1 <?xml version='
1.0' encoding='UTF-
8'
?>
2 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29 -->
6 * replace '. . .' with something else
10 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC
"-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.2//EN"
11 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.2/docbookx.dtd"
14 <!ENTITY translationblock
"">
19 <book id=
"index" lang=
"en">
21 <title>Free Culture
</title>
23 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
25 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
26 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY
</subtitle>
28 <pubdate>2004-
03-
25</pubdate>
30 <releaseinfo>Version
2004-
02-
10</releaseinfo>
34 <firstname>Lawrence
</firstname>
35 <surname>Lessig
</surname>
42 Lawrence Lessig. This version of Free Culture is licensed under a
43 Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
44 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
45 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
46 <ulink url=
"http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/
1.0/
</ulink>
51 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR
</title>
54 (
<ulink url=
"http://www.lessig.org/">http://www.lessig.org
</ulink>),
55 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
56 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
57 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
58 (
<ulink url=
"http://creativecommons.org/">http://creativecommons.org
</ulink>).
59 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House,
2001) and Code: And
60 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books,
1999), Lessig is a member of
61 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
62 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
63 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
64 twice listed in BusinessWeek's "e.biz
25," and named one of Scientific
65 American's "
50 visionaries." A graduate of the University of
66 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
67 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
77 You can buy a copy of this book by clicking on one of the links below:
79 <itemizedlist mark=
"number" spacing=
"compact">
80 <listitem><para><ulink url=
"http://www.amazon.com/">Amazon
</ulink></para></listitem>
81 <listitem><para><ulink url=
"http://www.barnesandnoble.com/">B
&N
</ulink></para></listitem>
82 <listitem><para><ulink url=
"http://www.penguin.com/">Penguin
</ulink></para></listitem>
83 <!-- <ulink url="">Local Bookstore</ulink> -->
89 ALSO BY LAWRENCE LESSIG
92 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
95 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
106 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
112 HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND
113 THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN CULTURE
114 AND CONTROL CREATIVITY
121 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
126 a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc.
375 Hudson Street New
130 Copyright
© Lawrence Lessig,
136 Excerpt from an editorial titled "The Coming of Copyright Perpetuity,"
137 The New York Times, January
16,
2003. Copyright
© 2003 by The New York Times Co.
138 Reprinted with permission.
141 Cartoon by Paul Conrad on page
159. Copyright Tribune Media Services, Inc.
144 All rights reserved. Reprinted with permission.
147 Diagram on page
164 courtesy of the office of FCC Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
150 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
154 Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law to lock down
155 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
164 ISBN
1-
59420-
006-
8 (hardcover)
167 1. Intellectual property
—United States.
2. Mass media
—United States.
170 3. Technological innovations
—United States.
4. Art
—United States. I. Title.
176 343.7309'
9—dc22
179 This book is printed on acid-free paper.
182 Printed in the United States of America
188 Designed by Marysarah Quinn
196 Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of
197 this publication may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a
198 retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means
199 (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise),
200 without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and
201 the above publisher of this book. The scanning, uploading, and
202 distribution of this book via the Internet or via any other means
203 without the permission of the publisher is illegal and punishable by
204 law. Please purchase only authorized electronic editions and do not
205 participate in or encourage electronic piracy of copyrighted
206 materials. Your support of the author's rights is appreciated.
210 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
213 To Eric Eldred
—whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
218 <figure id=
"CreativeCommons">
219 <title>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved
</title>
220 <graphic fileref=
"images/cc.png"></graphic>
228 <title>List of figures
</title>
235 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
236 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
237 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
238 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
243 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
247 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
248 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
249 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
250 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
251 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
252 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
256 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
257 2 Architecture and Law: Force
258 2 Market: Concentration
261 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
262 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
263 2 Constraining Creators
264 2 Constraining Innovators
265 2 Corrupting Citizens
267 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
268 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
272 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
273 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
275 2 1. More Formalities
276 3 Registration and Renewal
279 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
280 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
281 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
287 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
289 <preface id=
"preface">
290 <title>PREFACE
</title>
291 <indexterm id=
"idxpoguedavid" class='startofrange'
>
292 <primary>Pogue, David
</primary>
295 At the end of his review of my first book, Code: And Other Laws of
296 Cyberspace, David Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless
297 technical and computer-related texts, wrote this:
301 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
302 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
303 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
304 system, you can always flip off the modem.
<footnote id=
"preface01"><para>
305 David Pogue, "Don't Just Chat, Do Something," New York Times,
30 January
2000.
310 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book
—that
311 software, or "code," functioned as a kind of law
—and his review
312 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
313 could always "drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome"-like simply flip a
314 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
315 any troubles that exist in that space wouldn't "affect" us anymore.
318 Pogue might have been right in
1999—I'm skeptical, but maybe.
319 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now: Free Culture
320 is about the troubles the Internet causes even after the modem is turned
321 <!-- PAGE BREAK 12 -->
322 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
323 on-line have fundamentally affected "people who aren't online." There
324 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
326 <indexterm startref=
"idxpoguedavid" class='endofrange'
/>
328 But unlike Code, the argument here is not much about the Internet
329 itself. It is instead about the consequence of the Internet to a part of
330 our tradition that is much more fundamental, and, as hard as this is for
331 a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more important.
334 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
335 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of "free culture"
—not
336 "free" as in "free beer" (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
337 free software movement
<footnote>
339 Richard M. Stallman, Free Software, Free Societies
57 (Joshua Gay, ed.
2002).
340 </para></footnote>), but "free" as in "free speech," "free markets," "free
341 trade," "free enterprise," "free will," and "free elections." A free
342 culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does this
343 directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
344 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
345 follow-on creators and innovators remain as free as possible from the
346 control of the past. A free culture is not a culture without property,
347 just as a free market is not a market in which everything is free. The
348 opposite of a free culture is a "permission culture"
—a culture in
349 which creators get to create only with the permission of the powerful,
350 or of creators from the past.
353 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not "we"
354 on the Left or "you" on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
355 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
356 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
357 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
358 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
359 culture deem fundamental.
361 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace
</primary></indexterm>
363 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
364 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
365 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
366 generated more than
700,
000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
367 As William Safire described marching "uncomfortably alongside CodePink
368 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
369 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens," he formulated perhaps
370 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
372 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
376 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
377 power
—political, corporate, media, cultural
—should be anathema to
378 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
379 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
380 the greatest expression of democracy.
<footnote><para> William Safire,
381 "The Great Media Gulp," New York Times,
22 May
2003.
382 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
387 This idea is an element of the argument of Free Culture, though my
388 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
389 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
390 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
391 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
392 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
393 you
—whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
394 Safire's left or on his right. The inspiration for the title and for
395 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
396 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
397 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in Free Software, Free
398 Society, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
399 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
400 that this work is "merely" derivative.
403 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
404 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
405 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
406 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
407 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
408 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
409 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
410 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
412 <!-- PAGE BREAK 14 -->
413 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
414 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
415 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
416 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
417 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
421 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
422 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
423 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
424 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
425 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
426 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
427 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
432 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
434 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
435 <chapter id=
"c-introduction">
436 <title>INTRODUCTION
</title>
438 On December
17,
1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
439 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
440 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
441 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
442 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
443 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
446 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
447 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
448 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
449 and all the space above, to "an indefinite extent, upwards."
<footnote><para>
450 St. George Tucker, Blackstone's Commentaries
3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
451 Rothman Reprints,
1969),
18.
454 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
455 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
456 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
459 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
460 law
—deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
461 by the most important legal thinkers of our past
—mattered. If
462 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
463 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
464 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
465 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
467 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
468 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
470 In
1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
471 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
472 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
473 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
474 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
475 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
476 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to "an indefinite
477 extent, upwards," then the government was trespassing on their
478 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
480 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
481 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
483 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
484 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
485 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
486 "taking" of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
487 that "it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
488 the land extended to the periphery of the universe." But Justice Douglas
489 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
490 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
494 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
495 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
496 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
497 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
498 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
499 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
500 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
501 the public has a just claim.
<footnote>
503 United States v. Causby, U.S.
328 (
1946):
256,
261. The Court did find
504 that there could be a "taking" if the government's use of its land
505 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
506 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, "(Intellectual)
507 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
508 Authorship," Stanford Law Review
48 (
1996):
1293,
1333. See also Paul
509 Goldstein, Real Property (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press,
1984),
511 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
512 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
517 "Common sense revolts at the idea."
520 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
521 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
522 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 18 -->
524 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: "Common sense revolts
525 at the idea." But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
526 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
527 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
528 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
530 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
531 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
533 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
534 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
535 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
536 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
537 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
538 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
539 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
540 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
541 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by "what
542 seemed reasonable" given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
543 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
544 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
545 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
546 end, the force of what seems "obvious" to everyone else
—the power of
547 "common sense"
—would prevail. Their "private interest" would not be
548 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
551 Edwin Howard Armstrong is one of America's forgotten inventor
552 geniuses. He came to the great American inventor scene just after the
553 titans Thomas Edison and Alexander Graham Bell. But his work in
554 the area of radio technology was perhaps the most important of any
555 single inventor in the first fifty years of radio. He was better educated
556 than Michael Faraday, who as a bookbinder's apprentice had discovered
557 electric induction in
1831. But he had the same intuition about
558 how the world of radio worked, and on at least three occasions,
559 Armstrong invented profoundly important technologies that advanced our
560 understanding of radio.
561 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
562 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham
</primary></indexterm>
563 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
564 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
567 On the day after Christmas,
1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
568 for his most significant invention
—FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
569 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
570 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
571 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
572 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
573 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
574 much less transmitter power and static.
577 On November
5,
1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
578 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
579 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
580 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
581 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
582 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
583 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
584 "This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
585 frequency modulation at two and a half meters."
588 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
592 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
593 sounded like a glass of water being poured. . . . A paper was crumpled
594 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
595 fire. . . . Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
596 and guitar number were performed. . . . The music was projected with a
597 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio "music
598 box."
<footnote><para>
599 Lawrence Lessing, Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong
600 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company,
1956),
209.
605 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
606 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
607 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
608 AM radio market. By
1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
609 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
610 a handful of networks.
611 <!-- PAGE BREAK 20 -->
614 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
615 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
616 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
617 that removed static from "radio." But when Armstrong demonstrated
618 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
619 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David
</primary></indexterm>
623 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
624 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
625 revolution
— start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
626 RCA.
<footnote><para> See "Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
627 Electronic Era," First Electronic Church of America, at
628 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
630 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
1</ulink>.
635 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
636 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
637 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
639 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David
</primary></indexterm>
643 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
644 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
645 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
646 unrestrained, posed . . . a complete reordering of radio power
647 . . . and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
648 on which RCA had grown to power.
<footnote><para>Lessing,
226.
653 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
654 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
655 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
656 FM radio's deployment generally. In
1936, RCA hired the former head
657 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
658 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM
—principally by moving FM
659 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
660 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
661 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
662 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
663 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
665 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
668 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
669 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
670 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
671 deviousness.
<footnote><para>
676 <indexterm><primary>AT
&T
</primary></indexterm>
678 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
679 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
680 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
681 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
682 (This change was strongly supported by AT
&T, because the loss of
683 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
684 wired links from AT
&T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
688 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
689 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
690 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
691 invalid
—baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
692 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
693 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
694 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
695 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
696 now broke, in
1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
697 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
700 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
701 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
702 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
703 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
704 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
705 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
706 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
707 course always public spirited; the reality is something
708 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
709 to themselves, would crumble in
710 <!-- PAGE BREAK 22 -->
711 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
712 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
713 effect of technological change.
716 There's no single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
717 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
718 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
719 Internet and American Life Project,
58 percent of Americans had access
720 to the Internet in
2002, up from
49 percent two years
721 before.
<footnote><para>
722 Amanda Lenhart, "The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
723 Internet Access and the Digital Divide," Pew Internet and American
724 Life Project,
15 April
2003:
6, available at
725 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
2</ulink>.
727 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
731 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
732 changed things. Some of these changes are technical
—the Internet has
733 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
734 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
735 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
736 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
737 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
738 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
739 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
742 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
743 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
744 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
745 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
746 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
747 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
751 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
752 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
753 regulation of each. By "commercial culture" I mean that part of our
754 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
755 "noncommercial culture" I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
757 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
758 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
759 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his "Reader," or
760 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
763 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
764 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
765 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
766 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
767 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
768 left this culture "free." The ordinary ways in which ordinary
769 individuals shared and transformed their culture
—telling
770 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
771 clubs, sharing music, making tapes
—were left alone by the law.
774 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
775 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
776 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
777 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
778 marketplace.
<footnote>
780 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
781 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
782 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
783 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
784 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
785 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
786 D. Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy," Harvard Law Review
4 (
1890):
193,
788 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
790 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
791 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
792 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
793 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
796 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
797 been erased.
<footnote><para>
798 See Jessica Litman, Digital Copyright (New York: Prometheus Books,
801 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
802 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
803 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
804 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
805 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
806 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
807 the balance of our history
—between uses of our culture that were
808 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission
—has
809 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
810 culture, more and more a permission culture.
812 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
814 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
815 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
816 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
817 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
818 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
819 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
820 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
821 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
822 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
823 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
827 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
828 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
829 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
830 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
831 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
832 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
833 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
834 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
835 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
836 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
837 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
838 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
839 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
840 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
841 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
842 than creators do today
—all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
843 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
846 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
847 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
848 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
849 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
850 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
851 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
855 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
856 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
857 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
858 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions
—whether "piracy" will
859 be permitted, and whether "property" will be protected. The "war" that
860 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet
—what
861 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
862 calls his "own terrorist war"
<footnote><para>
863 Amy Harmon, "Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
864 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club," New York
865 Times,
17 January
2002.
866 </para></footnote>—has been framed as a battle about the
867 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
868 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
872 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
873 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
874 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
875 "creative property." I believe that "piracy" is wrong, and that the
876 law, properly tuned, should punish "piracy," whether on or off the
880 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
881 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
882 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet "pirates" will also rid our
883 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
886 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first
180 years of
887 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
888 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
889 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
890 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,
<footnote>
892 Neil W. Netanel, "Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society," Yale Law
893 Journal
106 (
1996):
283.
894 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
896 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
897 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
898 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
899 could cultivate and extend our culture.
902 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
903 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
904 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
905 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist
–like,
906 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
907 granted
—but it is not often granted to the critical or the
908 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
909 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
910 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
912 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Should "Is it" be "It is" ? -->
914 The story that follows is about this war. Is it not about the
915 "centrality of technology" to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
916 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
917 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
918 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
922 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
923 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
924 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
925 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
926 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
927 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
928 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
930 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
931 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
933 Like the Causbys' battle, this war is, in part, about "property." The
934 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
935 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
936 this "property" are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
937 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
938 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
939 of "intellectual property" now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
940 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
941 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
942 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
943 "trespassing" upon legitimate claims of "property." It is as plain to
944 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
947 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
948 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
950 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
951 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
952 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
953 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
955 <!-- PAGE BREAK 27 -->
956 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
960 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
961 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
962 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
963 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
964 our "culture" was as "owned" as it is now. And yet there has never
965 been a time when the concentration of power to control the uses of
966 culture has been as unquestioningly accepted as it is now.
969 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
970 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
971 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
972 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
975 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
976 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
979 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
980 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
981 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
982 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
983 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
986 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
987 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
988 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
989 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
992 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
993 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
995 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
996 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
997 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
998 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of "intellectual
999 property." What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1000 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1001 this silliness will be much more profound.
1002 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1005 The struggle that rages just now centers on two ideas: "piracy" and
1006 "property." My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1010 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1011 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1012 obscure French theorists
—however natural that is for the weird
1013 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1014 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1015 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1018 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1019 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1020 government, pushed by big media to respond to this "something new," is
1021 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1022 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let "common
1023 sense" resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1024 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1025 law
—and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1026 fundamental about who we have always been.
1029 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1030 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1031 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1032 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1033 of one more consequence of this form of corruption
—a consequence
1034 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1037 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1038 <chapter id=
"c-piracy">
1039 <title>"PIRACY"</title>
1041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1042 <indexterm id=
"idxmansfield1" class='startofrange'
>
1043 <primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord
</primary>
1046 Since the inception of the law regulating creative property, there has
1047 been a war against "piracy." The precise contours of this concept,
1048 "piracy," are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1049 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1050 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1054 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1055 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1056 of them for his own use.
<footnote><para>
1058 Bach v. Longman,
98 Eng. Rep.
1274 (
1777) (Mansfield).
1061 <indexterm startref=
"idxmansfield1" class='endofrange'
/>
1064 Today we are in the middle of another "war" against "piracy." The
1065 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1066 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1067 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1068 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1069 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1070 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1073 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1074 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1075 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1076 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1077 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will "rob the author of the
1081 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1082 increasingly to technology to defend their "property" against this
1083 "piracy." A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1084 raised to believe that "property" should be "free." Forget tattoos,
1085 never mind body piercing
—our kids are becoming thieves!
1088 There's no doubt that "piracy" is wrong, and that pirates should be
1089 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1090 notion of "piracy" in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1091 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1094 The idea goes something like this:
1098 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1099 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1100 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1101 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1102 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1106 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle
</primary></indexterm>
1108 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1109 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the "if value, then right"
1110 theory of creative property
<footnote><para>
1112 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, "Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1113 in the Pepsi Generation," Notre Dame Law Review
65 (
1990):
397.
1115 —if there is value, then someone must have a
1116 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1117 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1118 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.
<footnote><para>
1120 Lisa Bannon, "The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1121 Up," Wall Street Journal,
21 August
1996, available at
1122 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
3</ulink>; Jonathan
1123 Zittrain, "Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1124 Speech, No One Wins," Boston Globe,
24 November
2002.
1125 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
1127 There was "value" (the songs) so there must have been a
1128 "right"
—even against the Girl Scouts.
1130 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP
</primary></indexterm>
1132 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1133 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1134 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1135 of law protecting creative property. But the "if value, then right"
1136 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1137 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1140 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1141 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1142 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1143 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1144 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1147 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1148 takes care to draw
—the distinction between republishing someone's
1149 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1150 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1151 copyright law today regulates both.
1154 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1155 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1156 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1157 entities could bear the burden of the law
—even the burden of the
1158 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1159 more expense of doing business.
1161 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
1163 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1164 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1165 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1166 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1167 "copying," when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1168 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1169 outweighs any original benefit
—certainly as it affects
1170 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1171 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1172 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1173 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1174 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1175 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1176 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1177 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1178 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1179 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the "Rise of the Creative Class."
<footnote>
1182 In The Rise of the Creative Class (New York: Basic Books,
2002),
1183 Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of labor toward a
1184 labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't directly address the
1185 legal conditions under which that creativity is enabled or stifled. I
1186 certainly agree with him about the importance and significance of this
1187 change, but I also believe the conditions under which it will be
1188 enabled are much more tenuous.
1189 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
1191 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1192 this creative class.
1195 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1196 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1197 context the current battles about behavior labeled "piracy."
1200 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1201 <sect1 id=
"creators">
1202 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators
</title>
1204 In
1928, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1205 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called Plane Crazy.
1206 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1207 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, Steamboat Willie brought
1208 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1211 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1212 movie The Jazz Singer. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1213 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1214 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1215 Disney ran a test in the summer of
1928, the results were unambiguous.
1216 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1220 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1221 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1222 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1223 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1224 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1227 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1228 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1229 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1230 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1231 synchronization was pretty close.
1234 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1235 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1236 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1237 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1238 it was something new!
<footnote><para>
1240 Leonard Maltin, Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1241 Cartoons (New York: Penguin Books,
1987),
34–35.
1246 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1247 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: "I have never been so thrilled
1248 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it."
1249 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub
</primary></indexterm>
1252 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1253 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1254 rarely
—except in Disney's hands
—been anything more than
1255 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1256 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1257 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1258 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1261 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that
1928 also
1262 marks another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed
1263 to cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1264 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was Steamboat Bill, Jr.
1267 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in
1895. In the era of
1268 silent film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to
1269 spark uncontrollable laughter from his audience. Steamboat Bill, Jr. was
1270 a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its incredible stunts.
1271 The film was classic Keaton
—wildly popular and among the best of its
1275 Steamboat Bill, Jr. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat Willie.
1276 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1277 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1278 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,
<footnote><para>
1280 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1281 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
4</ulink>.
1282 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1283 use the music for five songs in Steamboat Willie: "Steamboat Bill," "The
1284 Simpleton" (Delille), "Mischief Makers" (Carbonara), "Joyful Hurry No.
1"
1285 (Baron), and "Gawky Rube" (Lakay). A sixth song, "The Turkey in the
1286 Straw," was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1287 Harry Surden,
10 July
2003, on file with author.
1289 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1290 the invention of synchronized sound in The Jazz Singer that we get
1291 Steamboat Willie. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1292 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song "Steamboat Bill,"
1293 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1297 This "borrowing" was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1298 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1299 films of his day.
<footnote><para>
1301 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, "The Mouse
1302 that Ate the Public Domain," Findlaw,
5 March
2002, at
1303 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
5</ulink>.
1305 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1306 knockoffs
—slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1307 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1308 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1309 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1310 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1311 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1312 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1316 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1317 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1318 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1319 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1320 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1321 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1322 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1325 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1326 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1327 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1328 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1329 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1330 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1331 work of others is astonishing when set together: Snow White (
1937),
1332 Fantasia (
1940), Pinocchio (
1940), Dumbo (
1941), Bambi (
1942), Song of
1333 the South (
1946), Cinderella (
1950), Alice in Wonderland (
1951), Robin
1334 Hood (
1952), Peter Pan (
1953), Lady and the Tramp
1335 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1336 (
1955), Mulan (
1998), Sleeping Beauty (
1959),
101 Dalmatians (
1961),
1337 The Sword in the Stone (
1963), and The Jungle Book (
1967)
—not to
1338 mention a recent example that we should perhaps quickly forget,
1339 Treasure Planet (
2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney,
1340 Inc.) ripped creativity from the culture around him, mixed that
1341 creativity with his own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix
1342 into the soul of his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1345 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1346 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1347 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1348 its importance. We could call this "Disney creativity," though that
1349 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, "Walt Disney
1350 creativity"
—a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1351 culture around us and makes it something different.
1353 <para> In
1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1354 relatively fresh. The public domain in
1928 was not very old and was
1355 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1356 thirty years
—for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1357 copyrighted.
<footnote><para>
1359 Until
1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1360 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the "average" term by
1362 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1363 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if
100 copyrights are registered in year
1364 1, and only
15 are renewed, and the renewal term is
28 years, then the
1366 term is
32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1367 Web site associated with this book, available at
1368 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
6</ulink>.
1370 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1371 copyright holders of a creative work had an "exclusive right" to control
1372 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1373 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1376 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1377 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1378 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a "lawyer-free
1379 zone." Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1380 for Disney to use and build upon in
1928. It was free for
1381 anyone
— whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1382 approved or not
—to use and build upon.
1385 This is the ways things always were
—until quite recently. For most
1386 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1387 until
1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1388 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1390 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1391 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1392 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the
1960s and
1970s
1393 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1394 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1395 content from before the Great Depression.
1398 Of course, Walt Disney had no monopoly on "Walt Disney creativity."
1399 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1400 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1404 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1405 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: manga, or
1406 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some
40 percent of
1407 publications are comics, and
30 percent of publication revenue derives
1408 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1409 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1410 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1413 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1414 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1415 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1416 the stories that these "graphic novels" tell. For the Japanese, manga
1417 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are "men in tights."
1418 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1419 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1420 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1421 interestingly different way.
1424 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1425 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1426 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1429 This is the phenomenon of doujinshi. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1430 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1431 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is just a copy; the artist must make a
1432 contribution to the art he copies, by transforming it either subtly or
1433 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1434 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1435 develop it differently
—with a different story line. Or the comic can
1436 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1437 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently "different." But they
1438 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1439 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1440 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1443 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1444 huge. More than
33,
000 "circles" of creators from across Japan produce
1445 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than
450,
000 Japanese come
1446 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1447 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1448 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1449 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1450 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1451 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1454 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1455 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1456 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1457 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1458 one. Doujinshi are plainly "derivative works." There is no general
1459 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1460 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1461 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with Steamboat Bill, Jr. Under
1462 both Japanese and American law, that "taking" without the permission
1463 of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an infringement of
1464 the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative work without the
1465 original copyright owner's permission.
1467 <indexterm id=
"idxwinickjudd" class='startofrange'
>
1468 <primary>Winick, Judd
</primary>
1471 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1472 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1473 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, "The
1474 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1475 in Japan now. . . . American comics were born out of copying each
1476 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1477 other. . . . That's how [the artists] learn to draw
—by going into comic
1478 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them"
1479 and building from them.
<footnote><para>
1481 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, Reinventing Comics (New
1482 York: Perennial,
2000).
1486 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1487 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1488 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, "there are these rules
1489 and you have to stick to them." There are things Superman "cannot"
1490 do. "As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1491 which are fifty years old."
1493 <indexterm startref=
"idxwinickjudd" class='endofrange'
/>
1495 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1496 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1497 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1498 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1499 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1500 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1501 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.
<footnote><para>
1503 See Salil K. Mehra, "Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1504 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?" Rutgers Law
1505 Review
55 (
2002):
155,
182. "[T]here might be a collective economic
1506 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1507 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1508 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1509 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1510 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved."
1514 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1515 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1516 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1517 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1518 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1519 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1520 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1521 a more general pattern of blocking this "free taking" by the doujinshi
1525 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1526 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1527 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. "We don't have enough
1528 lawyers," he told me one afternoon. There "just aren't enough resources
1529 to prosecute cases like this."
1532 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1533 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1534 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1535 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1536 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1537 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1538 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1539 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1540 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1541 their clients or hurt them?
1542 Let's pause for a moment.
1545 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1546 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1547 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1550 We live in a world that celebrates "property." I am one of those
1551 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1552 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1553 "intellectual property."
<footnote><para>
1555 The term intellectual property is of relatively recent origin. See
1556 Siva Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs,
11 (New York: New York
1557 University Press,
2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, The Future of Ideas
1558 (New York: Random House,
2001),
293 n.
26. The term accurately
1559 describes a set of "property" rights
—copyright, patents,
1560 trademark, and trade-secret
—but the nature of those rights is
1563 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1564 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1568 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1569 plenty of value out there that "property" doesn't capture. I don't
1570 mean "money can't buy you love," but rather, value that is plainly
1571 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1572 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1573 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1574 condemning that taking as wrong
— even though trivial, even if
1575 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1576 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1577 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1578 Disney's use would have been considered "fair." There was nothing
1579 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1583 Thus, even though the things that Disney took
—or more generally,
1584 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity
—are
1585 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1587 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1588 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1592 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1593 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1594 work
—or even one copy
—without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1595 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1596 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1597 form, whether large or small.
1600 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1601 say that the copycat comic artists are "stealing." This form of Walt
1602 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1603 particular find it hard to say why.
1606 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1607 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1608 without asking or paying for the privilege. ("Excuse me, Professor
1609 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1610 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?") Acting companies
1611 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1612 permission from anyone. (Does anyone believe Shakespeare would be
1613 better spread within our culture if there were a central Shakespeare
1614 rights clearinghouse that all productions of Shakespeare must appeal
1615 to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles with a certain kind of
1616 movie: five asteroid films in the late
1990s; two volcano disaster
1620 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1621 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1622 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1623 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1624 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1625 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1626 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking
—free
1627 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1628 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1631 The hard question is therefore not whether a culture is free. All
1632 cultures are free to some degree. The hard question instead is "How
1633 free is this culture?" How much, and how broadly, is the culture free
1634 for others to take and build upon? Is that freedom limited to party
1635 members? To members of the royal family? To the top ten corporations
1636 on the New York Stock Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To
1637 artists generally, whether affiliated with the Met or not? To
1638 musicians generally, whether white or not? To filmmakers generally,
1639 whether affiliated with a studio or not?
1642 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1643 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1644 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1647 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1649 <sect1 id=
"mere-copyists">
1650 <title>CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
</title>
1651 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis
</primary></indexterm>
1653 In
1839, Louis Daguerre invented the first practical technology for
1654 producing what we would call "photographs." Appropriately enough, they
1655 were called "daguerreotypes." The process was complicated and
1656 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1657 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1658 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1659 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1662 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1663 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1664 "automatic pictures." William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1665 making "negatives." But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1666 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1667 the
1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1668 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1669 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1672 <indexterm id=
"idxeastmangeorge" class='startofrange'
>
1673 <primary>Eastman, George
</primary>
1676 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1677 didn't happen until
1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1678 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1679 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1680 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1681 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1682 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1683 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1684 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1685 population of photographers.
