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
14647 by
14648 </para>
14649 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14650 <listitem><para>
14651 <!-- 1. -->
14652 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
14653 </para></listitem>
14654 <listitem><para>
14655 <!-- 2. -->
14656 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
14657 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
14658 statute;
14659 </para></listitem>
14660 <listitem><para>
14661 <!-- 3. -->
14662 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
14663 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
14664 </para></listitem>
14665 </orderedlist>
14666 <para>
14667 But what if <quote>piracy</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
14668 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
14669 consumers continue to <quote>take</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
14670 something then?
14671 </para>
14672 <para>
14673 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
14674 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
14675 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
14676 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
14677 technology that is 95 percent secure and produces a market of size <citetitle>x</citetitle>,
14678 or (b) to have a technology that is 50 percent secure but produces a
14679 market of five times <citetitle>x</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
14680 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
14681 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
14682 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
14683 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
14684 pirates.
14685 </para>
14686 <para>
14687 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
14688 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
14689 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
14690
14691 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
14692 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
14693 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
14694 </para>
14695 </section>
14696
14697 <section id="firelawyers">
14698 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers</title>
14699 <para>
14700 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
14701 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
14702 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
14703 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
14704 </para>
14705 <para>
14706 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
14707 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
14708 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
14709 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
14710 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
14711 strong view queers the law.
14712 </para>
14713 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville</primary></indexterm>
14714 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of</secondary></indexterm>
14715 <para>
14716 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
14717 <quote>radical</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
14718 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
14719 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
14720 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
14721 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
14722 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
14723 Nimmer, thought it obvious.<footnote><para>
14724 <!-- f10. -->
14725 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Copyright's First Amendment</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
14726 Memorial Lecture), <citetitle>UCLA Law Review</citetitle> 48 (2001): 1057, 1069&ndash;70.
14727 </para></footnote>
14728
14729 </para>
14730 <para>
14731 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
14732 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
14733 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
14734 </para>
14735 <para>
14736 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
14737 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
14738 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
14739 the legal system are slight.<footnote><para>
14740 <!-- f11. -->
14741 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
14742 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
14743 leading him to question his own publicly stated
14744 position&mdash;twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
14745 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
14746 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
14747 J. Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
14748 Drive the Digital Marketplace</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002), (reviewing his
14749 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
14750 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?</quote> working paper, June 2003,
14751 available at
14752 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #86</ulink>.
14753 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
14754 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
14755 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
14756 <citetitle>Rethinking</citetitle>, 174&ndash;76.
14757 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
14758 </para></footnote>
14759 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
14760 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
14761 them it works.
14762 </para>
14763 <para>
14764 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
14765 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
14766 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
14767 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
14768 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
14769 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
14770 practically never be done.
14771 </para>
14772 <para>
14773 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
14774 billed at the largest firms at more than $400 per hour. How much time
14775 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
14776 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
14777 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
14778 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
14779 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
14780 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
14781 </para>
14782 <para>
14783 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
14784 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
14785 their duty to change the way the law works&mdash;or better, to change the
14786 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
14787 top 1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
14788 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
14789 </para>
14790 <para>
14791 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
14792 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
14793 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
14794 its review.
14795 </para>
14796 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
14797 <para>
14798 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
14799 technology&mdash;the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
14800 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
14801 technology&mdash;a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
14802 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
14803 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
14804 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
14805 </para>
14806 <para>
14807 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture&mdash;but it should
14808 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
14809
14810 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311 -->
14811 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
14812 simple pragmatic question: <quote>Will it do good?</quote> When challenged about
14813 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, <quote>Why not?</quote>
14814 </para>
14815 <para>
14816 We should ask, <quote>Why?</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
14817 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
14818 keep your lawyers away.
14819 </para>
14820 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
14821 </section>
14822 </section>
14823 </chapter>
14824 <chapter label="17" id="c-notes">
14825 <title>NOTES</title>
14826 <para>
14827 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
14828 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
14829 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
14830 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
14831 this book. For each link below, you can go to
14832 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
14833 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
14834 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
14835 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
14836 the material.
14837 </para>
14838
14839 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
14840 <?latex \theendnotes ?>
14841
14842 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
14843
14844 </chapter>
14845 <chapter label="18" id="c-acknowledgments">
14846 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS</title>
14847 <para>
14848 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
14849 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
14850 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
14851 to him that this book is dedicated.
14852 </para>
14853 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
14854 <para>
14855 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
14856 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
14857 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
14858 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
14859 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
14860 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
14861 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
14862 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
14863 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
14864 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
14865 critical eye on much of this.
14866 </para>
14867 <para>
14868 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
14869 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
14870 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
14871 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
14872 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
14873 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
14874 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
14875 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
14876 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
14877 </para>
14878 <para>
14879 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
14880 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
14881 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
14882 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
14883 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
14884 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
14885 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
14886 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
14887 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
14888 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
14889 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
14890 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
14891 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
14892 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
14893 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, <quote>Wink,</quote> Roger Wood, <quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,</quote>
14894 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
14895 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
14896 a bunch of great replies.)
14897 </para>
14898 <para>
14899 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
14900 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
14901 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
14902 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
14903 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
14904 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
14905 throughout this book.
14906 </para>
14907 <para>
14908 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
14909 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
14910 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
14911 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
14912 </para>
14913 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->
14914
14915 </chapter>
14916 <index></index>
14917 </book>