1688 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1689 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1690 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. "You press the button and we
1691 do the rest."
<footnote><para>
1693 Reese V. Jenkins, Images and Enterprise (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1975),
112.
1694 </para></footnote> As he described in The Kodak Primer:
1698 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1699 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1700 that only an expert can do. . . . We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1701 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1702 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1703 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1704 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1705 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1706 chemicals.
<footnote>
1709 Brian Coe, The Birth of Photography (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1711 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian
</primary></indexterm>
1716 For $
25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1717 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1718 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1719 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1720 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1721 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in
1888; one
1722 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1723 From
1888 through
1909, while industrial production was rising by
4.7
1724 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by
1725 percent.
<footnote><para>
1728 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1729 an average annual increase of over
17 percent.
<footnote><para>
1731 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p.
178.
1734 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian
</primary></indexterm>
1737 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1738 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1739 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1740 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1741 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1742 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, "For the
1743 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1744 permanent record of his family and its activities. . . . For the first
1745 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1746 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1747 interpretation or bias."
<footnote><para>
1753 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1754 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1755 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1756 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1757 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1758 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its "quality";
1759 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1760 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1761 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1762 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1766 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1767 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1768 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1769 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1770 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1771 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1772 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1773 he wanted. Their answer was no.
<footnote><para>
1775 For illustrative cases, see, for example, Pavesich v. N.E. Life Ins. Co.,
50 S.E.
1779 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1780 familiar. The photographer was "taking" something from the person or
1781 building whose photograph he shot
—pirating something of
1782 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1783 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1785 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1786 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1787 that they thought valuable.
1789 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
1791 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1792 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1793 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1794 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1795 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.
<footnote>
1798 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy,"
1799 Harvard Law Review
4 (
1890):
193.
1800 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
1801 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.
</primary></indexterm>
1802 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1803 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1804 Steamboat Bill, Jr. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1805 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1808 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1809 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1810 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1811 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1812 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1813 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1814 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1815 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1816 clearing the rights to do the capturing.
<footnote><para>
1818 See Melville B. Nimmer, "The Right of Publicity," Law and Contemporary
1819 Problems
19 (
1954):
203; William L. Prosser, "Privacy," California Law
1820 Review
48 (
1960)
398–407; White v. Samsung Electronics America,
1821 Inc.,
971 F.
2d
1395 (
9th Cir.
1992), cert. denied,
508 U.S.
951
1826 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1827 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1828 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1829 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1830 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1831 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1832 Kodak would be benefiting from the "theft" committed by the
1833 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1834 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1835 from the "image-right" infringement of its photographers. We could
1836 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1837 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1838 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1842 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
1843 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
1844 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
1845 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
1846 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
1847 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
1848 technology as they did
—since professionals could have more
1849 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
1850 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
1851 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
1852 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
1853 realized. If you drive through San Francisco's Presidio, you might
1854 see two gaudy yellow school buses painted over with colorful and
1855 striking images, and the logo "Just Think!" in place of the name of a
1856 school. But there's little that's "just" cerebral in the projects that
1857 these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies that
1858 teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even the
1859 film of your VCR. Rather the "film" of digital cameras. Just Think!
1860 is a project that enables kids to make films, as a way to understand
1861 and critique the filmed culture that they find all around them. Each
1862 year, these busses travel to more than thirty schools and enable three
1863 hundred to five hundred children to learn something about media by
1864 doing something with media. By doing, they think. By tinkering, they
1867 <indexterm startref=
"idxeastmangeorge" class='endofrange'
/>
1869 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
1870 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
1871 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, "Five years ago, a good
1872 real-time digital video editing system cost $
25,
000. Today you can get
1873 professional quality for $
595."
<footnote><para>
1875 H. Edward Goldberg, "Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
1876 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,"
1877 cadalyst, February
2002, available at
1878 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
7</ulink>.
1880 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
1881 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
1882 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
1883 learning more and more of something teachers call "media literacy."
1886 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
1887 "Media literacy," as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
1888 Think!, puts it, "is the ability . . . to understand, analyze, and
1889 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
1890 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
1891 the way people access it."
1892 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave
</primary></indexterm>
1895 This may seem like an odd way to think about "literacy." For most
1896 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
1897 and noticing split infinitives are the things that "literate" people know
1901 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average
390 hours of
1902 television commercials per year, or between
20,
000 and
45,
000
1903 commercials generally,
<footnote><para>
1905 Judith Van Evra, Television and Child Development (Hillsdale, N.J.:
1906 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates,
1990); "Findings on Family and TV
1907 Study," Denver Post,
25 May
1997, B6.
1909 it is increasingly important to understand the "grammar" of media. For
1910 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
1911 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
1912 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
1913 (at least at first) terrible media.
1916 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
1917 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
1918 has written understands how difficult writing is
—how difficult
1919 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
1920 language to be understandable
—few of us have any real sense of
1921 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
1922 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
1923 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
1926 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
1927 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
1928 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
1929 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
1930 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
1931 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
1933 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
1935 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
1936 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
1937 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
1939 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
1940 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
1941 about "the placement of objects, color, . . . rhythm, pacing, and
1945 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish,
13 December
1947 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
1948 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth
</primary></indexterm>
1950 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
1951 "played" as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
1952 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
1953 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
1954 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
1955 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
1956 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
1957 to a wildly successful author.
<footnote><para>
1959 See Scott Steinberg, "Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs," E!online,
4
1960 November
2000, available at
1961 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
8</ulink>; "Timeline,"
22 November
2000,
1963 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
9</ulink>.
1966 <indexterm><primary>computer games
</primary></indexterm>
1968 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
1969 describes, "people are very surprised about how they are led through a
1970 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
1971 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
1972 led." If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
1975 Yet the push for an expanded literacy
—one that goes beyond text
1976 to include audio and visual elements
—is not about making better
1977 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
1978 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
1982 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
1983 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
1984 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
1985 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
1990 "Read-only." Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
1991 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
1995 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
1996 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
1997 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
1998 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2000 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2001 and this literacy in particular, is to "empower people to choose the
2002 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2006 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2007 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2008 </para></footnote> It is to enable students "to communicate in the
2009 language of the twenty-first century."
<footnote><para>
2014 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2016 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2017 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2018 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2019 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2020 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2021 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2022 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2023 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2024 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2025 students know something about
—gun violence.
2028 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2029 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2030 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2031 away. The "kids were showing up at
6 A.M. and leaving at
5 at night,"
2032 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2033 what education should be about
—learning how to express themselves.
2036 Using whatever "free web stuff they could find," and relatively simple
2037 tools to enable the kids to mix "image, sound, and text," Barish said
2038 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2039 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2040 close to the lives of these students. The project "gave them a tool
2041 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2042 it," Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2043 expression
—far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2044 been created using only text. "If you had said to these students, `you
2045 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2046 gone and done something else," Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2047 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2048 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which these ideas can be
2049 expressed well. The power of this message depended upon its connection
2050 to this form of expression.
2054 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2055 "But isn't education about teaching kids to write?" I asked. In part,
2056 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2057 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of "constructing
2058 meaning." To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2059 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2060 part
—and increasingly, not the most powerful part
—of
2061 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2066 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2067 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2068 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2069 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2070 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2071 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2072 you say, "Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters."
2073 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2074 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2075 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, "Well, with all these things that you
2076 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2077 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2078 for me something that reflects that." Not by giving a kid a video
2079 camera and . . . saying, "Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2080 make a little movie." But instead, really help you take these elements
2081 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2082 about the topic. . . .
2085 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2086 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2087 bump up against the fact, "I need to explain this and I really need
2088 to write something." And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2089 they would rewrite a paragraph
5,
6,
7,
8 times, till they got it right.
2092 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2093 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2094 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2095 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2096 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2097 had a lot of power with this language."
2101 When two planes crashed into the World Trade Center, another into the
2102 Pentagon, and a fourth into a Pennsylvania field, all media around the
2103 world shifted to this news. Every moment of just about every day for
2104 that week, and for weeks after, television in particular, and media
2105 generally, retold the story of the events we had just witnessed. The
2106 telling was a retelling, because we had seen the events that were
2107 described. The genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the
2108 delayed second attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole
2109 world would be watching.
2112 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2113 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2114 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was "balance,"
2115 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2116 increasingly come to expect it, "news as entertainment," even if the
2117 entertainment is tragedy.
2119 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
2120 <indexterm><primary>CBS
</primary></indexterm>
2122 But in addition to this produced news about the "tragedy of September
2123 11," those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2124 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2125 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2126 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2127 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2128 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2129 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2130 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2131 the term in his book Cyber Rights, around a news event that had
2132 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2133 was also the Internet.
2136 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet
—though I do think the
2137 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2138 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2139 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2141 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2142 by a student on the "Just Think!" bus, the visual images could be mixed
2146 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2147 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2148 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2149 tradition
—not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2150 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2151 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2152 spread practically instantaneously.
2155 September
11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around
2156 the same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically
2157 was just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2158 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures, such
2159 as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those cultures, it
2160 records private facts in a public way
—it's a kind of electronic Jerry
2161 Springer, available anywhere in the world.
2164 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2165 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2166 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2167 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2168 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2169 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2170 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2171 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2172 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2173 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2174 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2175 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2178 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2179 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2180 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2181 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2182 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2184 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2185 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2186 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2189 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2190 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2191 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2192 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2193 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2194 most important account of early "Democracy in America." It wasn't
2195 popular elections that fascinated him
—it was the jury, an
2196 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2197 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2198 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2199 deliberated. Members argued about the "right" result; they tried to
2200 persuade each other of the "right" result, and in criminal cases at
2201 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2202 come to an end.
<footnote><para>
2204 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, bk.
1, trans.
2205 Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books,
2000), ch.
16.
2209 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2210 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2211 are pushing to create just such an institution.
<footnote><para>
2213 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, "Deliberation Day," Journal of
2214 Political Philosophy
10 (
2) (
2002):
129.
2216 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2217 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2218 place for "democratic deliberation" to occur.
2221 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2222 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2223 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2224 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2225 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2226 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.
<footnote><para>
2228 Cass Sunstein, Republic.com (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2001),
2229 65–80,
175,
182,
183,
192.
2230 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2231 little beyond what our friends say.
2234 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2235 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2236 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2237 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2238 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2240 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2241 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2245 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2246 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2247 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2248 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2249 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2250 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2253 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2254 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the
2004 presidential race
2255 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2256 is having an effect.
2259 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2260 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2261 "misspoke" at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2262 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2263 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2264 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2265 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2266 more instances of the same "misspeaking" emerged. Finally, the story
2267 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2268 resign as senate majority leader.
<footnote><para>
2270 Noah Shachtman, "With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot," New
2271 York Times,
16 January
2003, G5.
2275 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2276 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2277 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2278 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2282 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2283 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2284 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2285 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2286 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2287 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2288 peer-generated rankings.
2290 <indexterm id=
"idxwinerdave" class='startofrange'
>
2291 <primary>Winer, Dave
</primary>
2294 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2295 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2296 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2297 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2298 difference is the absence of a financial "conflict of interest." "I think you
2299 have to take the conflict of interest" out of journalism, Winer told me.
2300 "An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2301 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2302 get it out of the way."
2304 <indexterm><primary>CNN
</primary></indexterm>
2306 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2307 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2308 from the public than an unconcentrated media can
—as CNN admitted
2309 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2310 its own employees.
<footnote><para>
2312 Telephone interview with David Winer,
16 April
2003.
2314 It also needs to sustain a more coherent
2315 account. (In the middle of the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet
2316 from someone who was at that time listening to a satellite uplink with
2317 a reporter in Iraq. The New York headquarters was telling the reporter
2318 over and over that her account of the war was too bleak: She needed to
2319 offer a more optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't
2320 warranted, they told her that they were writing "the story.")
2322 <para> Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2323 debate
—"amateur" not in the sense of inexperienced, but in the
2324 sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to give their
2325 reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a story, as
2326 reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds from across
2327 the southwest United States turned to the Internet to retell what they
2328 had seen.
<footnote><para>
2330 John Schwartz, "Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2331 Information Online," New York Times,
2 February
2003, A28; Staci
2332 D. Kramer, "Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,"
2333 Online Journalism Review,
2 February
2003, available at
2334 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
10</ulink>.
2336 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2337 "triangulate," as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2338 "communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2339 out of it"
—with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2342 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2343 with blogs. "It's going to become an essential skill," Winer predicts,
2344 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2345 not clear that "journalism" is happy about this
—some journalists
2346 have been told to curtail their blogging.
<footnote>
2349 See Michael Falcone, "Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?" New
2350 York Times,
29 September
2003, C4. ("Not all news organizations have
2351 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2352 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2353 war on March
9, stopped posting
12 days later at his bosses'
2354 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a Houston Chronicle reporter, was
2355 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2356 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.")
2357 <indexterm><primary>CNN
</primary></indexterm>
2359 But it is clear that we are still in transition. "A
2361 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2362 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises," Winer told me.
2363 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2364 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2365 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, "we will
2366 be the last thing that gets shut down."
2369 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because "you
2370 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper."
2371 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2372 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2373 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2374 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2375 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2376 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2377 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2378 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2379 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2380 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2381 extraordinary to report.
2383 <indexterm startref=
"idxwinerdave" class='endofrange'
/>
2384 <indexterm id=
"idxbrownjohnseely" class='startofrange'
>
2385 <primary>Brown, John Seely
</primary>
2388 John Seely Brown is the chief scientist of the Xerox Corporation.
2389 His work, as his Web site describes it, is "human learning and . . . the
2390 creation of knowledge ecologies for creating . . . innovation."
2393 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2394 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2395 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2396 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2400 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When "a lot of us grew up,"
2401 he explains, that tinkering was done "on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2402 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on." But digital technologies
2403 enable a different kind of tinkering
—with abstract ideas though
2404 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2405 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2406 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2407 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2408 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2409 or "free collage," as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2410 the tinkering of many others.
2413 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2414 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2415 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2416 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2417 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2420 This opportunity creates a "completely new kind of learning platform,"
2421 as Brown describes. "As soon as you start doing that, you . . .
2422 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2423 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2424 if they can improve it." Each effort is a kind of
2425 apprenticeship. "Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform."
2428 In this process, "the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2429 They are code." Kids are "shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2430 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2431 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2432 platform. . . . You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2433 you tinker the more you improve." The more you improve, the more you
2437 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2438 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2439 it, "the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2440 intelligence." Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2441 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2442 text. "The Web . . . says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2443 you are visual, if you are interested in film . . . [then] there is a
2444 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2445 these multiple forms of intelligence."
2447 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2449 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2450 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2452 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2453 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2454 kind of recognition.
2457 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2458 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2459 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2460 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2461 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2462 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2463 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2466 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2467 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2468 10) has developed a powerful argument in favor of the "right to
2469 tinker" as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2470 general.
<footnote><para>
2472 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, "Technological Access
2473 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship," Communications
2474 of the Association for Computer Machinery
43 (
2000):
9.
2476 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2477 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2480 "This is where education in the twenty-first century is going," Brown
2481 explains. We need to "understand how kids who grow up digital think
2485 "Yet," as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2486 evince, "we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2487 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. . . . We're building an
2488 architecture that unleashes
60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2489 system that closes down that part of the brain."
2491 <indexterm startref=
"idxbrownjohnseely" class='endofrange'
/>
2493 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2494 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2495 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2496 the law to close down that technology.
2499 "No way to run a culture," as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2500 chapter
9, quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2502 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2504 <sect1 id=
"catalogs">
2505 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
</title>
2507 In the fall of
2002, Jesse Jordan of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as
2508 a freshman at Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York.
2509 His major at RPI was information technology. Though he is not a
2510 programmer, in October Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search
2511 engine technology that was available on the RPI network.
2514 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2515 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2516 to information sciences. More than
65 percent of its five thousand
2517 undergraduates finished in the top
10 percent of their high school
2518 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2519 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2522 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2523 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2524 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2525 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2526 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2529 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2530 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2531 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2532 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2533 engines can do this even better. The idea of "intranet" search
2534 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2535 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2536 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2537 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2538 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2541 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2542 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2543 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2544 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2545 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2546 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2547 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2550 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2551 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2552 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2553 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2554 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2555 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2556 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2557 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2558 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2562 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2563 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2564 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2565 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2566 be on users' computers.
2569 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2570 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2571 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2572 might have created; university brochures
—basically anything that
2573 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2574 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2578 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2579 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2580 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and
—so that this
2581 point is absolutely clear
—Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2582 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2583 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2584 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2585 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2586 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2587 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2588 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2589 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2593 On April
3,
2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2594 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2595 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2596 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2597 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2598 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2599 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2602 "It was absurd," he told me. "I don't think I did anything
2603 wrong. . . . I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2604 engine that I ran or . . . what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2605 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2606 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2607 easier to use"
—again, a search engine, which Jesse had not
2608 himself built, using the Windows filesharing system, which Jesse had
2609 not himself built, to enable members of the RPI community to get
2610 access to content, which Jesse had not himself created or posted, and
2611 the vast majority of which had nothing to do with music.
2614 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2615 network and had therefore "willfully" violated copyright laws. They
2616 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2617 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2618 "willful infringement," the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2619 call "statutory damages." These damages permit a copyright owner to
2620 claim $
150,
000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2621 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2622 Jesse pay them at least $
15,
000,
000.
2625 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one
2626 other student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2627 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2628 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2629 huge demands for "damages" that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2630 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2631 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $
100 billion
—six
2632 times the total profit of the film industry in
2001.
<footnote><para>
2634 Tim Goral, "Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-
2-P Networks:
2635 Suit Alleges $
97.8 Billion in Damages," Professional Media Group LCC
6
2636 (
2003):
5, available at
2003 WL
55179443.
2640 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2641 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2642 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2643 $
12,
000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2644 $
12,
000 to dismiss the case.
2647 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2648 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2649 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2650 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2651 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2652 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2653 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, "You don't want to pay another
2654 visit to a dentist like me.") And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2655 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2658 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2659 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2660 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2661 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2662 at least $
250,
000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2663 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2664 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2665 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2668 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $
250,
000 and a chance at winning,
2669 or $
12,
000 and a settlement.
2672 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2673 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2674 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2675 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2676 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $
1 million a year.
2677 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2678 artist makes $
45,
900.
<footnote><para>
2680 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (
2001)
2681 (
27–2042—Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2682 the Arts, More Than One in a Blue Moon (
2000).
2684 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2685 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2686 student for running a search engine?
<footnote><para>
2688 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in "KaZaA and Punishment,"
2689 Wall Street Journal,
10 September
2003, A24.
2693 On June
23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2694 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2695 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $
15 million lawsuit became an
2700 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2701 an activist. . . . [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2702 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2703 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2707 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2708 his father told me, Jesse "considers himself very conservative, and so do
2709 I. . . . He's not a tree hugger. . . . I think it's bizarre that they would
2710 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2711 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record."
2713 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
2715 <sect1 id=
"pirates">
2716 <title>CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
</title>
2718 If "piracy" means using the creative property of others without
2719 their permission
—if "if value, then right" is true
—then the history of
2720 the content industry is a history of piracy. Every important sector of
2721 "big media" today
—film, records, radio, and cable TV
—was born of a
2722 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last generation's
2723 pirates join this generation's country club
—until now.
2728 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.
<footnote><para>
2730 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
2731 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs,
87–93,
2732 which details Edison's "adventures" with copyright and patent.
2734 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
2735 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
2736 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
2737 exercised through a monopoly "trust," the Motion Pictures Patents
2738 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
2739 property
—patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
2740 this creative property
2741 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
2742 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
2745 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
2749 A January
1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
2750 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
2751 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
2752 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
2753 summer of
1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
2754 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
2755 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
2758 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
2759 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
2760 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
2761 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
2762 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
2763 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
2764 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
2765 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
2766 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
2767 license was revoked.
<footnote><para>
2769 J. A. Aberdeen, Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
2770 Picture Producers (Cobblestone Entertainment,
2000) and expanded texts
2771 posted at "The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
2772 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws," available at
2773 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
11</ulink>. For a
2774 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
2775 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, "From
2776 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
2777 the Propertization of Copyright" (September
2002), University of
2778 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
2779 Working Paper No.
159.
</para></footnote>
2780 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company
</primary></indexterm>
2781 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
2785 The Napsters of those days, the "independents," were companies like
2786 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
2787 resisted. "Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
2788 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
2789 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred."
<footnote><para>
2791 Marc Wanamaker, "The First Studios," The Silents Majority, archived at
2792 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
12</ulink>.
2794 That led the independents to flee the East
2795 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
2796 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
2797 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
2801 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
2802 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
2803 patent holder a truly "limited" monopoly (just seventeen years at that
2805 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
2806 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
2807 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
2808 Edison's creative property.
2811 <sect2 id=
"recordedmusic">
2812 <title>Recorded Music
</title>
2814 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
2815 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
2818 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
2819 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
2820 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
2821 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
2822 their music. In other words, in
1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
2823 1899 hit "Happy Mose," the law said I would have to pay for the right
2824 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
2825 right to perform it publicly.
2827 <indexterm><primary>Beatles
</primary></indexterm>
2829 But what if I wanted to record "Happy Mose," using Edison's phonograph
2830 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
2831 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
2832 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
2833 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
2834 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
2835 "public performance" if I recorded the song in my own house (even
2836 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
2837 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
2838 brain are not
—yet
— regulated by copyright law). So if I
2839 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
2840 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
2841 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
2842 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
2843 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
2844 its composer anything.
2847 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
2848 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
2849 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
2854 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
2855 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
2856 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
2857 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
2858 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
2859 rights.
<footnote><para>
2861 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
2862 S.
6330 and H.R.
19853 Before the ( Joint) Committees on Patents,
59th
2863 Cong.
59,
1st sess. (
1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
2864 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in Legislative History of the
2865 Copyright Act, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
2866 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints,
1976).
2871 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
2872 people's works were "sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
2873 genius of American composers,"
<footnote><para>
2875 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
223
2876 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
2878 and the "music publishing industry"
2879 was thereby "at the complete mercy of this one pirate."
<footnote><para>
2881 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
226
2882 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
2885 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, "When they make money
2886 out of my pieces, I want a share of it."
<footnote><para>
2888 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
23
2889 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
2893 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
2894 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
2895 player piano argued that "it is perfectly demonstrable that the
2896 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
2897 of anything he had before their introduction." Rather, the machines
2898 increased the sales of sheet music.
<footnote><para>
2901 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
283–84
2902 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
2903 Perforating Company of New York).
2904 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
2905 Congress was "to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
2906 they represent, and whose servants they are." "All talk about
2907 `theft,'" the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
2908 wrote, "is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
2909 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
2910 statute."
<footnote><para>
2912 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
376 (prepared
2913 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
2914 Graphophone Company Association).
2918 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer and the
2919 recording artist. Congress amended the law to make sure that composers
2920 would be paid for the "mechanical reproductions" of their music. But
2921 rather than simply granting the composer complete control over the
2922 right to make mechanical reproductions, Congress gave recording
2923 artists a right to record the music, at a price set by Congress, once
2924 the composer allowed it to be recorded once. This is the part of
2926 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
2927 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
2928 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
2929 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
2932 American law ordinarily calls this a "compulsory license," but I will
2933 refer to it as a "statutory license." A statutory license is a license
2934 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
2935 Copyright Act in
1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
2936 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
2937 the fee set by the statute.
2940 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
2941 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
2942 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
2943 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
2944 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
2945 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
2947 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John
</primary></indexterm>
2950 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
2951 thus, in effect, the law subsidizes the recording industry through a
2952 kind of piracy
—by giving recording artists a weaker right than
2953 it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles have less control
2954 over their creative work than Grisham does. And the beneficiaries of
2955 this less control are the recording industry and the public. The
2956 recording industry gets something of value for less than it otherwise
2957 would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range of musical
2958 creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its reasons for
2959 granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of rights
2960 holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
2961 creativity.
<footnote><para>
2963 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S.
2499, S.
2900, H.R.
243, and
2964 H.R.
11794 Before the ( Joint) Committee on Patents,
60th Cong.,
1st
2965 sess.,
217 (
1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
2966 in Legislative History of the
1909 Copyright Act, E. Fulton Brylawski and
2967 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints,
1976).
2969 <indexterm><primary>Beatles
</primary></indexterm>
2972 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
2973 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
2974 records. As a
1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
2979 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
2980 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
2981 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
2982 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
2983 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
2984 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
2985 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
2986 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
2987 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before
1909 and
2988 the
1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
2989 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
2990 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
2991 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
2992 choice.
<footnote><para>
2994 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R.
2512, House Committee
2995 on the Judiciary,
90th Cong.,
1st sess., House Document no.
83, (
8
2996 March
1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
2997 this report.
</para></footnote>
3001 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3002 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3006 <title>Radio
</title>
3008 Radio was also born of piracy.
3011 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3012 "public performance" of the composer's work.
<footnote><para>
3014 See
17 United States Code, sections
106 and
110. At the beginning,
3015 record companies printed "Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast" and other
3016 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3017 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3018 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3019 station. See RCA Manufacturing Co. v. Whiteman,
114 F.
2d
86 (
2nd
3020 Cir.
1940). See also Randal C. Picker, "From Edison to the Broadcast
3021 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3022 Copyright," University of Chicago Law Review
70 (
2003):
281.
3023 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned
</primary></indexterm>
3024 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
3026 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3027 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3028 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3031 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3032 copy of the composer's work. The radio station is also performing a
3033 copy of the recording artist's work. It's one thing to have "Happy
3034 Birthday" sung on the radio by the local children's choir; it's quite
3035 another to have it sung by the Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The
3036 recording artist is adding to the value of the composition performed
3037 on the radio station. And if the law were perfectly consistent, the
3038 radio station would have to pay the recording artist for his work,
3039 just as it pays the composer of the music for his work.
3041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3044 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3045 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3046 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3047 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3048 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3049 of playing the song.
3052 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3053 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3054 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3055 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3058 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3059 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3060 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you get
3061 some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3062 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3063 "protected" right. The radio station thus gets to pirate the value of
3064 Madonna's work without paying her anything.
3067 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3068 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3069 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3070 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3071 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3072 to take something for nothing.
3075 <sect2 id=
"cabletv">
3076 <title>Cable TV
</title>
3079 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3082 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3083 television in
1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3084 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3085 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3086 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3087 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3088 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3089 did
— Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3092 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas
</primary></indexterm>
3093 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin
</primary></indexterm>
3095 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3096 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3097 "unfair and potentially destructive competition."
<footnote><para>
3099 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV: Hearing on S.
1006 Before the
3100 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3101 Committee on the Judiciary,
89th Cong.,
2nd sess.,
78 (
1966)
3102 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3105 There may have been a "public interest" in spreading the reach of cable
3106 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3107 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, "Does public
3108 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?"
<footnote><para>
3110 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3111 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3113 As another broadcaster put it,
3117 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3118 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3119 paid for.
<footnote><para>
3121 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3122 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3127 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3131 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3132 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3133 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3134 think there are harsher words which would fit it.
<footnote><para>
3136 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3137 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3138 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3143 These were "free-ride[rs]," Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3144 Heston said, who were "depriving actors of
3145 compensation."
<footnote><para>
3147 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3148 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3152 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3153 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3157 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3158 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3159 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3160 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. . . . The
3162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3163 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3164 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.
<footnote><para>
3166 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
216 (statement of Edwin M.
3167 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3168 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin
</primary></indexterm>
3170 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin
</primary></indexterm>
3174 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3175 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3178 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3179 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they "pirated."
3180 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3181 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3182 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3183 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3184 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3185 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3186 companies thus built their empire in part upon a "piracy" of the value
3187 created by broadcasters' content.
3190 These separate stories sing a common theme. If "piracy" means
3191 using value from someone else's creative property without permission
3192 from that creator
—as it is increasingly described
3193 today
<footnote><para>
3195 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, The Engine
3196 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet
—The Myth of Free
3197 Information, available at
3198 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
13</ulink>. "The
3199 threat of piracy
—the use of someone else's creative work without
3200 permission or compensation
—has grown with the Internet."
3202 — then every industry affected by copyright today is the product
3203 and beneficiary of a certain kind of piracy. Film, records, radio,
3204 cable TV. . . . The list is long and could well be expanded. Every
3205 generation welcomes the pirates from the last. Every
3206 generation
—until now.
3208 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3212 <title>CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
</title>
3214 There is piracy of copyrighted material. Lots of it. This piracy comes
3215 in many forms. The most significant is commercial piracy, the
3216 unauthorized taking of other people's content within a commercial
3217 context. Despite the many justifications that are offered in its
3218 defense, this taking is wrong. No one should condone it, and the law
3222 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of "taking"
3223 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3224 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3225 taking "piracy," however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3226 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3227 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3228 has so often done in the past.
3229 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3231 <sect2 id=
"piracy-i">
3232 <title>Piracy I
</title>
3234 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3235 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3236 content, copy it, and sell it
—all without the permission of a copyright
3237 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $
4.6 billion
3238 every year to physical piracy
<footnote><para>
3240 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), The
3241 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report
2003, July
2003, available
3242 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
14</ulink>. See
3243 also Ben Hunt, "Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk," Financial
3244 Times,
14 February
2003,
11.
3246 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3247 estimates that it loses $
3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3250 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3251 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3252 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3253 This piracy is wrong.
3256 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3257 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3258 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3259 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3260 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3261 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3262 of our existence, treated as right.
3265 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3266 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3267 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3268 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3269 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3270 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3271 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3272 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3273 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3276 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3277 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3278 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77 -->
3279 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3280 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3284 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3285 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3286 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3287 of intellectual property law.
<footnote><para>
3289 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism: Who
3290 Owns the Knowledge Economy? (New York: The New Press,
2003),
10–13,
3291 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights
3292 (TRIPS) agreement obligates member nations to create administrative
3293 and enforcement mechanisms for intellectual property rights, a costly
3294 proposition for developing countries. Additionally, patent rights may
3295 lead to higher prices for staple industries such as
3296 agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the disparity between burdens
3297 imposed upon developing countries and benefits conferred to
3298 industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit governments to use patents
3299 for public, noncommercial uses without first obtaining the patent
3300 holder's permission. Developing nations may be able to use this to
3301 gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower prices. This is a
3302 promising strategy for developing nations within the TRIPS framework.
3303 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
3304 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3305 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3306 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3310 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3311 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3312 to American CDs at
50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3313 bought those American CDs at $
15 a copy. So no one really has any
3314 less money than they otherwise would have had.
<footnote><para>
3316 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3317 Liebowitz, Rethinking the Network Economy (New York: Amacom,
2002),
3318 144–90. "In some instances . . . the impact of piracy on the
3319 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3320 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3321 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3322 pirating were not an option." Ibid.,
149.
3323 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
3327 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3328 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3329 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3330 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3331 "You wouldn't go into Barnes
& Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3332 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?"
3333 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes
&
3334 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3335 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3336 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3337 piracy of the tangible.
3340 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3341 property right of a very special sort, it is a property right. Like
3342 all property rights, the copyright gives the owner the right to decide
3343 the terms under which content is shared. If the copyright owner
3344 doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There are exceptions:
3345 important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted content
3346 regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses give
3347 people the right to "take" copyrighted content whether or not the
3348 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3350 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3351 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3352 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3353 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3354 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3355 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what "property" means.
3358 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3359 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese "steal"
3360 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3361 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3362 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3363 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3364 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3365 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3366 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3367 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3368 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3369 <indexterm><primary>Windows
</primary></indexterm>
3372 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3373 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3374 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3375 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3376 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3377 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3380 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3381 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3382 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3383 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3384 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3385 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3386 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3387 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3388 what
—at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3389 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3390 violating the law is still wrong.
3393 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3394 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3395 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3396 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3397 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3398 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3399 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3400 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3404 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3405 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all "piracy" is. Or
3406 at least, not all "piracy" is wrong if that term is understood in the
3407 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of "piracy" are useful
3408 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3409 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3410 "piracy" in that sense of the term.
3413 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3414 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3415 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3416 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3419 For (
1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3420 controlling industry; and (
2) like the original recording industry, it
3421 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (
3) unlike cable
3422 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3425 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3426 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3430 <sect2 id=
"piracy-ii">
3431 <title>Piracy II
</title>
3433 The key to the "piracy" that the law aims to quash is a use that "rob[s]
3434 the author of [his] profit."
<footnote><para>
3436 Bach v. Longman,
98 Eng. Rep.
1274 (
1777).
3438 This means we must determine whether
3439 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3440 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3441 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3442 author of his profit.
3445 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3446 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3447 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3448 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well
<footnote><para>
3450 See Clayton M. Christensen, The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3451 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business (New York:
3452 HarperBusiness,
2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3453 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3454 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3455 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3456 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3457 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, Future,
89–92,
139.
3458 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.
</primary></indexterm>
3459 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3460 put together components that had been developed independently.
3461 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn
</primary></indexterm>
3464 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July
1999,
3465 Napster amassed over
10 million users within nine months. After
3466 eighteen months, there were close to
80 million registered users of the
3467 system.
<footnote><para>
3469 See Carolyn Lochhead, "Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare," San
3470 Francisco Chronicle,
24 September
2002, A1; "Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,"
3471 New Scientist,
6 July
2002,
42; Benny Evangelista, "Napster Names CEO,
3472 Secures New Financing," San Francisco Chronicle,
23 May
2003, C1;
3473 "Napster's Wake-Up Call," Economist,
24 June
2000,
23; John Naughton,
3474 "Hollywood at War with the Internet" (London) Times,
26 July
2002,
18.
3476 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3477 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3478 boasts over
100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3479 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3480 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3481 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend
—
3482 or your
20,
000 best friends.
3485 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3486 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3487 September
2002 estimated that
60 million Americans had downloaded
3488 music
—28 percent of Americans older than
12.
<footnote><para>
3491 See Ipsos-Insight, TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution
3492 (September
2002), reporting that
28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3493 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and
30 percent have
3494 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3496 A survey by the NPD group quoted in The New York Times estimated that
3497 43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to exchange content in
3498 May
2003.
<footnote><para>
3500 Amy Harmon, "Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight," New
3501 York Times,
6 June
2003, A1.
3503 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3504 massive quantity of content is being "taken" on these networks. The
3505 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3506 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3509 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3510 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3511 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3512 complicated than one might think. So consider
—a bit more
3513 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3514 do
—the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3518 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3519 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3520 different kinds into four types.
3522 <orderedlist numeration=
"upperalpha">
3525 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3526 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3527 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3528 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3529 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3530 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3531 users who download instead of purchasing.
3535 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3536 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3537 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3538 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3539 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3540 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3541 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3546 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3547 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3548 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3549 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3550 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3551 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3552 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend "recalling" old
3553 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3554 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3555 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3556 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero
—the same
3557 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of
1960s
45-rpm records to
3561 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3563 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3564 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3569 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3572 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3573 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3574 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3575 harmful.
<footnote><para>
3577 See Liebowitz, Rethinking the Network Economy,
148–49.
3578 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
3580 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3581 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3582 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3583 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3584 answer
—and certainly much more difficult than the current
3585 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3588 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3589 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3590 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3591 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3592 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of "theft" that is
3593 "devastating" the industry.
3596 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3597 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3598 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3599 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3600 & Young put it, "Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3601 technology, the labels fought it."
<footnote><para>
3603 See Cap Gemini Ernst
& Young, Technology Evolution and the
3604 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis (
2003),
3. This report
3605 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3606 practice of cassette taping in the
1970s, including an advertising
3607 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption "Home taping
3608 is killing music." At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3609 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3610 behavior. In
1988,
40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3611 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3612 Assessment, Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law,
3613 OTA-CIT-
422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3614 October
1989),
145–56.
</para></footnote>
3615 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3616 when record sales fell by
11.4 percent in
1981, the industry claimed
3617 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3618 regulating technology was the answer.
3621 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3622 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3623 turnaround. "In the end," Cap Gemini concludes, "the `crisis' . . . was
3624 not the fault of the tapers
—who did not [stop after MTV came into
3625 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
3626 being]
—but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
3627 innovation at the major labels."
<footnote><para>
3629 U.S. Congress, Copyright and Home Copying,
4.
3633 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
3634 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
3635 the industry in particular, and society in general
—or at least
3636 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
3637 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
3638 VCR
—the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
3639 harmful. The question is also how harmful type A sharing is, and how
3640 beneficial the other types of sharing are.
3643 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from
3644 the standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
3645 The "net harm" to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
3646 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
3647 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
3648 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They
3649 would therefore have little static reason to resist them.
3652 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining
3654 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD
3655 sales actually suggest it might be close.
3658 In
2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by
8.9
3660 from
882 million to
803 million units; revenues fell
6.7 percent.
<footnote><para>
3662 See Recording Industry Association of America,
2002 Yearend Statistics,
3664 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
15</ulink>. A later report indicates even greater losses. See
3665 Recording Industry Association of America, Some Facts About Music Piracy,
3666 25 June
2003, available at
3667 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
16</ulink>: "In the past four years, unit shipments
3668 of recorded music have fallen by
26 percent from
1.16 billion units in
3669 to
860 million units in
2002 in the United States (based on units shipped).
3670 In terms of sales, revenues are down
14 percent, from $
14.6 billion in
3671 to $
12.6 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The
3673 industry worldwide has gone from a $
39 billion industry in
2000 down
3674 to a $
32 billion industry in
2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments)."
3676 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
3678 piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
3679 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
3680 than
20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since
1999. That
3681 no doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
3682 account for at least some of the loss. "From
1999 to
2001, the average
3683 price of a CD rose
7.2 percent, from $
13.04 to $
14.19."
<footnote>
3686 Jane Black, "Big Music's Broken Record," BusinessWeek online,
13
3687 February
2003, available at
3688 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
17</ulink>.
3689 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane
</primary></indexterm>
3692 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of the
3693 decline. As Jane Black of BusinessWeek notes, "The soundtrack to the film
3694 High Fidelity has a list price of $
18.98. You could get the whole movie
3695 [on DVD] for $
19.99."
<footnote><para>
3702 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
3703 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD
3704 sales is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
3705 that the RIAA estimates that
803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
3706 estimates that
2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
3708 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
3709 free, sales revenue fell by just
6.7 percent.
3712 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
3713 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
3714 The recording industry constantly asks, "What's the difference
3716 downloading a song and stealing a CD?"
—but their own
3718 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
3719 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
3720 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
3721 downloads. If every download were a lost sale
—if every use of Kazaa
3722 "rob[bed] the author of [his] profit"
—then the industry would have
3723 suffered a
100 percent drop in sales last year, not a
7 percent drop. If
2.6
3724 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for free, and yet sales
3725 revenue dropped by just
6.7 percent, then there is a huge difference
3727 "downloading a song and stealing a CD."
3730 These are the harms
—alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
3732 real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on the
3733 recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to these
3737 One benefit is type C sharing
—making available content that is
3738 technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
3740 This is not a small category of content. There are millions of
3741 tracks that are no longer commercially available.
<footnote><para>
3743 By one estimate,
75 percent of the music released by the major labels is no
3744 longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright Law
—Coming
3745 Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the Senate
3747 on the Judiciary,
107th Cong.,
1st sess. (
3 April
2001) (prepared
3749 of the Future of Music Coalition), available at
3750 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
18</ulink>.
3754 that some of this content is not available because the artist
3755 producing the content doesn't want it to be made available, the vast
3756 majority of it is unavailable solely because the publisher or the
3758 has decided it no longer makes economic sense to the company to
3762 In real space
—long before the Internet
—the market had a simple
3763 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
3764 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
3766 of used book and used record stores in America today.
<footnote><para>
3768 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores in
3769 existence, in
2002, there were
7,
198 used book dealers in the United States,
3770 an increase of
20 percent since
1993. See Book Hunter Press, The Quiet
3771 Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book Market (
2002), available at
3772 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
19</ulink>. Used records accounted for $
260 million in sales in
2002. See
3774 Association of Recording Merchandisers, "
2002 Annual Survey
3777 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
20</ulink>.
3780 stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they buy. And
3781 under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this content,
3782 even if the content is still under copyright, the copyright owner doesn't get
3783 a dime. Used book and record stores are commercial entities; their
3784 owners make money from the content they sell; but as with cable
3786 before statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright
3787 owner for the content they sell.
3789 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard
</primary></indexterm>
3791 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
3792 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
3793 the content available isn't making money from making the content
3794 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
3795 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
3796 when someone shares my
1949 recording of Bernstein's "Two Love Songs,"
3797 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
3798 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
3799 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
3800 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
3801 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
3804 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
3805 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
3806 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
3807 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
3808 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
3812 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
3813 type D sharing to occur
—the sharing of content that copyright owners
3814 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
3815 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
3816 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, Down and Out in
3817 the Magic Kingdom, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
3819 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
3820 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
3821 would be a great advertisement for the "real" book. People would read
3822 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
3823 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
3824 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
3825 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
3829 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
3830 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
3831 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
3832 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
3835 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
3836 understandably says, "This is how much we've lost," we must also ask,
3837 "How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
3838 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
3842 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
3843 chapter, much of the "piracy" that file sharing enables is plainly
3844 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4, much of
3845 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
3846 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
3847 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
3848 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
3849 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
3850 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
3851 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
3852 found only with time.
3855 "But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
3856 just what you call type A sharing?"
3859 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The
3861 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
3862 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
3864 case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
3866 a technology to block the transfer of
99.4 percent of identified
3867 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
3868 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster
99.4
3869 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
3870 "down to zero."
<footnote><para>
3872 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at
34-
3873 35 (N.D. Cal.,
11 July
2001), nos. MDL-
00-
1369 MHP, C
99-
5183
3875 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
21</ulink>. For an account of the litigation and its toll on
3876 Napster, see Joseph Menn, All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn
3878 Napster (New York: Crown Business,
2003),
269–82.
3882 If
99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
3883 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
3884 assure that a p2p system is used
100 percent of the time in compliance
3885 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that
100 percent of
3886 VCRs or
100 percent of Xerox machines or
100 percent of handguns
3887 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
3888 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
3889 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
3890 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
3893 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
3894 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
3895 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way
3897 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
3899 In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the legitimate rights
3900 of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes this has meant
3901 more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
3904 So, as we've seen, when "mechanical reproduction" threatened the
3905 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
3906 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
3908 but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be paid, but
3909 at a price set by Congress. But when radio started broadcasting the
3910 recordings made by these recording artists, and they complained to
3911 Congress that their "creative property" was not being respected (since
3912 the radio station did not have to pay them for the creativity it
3914 Congress rejected their claim. An indirect benefit was enough.
3917 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
3918 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
3919 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
3920 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
3922 the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory price.
3926 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
3927 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
3928 pianos, served two important goals
—indeed, the two central goals of
3929 any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new innovators
3930 would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver content.
3932 the law assured that copyright holders would be paid for the
3934 that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress simply
3935 required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they demanded
3936 for their content, then copyright holders associated with broadcasters
3937 would use their power to stifle this new technology, cable. But if
3939 had permitted cable to use broadcasters' content for free, then it
3940 would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus Congress chose a path that
3941 would assure compensation without giving the past (broadcasters)
3943 over the future (cable).
3945 <indexterm><primary>Betamax
</primary></indexterm>
3947 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
3948 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
3949 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
3950 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
3951 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
3952 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
3953 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
3954 "record" button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
3955 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
3956 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
3957 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
3960 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
3961 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
3962 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
3963 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
3964 machine to copy only if there were a special "copy me" signal on the
3965 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
3966 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
3967 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
3968 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
3969 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
3970 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
3971 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
3972 for the architecture it chose.
3975 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
3976 champion. Valenti called VCRs "tapeworms." He warned, "When there are
3977 20,
30,
40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
3978 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
3979 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
3980 copyright."
<footnote><para>
3982 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
3983 S.
1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary,
97th Cong.,
1st
3984 and
2nd sess.,
459 (
1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
3985 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
3987 "One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
3988 creative judgment," he told Congress, "to understand the devastation
3989 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
3990 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
3991 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
3992 and plain common sense."
<footnote><para>
3994 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders),
475.
3996 Indeed, as surveys would later show,
3997 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more
<footnote><para>
3999 Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Sony Corp. of America,
480 F. Supp.
429,
4002 — a use the Court would later hold was not "fair." By
4003 "allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4004 copyright infringementwithout creating a mechanism to compensate
4005 copyrightowners," Valenti testified, Congress would "take from the
4006 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4007 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4008 profit from its reproduction."
<footnote><para>
4010 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders),
485 (testimony
4015 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4016 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4017 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction
—leading Judge Alex Kozinski,
4018 who sits on that court, refers to it as the "Hollywood Circuit"
—held
4019 that Sony would be liable for the copyright infringement made possible
4020 by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's rule, this totally familiar
4021 technology
—which Jack Valenti had called "the Boston Strangler of the
4022 American film industry" (worse yet, it was a Japanese Boston Strangler
4023 of the American film industry)
—was an illegal
4024 technology.
<footnote><para>
4026 Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Sony Corp. of America,
659 F.
2d
963 (
9th Cir.
4031 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4033 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4034 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4035 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4040 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4041 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4043 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4045 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4046 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4048 by such new technology.
<footnote><para>
4050 Sony Corp. of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc.,
464 U.S.
417,
431 (
1984).
4055 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision.
4056 But as with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts,
4058 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film
4059 got enough, this "taking" notwithstanding.
4060 If we put these cases together, a pattern is clear:
4064 <title>Table
</title>
4065 <tgroup cols=
"4" align=
"char">
4069 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS "PIRATED"
</entry>
4070 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS
</entry>
4071 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS
</entry>
4076 <entry>Recordings
</entry>
4077 <entry>Composers
</entry>
4078 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4079 <entry>Statutory license
</entry>
4082 <entry>Radio
</entry>
4083 <entry>Recording artists
</entry>
4085 <entry>Nothing
</entry>
4088 <entry>Cable TV
</entry>
4089 <entry>Broadcasters
</entry>
4090 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4091 <entry>Statutory license
</entry>
4095 <entry>Film creators
</entry>
4096 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4097 <entry>Nothing
</entry>
4104 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4105 way content was distributed.
<footnote><para>
4107 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4108 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4109 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4110 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4111 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4112 1992 (Title
17 of the United States Code), Pub. L. No.
102-
563,
106 Stat.
4113 4237, codified at
17 U.S.C. §
1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4114 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4115 Lessig, Future,
71. See also Picker, "From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,"
4116 University of Chicago Law Review
70 (
2003):
293–96.
4117 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
4119 In each case, throughout our history,
4120 that change meant that someone got a "free ride" on someone else's
4124 In none of these cases did either the courts or Congress eliminate all
4125 free riding. In none of these cases did the courts or Congress insist that
4126 the law should assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his
4127 copyright created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of
4128 "piracy." In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the
4130 in the behavior of the "pirates." In each case, Congress allowed
4131 some new technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced
4132 the interests at stake.
4133 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4136 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4137 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4138 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4139 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4140 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4142 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4143 to $
15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4144 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4145 permission to record a song?
4148 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4149 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4150 copyright "has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4151 over all possible uses of his work."
<footnote><para>
4153 Sony Corp. of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc.,
464 U.S.
417,
4156 Instead, the particular uses that the
4157 law regulates have been defined by balancing the good that comes from
4158 granting an exclusive right against the burdens such an exclusive right
4159 creates. And this balancing has historically been done after a
4161 has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that facilitate
4162 the distribution of content.
4165 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4166 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4167 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4168 should not become a tool for "stealing" from artists. But neither should
4169 the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which artists
4170 (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in some detail
4171 in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing income to artists
4172 while we allow the market to secure the most efficient way to promote
4173 and distribute content. This will require changes in the law, at least
4174 in the interim. These changes should be designed to balance the
4176 of the law against the strong public interest that innovation
4181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4182 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4184 mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4185 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4187 Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4189 Yet these "potential public benefits," as John Schwartz writes in
4190 The New York Times, "could be delayed in the P2P fight."
<footnote><para>
4192 John Schwartz, "New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4193 Echoes Past Efforts," New York Times,
22 September
2003, C3.
4195 Yet when anyone begins to talk about "balance," the copyright
4197 raise a different argument. "All this hand waving about balance
4198 and incentives," they say, "misses a fundamental point. Our content,"
4199 the warriors insist, "is our property. Why should we wait for Congress
4200 to `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4201 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4202 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether the
4203 car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?"
4206 "It is our property," the warriors insist. "And it should be protected
4207 just as any other property is protected."
4209 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4213 <chapter id=
"c-property">
4214 <title>"PROPERTY"</title>
4217 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4218 The copyright warriors are right: A copyright is a kind of
4219 property. It can be owned and sold, and the law protects against its
4220 theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to hold out for any price he
4221 wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand that partially determine
4222 the price she can get.
4225 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a "property" right is a
4226 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of property.
4227 Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any expression is very
4228 odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the picnic table you
4229 put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic table, and after I
4230 take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking when I take the good
4231 idea you had to put a picnic table in the backyard
—by, for example,
4233 to Sears, buying a table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the
4234 thing I am taking then?
4237 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4238 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4239 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4240 in the ordinary case
—indeed, in practically every case except for a
4242 range of exceptions
—ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4243 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress
—though I
4244 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4245 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4246 when I copy the way someone else dresses), "He who receives an idea
4247 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4248 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me."
<footnote><para>
4250 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (
13 August
1813) in
4251 The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, vol.
6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4252 Ellery Bergh, eds.,
1903),
330,
333–34.
4256 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4257 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4258 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4260 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4264 But how, and to what extent, and in what form
—the details, in
4265 other words
—matter. To get a good sense of how this practice of
4267 the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4269 in its proper context.
<footnote><para>
4271 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4273 A property right is simply a right that an individual has against the
4274 world to do or not do certain things that may or may not attach to a
4276 object. The right itself is intangible, even if the object to which it is
4277 (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See Adam Mossoff, "What Is
4279 Putting the Pieces Back Together," Arizona Law Review
45 (
2003):
4284 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4286 part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of "copyright
4288 is property" in context. Where did the idea come from? What are
4289 its limits? How does it function in practice? After these stories, the
4290 significance of this true statement
—"copyright material is property"
—
4291 will be a bit more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite
4292 different from the implications that the copyright warriors would have
4296 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4297 <sect1 id=
"founders">
4298 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders
</title>
4300 William Shakespeare wrote Romeo and Juliet in
1595. The play
4301 was first published in
1597. It was the eleventh major play that
4303 had written. He would continue to write plays through
1613,
4304 and the plays that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American
4305 culture ever since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer
4306 seeped into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source.
4307 I once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's
4309 of Henry V: "I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of clichés."
4312 In
1774, almost
180 years after Romeo and Juliet was written, the
4313 "copy-right" for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4314 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.
<footnote><para>
4316 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4317 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4318 handsome "definitive editions" of classic works. In addition to Romeo and
4319 Juliet, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4320 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4321 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, "Jacob Tonson,
4322 Bookseller," American Scholar
61:
3 (
1992):
424–31.
4325 most prominent of a small group of publishers called the Conger
<footnote><para>
4327 Lyman Ray Patterson, Copyright in Historical Perspective (Nashville:
4329 University Press,
1968),
151–52.
4332 controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth century. The
4333 Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the "copy" of books that
4334 they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant that no
4335 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4336 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4338 Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4340 better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4343 Now, there's something puzzling about the year
1774 to anyone who
4344 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the history
4345 of copyright is
1710, the year that the British Parliament adopted the
4346 first "copyright" act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the act stated that
4347 all published works would get a copyright term of fourteen years,
4349 once if the author was alive, and that all works already
4351 by
1710 would get a single term of twenty-one additional years.
<footnote><para>
4353 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4355 law." See Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs,
40.
4357 Under this law, Romeo and Juliet should have been free in
1731. So why
4358 was there any issue about it still being under Tonson's control in
1774?
4361 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a
4363 was
—indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4364 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4365 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of
1662, had
4367 in
1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing, as
4368 a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was published.
4369 But after it expired, there was no positive law that said that the
4371 or "Stationers," had an exclusive right to print books.
4374 There was no positive law, but that didn't mean that there was no
4375 law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to both the words of
4376 legislatures and the words of judges to know the rules that are to
4378 how people are to behave. We call the words from legislatures
4380 law." We call the words from judges "common law." The common
4381 law sets the background against which legislatures legislate; the
4383 ordinarily, can trump that background only if it passes a law to
4384 displace it. And so the real question after the licensing statutes had
4386 was whether the common law protected a copyright,
4388 of any positive law.
4391 This question was important to the publishers, or "booksellers," as
4392 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4393 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4394 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4396 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4397 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4398 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4400 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4403 The Statute of Anne granted the author or "proprietor" of a book
4404 an exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4406 and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the bookseller
4407 that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the copyright
4409 and the work would then be free and could be published by
4410 anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have believed.
4413 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4414 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to the
4415 particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right at all?
4418 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a
4419 very strong claim. Take Romeo and Juliet as an example: That play was
4420 written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4421 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4422 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating this
4423 play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So why is it
4424 that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and take
4425 Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4427 is there to allow someone else to "steal" Shakespeare's work?
4430 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something
4432 about the notion of "copyright" that existed at the time of the
4433 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4437 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have
4438 come to apply the concept of "copyright" ever more broadly. But in
4439 1710, it wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4440 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4442 from reprinting a book. In
1710, the "copy-right" was a right to use
4443 a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not go
4445 that very narrow right. It did not control any more generally how
4446 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4447 a work could be used. Today the right includes a large collection of
4449 on the freedom of others: It grants the author the exclusive
4450 right to copy, the exclusive right to distribute, the exclusive right to
4454 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4455 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4456 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4458 of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4460 for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4461 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4462 allowed to make his films. The "copy-right" was only an exclusive right
4463 to print
—no less, of course, but also no more.
4466 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4467 They had had a long and ugly experience with "exclusive rights,"
4469 "exclusive rights" granted by the Crown. The English had fought
4470 a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4471 monopolies
—especially
4472 monopolies for works that already existed. King Henry
4473 VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a monopoly to Darcy to
4474 print playing cards. The English Parliament began to fight back
4475 against this power of the Crown. In
1656, it passed the Statute of
4477 limiting monopolies to patents for new inventions. And by
4478 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing monopoly in
4482 Thus the "copy-right," when viewed as a monopoly right, was
4484 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing
4485 the claim that "it's my property, and I should have it forever," try
4486 sounding convincing when uttering, "It's my monopoly, and I should
4487 have it forever.") The state would protect the exclusive right, but only
4488 so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4490 favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4493 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4494 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4495 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4496 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4497 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4498 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst kind
—tools of the
4499 Crown's repression, selling the liberty of England to guarantee
4501 a monopoly profit. The attacks against these monopolists were
4502 harsh: Milton described them as "old patentees and monopolizers in
4503 the trade of book-selling"; they were "men who do not therefore labour
4504 in an honest profession to which learning is indetted."
<footnote><para>
4506 Philip Wittenberg, The Protection and Marketing of Literary Property (New
4507 York: J. Messner, Inc.,
1937),
31.
4511 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread
4512 of knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the
4514 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4515 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of the
4516 time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering with
4520 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4521 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4522 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4523 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4524 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4525 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4527 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4528 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4529 construction and spread of culture.
4532 When
1731 (
1710 +
21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4533 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4534 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4535 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4536 to control publication. But in
1735 and
1737, they tried to persuade
4537 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4538 they said; they needed more time.
4541 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4542 words that echo today,
4546 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4547 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4548 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4549 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4550 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4551 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4552 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4553 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4554 Booksellers.
<footnote><para>
4556 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4557 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4558 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4559 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4560 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4561 mentioned (London,
1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4562 al.,
8, Eldred v. Ashcroft,
537 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618).
4567 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4568 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4569 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
4570 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
4571 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
4572 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
4573 creative "property" and use it without his permission. The Statute of
4574 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
4575 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
4576 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
4577 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
4578 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
4579 way to protect authors.
4582 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
4583 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
4584 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
4585 "The publishers . . . had as much concern for authors as a cattle
4586 rancher has for cattle."
<footnote><para>
4588 Lyman Ray Patterson, "Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use," Vanderbilt
4589 Law Review
40 (
1987):
28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
4590 Vaidhyanathan,
37–48.
4592 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
4593 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
4596 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
4597 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
4598 Donaldson.
<footnote><para>
4600 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, Authorship and Copyright
4601 (London: Routledge,
1992),
62–69.
4605 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
4606 career in Edinburgh in
1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
4607 reprints "of standard works whose copyright term had expired," at least
4608 under the Statute of Anne.
<footnote><para>
4610 Mark Rose, Authors and Owners (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
4613 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
4614 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
4615 and became "something of a center for literary Scotsmen." "[A]mong
4616 them," Professor Mark Rose writes, was "the young James Boswell
4617 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
4618 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson."
<footnote><para>
4622 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew
</primary></indexterm>
4625 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
4626 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
4627 inexpensive editions "of the most popular English books, in defiance
4628 of the supposed common law right of Literary
4629 Property."
<footnote><para>
4631 Lyman Ray Patterson, Copyright in Historical Perspective,
167 (quoting
4634 His books undercut the Conger prices by
30 to
50 percent, and he
4635 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
4636 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
4639 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block "piracy" like
4640 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the "pirates,"
4641 the most important early victory being Millar v. Taylor.
4644 Millar was a bookseller who in
1729 had purchased the rights to James
4645 Thomson's poem "The Seasons." Millar complied with the requirements of
4646 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
4647 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
4648 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
4649 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.
<footnote><para>
4651 Howard B. Abrams, "The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
4652 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright," Wayne Law Review
29
4656 <indexterm id=
"idxmansfield2" class='startofrange'
>
4657 <primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord
</primary>
4660 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
4661 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
4662 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
4663 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
4664 law would protect the author against subsequent "pirates."
4665 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
4666 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
4667 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
4668 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
4671 Considered as a matter of abstract justice
—reasoning as if
4672 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
4673 principles
—Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
4674 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
4675 with in
1710: How best to limit
4676 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
4677 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
4678 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in
1710, but
4679 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
4680 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
4681 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
4682 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
4684 <indexterm startref=
"idxmansfield2" class='endofrange'
/>
4686 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
4687 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
4689 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
4691 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
4692 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
4693 Thomas Beckett.
<footnote><para>
4697 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
4698 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in Millar,
4699 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
4700 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
4701 Court. In February of
1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
4702 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
4705 As few legal cases ever do, Donaldson v. Beckett drew an enormous
4706 amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers argued
4707 that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the Statute
4708 of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute of Anne,
4709 the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control publication
4710 came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term specified in
4711 the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been protected by the
4712 statute were no longer protected.
4715 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
4716 presented to the House and voted upon first by the "law lords,"
4717 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
4718 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
4719 House of Lords generally voted.
4722 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
4723 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
4724 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
4725 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
4726 (
22 to
11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
4727 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
4728 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
4729 passed into the public domain.
4732 "The public domain." Before the case of Donaldson v. Beckett, there
4733 was no clear idea of a public domain in England. Before
1774, there
4734 was a strong argument that common law copyrights were perpetual.
4735 After
1774, the public domain was born. For the first time in
4736 Anglo-American history, the legal control over creative works expired,
4737 and the greatest works in English history
—including those of
4738 Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson, and Bunyan
—were free of
4740 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis
</primary></indexterm>
4741 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John
</primary></indexterm>
4742 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel
</primary></indexterm>
4743 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John
</primary></indexterm>
4744 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
4747 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
4748 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
4749 where most of the "pirate publishers" did their work, people
4750 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the Edinburgh Advertiser
4751 reported, "No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
4752 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
4753 decision of which so many individuals were interested." "Great
4754 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
4755 and illuminations."
<footnote><para>
4761 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
4762 equally strong in the opposite direction. The Morning Chronicle
4767 By the above decision . . . near
200,
000 pounds worth of what was
4768 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
4769 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
4770 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
4771 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
4772 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
4773 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
4774 successors.
<footnote><para>
4781 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
4782 "Ruined" is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
4783 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
4784 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
4785 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
4786 free. Not in the sense that copyrights would not be respected, for of
4787 course, for a limited time after a work was published, the bookseller
4788 had an exclusive right to control the publication of that book. And
4789 not in the sense that books could be stolen, for even after a
4790 copyright expired, you still had to buy the book from someone. But
4791 free in the sense that the culture and its growth would no longer be
4792 controlled by a small group of publishers. As every free market does,
4793 this free market of free culture would grow as the consumers and
4794 producers chose. English culture would develop as the many English
4795 readers chose to let it develop
— chose in the books they bought
4796 and wrote; chose in the memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a
4797 competitive context, not a context in which the choices about what
4798 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
4799 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
4802 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
4803 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
4804 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
4807 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
4809 <sect1 id=
"recorders">
4810 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
</title>
4812 Jon Else is a filmmaker. He is best known for his documentaries and
4813 has been very successful in spreading his art. He is also a teacher, and
4814 as a teacher myself, I envy the loyalty and admiration that his students
4815 feel for him. (I met, by accident, two of his students at a dinner party.
4819 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
4820 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
4824 In
1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
4825 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
4826 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
4827 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
4828 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
4830 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera
</primary></indexterm>
4833 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
4834 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
4835 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
4836 and the opera company played Wagner, was The Simpsons. As Else judged
4837 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
4838 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
4842 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
4843 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of The Simpsons.
4844 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
4845 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
4846 unless "fair use" or some other privilege applies.
4849 Else called Simpsons creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
4850 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
4851 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
4852 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
4853 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
4854 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films
</primary></indexterm>
4857 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
4858 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
4859 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
4860 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
4861 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
4862 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films
</primary></indexterm>
4865 Then, as Else told me, "two things happened. First we discovered
4866 . . . that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation
—or at
4867 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation."
4868 And second, Fox "wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
4869 to use this four-point-five seconds of . . . entirely unsolicited
4870 Simpsons which was in the corner of the shot."
4873 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
4874 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
4875 explained to her, "There must be some mistake here. . . . We're
4876 asking for your educational rate on this." That was the educational
4877 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
4878 confirm what he had been told.
4881 "I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight," he told me. "Yes, you
4882 have your facts straight," she said. It would cost $
10,
000 to use the
4883 clip of The Simpsons in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
4886 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
4887 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, "And
4888 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys." As an assistant
4889 to Herrera told Else later on, "They don't give a shit. They just want
4893 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
4894 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
4895 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
4896 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
4897 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
4898 The Day After Trinity, from ten years before.
4899 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera
</primary></indexterm>
4902 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
4903 copyright to The Simpsons. That copyright is their property. To use
4904 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
4905 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
4906 Simpsons copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
4907 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
4908 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
4909 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
4910 says the owner gets to control.
4913 For example, "public performance" is a use of The Simpsons that the
4914 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
4915 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see "My
4916 Favorite Simpsons," then you need to get permission from the copyright
4917 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
4918 whatever she wants
—$
10 or $
1,
000,
000. That's her right, as set
4922 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
4923 thought is "fair use."
<footnote><para>
4925 For an excellent argument that such use is "fair use," but that
4926 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is "fair use," see Richard
4927 A. Posner with William F. Patry, "Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
4928 Wake of Eldred " (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
4929 Law School,
5 August
2003.
4931 Else's use of just
4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a Simpsons
4932 episode is clearly a fair use of The Simpsons
—and fair use does
4933 not require the permission of anyone.
4936 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
4937 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon "fair use." Here's his reply:
4941 The Simpsons fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
4942 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
4943 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
4944 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was "clearly
4945 fair use" in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
4946 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
4948 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
4951 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
4952 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
4953 "visual cue sheet" listing the source and licensing status of each
4954 shot in the film. They take a dim view of "fair use," and a claim of
4955 "fair use" can grind the application process to a halt.
4959 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
4960 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
4961 tracking down and stopping unlicensed Simpsons usage, just as George
4962 Lucas had a very high profile litigating Star Wars usage. So I decided
4963 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
4964 license to four seconds of Simpsons. As a documentary producer working
4965 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
4966 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
4971 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
4972 School . . . who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
4973 that Fox would "depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
4974 life," regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
4975 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
4976 pockets, me or them.
4977 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
4981 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
4982 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
4988 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
4989 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
4990 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
4991 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
4992 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
4993 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
4996 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
4997 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
4998 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
4999 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5002 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5004 <sect1 id=
"transformers">
5005 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
</title>
5006 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
5007 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5009 In
1993, Alex Alben was a lawyer working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave
5010 was an innovative company founded by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to
5011 develop digital entertainment. Long before the Internet became
5012 popular, Starwave began investing in new technology for delivering
5013 entertainment in anticipation of the power of networks.
5015 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5017 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5018 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology
—not to distribute
5019 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5020 difficult. In
1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5021 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5022 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5023 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5024 important to his career.
5026 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5028 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5029 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5030 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5031 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5034 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5035 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5036 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5037 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5038 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5039 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5041 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5043 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. "Our
5044 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5045 Eastwood's films," Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5046 arose. "No one had ever really done this before," Alben explained. "No
5047 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5050 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5052 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5053 Slade asked, "Well, what will it take?"
5055 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5057 Alben replied, "Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5058 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5059 else that we want to use in these film clips." Slade said, "Great! Go
5063 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5064 publicity
—rights an artist has to control the commercial
5065 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden "Rip, Mix,
5066 Burn" creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5068 <primary>artists
</primary>
5069 <secondary>publicity rights on images of
</secondary>
5074 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5075 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5076 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5077 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5078 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5081 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5082 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5083 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5087 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5088 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include
—of
5089 course we were going to use the "Make my day" clip from Dirty
5090 Harry. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5091 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5092 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5095 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5096 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5097 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5098 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5099 rate at the time was about $
600. So we had to identify the
5100 people
—some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5101 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5102 glass
—is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5103 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5104 started calling people.
5107 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5109 Some actors were glad to help
—Donald Sutherland, for example,
5110 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5111 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5112 "Hey, can I pay you $
600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5113 know, $
1,
200?" And they would say, "Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5114 to get $
1,
200." And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5115 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5116 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5120 It was one year later
—"and even then we weren't sure whether we
5121 were totally in the clear."
5123 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5125 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5126 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5127 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5131 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5132 hands and said, "Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5133 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5134 actors." But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5135 constituent parts and said, "Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5136 directors, . . . this many musicians," and we just went at it very
5137 systematically and cleared the rights.
5142 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5143 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5144 loved it, and it sold very well.
5146 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5147 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
5149 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5150 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5151 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, "There is
5152 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5153 at all."
<footnote><para>
5155 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, Seven
5156 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition, available at
5157 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
22</ulink>.
5159 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5163 For, as he acknowledged, "very few . . . have the time and resources,
5164 and the will to do this," and thus, very few such works would ever be
5165 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5166 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5167 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5171 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5172 he or she gets paid very well. . . . And then when
30 seconds of
5173 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5174 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person . . . should be
5175 compensated for that.
5179 Or at least, is this how the artist should be compensated? Would it
5180 make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind of statutory license
5181 that someone could pay and be free to make derivative use of clips
5182 like this? Did it really make sense that a follow-on creator would
5183 have to track down every artist, actor, director, musician, and get
5184 explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a lot more be created if the
5185 legal part of the creative process could be made to be more clean?
5189 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5190 mechanism
—where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5191 subject to estranged former spouses
—you'd see a lot more of this
5192 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5193 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5194 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5195 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5196 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5197 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5198 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5199 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5200 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5201 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5202 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, "Oh, I
5203 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5204 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5205 money," then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5208 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5210 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5211 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5212 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5213 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5214 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5215 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5216 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5217 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5218 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5219 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5220 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5221 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5222 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5223 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5224 "Does this still make sense?"
5227 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5228 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5229 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5230 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5232 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5233 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5234 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5237 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5238 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a
60 Minutes episode.
5239 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5240 judges loved every minute of it.
5242 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David
</primary></indexterm>
5244 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5245 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5246 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5247 room of over
250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5248 began his talk with a question: "Do you know how many federal laws
5249 were just violated in this room?"
5251 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David
</primary></indexterm>
5253 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5254 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5255 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5256 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5257 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of
250 judges and a gaggle
5258 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5259 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5260 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5261 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5262 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5263 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5264 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5265 couldn't easily do them legally.
5268 We live in a "cut and paste" culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5269 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5270 and paste architecture of the Internet created
—in a second you can
5271 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5272 planted in your presentation.
5275 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5276 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5277 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5278 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5279 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5280 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5281 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5282 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5283 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5284 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos
</primary></indexterm>
5287 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5288 wanted to be "legal," the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5289 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5290 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5291 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5294 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5295 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5296 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5297 necessarily requiring that the "free" use be free as in "free beer."
5298 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5299 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5300 along: a rule, for example, that says "the royalty owed the copyright
5301 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5302 will be a flat
1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5303 copyright owner." Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5304 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5305 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5309 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5310 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5311 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5312 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5315 In February
2003, DreamWorks studios announced an agreement with Mike
5316 Myers, the comic genius of Saturday Night Live and
5317 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5318 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5319 would work together to form a "unique filmmaking pact." Under the
5320 agreement, DreamWorks "will acquire the rights to existing motion
5321 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and
—with the use
5322 of stateof-the-art digital technology
—insert Myers and other
5323 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5327 The announcement called this "film sampling." As Myers explained,
5328 "Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5329 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5330 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5331 to take that same concept and apply it to film." Steven Spielberg is
5332 quoted as saying, "If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5333 new audiences, it is Mike."
5336 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5337 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5338 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5339 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5340 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5341 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5342 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5343 privilege reserved for the funny and famous
—and presumably rich.
5346 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5347 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of "fair use."
5348 Much of "sampling" should be considered "fair use." But few would
5349 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5350 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5351 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5352 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5353 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5354 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5355 process is a process of paying lawyers
—again a privilege, or perhaps a
5356 curse, reserved for the few.
5358 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5360 <sect1 id=
"collectors">
5361 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
</title>
5363 In April
1996, millions of "bots"
—computer codes designed to
5364 "spider," or automatically search the Internet and copy content
—began
5365 running across the Net. Page by page, these bots copied Internet-based
5366 information onto a small set of computers located in a basement in San
5367 Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots finished the whole of the Internet,
5368 they started again. Over and over again, once every two months, these
5369 bits of code took copies of the Internet and stored them.
5372 By October
2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5373 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5374 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5375 the world. Using a technology called "the Way Back Machine," you could
5376 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to
1996, as
5377 well as when those pages changed.
5380 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5381 appreciated. In the dystopia described in
1984, old newspapers were
5382 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5383 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5387 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5388 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5389 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5390 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5393 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5394 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5395 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5396 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5397 library
—constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5400 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5401 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5402 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5403 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5404 what others might prefer you forget.
<footnote><para>
5406 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5407 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May
13,
2003,
5408 press release stated, "Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended." That was
5409 later changed, without notice, to "Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5410 Have Ended." E-mail from Brewster Kahle,
1 December
2003.
5414 We take it for granted that we can go back to see what we remember
5415 reading. Think about newspapers. If you wanted to study the reaction
5416 of your hometown newspaper to the race riots in Watts in
1965, or to
5417 Bull Connor's water cannon in
1963, you could go to your public
5418 library and look at the newspapers. Those papers probably exist on
5419 microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in paper, too. Either way, you
5420 are free, using a library, to go back and remember
—not just what
5421 it is convenient to remember, but remember something close to the
5425 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5426 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We all forget history. The key is
5427 whether we have a way to go back to rediscover what we forget. More
5428 directly, the key is whether an objective past can keep us
5429 honest. Libraries help do that, by collecting content and keeping it,
5430 for schoolchildren, for researchers, for grandma. A free society
5431 presumes this knowedge.
5434 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5435 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5436 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5437 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5438 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5439 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5440 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5441 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet
—the
5442 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5445 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5446 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5447 researcher. In the
1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5448 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5449 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5450 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5451 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of
2002, the archive had over
10
5452 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5455 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
5456 human history. At the end of
2002, it held "two hundred and thirty
5457 terabytes of material"
—and was "ten times larger than the
5458 Library of Congress." And this was just the first of the archives that
5459 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
5460 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
5461 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
5462 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
5463 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
5464 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University
—thanks to a
5465 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
5466 is available to scholars for a very low fee. "But other than that,
5467 [television] is almost unavailable," Kahle told me. "If you were
5468 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
5469 just a graduate student?" As Kahle put it,
5473 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
5474 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
5475 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
5476 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
5477 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
5479 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
5480 60 Minutes episode that came out after it . . . it would be almost
5481 impossible. . . . Those materials are almost unfindable. . . .
5485 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
5486 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
5487 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
5488 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
5489 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
5490 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
5493 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
5494 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
5495 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
5496 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
5497 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
5501 These rules applied to film as well. But in
1915, the Library
5502 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
5503 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
5504 borrow back the deposits
—for an unlimited time at no cost. In
5505 1915 alone, there were more than
5,
475 films deposited and "borrowed
5506 back." Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
5507 held by any library. The copy exists
—if it exists at
5508 all
—in the library archive of the film company.
<footnote><para>
5510 Doug Herrick, "Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
5511 the Library of Congress," Film Library Quarterly
13 nos.
2–3
5512 (
1980):
5; Anthony Slide, Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
5513 Preservation in the United States ( Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland
&
5518 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
5519 were originally not copyrighted
—there was no way to capture the
5520 broadcasts, so there was no fear of "theft." But as technology enabled
5521 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
5522 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
5523 "copyrighted." But those copies were simply kept by the
5524 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
5525 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
5526 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
5529 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September
11,
2001, he and
5530 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
5531 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
5532 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
5533 September
11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
5534 stations from around the world and, beginning October
11,
2001, made
5535 their coverage during the week of September
11 available free on-line.
5536 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
5540 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
5541 archive of film includes close to
45,
000 "ephemeral films" (meaning
5542 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
5543 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
5544 1,
300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
5545 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
5546 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
5547 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
5548 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
5549 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
5550 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
5551 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
5552 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the "Duck and Cover" film
5553 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
5554 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
5555 few minutes
—for free.
5558 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
5559 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
5560 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
5561 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
5562 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
5566 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
5567 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
5568 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
5569 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
5570 property, but during a second life that all creative property
5571 has
—a noncommercial life.
5574 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
5575 of creative property goes through different "lives." In its first
5578 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
5579 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
5580 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
5581 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
5582 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
5583 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
5586 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
5587 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
5588 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
5589 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
5590 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
5591 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
5595 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
5596 very quickly (the average today is after about a year
<footnote><para>
5598 Dave Barns, "Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
5599 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business," Chicago Tribune,
5600 5 September
1997, at Metro Lake
1L. Of books published between
1927
5601 and
1946, only
2.2 percent were in print in
2002. R. Anthony Reese,
5602 "The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks," Boston
5603 College Law Review
44 (
2003):
593 n.
51.
5604 </para></footnote>). After
5605 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
5606 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
5607 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
5608 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
5609 important to the spread and stability of culture.
5612 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
5613 creative property does not hold true with the most important
5614 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
5615 centuries. For these
—television, movies, music, radio, the
5616 Internet
—there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
5617 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes
&
5618 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
5619 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
5623 For most of the twentieth century, it was economics that made this
5624 so. It would have been insanely expensive to collect and make
5625 accessible all television and film and music: The cost of analog
5626 copies is extraordinarily high. So even though the law in principle
5627 would have restricted the ability of a Brewster Kahle to copy culture
5629 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
5630 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
5631 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
5632 little practical effect.
5635 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
5636 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
5637 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
5638 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
5639 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
5640 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
5643 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
5644 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
5645 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
5650 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
5651 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
5652 movies, . . . and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
5653 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
5654 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
5655 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
5656 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
5657 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
5658 . . . thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
5659 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
5660 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
5664 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
5665 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
5666 libraries or archives could be. When the commercial life of creative
5667 property ends, I don't know. But it does. And whenever it does, Kahle
5668 and his archive hint at a world where this knowledge, and culture,
5669 remains perpetually available. Some will draw upon it to understand
5671 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
5672 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
5673 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
5674 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past
—a
5675 future for our past. The technology of digital arts could make the
5676 dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
5679 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
5680 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
5681 call these "archives," as warm as the idea of a "library" might seem,
5682 the "content" that is collected in these digital spaces is also
5683 someone's "property." And the law of property restricts the freedoms
5684 that Kahle and others would exercise.
5686 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
5688 <sect1 id=
"property-i">
5689 <title>CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
</title>
5691 Jack Valenti has been the president of the Motion Picture Association
5692 of America since
1966. He first came to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon
5693 Johnson's administration
—literally. The famous picture of
5694 Johnson's swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of
5695 President Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty
5696 years of running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps
5697 the most prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
5698 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon
</primary></indexterm>
5701 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
5702 Association. It was formed in
1922 as a trade association whose goal
5703 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
5704 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
5705 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
5706 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
5707 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
5708 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
5709 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
5711 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.
</primary></indexterm>
5712 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment
</primary></indexterm>
5713 <indexterm><primary>MGM
</primary></indexterm>
5714 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures
</primary></indexterm>
5715 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox
</primary></indexterm>
5716 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures
</primary></indexterm>
5717 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
5720 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
5721 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
5722 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
5723 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
5724 political skill of a Southerner
—the ability to appear simple and
5725 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
5726 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
5727 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
5728 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
5729 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
5733 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
5734 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
5735 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
5736 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
5737 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
5738 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
5739 redefine the meaning of "creative property."
5742 In
1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
5747 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
5748 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
5749 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
5750 theme which animates this entire debate: Creative property owners must
5751 be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all other
5752 property owners in the nation. That is the issue. That is the
5753 question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire hearing and the
5754 debates to follow must rest.
<footnote><para>
5756 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R.
4783, H.R.
5757 4794, H.R.
4808, H.R.
5250, H.R.
5488, and H.R.
5705 Before the
5758 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
5759 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
5760 Representatives,
97th Cong.,
2nd sess. (
1982):
65 (testimony of Jack
5766 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
5767 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
5768 "central theme" to which "reasonable men and women" will return is
5770 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
5771 "Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
5772 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation."
5773 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
5774 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
5777 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
5778 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
5779 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
5780 extreme a claim made by anyone who is serious in this debate than this
5781 claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet and however brilliant,
5782 is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when it comes to the nature
5783 and scope of "creative property." His views have no reasonable
5784 connection to our actual legal tradition, even if the subtle pull of
5785 his Texan charm has slowly redefined that tradition, at least in
5789 While "creative property" is certainly "property" in a nerdy and
5790 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,
<footnote><para>
5792 Lawyers speak of "property" not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
5793 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
5794 object. Thus, my "property right" to my car gives me the right to
5795 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at
150 miles an hour. For
5796 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of "property" to
5797 "lawyer talk," see Bruce Ackerman, Private Property and the
5798 Constitution (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1977),
26–27.
5799 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
5800 "creative property owners" have been "accorded the same rights and
5801 protection resident in all other property owners." Indeed, if creative
5802 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
5803 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
5807 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
5808 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
5809 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
5810 overturned in
1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
5811 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
5812 culture would develop.
5815 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
5816 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
5817 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
5818 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
5819 differently from the rights resident in all other property
5820 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
5821 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
5822 the same would be to
5824 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
5825 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
5826 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
5830 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
5831 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
5832 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
5833 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
5834 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
5835 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
5836 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old. To
5837 get just a hint that there is something fundamentally wrong in
5838 Valenti's argument, we need look no further than the United States
5839 Constitution itself.
5842 The framers of our Constitution loved "property." Indeed, so strongly
5843 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
5844 important requirement. If the government takes your property
—if
5845 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
5846 farm
—it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's "Takings
5847 Clause," to pay you "just compensation" for that taking. The
5848 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
5849 sacred. It cannot ever be taken from the property owner unless the
5850 government pays for the privilege.
5853 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
5854 Valenti calls "creative property." In the clause granting Congress the
5855 power to create "creative property," the Constitution requires that
5856 after a "limited time," Congress take back the rights that it has
5857 granted and set the "creative property" free to the public domain. Yet
5858 when Congress does this, when the expiration of a copyright term
5859 "takes" your copyright and turns it over to the public domain,
5860 Congress does not have any obligation to pay "just compensation" for
5861 this "taking." Instead, the same Constitution that requires
5862 compensation for your land
5863 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
5864 requires that you lose your "creative property" right without any
5865 compensation at all.
5868 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
5869 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
5870 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
5871 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
5872 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
5873 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
5877 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
5878 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
5879 The Constitution of
1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
5880 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
5881 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
5882 president (as it did in
1800). The framers were no doubt
5883 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
5884 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
5885 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
5886 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
5889 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
5890 least try to understand why. Why did the framers, fanatical property
5891 types that they were, reject the claim that creative property be given
5892 the same rights as all other property? Why did they require that for
5893 creative property there must be a public domain?
5896 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
5897 history of these "creative property" rights, and the control that they
5898 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
5899 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
5900 should be at the core of this war: Not whether creative property
5901 should be protected, but how. Not whether we will enforce the rights
5902 the law gives to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix
5903 of rights ought to be. Not whether artists should be paid, but whether
5904 institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need also
5905 control how culture develops.
5909 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
5910 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
5911 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
5912 than the narrow language of the law allows. In Code and Other Laws of
5913 Cyberspace, I used a simple model to capture this more general
5914 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
5915 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
5916 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
5918 <figure id=
"fig-1331">
5919 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.
</title>
5920 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.png"></graphic>
5923 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
5924 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
5925 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
5926 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
5927 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
5928 be regulated
— either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
5929 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
5930 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
5931 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
5932 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
5933 Web, you can be punished
5934 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
5935 with a $
150,
000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
5936 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
5939 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
5940 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
5941 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
5942 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
5943 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
5944 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
5945 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
5946 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
5947 the source of the enforcement.
5950 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
5951 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
5952 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
5953 norms
—it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
5954 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
5955 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
5956 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
5957 individual or group might behave.
5960 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
5961 "architecture"
—the physical world as one finds it
—is a
5962 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
5963 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
5964 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
5965 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
5966 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
5967 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
5968 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
5969 theft, but by nature, by "architecture." If a
500-pound boulder
5970 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
5971 constraint. If a $
500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
5972 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
5976 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
5977 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
5978 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
5979 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
5980 undermined by another.
5983 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
5984 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
5985 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
5986 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
5987 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
5988 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
5989 must consider how these four in particular interact.
5991 <indexterm id=
"idxdrivespeed" class='startofrange'
>
5992 <primary>driving speed, constraints on
</primary>
5995 So, for example, consider the "freedom" to drive a car at a high
5996 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
5997 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
5998 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
5999 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6000 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6001 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6002 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6003 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6004 the freedom to speed. Drive at
50 mph by a school in your own
6005 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6006 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6009 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6010 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6011 special role in affecting the three.
<footnote><para>
6013 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6014 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6015 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6016 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6017 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, Code: And
6018 Other Laws of Cyberspace (New York: Basic Books,
1999):
90–95;
6019 Lawrence Lessig, "The New Chicago School," Journal of Legal Studies,
6022 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6023 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6024 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6025 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6026 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6027 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6028 used to require that other laws be more
6029 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6030 strict
—a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6031 limit, for example
—so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6034 <indexterm startref=
"idxdrivespeed" class='endofrange'
/>
6036 <figure id=
"fig-1361">
6037 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.
</title>
6038 <graphic fileref=
"images/1361.png"></graphic>
6041 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6042 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6043 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6044 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6045 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6049 Some people object to this way of talking about "liberty." They object
6050 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6051 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6052 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6053 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6054 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6055 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6056 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6057 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6058 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6059 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6060 of liberty. As I argued in Code, we come from a long tradition of
6061 political thought with a broader focus than the narrow question of
6062 what the government did when. John Stuart Mill defended freedom of
6063 speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow minds, not from the
6064 fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (Indiana:
6065 Hackett Publishing Co.,
1978),
19. John R. Commons famously defended
6066 the economic freedom of labor from constraints imposed by the market;
6067 John R. Commons, "The Right to Work," in Malcom Rutherford and Warren
6068 J. Samuels, eds., John R. Commons: Selected Essays (London:
6069 Routledge:
1997),
62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6070 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6071 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6072 places easier;
42 United States Code, section
12101 (
2000). Each of
6073 these interventions to change existing conditions changes the liberty
6074 of a particular group. The effect of those interventions should be
6075 accounted for in order to understand the effective liberty that each
6076 of these groups might face.
6077 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.
</primary></indexterm>
6080 <sect2 id=
"hollywood">
6081 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right
</title>
6083 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6084 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6085 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6086 rallying makes sense.
6089 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6092 <figure id=
"fig-1371">
6093 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.
</title>
6094 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.png"></graphic>
6097 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6098 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6099 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6100 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6101 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6102 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6103 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6104 recognize
—kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6105 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6106 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6107 this form of infringement.
6110 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6111 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6112 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6113 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6114 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6115 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6118 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6119 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6120 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6121 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6123 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6124 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6125 looting that results.
6127 <figure id=
"fig-1381">
6128 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
</title>
6129 <graphic fileref=
"images/1381.png"></graphic>
6132 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6133 warriors. Indeed, in a "White Paper" prepared by the Commerce
6134 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in
1995,
6135 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6136 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6137 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (
1) Congress should
6138 strengthen intellectual property law, (
2) businesses should adopt
6139 innovative marketing techniques, (
3) technologists should push to
6140 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (
4) educators should
6141 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6144 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed
—if it was to
6145 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6146 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6147 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6148 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6149 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6150 life. Homeowners living in a
6152 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6153 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6154 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6155 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6156 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6157 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6158 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6161 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6162 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6163 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6164 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6165 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6166 Brown describes it, its "architecture of revenue."
6169 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6170 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6171 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6172 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6173 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as
20
6174 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6175 of digital cameras.
<footnote><para>
6177 See Geoffrey Smith, "Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?"
6178 BusinessWeek online,
2 August
1999, available at
6179 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
23</ulink>. For a more
6180 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6181 R. Schoenberger, "Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?" Forbes.com,
6
6182 October
2003, available at
6183 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
24</ulink>.
6186 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6187 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6188 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads for the
6189 purpose of protecting the railroads? Closer to the subject of this
6190 book, remote channel changers have weakened the "stickiness" of
6191 television advertising (if a boring commercial comes on the TV, the
6192 remote makes it easy to surf ), and it may well be that this change
6193 has weakened the television advertising market. But does anyone
6194 believe we should regulate remotes to reinforce commercial television?
6195 (Maybe by limiting them to function only once a second, or to switch
6196 to only ten channels within an hour?)
6199 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6200 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6201 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6202 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6203 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6204 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6205 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6206 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, "established companies
6207 have an interest in excluding future competitors."
<footnote><para>
6209 Fred Warshofsky, The Patent Wars (New York: Wiley,
1994),
170–71.
6212 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6213 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6214 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6215 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6216 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6218 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
6221 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6222 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6223 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6224 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6225 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6226 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6227 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6228 opportunities for innovation and change.
6231 In the context of laws regulating speech
—which include,
6232 obviously, copyright law
—that duty is even stronger. When the
6233 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6234 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6235 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6236 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6237 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6238 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: "Congress
6239 shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech." So when
6240 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would "abridge" the freedom
6241 of speech, it should ask
— carefully
—whether such
6242 regulation is justified.
6245 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6246 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6247 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6248 "justified." My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6249 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6250 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6251 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6254 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6257 In
1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In
1948, Swiss
6258 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6259 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the
1950s, the
6260 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6261 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6264 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6265 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6266 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6268 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel
</primary></indexterm>
6270 But in
1962, Rachel Carson published Silent Spring, which argued that
6271 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6272 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6273 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6274 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel
</primary></indexterm>
6275 <indexterm><primary>Silent Sprint (Carson)
</primary></indexterm>
6278 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6279 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6280 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6281 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6282 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6283 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6284 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6287 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6288 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an "environmentalism" for
6289 culture.
<footnote><para>
6291 See, for example, James Boyle, "A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6292 Environmentalism for the Net?" Duke Law Journal
47 (
1997):
87.
6294 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6295 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6296 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6297 "for free." The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6298 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6299 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6300 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6301 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6302 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6303 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6304 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6305 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6308 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6309 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6310 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6311 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6312 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6313 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6314 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6315 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6316 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6319 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6320 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6324 <sect2 id=
"beginnings">
6325 <title>Beginnings
</title>
6327 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6328 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of "creative
6329 property" rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6330 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6333 The power to establish "creative property" rights is granted to
6334 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6335 odd. Article I, section
8, clause
8 of our Constitution states that:
6338 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6339 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6340 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
6342 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
6343 We can call this the "Progress Clause," for notice what this clause
6344 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
6345 "creative property rights." It says that Congress has the power to
6346 promote progress. The grant of power is its purpose, and its purpose
6347 is a public one, not the purpose of enriching publishers, nor even
6348 primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
6351 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
6352 in chapter
6, the English limited the term of copyright so as to
6353 assure that a few would not exercise disproportionate control over
6354 culture by exercising disproportionate control over publishing. We can
6355 assume the framers followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed,
6356 unlike the English, the framers reinforced that objective, by
6357 requiring that copyrights extend "to Authors" only.
6360 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
6361 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
6362 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
6363 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
6364 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
6365 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
6366 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
6367 to reinforce the power of the states
—including the Senate, whose
6368 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
6369 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
6370 case, a structure built checks and balances into the constitutional
6371 frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable concentrations of
6375 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call "copyright"
6376 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
6377 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
6378 "copyright" in context: We need to see how it has changed in the
210
6379 years since they first struck its design.
6382 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
6383 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
6384 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
6385 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
6388 <figure id=
"fig-1441">
6389 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.
</title>
6390 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.png"></graphic>
6395 <figure id=
"fig-1442">
6396 <title>"Copyright
" today.
</title>
6397 <graphic fileref=
"images/1442.png"></graphic>
6401 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
6404 <sect2 id=
"lawduration">
6405 <title>Law: Duration
</title>
6407 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
6408 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
6409 the English had confronted in
1774. Many states had passed laws
6410 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
6411 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
6412 authorship.
<footnote>
6415 William W. Crosskey, Politics and the Constitution in the History of
6416 the United States (London: Cambridge University Press,
1953), vol.
1,
6417 485–86: "extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
6418 Law of the Land,' the perpetual rights which authors had, or were
6419 supposed by some to have, under the Common Law" (emphasis added).
6420 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.
</primary></indexterm>
6422 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
6423 States in
1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
6424 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
6425 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
6426 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
6427 domain to reprint and distribute works.
6430 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
6431 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
6432 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
6433 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
6434 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
6435 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
6438 In
1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
6439 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
6440 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
6441 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
6442 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
6445 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
6446 ten years of the Republic, only
5 percent of the works were actually
6447 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
6448 in the United States both before
1790 and from
1790 through
1800,
95
6449 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
6450 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
6451 likely within fourteen years.
<footnote><para>
6453 Although
13,
000 titles were published in the United States from
1790
6454 to
1799, only
556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, A
6455 History of Book Publishing in the United States, vol.
1, The Creation
6456 of an Industry,
1630–1865 (New York: Bowker,
1972),
141. Of the
21,
000
6457 imprints recorded before
1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
6458 1790 act; William J. Maher, Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
6459 and the Copyright Law of
1790 in Historical Context,
7–10 (
2002),
6460 available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
6461 #
25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
6462 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
6463 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
6464 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
6465 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
6466 Act of May
31,
1790, §
1,
1 stat.
124.
</para></footnote>
6469 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
6470 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
6471 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
6472 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
6473 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
6474 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
6478 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
6479 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
6480 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
6481 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
6482 domain.
<footnote><para>
6484 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
6485 instance, of the
25,
006 copyrights registered in
1883, only
894 were
6486 renewed in
1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
6487 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, "Study No.
31: Renewal of Copyright,"
6488 Studies on Copyright, vol.
1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
6489 1963),
618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
6490 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, "Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,"
6491 University of Chicago Law Review
70 (
2003):
471,
498–501, and
6492 accompanying figures.
</para></footnote>
6495 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
6496 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
6497 out of print after one year.
<footnote><para>
6499 See Ringer, ch.
9, n.
2.
</para></footnote> When that happens, the
6500 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
6501 no longer effectively controlled by copyright. The only practical
6502 commercial use of the books at that time is to sell the books as used
6503 books; that use
—because it does not involve publication
—is
6507 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
6508 changed once. In
1831, the term was increased from a maximum of
28
6509 years to a maximum of
42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
6510 from
14 years to
28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
6511 the term increased once again. In
1909, Congress extended the renewal
6512 term of
14 years to
28 years, setting a maximum term of
56 years.
6515 Then, beginning in
1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
6516 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
6517 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
6518 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
6519 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
6520 In
1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
6521 And in
1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
6522 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
6525 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
6526 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
6527 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
6528 years, or
70 percent of the time since
1962. Thus, in the twenty years
6530 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
6531 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
6532 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
6533 of the expiration of a copyright term.
6536 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
6537 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
6538 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
6539 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
6540 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
6541 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
6542 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
6546 The United States abandoned this sensible system in
1976. For
6547 all works created after
1978, there was only one copyright term
—the
6548 maximum term. For "natural" authors, that term was life plus fifty
6549 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in
1992,
6550 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
6551 before
1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
6552 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
6553 was ninety-five years.
6556 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
6557 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
6558 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
6559 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
6560 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
6561 that terms be "limited," we have no evidence that anything will limit
6565 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
6566 dramatic. In
1973, more than
85 percent of copyright owners failed to
6567 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
6568 in
1973 was just
32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
6569 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
6570 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from
32.2 years to
95
6571 years.
<footnote><para>
6573 These statistics are understated. Between the years
1910 and
1962 (the
6574 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
6575 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
6576 Posner, "Indefinitely Renewable Copyright," loc. cit.
6579 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
6581 <sect2 id=
"lawscope">
6582 <title>Law: Scope
</title>
6584 The "scope" of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
6585 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
6586 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
6587 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
6590 In
1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only "maps,
6591 charts, and books." That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
6592 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
6593 the author the exclusive right to "publish" copyrighted works. That
6594 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
6595 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
6596 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
6597 did not extend to what lawyers call "derivative works." It would not,
6598 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
6599 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
6600 (such as a drama based on a published book).
6603 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
6604 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
6605 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
6606 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
6607 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
6608 work not only the exclusive right to "publish" the work, but also the
6609 exclusive right of control over any "copies" of that work. And most
6610 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
6611 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
6612 "derivative work" that might grow out of the original work. In this
6613 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
6614 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
6615 on the initial creative work.
6618 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
6619 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
6620 complete removal of the renewal requirement in
1992. In addition
6621 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
6622 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
6623 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
6624 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
6625 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
6626 famous
© or the word copyright. And for most of the history of
6627 American copyright law, there was a requirement that works be
6628 deposited with the government before a copyright could be secured.
6631 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
6632 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
6633 in the first ten years of the Republic,
95 percent of works eligible
6634 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
6635 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
6636 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
6637 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
6638 copyrighted
—that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
6639 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
6640 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
6641 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
6645 All of these "formalities" were abolished in the American system when
6646 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
6647 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
6648 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
6649 a
©; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
6650 copy available for others to copy.
6653 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
6657 If, in
1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the
5 percent who
6658 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
6659 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
6660 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
6661 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In
1790, there were
6662 174 publishers in the United States.
<footnote><para>
6664 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, "Poets, Pirates, and the
6666 of American Literature,"
29 New York University Journal of
6668 Law and Politics
255 (
1997), and James Gilraeth, ed., Federal
6669 Copyright Records,
1790–1800 (U.S. G.P.O.,
1987).
6671 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
6672 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
6673 the United States
—publishers.
6676 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
6677 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your
6678 poem by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my
6679 act was totally unregulated by the
1790 act. If I took your novel and
6680 made a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
6681 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
6683 activities remained free, while the activities of publishers were
6687 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
6688 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
6689 every note to your spouse, every doodle, every creative act that's
6691 to a tangible form
—all of this is automatically copyrighted.
6692 There is no need to register or mark your work. The protection follows
6693 the creation, not the steps you take to protect it.
6696 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
6697 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
6698 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
6701 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
6703 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
6704 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of "derivative
6705 rights." If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
6706 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
6707 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
6708 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
6709 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
6711 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
6712 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
6715 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
6716 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
6718 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
6720 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
6721 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
6722 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
6723 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
6727 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
6728 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power within
6729 a free culture
—at least, it's astonishing when you understand that the
6730 law applies not just to the commercial publisher but to anyone with a
6731 computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating and selling someone
6732 else's work. But whatever that wrong is, transforming someone else's
6733 work is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
6734 all
—they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should not
6736 derivative rights at all.
<footnote><para>
6738 Jonathan Zittrain, "The Copyright Cage," Legal Affairs, July/August
6740 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
26</ulink>.
6741 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
6743 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
6744 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
6745 the wrong of direct piracy.
6748 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same
6749 way. I can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my
6750 book. I can go to court and get an injunction against your
6752 use of my book.
<footnote><para>
6754 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
6755 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the perspective
6756 of the First Amendment) between mere "copies" and derivative works. See
6757 Jed Rubenfeld, "The Freedom of Imagination: Copyright's
6759 Yale Law Journal
112 (
2002):
1–60 (see especially pp.
53–59).
6761 These two different uses of my creative work are
6765 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why
6766 should you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes
6767 money from it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney
6769 a creature called "Mickey Mouse," why should you be able to make
6770 Mickey Mouse toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney
6774 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
6775 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
6777 to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from the
6778 rights originally granted.
6781 <sect2 id=
"lawreach">
6782 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach
</title>
6784 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
6785 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
6786 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
6787 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.
<footnote><para>
6789 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law certainly
6790 regulates more than "copies"
—a public performance of a copyrighted
6791 song, for example, is regulated even though performance per se doesn't
6792 make a copy;
17 United States Code, section
106(
4). And it certainly
6794 doesn't regulate a "copy";
17 United States Code, section
112(a). But
6795 the presumption under the existing law (which regulates "copies;"
17
6796 United States Code, section
102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
6800 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
6801 "Copies." That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for copyright
6802 law to regulate. But as with Jack Valenti's argument at the start of this
6803 chapter, that "creative property" deserves the "same rights" as all other
6804 property, it is the obvious that we need to be most careful about. For
6805 while it may be obvious that in the world before the Internet, copies
6806 were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon reflection, it should be
6807 obvious that in the world with the Internet, copies should not be the
6808 trigger for copyright law. More precisely, they should not always be the
6809 trigger for copyright law.
6812 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
6813 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
6814 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
6815 the law of copyright automatically applies,
<footnote><para>
6817 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law extends,
6818 we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good argument for
6819 its extending where it does, and should not determine its reach on the
6821 of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by technology.
6823 because it is clear that the
6824 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
6825 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
6828 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
6831 <figure id=
"fig-1521">
6832 <title>All potential uses of a book.
</title>
6833 <graphic fileref=
"images/1521.png"></graphic>
6836 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
6837 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
6838 all its potential uses. Most of these uses are unregulated by
6839 copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If you read a
6840 book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you give someone
6841 the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you resell a
6842 book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly states that
6843 after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can impose no
6844 further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you sleep on
6845 the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew it up,
6846 those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those acts do
6849 <figure id=
"fig-1531">
6850 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.
</title>
6851 <graphic fileref=
"images/1531.png"></graphic>
6854 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
6855 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
6856 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
6857 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
6858 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see first
6859 diagram on next page).
6862 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
6863 that remain unregulated because the law considers these "fair uses."
6865 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
6866 <figure id=
"fig-1541">
6867 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.
</title>
6868 <graphic fileref=
"images/1541.png"></graphic>
6871 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law treats
6872 as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
6874 You are free to quote from this book, even in a review that
6875 is quite negative, without my permission, even though that quoting
6876 makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright owner the
6877 exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not, but the law
6878 denies the owner any exclusive right over such "fair uses" for public
6879 policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
6881 <figure id=
"fig-1542">
6882 <title>Unregulated copying considered
"fair uses.
"</title>
6883 <graphic fileref=
"images/1542.png"></graphic>
6886 <figure id=
"fig-1551">
6887 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.
</title>
6888 <graphic fileref=
"images/1551.png"></graphic>
6891 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
6892 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
6893 sorts: (
1) unregulated uses, (
2) regulated uses, and (
3) regulated uses that
6894 are nonetheless deemed "fair" regardless of the copyright owner's views.
6897 Enter the Internet
—a distributed, digital network where every use
6898 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.
<footnote><para>
6900 I don't mean "nature" in the sense that it couldn't be different, but rather that
6901 its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks need not make
6902 copies of content they transmit, and a digital network could be designed to
6903 delete anything it copies so that the same number of copies remain.
6905 And because of this single,
6906 arbitrary feature of the design of a digital network, the scope of
6908 1 changes dramatically. Uses that before were presumptively
6910 are now presumptively regulated. No longer is there a set of
6911 presumptively unregulated uses that define a freedom associated with a
6912 copyrighted work. Instead, each use is now subject to the copyright,
6913 because each use also makes a copy
—category
1 gets sucked into
6915 2. And those who would defend the unregulated uses of
6917 work must look exclusively to category
3, fair uses, to bear the
6918 burden of this shift.
6921 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
6922 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would be
6923 no plausible copyright-related argument that the copyright owner could
6924 make to control that use of her book. Copyright law would have
6926 to say about whether you read the book once, ten times, or every
6927 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
6928 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of use
—reading
—
6929 could be regulated by copyright law because none of those uses
6934 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a
6936 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
6937 only once or only once a month, then copyright law would aid the
6939 owner in exercising this degree of control, because of the
6941 feature of copyright law that triggers its application upon there
6942 being a copy. Now if you read the book ten times and the license says
6943 you may read it only five times, then whenever you read the book (or
6944 any portion of it) beyond the fifth time, you are making a copy of the
6945 book contrary to the copyright owner's wish.
6948 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
6949 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
6950 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
6951 points also become clear:
6954 First, making category
1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
6955 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
6957 unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
6959 at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they allowed
6960 our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important part of
6961 free culture before the Internet.
6964 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
6966 uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand the wrong
6967 in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate any
6969 you make of creative work using a machine. "Copy and paste"
6970 and "cut and paste" become crimes. Tinkering with a story and
6972 it to others exposes the tinkerer to at least a requirement of
6974 However troubling the expansion with respect to copying a
6975 particular work, it is extraordinarily troubling with respect to
6977 uses of creative work.
6980 Third, this shift from category
1 to category
2 puts an extraordinary
6982 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
6983 burden on category
3 ("fair use") that fair use never before had to bear.
6984 If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I could read
6985 a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that this is a
6986 violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been any litigation
6987 about whether I have a fair use right to read, because before the
6989 reading did not trigger the application of copyright law and hence
6990 the need for a fair use defense. The right to read was effectively
6992 before because reading was not regulated.
6995 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
6996 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
6998 upon fair use
—never even addressing the earlier question about
6999 the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection grounded in
7000 fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are unregulated. But
7001 when everything becomes presumptively regulated, then the
7003 of fair use are not enough.
7006 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7007 in the business of making "trailer" advertisements for movies available
7008 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7009 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7010 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7013 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in
1997, it
7015 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7017 The idea was to expand their "selling by sampling" technique by
7018 giving on-line stores the same ability to enable "browsing." Just as in a
7019 bookstore you can read a few pages of a book before you buy the book,
7020 so, too, you would be able to sample a bit from the movie on-line
7025 In
1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film
7027 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7028 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7029 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7030 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7031 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter
—he had built a
7033 on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney films; he
7034 had customers who depended upon his delivering this content. Disney
7035 would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the distribution
7037 Video Pipeline thought it was within their "fair use" rights
7038 to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a lawsuit to ask the
7039 court to declare that these rights were in fact their rights.
7042 Disney countersued
—for $
100 million in damages. Those damages
7043 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had "willfully
7045 on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7047 infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the actual
7048 harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set in the
7049 statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred clips of
7050 Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those movies,
7051 Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $
100 million.
7054 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7055 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7056 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7057 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7058 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7059 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7060 Disney's permission.
7063 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts would
7064 consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change that gives
7065 Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't really control
7066 how people got access to their content. Once a video was in the
7068 the "first-sale doctrine" would free the seller to use the video as he
7069 wished, including showing portions of it in order to engender sales of the
7070 entire movie video. But with the Internet, it becomes possible for Disney
7071 to centralize control over access to this content. Because each use of the
7072 Internet produces a copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the
7073 copyright owner's control. The technology expands the scope of effective
7074 control, because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7077 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7078 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7080 is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes
& Noble has the right to say
7081 you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives them that right.
7082 But the market effectively protects against that abuse. If Barnes
&
7084 banned browsing, then consumers would choose other bookstores.
7085 Competition protects against the extremes. And it may well be (my
7087 so far does not even question this) that competition would prevent
7088 any similar danger when it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers
7090 the rights that authors have assigned to them might try to regulate
7091 how many times you read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book
7092 with anyone. But in a competitive market such as the book market, the
7093 dangers of this happening are quite slight.
7096 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7097 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7098 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7099 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7101 choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But in some
7102 contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7105 <sect2 id=
"lawforce">
7106 <title>Architecture and Law: Force
</title>
7108 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7109 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7110 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7111 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7114 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7115 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7116 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7117 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7118 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7121 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca
</primary></indexterm>
7123 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7124 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7125 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7126 Casablanca. Warner Brothers objected. They wrote a nasty letter to the
7127 Marxes, warning them that there would be serious legal consequences
7128 if they went forward with their plan.
<footnote><para>
7130 See David Lange, "Recognizing the Public Domain," Law and
7132 Problems
44 (
1981):
172–73.
7136 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7137 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers "were brothers long before
7138 you were."
<footnote><para>
7140 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs,
1–3.
7142 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word brothers,
7143 and if Warner Brothers insisted on trying to control Casablanca, then
7144 the Marx Brothers would insist on control over brothers.
7147 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7148 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7149 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7150 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7153 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because
7154 on the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by
7155 a machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7156 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7158 content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the problem
7159 with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no shame. Code
7160 would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The consequence of
7161 that is not at all funny.
7164 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7167 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook
7168 is not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7169 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7171 and the publisher delivers the content by using the technology.
7174 On the next page is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook
7178 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7179 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7180 public domain: Middlemarch, for example, is in the public domain.
7181 Some of them reproduce content that is not in the public domain: My
7182 own book The Future of Ideas is not yet within the public domain.
7183 Consider Middlemarch first. If you click on my e-book copy of
7184 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7185 Middlemarch, you'll see a fancy cover, and then a button at the bottom
7188 <figure id=
"fig-1611">
7189 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader
</title>
7190 <graphic fileref=
"images/1611.png"></graphic>
7193 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7194 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7196 <figure id=
"fig-1612">
7197 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.
</title>
7198 <graphic fileref=
"images/1612.png"></graphic>
7201 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7202 According to my eBook
7203 Reader, I have the permission
7204 to copy to the clipboard of the
7205 computer ten text selections
7206 every ten days. (So far, I've
7207 copied no text to the clipboard.)
7208 I also have the permission to
7209 print ten pages from the book
7210 every ten days. Lastly, I have
7211 the permission to use the Read
7212 Aloud button to hear
7214 read aloud through the
7218 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7219 translation): Aristotle's Politics.
7221 <figure id=
"fig-1621">
7222 <title>E-book of Aristotle;s
"Politics
"</title>
7223 <graphic fileref=
"images/1621.png"></graphic>
7226 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7227 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
7230 <figure id=
"fig-1622">
7231 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle;s
"Politics
".
</title>
7232 <graphic fileref=
"images/1622.png"></graphic>
7235 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
7236 original e-book version of my last book, The Future of Ideas:
7238 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
7239 <figure id=
"fig-1631">
7240 <title>List of the permissions for
"The Future of Ideas
".
</title>
7241 <graphic fileref=
"images/1631.png"></graphic>
7244 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
7247 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls "permissions"
—
7248 as if the publisher has the power to control how you use these works.
7249 For works under copyright, the copyright owner certainly does have
7250 the power
—up to the limits of the copyright law. But for work not
7252 copyright, there is no such copyright power.
<footnote><para>
7254 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might, for
7255 example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I will read
7256 it only three times, or that I promise to read it three times. But that
7258 (and the limits for creating that obligation) would come from the
7259 contract, not from copyright law, and the obligations of contract would
7260 not necessarily pass to anyone who subsequently acquired the book.
7263 Middlemarch says I have the permission to copy only ten text selections
7264 into the memory every ten days, what that really means is that the
7265 eBook Reader has enabled the publisher to control how I use the book
7266 on my computer, far beyond the control that the law would enable.
7269 The control comes instead from the code
—from the technology
7270 within which the e-book "lives." Though the e-book says that these are
7271 permissions, they are not the sort of "permissions" that most of us deal
7272 with. When a teenager gets "permission" to stay out till midnight, she
7273 knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out till
2 A.M., but
7274 will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when the Adobe eBook
7275 Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies of the text into
7276 the computer's memory, that means that after I've made ten copies, the
7277 computer will not make any more. The same with the printing
7279 After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not print any more pages.
7280 It's the same with the silly restriction that says that you can't use the
7281 Read Aloud button to read my book aloud
—it's not that the company
7282 will sue you if you do; instead, if you push the Read Aloud button with
7283 my book, the machine simply won't read aloud.
7286 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
7287 These are controls, not permissions. Imagine a world where the
7288 Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when you tried to
7289 type "Warner Brothers," erased "Brothers" from the sentence.
7292 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright law as
7293 copyright code. The controls over access to content will not be controls
7294 that are ratified by courts; the controls over access to content will be
7295 controls that are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that
7296 are built into the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls
7297 that are built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
7300 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
7301 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
7303 that limited the ability of users to copy the software, but those
7304 were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial to defeat these
7305 protections as well?
7308 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
7312 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a
7314 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for
7315 free on the Adobe site was a copy of Alice's Adventures in Wonderland.
7316 This wonderful book is in the public domain. Yet when you clicked on
7317 Permissions for that book, you got the following report:
7319 <figure id=
"fig-1641">
7320 <title>List of the permissions for
"Alice's Adventures in
7321 Wonderland
".
</title>
7322 <graphic fileref=
"images/1641.png"></graphic>
7325 <!-- PAGE BREAK 164 -->
7326 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not
7328 to copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
7330 indicated, not allowed to "read aloud"!
7333 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
7334 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
7335 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
7336 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
7337 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
7338 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
7341 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
7342 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
7343 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
7344 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
7345 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
7346 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
7347 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
7348 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
7349 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
7350 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
7351 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
7354 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
7355 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
7356 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
7357 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
7358 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
7362 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
7363 story of mine that makes the same point.
7365 <indexterm id=
"idxaibo" class='startofrange'
>
7366 <primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary>
7369 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named "Aibo." The Aibo
7370 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
7371 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
7374 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
7375 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
7376 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
7377 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165 -->
7378 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
7379 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
7380 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
7383 "Teach" here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
7384 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
7385 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
7386 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
7387 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
7388 their computer "dog" to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
7391 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the
7392 word hack has a particularly unfriendly connotation. Nonprogrammers
7393 hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in horror movies do even
7394 worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call them, hack is a much
7395 more positive term. Hack just means code that enables the program to
7396 do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to do. If you buy
7397 a new printer for an old computer, you might find the old computer
7398 doesn't run, or "drive," the printer. If you discovered that, you'd later be
7399 happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone who has written a
7400 driver to enable the computer to drive the printer you just bought.
7403 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
7404 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
7405 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
7406 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
7410 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
7411 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
7412 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
7413 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
7414 than Sony had built.
7416 <indexterm startref=
"idxaibo" class='endofrange'
/>
7418 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
7419 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
7420 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
7421 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
7424 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
7425 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
7426 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
7427 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
7428 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
7429 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
7430 thought, What possible problem could there be with teaching a robot
7434 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show
—
7435 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
7436 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
7437 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
7438 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
7439 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
7440 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
7441 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
7442 into being silent about something he knew very well.
7445 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April
2001.
<footnote><para>
7447 See Pamela Samuelson, "Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,"
7448 Science
293 (
2001):
2028; Brendan I. Koerner, "Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
7449 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks," American Prospect,
7450 January
2002; "Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
7451 DMCA," Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter,
11 December
2001; Bill
7452 Holland, "Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns," Billboard,
7453 May
2001; Janelle Brown, "Is the RIAA Running Scared?" Salon.com,
7454 April
2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, "Frequently Asked
7455 Questions about Felten and USENIX v. RIAA Legal Case," available at
7456 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
27</ulink>.
7457 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation
</primary></indexterm>
7459 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
7460 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
7461 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
7462 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
7465 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
7466 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
7467 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
7468 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
7469 "this music cannot be copied," and have a computer respect that
7470 command. The technology was to be part of a "trusted system" of
7471 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
7475 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
7476 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
7477 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
7478 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
7481 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
7482 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
7483 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
7484 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
7485 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
7488 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
7489 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
7490 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
7491 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
7492 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
7493 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
7496 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
7497 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
7498 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
7499 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
7500 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
7501 constituted, succeed.
7504 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
7505 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
7506 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
7511 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
7512 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
7513 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
7517 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
7518 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
7519 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
7523 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
7524 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
7525 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
7526 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
7527 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act ("DMCA").
7531 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
7532 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
7533 spreading such information an offense.
7536 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
7537 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
7538 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
7539 These new technologies would be copyright protection technologies
—
7540 technologies to control the replication and distribution of copyrighted
7541 material. They were designed as code to modify the original code of the
7542 Internet, to reestablish some protection for copyright owners.
7545 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
7546 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
7547 legal code intended to buttress software code which itself was
7548 intended to support the legal code of copyright.
7551 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
7552 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
7553 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
7554 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
7555 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
7556 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
7557 have been a copyright violation.
7560 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
7561 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
7562 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
7563 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
7564 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
7565 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
7566 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
7567 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
7568 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
7569 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
7572 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
7573 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
7574 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
7575 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
7576 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
7577 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
7580 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
7581 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
7582 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
7583 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
7584 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
7585 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka "Mr. Rogers," for example, had
7586 testified in that case that he wanted people to feel free to tape
7587 Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
7591 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
7592 "Neighborhood" at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
7593 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
7594 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
7595 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
7596 "Neighborhood" off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the "Neighborhood"
7597 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
7598 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
7599 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
7600 broadcasting has always been "You are an important person just the way
7601 you are. You can make healthy decisions." Maybe I'm going on too long,
7602 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
7603 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
7604 important.
<footnote><para>
7606 Sony Corporation of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc.,
464 U.S.
417,
7607 455 fn.
27 (
1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
7608 James Lardner, Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
7609 the VCR (New York: W. W. Norton,
1987),
270–71.
7614 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
7615 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
7616 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
7617 the VCR responsible.
7620 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
7624 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
7627 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
7628 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
7629 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
7630 pirating of copyrighted material
—a bad end. Or they can be used
7631 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
7632 would be considered fair use
—a good end.
7635 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
7636 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
7637 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
7638 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
7639 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
7642 <figure id=
"fig-1711">
7643 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.
</title>
7644 <graphic fileref=
"images/1711.png"></graphic>
7647 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
7648 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
7649 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: No one ever died from
7650 copyright circumvention. Yet the law bans circumvention technologies
7651 absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some good, but
7652 permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
7655 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
7656 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
7657 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
7658 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
7659 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
7660 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
7663 This is how code becomes law. The controls built into the technology
7664 of copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
7665 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the law
—increasing its
7666 regulation, even if the subject it regulates (activities that would otherwise
7667 plainly constitute fair use) is beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes
7668 law; code extends the law; code thus extends the control that copyright
7669 owners effect
—at least for those copyright holders with the lawyers
7670 who can write the nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
7673 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
7674 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
7675 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
7676 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
7677 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
7678 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
7679 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
7680 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
7681 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
7685 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
7686 For example, imagine you were part of a Star Trek fan club. You
7687 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
7688 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
7689 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
7690 simply continue it.
<footnote><para>
7692 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, "Legal Fictions,
7693 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law," Loyola of Los Angeles
7694 Entertainment Law Journal
17 (
1997):
651.
7698 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
7699 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
7700 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
7701 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
7702 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
7705 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
7706 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
7707 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
7708 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
7709 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
7710 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
7711 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
7712 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
7715 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
7716 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
7717 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
7718 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
7719 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
7720 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
7723 <sect2 id=
"marketconcentration">
7724 <title>Market: Concentration
</title>
7726 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically
—tripled in
7727 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
7728 well
—from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
7729 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
7730 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
7732 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
7733 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
7734 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
7735 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
7736 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
7737 market for creative work, has become the single most important
7738 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
7739 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
7740 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
7744 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
7745 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
7746 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
7747 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
7748 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
7751 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
7752 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
7753 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
7754 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
7755 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
7756 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
7757 announced in June
2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
7758 live in a world where just three companies control more than percent
7762 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
7765 <indexterm><primary>BMG
</primary></indexterm>
7767 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
7768 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
7769 ownership, "five companies control
85 percent of our media sources."
<footnote><para>
7771 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
7772 Transportation Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st sess. (
22 May
2003)
7773 (statement of Senator John McCain).
</para></footnote>
7774 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
7775 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control
84.8 percent of the
7776 U.S. music market.
<footnote><para>
7778 Lynette Holloway, "Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
7779 Slide," New York Times,
23 December
2002.
7781 The "five largest cable companies pipe
7782 programming to
74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide."
<footnote><para>
7784 Molly Ivins, "Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped," Charleston Gazette,
7789 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
7790 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
7791 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
7792 seventy-five stations. Today one company owns more than
1,
200
7793 stations. During that period of consolidation, the total number of
7794 radio owners dropped by
34 percent. Today, in most markets, the two
7795 largest broadcasters control
74 percent of that market's
7796 revenues. Overall, just four companies control
90 percent of the
7797 nation's radio advertising revenues.
7800 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
7801 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
7802 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
7803 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
7804 the United States. The top ten film studios receive
99 percent of all
7805 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for
85 percent
7806 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
7807 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
7808 protected
— by the market.
7811 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
7812 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
7813 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
7814 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James
</primary></indexterm>
7818 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
7819 unmatched in its integration. They supply content
—Fox movies
7820 . . . Fox TV shows . . . Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
7821 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
7822 advertisers
—in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
7823 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
7824 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
7825 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
7826 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
7827 the same function in the United States.
<footnote><para>
7829 James Fallows, "The Age of Murdoch," Atlantic Monthly (September
7831 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James
</primary></indexterm>
7836 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
7837 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
7838 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
7839 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
7841 <figure id=
"fig-1761">
7842 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.
</title>
7843 <graphic fileref=
"images/1761.png"></graphic>
7846 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
7847 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
7848 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
7852 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
7853 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
7854 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
7855 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
7858 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
7859 integration may matter.
7861 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman
</primary></indexterm>
7862 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
7863 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family
</primary></indexterm>
7865 In
1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for All in the Family. He took
7866 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
7867 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
7868 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
7869 We wanted less edgy, not more.
7872 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
7873 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
7874 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
7875 control.
<footnote><para>
7877 Leonard Hill, "The Axis of Access," remarks before Weidenbaum Center
7878 Forum, "Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry," St. Louis,
7880 3 April
2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
7881 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
28</ulink>;
7882 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
7883 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
29</ulink>).
7888 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
7889 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
7890 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
7891 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
7892 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as
1992,
7893 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
7894 television
—75 percent of it
—was "independent" of the
7898 In
1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
7899 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In
1985,
7900 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
7901 2002, only five independent television studios remained. "In
1992,
7902 only
15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
7903 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
7904 controlled companies more than quintupled to
77 percent." "In
1992,
16
7905 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
7906 year there was one."
<footnote><para>
7908 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
7909 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st
7910 sess. (
2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
7911 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
7912 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
30</ulink>. Kimmelman
7913 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
7914 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia,
27 February
7917 In
2002,
75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
7918 that ran it. "In the ten-year period between
1992 and
2002, the number
7919 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
7920 increased over
200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
7921 per week produced by independent studios decreased
7922 63%."
<footnote><para>
7927 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family
</primary></indexterm>
7929 Today, another Norman Lear with another All in the Family would
7930 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
7931 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
7932 owned by the network.
7935 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
7936 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
7937 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
7938 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry
</primary></indexterm>
7939 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
7943 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
7944 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
7945 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
7946 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
7947 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
7948 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
7949 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
7950 handful.
<footnote><para>
7952 "Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation," Now with Bill Moyers, Bill
7953 Moyers,
25 April
2003, edited transcript available at
7954 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
31</ulink>.
7959 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
7960 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
7961 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
7962 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
7963 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
7964 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
7965 question without risk of consequence
—not necessarily banishment
7966 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
7967 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
7970 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.
</primary></indexterm>
7972 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
7973 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the "Innovator's
7974 Dilemma": the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
7975 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
7976 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
7977 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.
<footnote><para>
7979 Clayton M. Christensen, The Innovator's Dilemma: The
7980 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business
7981 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press,
1997). Christensen
7982 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
7983 Kim B. Clark, "The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
7984 Concepts in Technological Evolution," Research Policy
14 (
1985):
7985 235–51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
7986 Kaplan, Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
7987 Underperform the Market
—and How to Successfully Transform Them
7988 (New York: Currency/Doubleday,
2001).
</para></footnote>
7990 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
7991 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
7993 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.
</primary></indexterm>
7996 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
7997 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
7998 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8002 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8003 suggest the concern.
8006 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8007 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8008 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8011 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8012 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8013 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8015 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8016 wrecked by drugs
—though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8017 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8018 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8019 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8020 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8021 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8022 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8023 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8024 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8025 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8026 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8027 outweigh these costs.
8030 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8031 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8032 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8036 Beginning in
1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8037 a media campaign as part of the "war on drugs." The campaign produced
8038 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8039 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8040 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8041 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8042 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8043 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8044 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8045 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8048 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8049 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8052 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8053 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8054 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8058 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8059 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8060 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8061 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8062 message will be heard then?
8065 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8066 "controversial" ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8067 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8068 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8069 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8070 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8071 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8072 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8073 rights of the stations to be this biased.
<footnote><para>
8075 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February
2003, sought to place ads
8076 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8077 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as "against
8078 [their] policy." The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8079 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8080 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8081 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8082 Neal Levine,
15 October
2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8083 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, "On the Issue of
8084 an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV Networks," New
8085 York Times,
13 March
2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time
8086 there is very little that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to
8087 even the playing field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, "Ad
8088 Hoc Access: The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8089 Radio," Yale Law and Policy Review
6 (
1988):
449–79, and for a
8090 more recent summary of the stance of the FCC and the courts, see
8091 Radio-Television News Directors Association v. FCC,
184 F.
3d
872
8092 (D.C. Cir.
1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8093 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8094 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8095 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, "Antidiesel Group Fuming
8096 After Muni Rejects Ad," SFGate.com,
16 June
2003, available at
8097 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
32</ulink>. The ground
8098 was that the criticism was "too controversial."
8099 <indexterm><primary>Comcast
</primary></indexterm>
8100 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project
</primary></indexterm>
8101 <indexterm><primary>WJOA
</primary></indexterm>
8105 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well
—if we lived
8106 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8107 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8108 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8109 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8110 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8111 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8112 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8113 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8116 <sect2 id=
"together">
8117 <title>Together
</title>
8119 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8120 copyright warriors that the government should "protect my property."
8121 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8122 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8125 But when we see how dramatically this "property" has changed
—
8126 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8127 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8128 cultivate our culture is dramatically different
—the claim begins
8131 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8132 less innocent and obvious. Given (
1) the power of technology to
8133 supplement the law's control, and (
2) the power of concentrated
8134 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8135 the massively expanded "property" rights granted by copyright
8136 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8137 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8141 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8142 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8143 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8147 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8148 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8149 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8150 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8151 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8152 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8153 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8154 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8155 traditionally defined copyright's regulation
—a weakening of that
8156 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
8159 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
8160 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
8161 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
8162 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
8163 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
8164 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
8165 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
8166 future. And these changes have to be reductions in the scope of
8167 copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase in control that
8168 technology and the market enable.
8171 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
8172 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
8173 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
8174 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
8175 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
8176 Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control more of
8177 the development of our culture than now.
8179 <para> Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
8180 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
8181 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
8182 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
8183 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
8184 were independent of the networks. Never has copyright protected such a
8185 wide range of rights, against as broad a range of actors, for a term
8186 that was remotely as long. This form of regulation
—a tiny
8187 regulation of a tiny part of the creative energy of a nation at the
8188 founding
—is now a massive regulation of the overall creative
8189 process. Law plus technology plus the market now interact to turn this
8190 historically benign regulation into the most significant regulation of
8191 culture that our free society has known.
<footnote><para>
8193 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his "four surrenders" of
8194 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan,
159–60.
8198 This has been a long chapter. Its point can now be briefly stated.
8201 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
8202 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
8203 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
8204 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
8205 that copyright law has undergone. In
1790, the law looked like this:
8210 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"char">
8214 <entry>PUBLISH
</entry>
8215 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
8220 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
8221 <entry>©</entry>
8225 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
8234 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
8235 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
8236 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
8238 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
8239 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
8240 noncommercial work was also free.
8243 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
8248 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"char">
8252 <entry>PUBLISH
</entry>
8253 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
8258 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
8259 <entry>©</entry>
8260 <entry>©</entry>
8263 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
8272 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law
—if
8273 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
8274 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
8275 transformation were still essentially free.
8278 In
1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
8279 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
8280 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
8281 expanded. Thus by
1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
8282 we could say the law began to look like this:
8287 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"char">
8292 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
8297 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
8298 <entry>©</entry>
8299 <entry>©</entry>
8302 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
8303 <entry>©/Free
</entry>
8311 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
8312 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
8313 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
8314 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
8315 that the law now looks like this:
8320 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"char">
8325 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
8330 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
8331 <entry>©</entry>
8332 <entry>©</entry>
8335 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
8336 <entry>©</entry>
8337 <entry>©</entry>
8344 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
8345 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
8347 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
8348 commercial or not, transformative or not
—with the same rules
8349 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
8352 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
8353 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
8354 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
8355 these domains actually does any good.
8358 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
8359 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
8360 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
8361 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
8362 reasons sketched especially in chapters
7 and
8, one might well wonder
8363 whether it does more harm than good for commercial transformation.
8364 More commercial transformative work would be created if derivative
8365 rights were more sharply restricted.
8368 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
8369 course copyright is a kind of "property," and of course, as with any
8370 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
8371 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
8372 property rights
<footnote><para>
8374 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
8375 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
8376 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, "The
8377 Disintegration of Property," in Nomos XXII: Property, J. Roland
8378 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
8381 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
8382 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
8383 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
8384 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the "copyright"
8385 did not control at all the freedom of others to build upon or
8386 transform a creative work. American culture was born free, and for
8387 almost
180 years our country consistently protected a vibrant and rich
8391 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
8392 limits on the scope of the interests protected by "property." The very
8393 birth of "copyright" as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
8394 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
8395 story of chapter
6). The tradition of "fair use" is animated by a
8396 similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the costs of
8397 exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the story of
8399 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
8400 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
8401 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter
8402 8). And granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect,
8403 claims of property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing
8404 the soul of a culture (chapter
9). Free cultures, like free markets,
8405 are built with property. But the nature of the property that builds a
8406 free culture is very different from the extremist vision that
8407 dominates the debate today.
8410 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
8411 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
8412 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
8413 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
8414 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
8415 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
8416 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
8417 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
8418 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
8419 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
8422 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
8426 <chapter id=
"c-puzzles">
8427 <title>PUZZLES
</title>
8429 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
8430 <sect1 id=
"chimera">
8431 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
</title>
8432 <indexterm id=
"idxchimera" class='startofrange'
>
8433 <primary>chimeras
</primary>
8435 <indexterm id=
"idxwells" class='startofrange'
>
8436 <primary>Wells, H. G.
</primary>
8438 <indexterm id=
"idxtcotb" class='startofrange'
>
8439 <primary>"Country of the Blind, The
" (Wells)
</primary>
8443 In a well-known short story by H. G. Wells, a mountain climber
8444 named Nunez trips (literally, down an ice slope) into an unknown and
8445 isolated valley in the Peruvian Andes.
<footnote><para>
8447 H. G. Wells, "The Country of the Blind" (
1904,
1911). See H. G. Wells,
8448 The Country of the Blind and Other Stories, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
8449 York: Oxford University Press,
1996).
8451 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with "sweet water, pasture,
8452 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
8453 that bore an excellent fruit." But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
8454 takes this as an opportunity. "In the Country of the Blind," he tells
8455 himself, "the One-Eyed Man is King." So he resolves to live with the
8456 villagers to explore life as a king.
8459 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
8460 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
8461 "blind." They don't have the word blind. They think he's just thick.
8462 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
8463 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
8464 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. "`You
8465 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
8466 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
8470 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
8471 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
8472 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
8473 affection, a young woman who to him seems "the most beautiful thing in
8474 the whole of creation," understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
8475 description of what he sees "seemed to her the most poetical of
8476 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
8477 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
8478 indulgence." "She did not believe," Wells tells us, and "she could
8479 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted."
8482 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his "mysteriously delighted"
8483 love, the father and the village object. "You see, my dear," her
8484 father instructs, "he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
8485 anything right." They take Nunez to the village doctor.
8488 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. "His brain
8489 is affected," he reports.
8492 "What affects it?" the father asks. "Those queer things that are
8493 called the eyes . . . are diseased . . . in such a way as to affect
8497 The doctor continues: "I think I may say with reasonable certainty
8498 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
8499 simple and easy surgical operation
—namely, to remove these
8500 irritant bodies [the eyes]."
8503 "Thank Heaven for science!" says the father to the doctor. They inform
8504 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
8505 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
8506 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
8507 It sometimes happens that the eggs of twins fuse in the mother's
8508 womb. That fusion produces a "chimera." A chimera is a single creature
8509 with two sets of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be
8510 different from the DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
8512 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
8513 plot for murder mysteries. "But the DNA shows with
100 percent
8514 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
8517 <indexterm startref=
"idxtcotb" class='endofrange'
/>
8518 <indexterm startref=
"idxwells" class=
"endofrange"/>
8520 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
8521 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
8522 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
8523 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
8524 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
8525 understanding of a "person" should reflect this reality.
8528 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
8529 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
8530 unfairly enough, "the copyright wars," the more I think we're dealing
8531 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question "What is
8532 p2p file sharing?" both sides have it right, and both sides have it
8533 wrong. One side says, "File sharing is just like two kids taping each
8534 others' records
—the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
8535 thirty years without any question at all." That's true, at least in
8536 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
8537 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
8538 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
8539 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
8542 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
8543 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
8544 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
8545 "friends" beyond recognition to say "my ten thousand best friends" can
8546 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
8547 what "we have always been allowed to do," we have not always been
8548 allowed to share music with "our ten thousand best friends."
8551 Likewise, when the other side says, "File sharing is just like walking
8552 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
8553 with it," that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
8554 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
8555 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
8560 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
8561 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
8562 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
8563 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
8564 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
8565 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
8566 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
8567 $
1,
000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
8568 CD, I'm liable for $
1,
500,
000 in damages.)
8571 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
8572 that it is both
—both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
8573 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
8574 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
8575 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
8578 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
8579 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
8580 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
8581 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
8582 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
8583 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
8584 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
8585 implemented.
<footnote><para>
8587 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
8588 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
8589 "Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,"
27 June
2003,
8591 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
8592 #
33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
8593 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
8594 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
8595 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, "House Bill Aims to Up
8596 Stakes on Piracy," Los Angeles Times,
17 July
2003, available at
8597 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
34</ulink>. Civil
8598 penalties are currently set at $
150,
000 per copied song. For a recent
8599 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
8600 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than
600 songs
8601 through a family computer, see RIAA v. Verizon Internet Services (In
8602 re. Verizon Internet Services),
240 F. Supp.
2d
24
8603 (D.D.C.
2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $
90
8604 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
8605 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
8606 $
12,
000 to $
17,
500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
8607 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $
98
8608 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
8609 Elizabeth Young, "Downloading Could Lead to Fines," redandblack.com,
8610 August
2003, available at
8611 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
35</ulink>. For an
8612 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
8613 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
8614 identities, see James Collins, "RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
8615 Name Students," Boston Globe,
8 August
2003, D3, available at
8616 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
36</ulink>.
8617 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.
</primary></indexterm>
8621 <indexterm startref=
"idxchimera" class='endofrange'
/>
8623 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
8624 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
8625 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
8626 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
8627 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
8630 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
8631 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
8632 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
8633 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
8634 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
8635 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe either extreme would be worse than a
8636 reasonable alternative. But I believe the zero-tolerance solution
8637 would be the worse of the two extremes.
8641 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
8642 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
8643 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
8644 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
8645 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
8646 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
8647 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
8650 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to "steal" music. My
8651 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
8652 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
8653 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
8654 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
8655 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
8656 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
8657 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
8658 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
8659 protection for copyrighted material,
8663 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
8664 material, and we want to protect those rights.
8667 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of
8668 the major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
8669 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
8671 that question. Market forces operating naturally may very
8672 well produce a totally different industry model.
8675 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
8676 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
8677 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
8678 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
8679 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
8680 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
8681 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
8682 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
8683 interests.
<footnote><para>
8684 <!-- f3. --> WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to
8685 Digital Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before
8686 the Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer
8688 House Committee on Commerce,
106th Cong.
29 (
1999) (statement
8689 of Peter Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
8691 available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
8697 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
8699 In April
2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
8700 one of "the major labels." Its position on these matters has now
8704 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
8705 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture, and will
8706 kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
8709 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
8712 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
</title>
8715 To fight "piracy," to protect "property," the content industry has
8716 launched a war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have
8717 now brought the government into this war. As with any war, this one
8718 will have both direct and collateral damage. As with any war of
8720 these damages will be suffered most by our own people.
8723 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
8724 particular, the consequences for "free culture." But my aim now is to
8726 this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
8730 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
8731 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
8732 power of the property called "intellectual property" is at its greatest in
8735 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
8736 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
8738 Yet "common sense" does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
8739 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
8740 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
8741 rejection of "piracy" still has play.
8744 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
8745 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
8746 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
8747 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
8748 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
8749 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
8751 <sect2 id=
"constrain">
8752 <title>Constraining Creators
</title>
8754 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
8755 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
8756 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
8757 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
8758 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
8759 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
8760 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
8761 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
8762 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
8763 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
8764 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
8765 weave together a string
—a mash-up
— of songs from your
8766 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
8769 This digital "capturing and sharing" is in part an extension of the
8770 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
8771 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
8772 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
8773 of digital "capturing and sharing" promises a world of extraordinarily
8774 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
8775 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
8776 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
8777 the culture all around.
8780 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
8781 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
8783 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
8785 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
8786 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
8787 storytelling extended across the globe.
8790 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
8791 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
8792 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
8793 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
8794 that catalog cartoons from the
1960s; sites that mix images and sound
8795 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
8796 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
8797 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
8798 work is presumptively illegal.
8801 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
8802 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
8803 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
8804 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
8805 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
8806 by the RIAA ( Jesse Jordan of chapter
3 was just one) were threatened
8807 with a $
98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted
8808 songs to be copied. Yet World-Com
—which defrauded investors of
8809 $
11 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization
8810 of over $
200 billion
—received a fine of a mere $
750
8811 million.
<footnote><para>
8813 See Lynne W. Jeter, Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom
8814 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley
& Sons,
2003),
176,
204; for details of
8815 the settlement, see MCI press release, "MCI Wins U.S. District Court
8816 Approval for SEC Settlement" (
7 July
2003), available at
8817 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
37</ulink>.
8818 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom
</primary></indexterm>
8820 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
8821 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
8822 no more than $
250,
000 in damages for pain and
8823 suffering.
<footnote>
8825 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
8826 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July
2003. For
8827 an overview, see Tanya Albert, "Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
8828 Say Tort Reformers," amednews.com,
28 July
2003, available at
8829 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
38</ulink>,
8830 and "Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps," CBSNews.com,
9 July
2003,
8832 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
8834 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.
</primary></indexterm>
8836 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
8837 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
8838 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
8839 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom
</primary></indexterm>
8842 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
8843 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will either
8844 never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive this
8846 process underground by branding the modern-day Walt Disneys
8847 "pirates." We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a public
8848 domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are designed to
8850 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
8851 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right to
8853 and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As was the
8854 case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons, we will
8856 to see a world of underground art
—not because the message is
8858 political, or because the subject is controversial, but because the
8859 very act of creating the art is legally fraught. Already, exhibits of
8861 art" tour the United States.
<footnote><para>
8862 <!-- f3. --> See Danit Lidor, "Artists Just Wanna Be Free," Wired,
7 July
2003,
8865 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
8866 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
41</ulink>.
8868 In what does their "illegality" consist?
8869 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
8870 critical or reflective.
8873 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
8874 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
10. But an
8875 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
8876 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
8877 discovered in
2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
8878 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
8879 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
8880 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
8881 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
8884 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
8885 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
8886 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
8887 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
8888 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
8889 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
8890 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
8891 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
8892 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
8895 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
8896 described in chapter
7, in response to the story about documentary
8897 filmmaker Jon Else, I have been lectured again and again by lawyers
8898 who insist Else's use was fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the
8899 law regulates such a use.
8903 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
8904 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
8905 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
8906 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad
—in
8907 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
8908 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
8909 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
8910 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
8911 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
8914 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
8915 "breathing room" between regulation by the law and the access the law
8916 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
8917 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
8918 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
8919 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
8920 journalists
— these are the real laws governing creativity. And
8921 these rules have little relationship to the "law" with which judges
8925 For in a world that threatens $
150,
000 for a single willful
8926 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
8927 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
8928 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
8929 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak
—in that
8930 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
8931 "copyright" silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
8932 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
8933 culture that is free.
8936 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
8940 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
8941 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
8942 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
8943 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made . . . you're not
8944 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
8945 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
8946 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, "This has been
8947 cleared." You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
8948 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
8952 <sect2 id=
"innovators">
8953 <title>Constraining Innovators
</title>
8955 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
8956 story
—creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
8957 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
8958 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
8959 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
8960 think there's little in this story to worry you.
8963 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
8964 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
8965 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
8966 one at that,
188 pages into a book like this), then you can see this
8967 other aspect by substituting "free market" every place I've spoken of
8968 "free culture." The point is the same, even if the interests
8969 affecting culture are more fundamental.
8972 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
8973 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
8974 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary
—at
8975 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
8976 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
8977 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
8978 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
8979 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
8980 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
8981 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
8982 against the competitors of tomorrow.
8984 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
8986 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
8987 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
8988 strategy that I described in chapter
10. The consequence of this
8989 massive threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright
8990 law is that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely
8991 innovate only if they have the sign-off from last generation's
8992 dominant industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of
8993 cases that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
8994 lesson. That lesson
—what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
8995 "nuclear pall" that has fallen over the Valley
—has been learned.
8998 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
8999 I told in The Future of Ideas and which has progressed in a way that
9000 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9003 In
1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9004 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9005 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9006 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9007 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9008 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9011 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9012 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9013 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9014 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9018 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9019 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9020 preference data. In January
2000, the company launched a service
9021 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9022 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9023 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9024 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9025 wherever you were
—at work or at home
—you could get access
9026 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9027 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9030 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9031 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9033 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9034 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9035 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9036 the kind of content the users liked.
9039 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy
50,
000
9040 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9041 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9042 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9043 therefore purchased
50,
000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9044 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9045 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9046 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was
50,
000
9047 copies, it was
50,
000 copies directed at giving customers something
9048 they had already bought.
9051 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9052 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9053 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9054 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9055 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9056 MP3.com of $
118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9057 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $
54 million. Vivendi
9058 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9061 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9064 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9065 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9066 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9067 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9068 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9069 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9070 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9074 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9075 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9076 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9078 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9079 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9080 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9081 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9082 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9084 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John
</primary></indexterm>
9085 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
9087 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April
2003,
9088 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9089 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9090 its development, its cofounder ( John Hummer), and general partner
9091 (Hank Barry).
<footnote><para>
9092 <!-- f4. --> See Joseph Menn, "Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor," Los Angeles
9093 Times,
23 April
2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9095 in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, "The Music
9097 Will Not Be Digitized," Salon.com,
1 June
2001, available at
9098 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
42</ulink>.
9099 See also Jon Healey, "Online Music Services Besieged," Los Angeles
9102 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have
9103 recognized the right of the content industry to control how the
9105 should develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a
9106 company whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again,
9107 the aim of the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if
9108 you fund a company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs,
9109 you are at risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well.
9110 Your investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
9111 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers
9112 are afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in Business
9113 2.0, Rafe Needleman describes a discussion with BMW:
9116 <indexterm><primary>BMW
</primary></indexterm>
9118 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
9119 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
9120 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
9121 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
9122 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
9123 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
9124 United States with bona fide MP3 players. . . .
<footnote>
9127 Rafe Needleman, "Driving in Cars with MP3s," Business
2.0,
16 June
9129 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
43</ulink>. I am grateful
9130 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
9131 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe
</primary></indexterm>
9136 This is the world of the mafia
—filled with "your money or your
9137 life" offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
9138 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
9139 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
9140 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
9141 constantly threatened by litigation.
9145 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
9146 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
9147 enterprises. The point is the definition of "illegal." The law is a mess of
9148 uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply to new
9149 technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial deference, and
9150 by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that copyright law
9152 that uncertainty now yields a reality which is far more
9154 than is right. If the law imposed the death penalty for parking
9155 tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets, we'd also have much
9156 less driving. The same principle applies to innovation. If innovation is
9157 constantly checked by this uncertain and unlimited liability, we will
9158 have much less vibrant innovation and much less creativity.
9161 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
9162 use. Whatever the "real" law is, realism about the effect of law in
9163 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
9164 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
9165 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
9166 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
9167 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
9168 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
9169 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
9170 produce an overregulatedregulated market.
9173 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
9174 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
9175 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
9176 culture
—a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
9177 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
9178 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
9179 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
9180 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
9181 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
9182 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
9183 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
9184 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
9185 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
9186 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
9187 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
9188 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
9189 result. The uncertainty of the law is one burden on innovation. There
9190 is a second burden that operates more directly. This is the effort by
9191 many in the content industry to use the law to directly regulate the
9192 technology of the Internet so that it better protects their content.
9195 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
9196 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
9197 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
9198 this feature is a "bug." The efficient spread of content means that
9199 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
9200 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
9201 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables "piracy," then,
9202 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
9205 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
9206 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
9207 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
9208 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.
<footnote><para>
9209 <!-- f6. --> "Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World," GartnerG2 and
9210 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
9211 (
2003),
33–35, available at
9212 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
44</ulink>.
9216 has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
9218 flag" that would be required on any device capable of transmitting
9219 digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable the copying of
9220 any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other members of
9221 Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from liability
9222 for technology they might deploy that would hunt down copyright
9224 and disable their machines.
<footnote><para>
9225 <!-- f7. --> GartnerG2,
26–27.
9230 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
9231 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
9233 of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the particular
9234 technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens and costs on
9236 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
9237 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
9241 In March
2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
9242 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation would
9243 impose.
<footnote><para>
9244 <!-- f8. --> See David McGuire, "Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy," Newsbytes,
9245 February
2002 (Entertainment).
9247 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not
9248 be protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
9252 There is one more obvious way in which this war has harmed
9253 innovation
—again,
9254 a story that will be quite familiar to the free market
9258 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
9259 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
9260 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
9261 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
9264 As I described in chapter
10, despite this feature of copyright as
9265 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by Jessica
9266 Litman in her book Digital Copyright,
<footnote><para>
9267 <!-- f9. --> Jessica Litman, Digital Copyright (Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books,
9270 overall this history of copyright
9271 is not bad. As chapter
10 details, when new technologies have come
9272 along, Congress has struck a balance to assure that the new is protected
9273 from the old. Compulsory, or statutory, licenses have been one part of
9274 that strategy. Free use (as in the case of the VCR) has been another.
9277 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
9278 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
9279 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
9280 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
9281 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
9284 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.
<footnote><para>
9285 <!-- f10. --> The only circuit court exception is found in Recording Industry Association
9286 of America (RIAA) v. Diamond Multimedia Systems,
180 F.
3d
1072 (
9th
9287 Cir.
1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit reasoned that
9288 makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for contributory
9290 infringement for a device that is unable to record or redistribute
9292 (a device whose only copying function is to render portable a music file
9293 already stored on a user's hard drive).
9294 At the district court level, the only exception is found in
9296 Studios, Inc. v. Grokster, Ltd.,
259 F. Supp.
2d
1029 (C.D.
9297 Cal.,
2003), where the court found the link between the distributor and
9298 any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the distributor liable for
9299 contributory or vicarious infringement liability.
9302 mirrored in the responses threatened and actually implemented by
9303 Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses here.
<footnote><para>
9305 For example, in July
2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
9306 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R.
5211), which would immunize
9307 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
9308 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
9309 August
2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
9310 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
9311 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a "broadcast flag" that
9312 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
9313 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
9314 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
9315 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, "Copyright and
9316 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,"
27 June
2003,
33–34,
9318 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
44</ulink>.
9319 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.
</primary></indexterm>
9321 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
9322 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
9326 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
9327 As I described in chapter
4, when a radio station plays a song, the
9328 recording artist doesn't get paid for that "radio performance" unless
9329 he or she is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had
9330 recorded a version of "Happy Birthday"
—to memorialize her famous
9331 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden
—
9332 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
9333 copyright owners of "Happy Birthday" would get some money, whereas
9334 Marilyn Monroe would not.
9337 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
9338 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
9339 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
9340 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
9341 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
9342 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
9343 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
9344 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
9348 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
9349 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
9350 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
9351 spectrum. Thus, I can "tune in" to an Internet radio station in
9352 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
9353 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
9357 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
9358 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
9359 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
9360 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
9361 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
9362 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
9363 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
9364 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
9365 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
9366 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
9367 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
9371 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
9372 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
9373 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
9374 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
9375 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
9376 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
9377 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
9382 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
9383 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
9384 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
9385 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
9386 than by technical restrictions. . . . Armstrong likened the situation
9387 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
9388 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
9389 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
9390 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
9391 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
9392 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
9393 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
9394 shackles.
<footnote><para>
9401 This potential for FM radio was never realized
—not
9402 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
9403 underestimated the power of "vested interests, habits, customs and
9404 legislation"
<footnote><para>
9408 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
9411 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
9412 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
9413 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
9414 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
9415 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
9419 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
9420 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
9422 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
9423 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the
9425 of Internet radio in
1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress
9426 to adopt a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
9427 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
9429 Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording of
9430 "Happy Birthday" on the air, Internet radio does. Not only is the law not
9431 neutral toward Internet radio
—the law actually burdens Internet radio
9432 more than it burdens terrestrial radio.
9435 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
9436 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
9437 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
9438 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
9439 over $
1 million a year.
<footnote>
9442 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
9443 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
9444 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
9445 iLaw (Stanford),
3 July
2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
9446 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
9447 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
9448 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No.
2000-
9, CARP
9449 DTRA
1 and
2, available at
9450 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
45</ulink>.
9451 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
9452 C. Picker, "Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
9453 Distribution," Antitrust Bulletin (Summer/Fall
2002):
461: "This was
9454 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
9455 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
9456 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
9457 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
9458 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way."
9459 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)
</primary></indexterm>
9460 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
9462 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
9466 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
9467 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio station)
9468 would have to collect the following data from every listening transaction:
9470 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
9471 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
9473 name of the service;
9476 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
9479 type of program (archived/looped/live);
9482 date of transmission;
9485 time of transmission;
9488 time zone of origination of transmission;
9491 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
9494 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
9497 sound recording title;
9500 ISRC code of the recording;
9503 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
9506 featured recording artist;
9515 UPC code of the retail album;
9521 copyright owner information;
9524 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
9527 name of the service or entity;
9533 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
9536 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
9539 time zone where the signal was received (user);
9542 Unique User identifier;
9545 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
9550 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
9551 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
9552 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
9553 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
9554 Internet radio has to pay a type of copyright fee that terrestrial radio
9558 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
9559 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
9560 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
9562 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
9564 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
9565 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
9566 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
9570 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
9571 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
9572 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
9573 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
9574 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
9575 webcasters asked the RIAA, . . . "How do you come up with a
9577 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
9578 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio?
9580 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who
9581 want to pay, and that should establish the market rate, and if you
9582 set the rate so high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out
9586 And the RIAA experts said, "Well, we don't really model this
9587 as an industry with thousands of webcasters, we think it should be
9588 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
9589 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market." (Emphasis added.)
9593 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
9594 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
9595 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
9596 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
9597 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
9598 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
9599 effective to prevent it.
9602 <sect2 id=
"corruptingcitizens">
9603 <title>Corrupting Citizens
</title>
9605 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
9607 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
9608 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
9611 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
9612 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
9613 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
9616 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
9617 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
9618 large number of citizens. According to The New York Times,
43 million
9619 Americans downloaded music in May
2002.
<footnote><para>
9620 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, "The Music Downloading Deluge," Pew
9621 Internet and American Life Project (
24 April
2001), available at
9622 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
46</ulink>.
9623 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that
37 million
9624 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early
2001.
9626 According to the RIAA,
9627 the behavior of those
43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
9628 set of rules that transform
20 percent of America into criminals. As the
9630 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
9631 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
9632 the world, but against students building search engines, and
9634 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
9635 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
9636 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
9638 response by the other.
9641 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
9642 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
9643 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
9644 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
9645 ($
15,
000,
000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
9646 paying all the money in the world in damages ($
250,
000 in legal fees)
9647 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
9648 ($
12,
000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
9649 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September
2003, the RIAA
9650 sued
261 individuals
—including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
9651 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
9652 was.
<footnote><para>
9654 Alex Pham, "The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case," Los
9655 Angeles Times,
10 September
2003, Business.
9657 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
9658 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
9659 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $
2,
000
9660 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
9661 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
9662 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
9666 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
9667 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
9668 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
9669 consumption of alcohol was
1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
9670 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just
30 percent
9671 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
9672 consumption was up to
70 percent of the preprohibition
9673 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
9674 number were criminals.
<footnote><para>
9676 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, "Alcohol Consumption During
9677 Prohibition," American Economic Review
81, no.
2 (
1991):
242.
9680 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
9681 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
9682 narcotics that
7 percent (or
16 million) Americans now use.
<footnote><para>
9684 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
9685 Reform Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st sess. (
5 March
2003) (statement of
9686 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
9688 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in
1979 of
14 percent of
9689 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
9690 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
9691 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
9692 cheat.
<footnote><para>
9694 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, "Tax
9695 Compliance," Journal of Economic Literature
36 (
1998):
818 (survey of
9696 compliance literature).
9698 We pride ourselves on our "free society," but an endless array of
9699 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
9700 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
9703 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
9704 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
9705 students about the importance of "ethics." As my colleague Charlie
9706 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
9707 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
9708 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
9709 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
9710 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
9711 teach them how to behave ethically
—how to say no to bribes, or
9712 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
9713 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
9714 Americans
—more significantly in some parts of America than in
9715 others, but still, everywhere in America today
—can't live their
9716 lives both normally and legally, since "normally" entails a certain
9717 degree of illegality.
9720 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
9721 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
9722 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
9723 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
9724 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
9725 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
9726 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
9727 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
9728 to consider the alternative.
9732 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
9733 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
9734 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
9735 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
9736 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
9737 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
9740 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
9741 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
9742 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
9743 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
9744 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
9745 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
9746 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
9747 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
9748 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
9749 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
9750 introduced this different idea of "sharing." We need to be able to
9751 call these twenty million Americans "citizens," not "felons."
9754 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
9755 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
9756 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
9757 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
9758 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
9759 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
9760 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
9761 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
9762 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
9766 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
9769 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
9770 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
9771 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
9772 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
9775 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
9776 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That "use" of the
9780 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
9781 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
9782 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am "free" to copy,
9783 or "rip," music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
9784 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that "freedom" was a
9785 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the "Rip, Mix, Burn"
9786 capacities of digital technologies.
9788 <indexterm><primary>Adromeda
</primary></indexterm>
9790 This "use" of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
9791 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
9792 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
9793 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
9794 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
9795 Others
—the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
9796 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
9797 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
9798 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
9801 This use is enabled by unprotected media
—either CDs or records.
9802 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
9803 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
9804 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
9805 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
9806 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
9807 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
9808 on people's machines.
9811 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
9812 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
9813 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
9814 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
9815 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
9816 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
9818 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
9819 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
9820 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
9821 plastic or were part of a massively complex "digital rights
9825 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
9826 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
9827 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
9828 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
9829 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
9830 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
9831 freedom to move content easily?
9834 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
9835 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
9836 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
9837 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
9838 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
9839 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
9840 alternative
—namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
9841 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
9842 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
9845 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
9846 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
9847 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
9848 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
9849 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
9850 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
9851 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
9854 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
9855 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
9856 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
9857 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
9860 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
9861 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
9863 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
9865 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
9866 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
9867 There's one more aspect to this corruption that is particularly
9868 important to civil liberties, and follows directly from any war of
9869 prohibition. As Electronic Frontier Foundation attorney Fred von
9870 Lohmann describes, this is the "collateral damage" that "arises
9871 whenever you turn a very large percentage of the population into
9872 criminals." This is the collateral damage to civil liberties
9874 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation
</primary></indexterm>
9877 "If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker," von Lohmann
9882 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
9883 evaporate to one degree or another. . . . If you're a copyright
9884 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
9885 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
9886 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
9887 access? . . . Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, "Oh, well,
9888 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker." Well, what this campaign
9889 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
9890 American Internet-using population into "lawbreakers."
9894 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
9895 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
9896 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
9899 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in
2003 as the RIAA
9900 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
9901 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
9902 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
9903 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
9904 an Internet user is revealed.
9907 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
9908 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
9909 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
9910 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
9911 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
9912 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
9913 the family could be liable for $
2 million in damages. That didn't stop
9914 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
9915 Jesse Jordan.
<footnote><para>
9917 See Frank Ahrens, "RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
9918 Mother in Calif.,
12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,"
9919 Washington Post,
10 September
2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, "Worried Parents
9920 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
9921 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
9922 Being Sued," Orlando Sentinel Tribune,
30 August
2003, C1; Jefferson
9923 Graham, "Recording Industry Sues Parents," USA Today,
15 September
9924 2003,
4D; John Schwartz, "She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
9925 Fan, Either," New York Times,
25 September
2003, C1; Margo Varadi, "Is
9926 Brianna a Criminal?" Toronto Star,
18 September
2003, P7.
9931 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
9932 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
9933 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.
<footnote><para>
9935 See "Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
9936 Some Methods Used," CNN.com, available at
9937 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
47</ulink>.
9939 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
9940 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
9941 one of those MP3s will have the same "fingerprint."
9944 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
9945 friend gives a CD to your daughter
—a collection of songs just
9946 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
9947 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
9948 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
9949 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
9950 network is "cooperating" with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
9951 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
9952 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
9953 as a "criminal." And under the rules that universities are beginning
9954 to deploy,
<footnote><para>
9956 See Jeff Adler, "Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,"
9957 Boston Globe,
18 May
2003, City Weekly,
1; Frank Ahrens, "Four
9958 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
9959 Colleges," Washington Post,
4 April
2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
9960 "Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk," Christian Science
9961 Monitor,
2 September
2003,
20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, "Music
9962 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
9963 Lawsuit Possible," Chicago Tribune,
16 July
2003,
1C; Beth Cox, "RIAA
9964 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities," Internet News,
30 January
9965 2003, available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9966 #
48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, "Download Warning
101: Freshman
9967 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
9968 Sharing," San Francisco Chronicle,
11 August
2003, E11; "Raid, Letters
9969 Are Weapons at Universities," USA Today,
26 September
2000,
3D.
9971 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
9972 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
9975 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
9976 a lawyer for her (at $
300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
9977 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
9978 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
9979 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
9980 this "contraband" as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
9983 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
9984 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
9985 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
9990 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
9991 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
9992 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
9993 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
9994 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
9995 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
9996 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
9997 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
9998 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
9999 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10000 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10001 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10002 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10003 larger number of Americans than drug use. . . . If forty to sixty
10004 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10005 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10010 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered "criminals" under
10011 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective
—
10012 securing rights to authors
—without these millions being
10013 considered "criminals," who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10014 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10015 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10018 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10022 <chapter id=
"c-balances">
10023 <title>BALANCES
</title>
10025 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10027 So here's the picture: You're standing at the side of the road. Your
10028 car is on fire. You are angry and upset because in part you helped start
10029 the fire. Now you don't know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket,
10030 filled with gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10033 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10034 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10035 stop
—or before she understands just why she should
10036 stop
—the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10037 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10041 A war about copyright rages all around
—and we're all focusing on
10042 the wrong thing. No doubt, current technologies threaten existing
10043 businesses. No doubt they may threaten artists. But technologies
10044 change. The industry and technologists have plenty of ways to use
10045 technology to protect themselves against the current threats of the
10046 Internet. This is a fire that if let alone would burn itself out.
10049 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
10050 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
10051 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
10052 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
10053 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
10054 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
10055 made that is happening all around.
10058 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
10059 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
10060 gasoline onto this fire.
10063 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
10064 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
10065 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
10066 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
10069 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
10070 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
10071 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
10072 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
10073 success will require.
10076 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
10077 <sect1 id=
"eldred">
10078 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
</title>
10080 In
1995, a father was frustrated that his daughters didn't seem to
10081 like Hawthorne. No doubt there was more than one such father, but at
10082 least one did something about it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer
10083 programmer living in New Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the
10084 Web. An electronic version, Eldred thought, with links to pictures and
10085 explanatory text, would make this nineteenth-century author's work
10089 It didn't work
—at least for his daughters. They didn't find
10090 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
10091 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
10092 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
10093 them available for free.
10096 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
10097 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
10098 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
10099 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
10100 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
10101 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
10102 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
10103 many others, into a form more accessible
—technically
10104 accessible
—today.
10107 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
10108 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's Scarlet Letter had passed into the
10109 public domain in
1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
10110 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
10111 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
10112 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
10113 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
10114 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (Cinderella), sometimes not
10115 (The Hunchback of Notre Dame, Treasure Planet). These are all
10116 commercial publications of public domain works.
10119 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
10120 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
10121 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
10122 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
10123 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
10124 call the "noncommercial publishing industry," which before the
10125 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
10126 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
10127 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
10128 generally.
<footnote><para>
10130 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
10131 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
10132 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers
—people who
10133 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
10134 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
10135 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
10136 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
10137 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
10138 Decency Act of
1996. It was partly because of the burden on
10139 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
10140 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
10141 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
10142 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
10143 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
10144 protect noncommercial pornographers.
</para></footnote>
10147 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In
1998, Robert Frost's
10148 collection of poems New Hampshire was slated to pass into the public
10149 domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in his free public
10150 library. But Congress got in the way. As I described in chapter
10,
10151 in
1998, for the eleventh time in forty years, Congress extended the
10152 terms of existing copyrights
—this time by twenty years. Eldred
10153 would not be free to add any works more recent than
1923 to his
10154 collection until
2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work would pass into
10155 the public domain until that year (and not even then, if Congress
10156 extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period, more than
1
10157 million patents will pass into the public domain.
10161 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
10162 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
10163 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
10164 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
10165 "copyrights should be forever."
<footnote><para>
10167 The full text is: "Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
10168 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
10169 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
10170 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
10171 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
10172 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
10173 Congress,"
144 Cong. Rec. H9946,
9951-
2 (October
7,
1998).
10178 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
10179 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
10180 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
10181 second law passed in
1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
10182 of publishing would make Eldred a felon
—whether or not anyone
10183 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
10187 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
10189 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
10191 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
10192 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
10194 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
10198 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science . . .
10199 by securing for limited Times to Authors . . . exclusive Right to
10200 their . . . Writings. . . .
10204 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
10205 clause of Article I, section
8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
10206 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
10207 something
—for example, to regulate "commerce among the several
10208 states" or "declare War." But here, the "something" is something quite
10209 specific
—to "promote . . . Progress"
—through means that
10210 are also specific
— by "securing" "exclusive Rights" (i.e.,
10211 copyrights) "for limited Times."
10214 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
10215 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
10216 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
10217 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be "limited" will have
10218 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
10219 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
10220 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
10221 what the Constitution plainly forbids
—perpetual terms "on the
10222 installment plan," as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
10223 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
10226 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
10227 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
10228 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
10229 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
10230 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
10231 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
10232 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
10233 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
10234 this gravy train going.
10237 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
10238 government. "Corruption" not in the sense that representatives are
10239 bribed. Rather, "corruption" in the sense that the system induces the
10240 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
10241 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
10242 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
10243 do
—and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
10246 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
10247 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
10248 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
10249 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in
1963. His poetry
10250 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
10251 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
10252 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
10253 published by anyone for free.
10256 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $
100,
000 a year from
10257 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
10258 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
10259 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
10263 "Next year," the adviser announces, "our copyrights in works A, B,
10265 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
10266 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
10267 receiving the annual royalty check of $
100,
000 from the publishers of
10271 "There's a proposal in Congress, however," she continues, "that
10272 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
10273 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
10274 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes."
10277 "Hope?" a fellow board member says. "Can't we be doing something
10281 "Well, obviously, yes," the adviser responds. "We could contribute
10282 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
10283 they support the bill."
10286 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
10287 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. "How much
10288 would we get if this extension were passed?" you ask the adviser. "How
10292 "Well," the adviser says, "if you're confident that you will continue
10293 to get at least $
100,
000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
10294 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (
6 percent),
10295 then this law would be worth $
1,
146,
000 to the estate."
10298 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
10299 correct conclusion:
10302 "So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
10303 $
1,
000,
000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
10305 would assure that the bill was passed?"
10308 "Absolutely," the adviser responds. "It is worth it to you to
10310 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
10311 copyrights. Which for us means over $
1,
000,
000."
10314 You quickly get the point
—you as the member of the board and, I
10315 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
10316 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
10317 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
10318 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
10319 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
10321 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
10322 the copyright term extended.
10325 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as
10327 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
10328 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
10331 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
10333 Term Extension Act, this "theory" about incentives was proved
10334 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
10335 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
10336 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
10337 contributions.
<footnote><para>
10338 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, "Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
10339 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators
20 More Years,"
10340 Chicago Tribune,
17 October
1998,
22.
10342 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
10343 $
1.5 million lobbying in the
1998 election cycle. They paid out more
10344 than $
200,
000 in campaign contributions.
<footnote><para>
10345 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, "Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
10347 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
49</ulink>.
10349 Disney is estimated to have
10350 contributed more than $
800,
000 to reelection campaigns in the
10351 cycle.
<footnote><para>
10352 <!-- f5. --> Alan K. Ota, "Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,"
10354 Quarterly This Week,
8 August
1990, available at
10355 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
50</ulink>.
10360 Constitutional law is not oblivious to the obvious. Or at least,
10361 it need not be. So when I was considering Eldred's complaint, this
10363 about the never-ending incentives to increase the copyright term
10364 was central to my thinking. In my view, a pragmatic court committed
10365 to interpreting and applying the Constitution of our framers would see
10366 that if Congress has the power to extend existing terms, then there
10367 would be no effective constitutional requirement that terms be
10369 If they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again
10373 It was also my judgment that this Supreme Court would not allow
10374 Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to the Supreme
10375 Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted the power
10376 of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as exceeding the
10377 power granted to it by the Constitution. Among constitutional
10379 the most famous example of this trend was the Supreme Court's
10381 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
10382 decision in
1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
10386 Since
1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
10387 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
10388 power to regulate only "commerce among the several states" (aka
10390 commerce"), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
10391 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
10396 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there
10397 was no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
10399 when considered on a national scale, affects interstate commerce.
10400 A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was instead
10402 to impose no limit.
10405 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command,
10406 changed that in United States v. Lopez. The government had argued
10407 that possessing guns near schools affected interstate commerce. Guns
10408 near schools increase crime, crime lowers property values, and so on. In
10409 the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the government whether
10410 there was any activity that would not affect interstate commerce under
10411 the reasoning the government advanced. The government said there
10412 was not; if Congress says an activity affects interstate commerce, then
10413 that activity affects interstate commerce. The Supreme Court, the
10415 said, was not in the position to second-guess Congress.
10418 "We pause to consider the implications of the government's
10420 the Chief Justice wrote.
<footnote><para>
10421 <!-- f6. --> United States v. Lopez,
514 U.S.
549,
564 (
1995).
10423 If anything Congress says is interstate
10424 commerce must therefore be considered interstate commerce, then
10425 there would be no limit to Congress's power. The decision in Lopez was
10426 reaffirmed five years later in United States v. Morrison.
<footnote><para>
10427 <!-- f7. --> United States v. Morrison,
529 U.S.
598 (
2000).
10432 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
10433 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.
<footnote><para>
10434 <!-- f8. --> If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle carries
10435 from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in the
10437 of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered by the
10438 government would allow the government unending power to regulate
10439 commerce
—the limitation to interstate commerce notwithstanding. The
10440 same point is true in the context of the Copyright Clause. Here, too, the
10441 government's interpretation would allow the government unending power
10442 to regulate copyrights
—the limitation to "limited times" notwithstanding.
10444 And if it is applied to the
10445 Progress Clause, the principle should yield the conclusion that
10447 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
10448 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an
10450 term, then there would be no "stopping point" to Congress's power
10451 over terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such
10452 a limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
10454 should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the term of
10455 existing copyrights.
10458 If, that is, the principle announced in Lopez stood for a principle.
10459 Many believed the decision in Lopez stood for politics
—a conservative
10460 Supreme Court, which believed in states' rights, using its power over
10461 Congress to advance its own personal political preferences. But I
10463 that view of the Supreme Court's decision. Indeed, shortly after
10464 the decision, I wrote an article demonstrating the "fidelity" in such an
10465 interpretation of the Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court
10466 decides cases based upon its politics struck me as extraordinarily
10468 I was not going to devote my life to teaching constitutional law if
10469 these nine Justices were going to be petty politicians.
10472 Now let's pause for a moment to make sure we understand what
10473 the argument in Eldred was not about. By insisting on the
10475 limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing piracy.
10476 Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of piracy
—piracy of
10477 the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his work and when Walt
10478 Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright term was just
10479 fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and Disney had
10481 enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their work. They had
10482 gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution envisions: In
10483 exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years, they created new
10484 work. But now these entities were using their power
—expressed
10485 through the power of lobbyists' money
—to get another twenty-year
10486 dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop would be taken from the
10487 public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a piracy that affects us all.
10490 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
10492 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
10493 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
10494 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than "legal piracy."
<footnote><para>
10495 <!-- f9. --> Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, Eldred v. Ashcroft,
537 U.S.
10496 186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618), n
.10, available at
10497 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
51</ulink>.
10500 it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional system,
10501 our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's requirements,
10502 but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's charter.
10505 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
10507 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
10509 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
10510 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
10511 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
10512 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
10513 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
10514 bought to extend them again.
10517 It is valuable copyrights that are responsible for terms being
10519 Mickey Mouse and "Rhapsody in Blue." These works are too
10520 valuable for copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our
10522 from copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains
10524 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works
10525 from the
1920s and
1930s that have continuing commercial value. The
10526 real harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The
10527 real harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially
10529 and no longer available as a result.
10532 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (
1923 to
10533 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
10534 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
10535 copyright holders for that
2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
10536 But the law and its effect were not limited to that
2 percent. The law
10537 extended the terms of copyright generally.
<footnote><para>
10538 <!-- f10. --> The figure of
2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
10540 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
10541 of Petitioners, Eldred v. Ashcroft,
7, available at
10542 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
52</ulink>.
10547 Think practically about the consequence of this
10548 extension
—practically,
10549 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
10551 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
10552 work. In
1930,
10,
047 books were published. In
2000,
174 of those
10553 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
10554 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
10556 9,
873. What would you have to do?
10559 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the
9,
873 books were
10560 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
10561 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
10562 titles and authors of the
9,
873 books with the copyright registration
10563 and renewal records for works published in
1930. That will produce a
10564 list of books still under copyright.
10567 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
10568 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
10571 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
10573 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
10574 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
10575 being at least a list?
10578 But there is no list. There may be a name from
1930, and then in
10579 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
10581 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
10583 of such records
—especially since the person who registered is
10584 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about
1930!
10587 "But there isn't a list of who owns property generally," the
10589 for the system respond. "Why should there be a list of copyright
10593 Well, actually, if you think about it, there are plenty of lists of who
10594 owns what property. Think about deeds on houses, or titles to cars.
10595 And where there isn't a list, the code of real space is pretty good at
10597 who the owner of a bit of property is. (A swing set in your
10598 backyard is probably yours.) So formally or informally, we have a pretty
10599 good way to know who owns what tangible property.
10602 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
10603 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
10604 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
10606 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
10607 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
10608 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
10610 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
10611 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
10612 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
10613 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
10614 know quite well who owns what property.
10617 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
10618 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
10620 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
10621 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
10622 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
10623 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
10624 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
10625 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
10626 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
10629 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
10630 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
10632 for other creative works is much more dire.
10634 <indexterm><primary>Agee, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
10636 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
10637 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
10638 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
10639 made between
1921 and
1951. Only one of these films, The Lucky Dog, is
10640 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after
1923
10641 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
10642 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
10643 money. According to one estimate, "Roach has sold about
60,
000
10644 videocassettes and
50,
000 DVDs of the duo's silent
10645 films."
<footnote><para>
10647 See David G. Savage, "High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,"
10648 Los Angeles Times,
6 October
2002; David Streitfeld, "Classic Movies,
10649 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
10650 Down Copyright Extension," Orlando Sentinel Tribune,
9 October
2002.
10655 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
10656 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
10657 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
10658 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
10661 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
10663 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
10664 any continuing commercial value. The rest
—to the extent it
10665 survives at all
—sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
10666 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
10667 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
10668 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
10669 work available for distribution.
10672 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
10673 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
10674 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
10675 it cost more than $
10,
000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
10676 film in
1993, it can now cost as little as $
100 to digitize one hour of
10677 mm film.
<footnote><para>
10678 <!-- f12. --> Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
10680 the Petitoners, Eldred v. Ashcroft,
537 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
10681 618),
12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae filed on behalf of Petitioners by
10682 the Internet Archive, Eldred v. Ashcroft, available at
10683 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
53</ulink>.
10688 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
10690 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
10691 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
10692 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
10693 locate the copyright owner.
10696 Or more accurately, owners. As we've seen, there isn't only a single
10697 copyright associated with a film; there are many. There isn't a single
10698 person whom you can contact about those copyrights; there are as
10699 many as can hold the rights, which turns out to be an extremely large
10700 number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights to these films is
10705 "But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
10706 copyright owner when she shows up?" Sure, if you want to commit a
10707 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
10708 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
10709 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
10710 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
10711 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
10712 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
10713 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
10716 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
10718 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
10719 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
10721 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
10722 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
10723 the copyright expires.
10726 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
10727 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
10728 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
10730 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
10734 Of all the creative work produced by humans anywhere, a tiny
10735 fraction has continuing commercial value. For that tiny fraction, the
10736 copyright is a crucially important legal device. For that tiny fraction,
10737 the copyright creates incentives to produce and distribute the
10739 work. For that tiny fraction, the copyright acts as an "engine of
10743 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
10744 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
10746 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
10747 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
10748 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
10750 the commercial life ends.
10753 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
10754 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes
& Noble, and
10755 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
10757 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
10759 night watching a
1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
10760 of culture is important and valuable
—for entertainment but also, and
10761 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
10762 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
10763 have, we need to have access to this history.
10766 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
10768 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
10769 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
10770 this context do no good.
10773 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
10774 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
10775 copyright-related use that would be inhibited by an exclusive right.
10776 When a book went out of print, you could not buy it from a publisher.
10777 But you could still buy it from a used book store, and when a used
10778 book store sells it, in America, at least, there is no need to pay the
10779 copyright owner anything. Thus, the ordinary use of a book after its
10780 commercial life ended was a use that was independent of copyright law.
10783 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
10784 a film
—the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs
—were
10785 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
10786 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
10787 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
10788 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
10789 market didn't have more to offer.
10792 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
10793 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
10794 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
10795 would not have interfered with anything.
10798 But this situation has now changed.
10801 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
10802 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
10803 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
10804 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
10805 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
10806 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
10807 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
10808 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
10809 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
10810 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
10813 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
10814 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
10815 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
10816 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
10817 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
10818 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
10819 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
10820 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
10821 written for a radically different context.
10824 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
10825 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
10826 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
10827 copyright purpose, for the purpose of copyright is to enable the
10828 commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are talking about
10829 culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this context,
10830 copyright is serving no purpose at all related to the spread of
10831 knowledge. In this context, copyright is not an engine of free
10832 expression. Copyright is a brake.
10835 You may well ask, "But if digital technologies lower the costs for
10836 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
10837 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
10841 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
10842 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes
& Noble
10843 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
10844 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
10845 of a library is to serve what "the market" would demand. But if you
10846 think the role of a library is bigger than this
—if you think its
10847 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
10848 particular bit of that culture or not
—then we can't count on the
10849 commercial market to do our library work for us.
10852 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
10853 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
10854 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
10855 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
10857 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
10858 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
10859 culture,
94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
10860 and
1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
10861 commercial market, if access is a value, then
6 percent is a failure
10862 to provide that value.
<footnote><para>
10864 Jason Schultz, "The Myth of the
1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,"
20
10865 December
2002, available at
10866 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
54</ulink>.
10871 In January
1999, we filed a lawsuit on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal
10872 district court in Washington, D.C., asking the court to declare the
10873 Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act unconstitutional. The two
10874 central claims that we made were (
1) that extending existing terms
10875 violated the Constitution's "limited Times" requirement, and (
2) that
10876 extending terms by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
10879 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
10880 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
10881 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
10882 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
10883 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
10886 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
10887 copyrights be for "limited Times" only. His argument was as elegant as
10888 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
10889 "stopping point" to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
10890 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
10891 terms that are "limited." Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
10892 to interpret the term "limited Times" to give it meaning. And the best
10893 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
10894 power to extend existing terms.
10897 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
10898 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
10899 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
10900 whole, where the court will sit "en banc" to hear the case.
10903 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
10904 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
10906 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
10907 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
10908 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
10909 overstepped its bounds.
10912 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
10913 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
10914 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
10915 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
10916 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
10919 But in February
2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
10920 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
10921 was set for October of
2002. The summer would be spent writing
10922 briefs and preparing for argument.
10925 It is over a year later as I write these words. It is still
10926 astonishingly hard. If you know anything at all about this story, you
10927 know that we lost the appeal. And if you know something more than just
10928 the minimum, you probably think there was no way this case could have
10929 been won. After our defeat, I received literally thousands of missives
10930 by well-wishers and supporters, thanking me for my work on behalf of
10931 this noble but doomed cause. And none from this pile was more
10932 significant to me than the e-mail from my client, Eric Eldred.
10935 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
10936 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
10937 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
10940 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey
</primary></indexterm>
10942 The mistake was made early, though it became obvious only at the very
10943 end. Our case had been supported from the very beginning by an
10944 extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart, and by the law firm he had
10945 moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of
10947 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
10948 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
10949 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
10950 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
10952 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
10953 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan
</primary></indexterm>
10954 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey
</primary></indexterm>
10956 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
10957 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
10958 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
10959 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
10960 told me, if we could make the issue seem "important" to the Supreme
10961 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
10962 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against "the
10963 most powerful media companies in the world."
10966 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
10967 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
10968 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
10969 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
10970 "right" as in "true," I thought, but it is "wrong" as in "it just shouldn't be
10971 that way." As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
10972 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
10973 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
10975 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
10976 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
10978 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
10979 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
10980 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
10982 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
10983 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
10984 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
10987 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
10988 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
10989 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
10990 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
10991 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
10992 why it was unconstitutional.
10995 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
10997 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
10998 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
10999 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
11000 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
11001 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed that
11002 this field of review was simply the preference of a small political
11004 Although my focus in the case was not to demonstrate how bad the
11005 Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it was unconstitutional,
11006 my hope was to make this argument against a background of briefs that
11007 covered the full range of political views. To show that this claim against
11008 the CTEA was grounded in law and not politics, then, we tried to
11009 gather the widest range of credible critics
—credible not because they
11010 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
11011 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
11014 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
11015 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
11016 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
11017 Congress. In November
1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
11018 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
11019 "Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
11020 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
11021 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
11022 to get bogged down?" The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
11023 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
11024 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
11025 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
11026 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum
</primary></indexterm>
11027 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis
</primary></indexterm>
11030 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
11031 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
11032 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
11033 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
11034 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
11035 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
11038 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
11039 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
11041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
11042 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/ Linux
11043 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
11044 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
11045 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
11046 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
11047 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
11048 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
11049 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum
</primary></indexterm>
11052 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
11053 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
11054 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
11055 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
11058 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
11059 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
11060 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
11061 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
11064 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George
</primary></indexterm>
11065 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
11066 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James
</primary></indexterm>
11067 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
11068 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton
</primary></indexterm>
11070 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
11071 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
11072 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
11073 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
11074 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
11075 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
11076 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
11077 nothing more than "rent-seeking"
—the fancy term economists use
11078 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
11081 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
11082 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
11083 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
11084 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
11085 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
11086 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
11087 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
11088 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
11090 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
11091 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
11092 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
11093 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
11096 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
11097 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
11098 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
11099 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
11100 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
11101 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
11102 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
11103 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
11104 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
11105 confidence in our argument.
11106 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
11109 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
11110 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these "friends" included
11111 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
11112 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
11116 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
11117 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either
—they
11118 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
11119 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
11120 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
11121 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
11125 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
11126 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
11127 Dr. Seuss's work
— better than allowing it to fall into the
11128 public domain
—because if this creativity were in the public
11129 domain, then people could use it to "glorify drugs or to create
11130 pornography."
<footnote><para>
11132 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., Eldred v. Ashcroft,
537
11133 U.S. (
2003) (No.
01-
618),
19.
11135 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
11136 "protection" of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
11137 to license Porgy and Bess to anyone who refuses to use African
11138 Americans in the cast.
<footnote><para>
11140 Dinitia Smith, "Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
11141 Mouse Joins the Fray," New York Times,
28 March
1998, B7.
11144 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
11145 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
11146 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
11147 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George
</primary></indexterm>
11150 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
11151 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
11152 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
11153 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
11154 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, "Give us twenty years
11155 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
11156 better with them than anyone else." Congress of course likes to reward
11157 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
11158 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
11159 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
11162 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
11163 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
11164 copyrights
—extensions that would further concentrate the market;
11165 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
11166 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
11167 Between February and October, there was little I did beyond preparing
11168 for this case. Early on, as I said, I set the strategy.
11171 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One
11172 camp we called "the Conservatives." The other we called "the Rest."
11173 The Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
11174 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
11175 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
11176 five who had supported the Lopez/Morrison line of cases that said that
11177 an enumerated power had to be interpreted to assure that Congress's
11180 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
11182 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
11183 Congress's power. These four
—Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
11184 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer
—had repeatedly argued that
11186 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
11187 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
11188 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
11189 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
11190 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
11191 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
11194 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
11195 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
11196 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
11197 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
11198 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
11199 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
11200 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
11201 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
11204 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
11206 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
11207 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
11208 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
11209 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
11210 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
11211 these retrospective extensions.
11214 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
11215 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
11216 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
11217 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
11218 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
11219 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
11222 This analysis of "the Rest" showed most clearly where our focus
11223 had to be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open
11224 these five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
11226 argument that animated our claim rested on the Conservatives'
11227 most important jurisprudential innovation
—the argument that Judge
11228 Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals, that Congress's power
11229 must be interpreted so that its enumerated powers have limits.
11232 This then was the core of our strategy
—a strategy for which I am
11233 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the Lopez
11235 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
11236 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always
11237 have unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain
11238 about Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this
11239 power was supposed to be "limited." Our aim would be to get the
11240 Court to reconcile Eldred with Lopez: If Congress's power to regulate
11241 commerce was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate
11242 copyright be limited.
11245 The argument on the government's side came down to this:
11247 has done it before. It should be allowed to do it again. The
11249 claimed that from the very beginning, Congress has been
11250 extending the term of existing copyrights. So, the government argued,
11251 the Court should not now say that practice is unconstitutional.
11254 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
11255 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in
11256 and in
1909. And of course, in
1962, Congress began extending
11258 terms regularly
—eleven times in forty years.
11261 But this "consistency" should be kept in perspective. Congress
11263 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
11264 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
11265 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
11267 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
11269 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
11270 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
11272 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
11273 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
11274 Oral argument was scheduled for the first week in October. I
11276 in D.C. two weeks before the argument. During those two
11277 weeks, I was repeatedly "mooted" by lawyers who had volunteered to
11279 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
11280 help in the case. Such "moots" are basically practice rounds, where
11281 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
11284 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
11285 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
11286 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
11287 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
11289 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
11290 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
11293 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11295 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
11296 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
11297 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
11298 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
11299 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
11302 "I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
11303 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
11304 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
11305 the harm
—passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
11306 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning."
11308 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11310 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
11311 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
11312 right thing
—not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
11313 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
11314 does the right thing
—not because of politics but because it is right. As
11315 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
11316 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
11317 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
11318 The night before the argument, a line of people began to form
11319 in front of the Supreme Court. The case had become a focus of the
11320 press and of the movement to free culture. Hundreds stood in line
11322 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
11323 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
11324 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
11327 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
11328 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
11329 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
11330 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
11332 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
11333 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
11334 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
11335 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
11336 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
11337 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
11338 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
11339 family of the Justices.
11342 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
11343 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
11344 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
11345 those enumerated powers had any limit.
11348 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
11349 The history was bothering her.
11353 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
11354 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
11355 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
11356 practice that began with the very first act.
11360 She was quite willing to concede "that this flies directly in the face
11361 of what the framers had in mind." But my response again and again
11362 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
11366 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
11367 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
11368 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
11369 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
11374 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
11375 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
11376 Kennedy, who observed,
11380 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
11381 the '
76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
11382 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
11383 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
11384 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
11388 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
11394 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
11395 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
11396 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
11397 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an
11399 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
11402 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11404 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
11405 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
11406 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
11407 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
11408 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
11411 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had
11412 been crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the Lopez ruling, and we
11413 hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
11416 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
11418 To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
11420 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
11424 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
11425 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
11428 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
11429 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
11431 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
11432 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
11433 into the Copyright Clause.
11437 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
11438 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
11439 asked Solicitor General Olson,
11443 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11444 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
11445 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
11446 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11451 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
11452 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
11453 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
11454 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
11455 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
11456 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
11457 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
11458 Patent Clause
— indeed, the very first case striking a law of
11459 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
11460 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
11464 As I left the court that day, I knew there were a hundred points I
11465 wished I could remake. There were a hundred questions I wished I had
11467 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
11468 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
11472 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
11473 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
11474 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
11475 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
11476 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
11477 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
11478 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
11479 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
11480 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
11481 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
11482 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court
—in particular,
11483 the Conservatives
—would feel itself constrained by the rule of
11484 law that it had established elsewhere.
11487 The morning of January
15,
2003, I was five minutes late to the office
11488 and missed the
7:
00 A.M. call from the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to
11489 the message, I could tell in an instant that she had bad news to report.The
11490 Supreme Court had affirmed the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven
11491 justices had voted in the majority. There were two dissents.
11494 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
11495 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
11496 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
11499 My reasoning. Here was a case that pitted all the money in the world
11500 against reasoning. And here was the last naïve law professor, scouring
11501 the pages, looking for reasoning.
11504 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
11505 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
11506 Lopez. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
11507 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
11508 even appear in the Court's opinion.
11512 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
11513 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
11514 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
11515 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
11518 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable
—for her, and for Justice
11519 Souter. Neither believes in Lopez. It would be too much to expect them
11520 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
11521 they had worked so hard to defeat.
11524 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
11525 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
11526 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
11527 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
11528 reconcile the two simply by not addressing the argument. There was no
11529 inconsistency because they would not talk about the two together.
11530 There was therefore no principle that followed from the Lopez case: In
11531 that context, Congress's power would be limited, but in this context
11535 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
11536 they would respect? By what right did they
—the silent
11537 five
—get to select the part of the Constitution they would
11538 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
11539 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
11540 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
11541 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
11542 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
11543 the system we have.
11545 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
11547 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
11548 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
11549 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
11550 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
11551 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
11552 the Court discounted the parallel
—without explaining how the
11553 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
11554 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
11555 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
11557 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
11559 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
11560 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
11561 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
11562 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
11563 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author
99.8
11564 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
11565 that the actual number was
99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
11566 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
11567 "limited," and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
11568 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
11571 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
11572 because neither believed in the Lopez case, neither was willing to push
11573 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
11574 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
11575 Sentelle. It was Hamlet without the Prince.
11578 Defeat brings depression. They say it is a sign of health when
11579 depression gives way to anger. My anger came quickly, but it didn't cure
11580 the depression. This anger was of two sorts.
11583 It was first anger with the five "Conservatives." It would have been
11584 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of Lopez didn't
11585 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
11586 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
11587 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
11588 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
11589 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is "originalism"
—to
11590 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
11591 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
11592 Lopez and many other "originalist" rulings. Where was their
11596 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
11597 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
11598 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
11599 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
11601 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
11602 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
11603 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
11604 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
11605 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
11606 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
11607 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
11611 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
11613 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
11616 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11618 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
11619 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
11620 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
11621 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
11622 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
11623 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
11624 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
11625 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
11626 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
11629 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
11630 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
11631 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
11632 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
11633 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
11634 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
11635 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
11636 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
11637 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
11638 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
11639 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
11640 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
11641 effort to persuade; but I
11642 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
11643 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
11644 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
11645 should decide the issue.
11647 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11649 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
11650 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
11652 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
11655 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
11656 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
11657 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
11658 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
11661 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
11662 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
11663 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
11664 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
11668 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
11669 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
11670 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
11671 case was a mistake. "The Court is not ready," Peter Jaszi said; this
11672 issue should not be raised until it is.
11673 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
11676 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
11677 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
11678 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
11679 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
11680 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
11681 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
11682 this case
—a decision I had made four years before
—was wrong.
11683 While the reaction to the Sonny Bono Act itself was almost
11684 unanimously negative, the reaction to the Court's decision was mixed.
11685 No one, at least in the press, tried to say that extending the term of
11686 copyright was a good idea. We had won that battle over ideas. Where
11688 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
11689 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
11690 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
11691 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
11692 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
11693 harmful law. The New York Times wrote in its editorial,
11697 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
11698 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
11699 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
11700 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
11701 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
11702 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
11706 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
11707 hilarious images
—of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
11708 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced on the next
11709 page. The "powerful and wealthy" line is a bit unfair. But the punch
11710 in the face felt exactly like that.
11711 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben
</primary></indexterm>
11714 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
11715 quote from The New York Times. That "grand experiment" we call the
11716 "public domain" is over? When I can make light of it, I think, "Honey,
11717 I shrunk the Constitution." But I can rarely make light of it. We had
11718 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
11719 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
11720 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
11722 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
11724 <sect1 id=
"eldred-ii">
11725 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
</title>
11727 The day Eldred was decided, fate would have it that I was to travel to
11728 Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in Eldred was
11729 denied
—meaning the case was really finally over
—fate would
11730 have it that I was giving a speech to technologists at Disney World.)
11731 This was a particularly long flight to my least favorite city. The
11732 drive into the city from Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I
11733 opened up my computer and wrote an op-ed piece.
11735 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11737 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
11738 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
11739 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
11740 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
11741 Justice Kennedy: "For all these years the act has impeded progress in
11742 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
11743 that." And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
11744 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
11747 The New York Times published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
11748 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
11749 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
11750 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
11751 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
11752 the work passed into the public domain.
11755 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
11756 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
11757 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
11760 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
11761 is either the "Public Domain Enhancement Act" or the "Copyright
11762 Term Deregulation Act." Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
11763 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
11764 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
11765 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $
1. But for
11766 everything else, let the content go.
11768 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
11770 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
11771 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
11772 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
11773 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
11774 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
11775 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
11776 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
11777 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
11778 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
11779 the stupid harm of the present system.
11782 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
11783 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
11784 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
11785 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
11786 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
11787 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
11788 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
11789 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
11790 where copyright owners could be identified.
11792 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
11793 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
11795 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
11796 As I described in chapter
10, formalities in copyright law were
11797 removed in
1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
11798 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.
<footnote><para>
11800 Until the
1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
11801 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
11802 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
11803 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the
1908 act,
11804 every text of the Convention has provided that "the enjoyment and the
11805 exercise" of rights guaranteed by the Convention "shall not be subject
11806 to any formality." The prohibition against formalities is presently
11807 embodied in Article
5(
2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
11808 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
11809 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
11810 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
11811 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
11812 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
11813 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
11814 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
11815 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, International
11816 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials (New York: Foundation
11817 Press,
2001),
153–54.
</para></footnote>
11818 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a "natural right." Natural
11819 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
11820 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
11821 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
11822 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
11823 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
11826 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
11827 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
11828 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
11829 "Walt Disney creativity" is destroyed when there is no simple way to
11830 know what's protected and what's not.
11832 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
11834 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
11835 Berlin in
1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
11836 Convention in
1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
11837 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
11838 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
11839 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
11840 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an i or cross a t resulted
11841 in the loss of widows' only income.
11844 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
11845 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
11846 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
11847 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
11848 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
11849 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
11852 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
11853 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
11854 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
11855 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
11857 imposed upon creators.
11860 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in
1908, there was
11861 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
11863 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
11864 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
11865 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
11866 the government. He has a property right over the table "naturally,"
11867 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
11868 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
11872 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
11873 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
11874 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
11875 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
11876 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
11877 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
11881 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
11882 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
11883 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
11884 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
11885 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
11886 important reason to secure registration
—both because it makes
11887 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
11888 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
11889 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
11890 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
11891 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
11892 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
11893 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
11894 system of protection for property generally.
11897 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
11898 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
11899 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
11900 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
11901 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
11902 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
11903 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
11904 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
11906 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
11907 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive, lawyer transactions
11911 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
11912 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
11913 didn't "get." Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
11914 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
11915 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, "short," then this
11916 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
11917 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
11918 be presumptively uncontrolled.
11921 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
11922 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
11923 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
11924 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
11925 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
11926 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
11927 seen before because there are no formalities.
11930 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
11931 it is worth $
1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
11932 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
11933 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
11934 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
11937 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
11938 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
11939 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
11940 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
11941 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $
1 to you.
11944 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
11945 registering the work mean that the $
1 is really misleading? Isn't the
11946 hassle worth more than $
1? Isn't that the real problem with
11950 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
11951 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
11952 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
11954 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
11955 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
11956 address the real problem of governments standing at the core of any
11957 system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a solution. That
11958 solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For now, assume it
11959 was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it was one-click
11960 registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple, one-click
11961 registration fifty years after a work was published. Based upon
11962 historical data, that system would move up to
98 percent of commercial
11963 work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life, into the
11964 public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
11966 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
11968 When Steve Forbes endorsed the idea, some in Washington began to pay
11969 attention. Many people contacted me pointing to representatives who
11970 might be willing to introduce the Eldred Act. And I had a few who
11971 directly suggested that they might be willing to take the first step.
11974 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
11975 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
11976 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
11977 possible. In May
2003, it looked as if the bill would be
11978 introduced. On May
16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, "we are
11979 close." There was a general reaction in the blog community that
11980 something good might happen here.
11983 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
11984 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
11985 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
11986 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
11987 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
11988 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
11991 The MPAA argued first that Congress had "firmly rejected the central
11992 concept in the proposed bill"
—that copyrights be renewed. That
11993 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's "firm rejection" had occurred
11994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
11995 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
11996 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
11997 owners
—apparently those who could not afford the $
1 fee. Third,
11998 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
11999 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
12000 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
12001 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
12002 off the extended term unless the $
1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
12003 argued that the bill would impose "enormous" costs, since a
12004 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
12005 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
12006 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
12007 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
12008 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
12009 film is a valid derivative use.
12012 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
12013 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
12014 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
12015 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
12016 or not
—a controversial claim in any case
—unless they know
12017 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
12020 At the beginning of this book, I told two stories about the law
12021 reacting to changes in technology. In the one, common sense prevailed.
12022 In the other, common sense was delayed. The difference between the two
12023 stories was the power of the opposition
—the power of the side
12024 that fought to defend the status quo. In both cases, a new technology
12025 threatened old interests. But in only one case did those interest's
12026 have the power to protect themselves against this new competitive
12030 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
12031 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
12032 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
12033 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
12038 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
12039 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
12040 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
12041 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
12042 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
12043 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
12044 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
12045 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
12046 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
12047 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
12050 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
12051 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
12052 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
12053 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
12054 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
12055 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the "Dark
12056 Content" that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
12057 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
12060 What does this industry really want?
12063 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
12064 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
12065 protecting their content. The effort to block the Eldred Act is an effort
12066 to assure that nothing more passes into the public domain. It is another
12067 step to assure that the public domain will never compete, that there
12068 will be no use of content that is not commercially controlled, and that
12069 there will be no commercial use of content that doesn't require their
12073 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
12074 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
12075 its aim not the protection of "property" but the rejection of a
12076 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is theirs. Their
12077 aim is to assure that all there is is what is theirs.
12080 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
12081 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
12083 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
12084 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
12085 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
12086 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
12087 and to share its own creation.
12089 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
12090 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
12092 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
12093 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
12094 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
12095 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
12096 block the progress of others.
12099 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
12100 "property" in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
12101 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
12102 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing "permission
12103 society." The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
12104 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
12105 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
12107 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
12110 <chapter id=
"c-conclusion">
12111 <title>CONCLUSION
</title>
12113 There are more than
35 million people with the AIDS virus
12114 worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live in sub-Saharan Africa.
12115 Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen million Africans
12116 is proportional percentage-wise to seven million Americans. More
12117 importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
12120 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
12121 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
12122 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
12123 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
12124 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
12125 the disease almost invisible.
12128 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
12129 United States, they cost between $
10,
000 and $
15,
000 per person per
12130 year. Today, some cost $
25,
000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
12131 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
12133 $
15,
000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
12134 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.
<footnote><para>
12135 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, "Final Report: Integrating
12136 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy" (London,
2002),
12138 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
12140 issued
9 July
2002, only
230,
000 of the
6 million who need drugs in
12141 the developing world receive them
—and half of them are in Brazil.
12145 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
12146 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
12147 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
12148 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
12149 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
12150 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
12151 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
12154 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
12155 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
12156 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
12157 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
12158 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
12159 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
12160 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
12161 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
12165 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
12166 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
12167 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
12168 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
12169 costs significantly below the market price.
12172 In
1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
12173 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
12174 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
12175 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
12176 Africa from India. This is called "parallel importation," and it is
12177 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
12178 permitted within the European Union.
<footnote>
12181 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism: Who
12182 Owns the Knowledge Economy? (New York: The New Press,
2003),
37.
12183 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John
</primary></indexterm>
12184 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
12188 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed,
12189 more than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property
12191 characterized it, "The U.S. government pressured South Africa . . .
12192 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel imports."
<footnote><para>
12193 <!-- f3. --> International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), Patent Protection and
12194 Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan Africa, a Report
12196 for the World Intellectual Property Organization (Washington, D.C.,
12197 2000),
14, available at
12198 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
56</ulink>. For a firsthand account of the struggle over
12199 South Africa, see Hearing Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice,
12200 Drug Policy, and Human Resources, House Committee on Government
12201 Reform, H. Rep.,
1st sess., Ser. No.
106-
126 (
22 July
1999),
150–57
12202 (statement of James Love).
12205 Office of the United States Trade Representative, the government
12206 asked South Africa to change the law
—and to add pressure to that
12208 in
1998, the USTR listed South Africa for possible trade sanctions.
12209 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
12210 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies
12212 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the
12214 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments
12215 from the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical
12217 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
12219 law by discriminating against a particular kind of patent
—
12220 pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments, with the
12221 United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect these patents
12222 as it respects any other patent, regardless of any effect on the treatment
12223 of AIDS within South Africa.
<footnote><para>
12225 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), Patent
12226 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12227 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12228 Organization (Washington, D.C.,
2000),
15.
</para></footnote>
12231 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
12232 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
12233 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
12234 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
12235 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
12236 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
12237 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
12238 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
12241 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
12242 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
12243 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
12244 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
12245 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
12246 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save
15 to
30 million lives.
12249 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
12250 profits of United States drug companies
—at least, not substantially. It
12251 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
12252 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
12253 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
12254 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
12258 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
12259 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
12261 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
12262 about the sanctity of property.
<footnote><para>
12264 See Sabin Russell, "New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
12265 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive," San Francisco Chronicle,
24
12266 May
1999, A1, available at
12267 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
57</ulink>
12268 ("compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
12269 system of intellectual property protection"); Robert Weissman, "AIDS
12270 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
12271 Medicines," Foreign Policy in Focus
4:
23 (August
1999), available at
12272 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
58</ulink>
12273 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, "TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
12274 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
12275 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis," Widener Law
12276 Symposium Journal (Spring
2001):
175.
12277 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
12279 It was because "intellectual property" would be violated that these
12280 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
12281 importance of "intellectual property" that led these government actors
12282 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
12285 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
12286 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
12287 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
12288 direct cost would be to speed the death of
15 to
30 million Africans,
12289 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the "sanctity" of an
12290 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
12291 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
12292 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
12295 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
12296 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
12297 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
12298 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
12299 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system
—
12300 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
12303 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
12304 drug companies would love
—they say, and I believe them
—to
12305 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
12306 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
12307 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
12308 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
12311 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
12312 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
12313 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, "How
12314 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $
1 a pill, but the same
12315 drug would cost an American $
1,
500?" Because there is no "sound
12316 bite" answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
12317 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
12318 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
12319 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
12320 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
12321 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
12322 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal
—the sanctity of an
12323 idea called "intellectual property."
12326 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
12327 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
12328 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
12329 What is the argument?
12332 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
12333 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
12334 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
12335 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
12336 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
12337 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
12338 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
12339 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
12340 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
12341 were balanced in just this sense.
12344 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
12345 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
12346 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
12347 our tradition, now reigns in this culture
—bizarrely, and with
12348 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
12349 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make. A
12350 simple idea blinds us, and under the cover of darkness, much happens
12351 that most of us would reject if any of us looked. So uncritically do
12352 we accept the idea of property in ideas that we don't even notice how
12353 monstrous it is to deny ideas to a people who are dying without
12354 them. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in culture
12355 that we don't even question when the control of that property removes
12357 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
12358 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
12359 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
12360 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
12361 this common sense open its eyes.
12364 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
12365 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
12366 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
12367 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
12368 to fight "piracy," and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
12369 the idea of "creative property," while transforming real creators into
12370 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
12371 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
12372 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
12373 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
12374 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
12375 produce the "perfect storm" for free culture.
12378 In August
2003, a fight broke out in the United States about a
12379 decision by the World Intellectual Property Organization to cancel a
12380 meeting.
<footnote><para>
12381 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, "The Quiet War over Open-Source," Washington Post,
12382 August
2003, E1, available at
12383 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
59</ulink>; William New, "Global Group's
12384 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir," National Journal's Technology
12385 Daily,
19 August
2003, available at
12386 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
60</ulink>; William New, "U.S. Official
12387 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO," National Journal's Technology
12388 Daily,
19 August
2003, available at
12389 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
61</ulink>.
12391 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
12392 a meeting to discuss "open and collaborative projects to create public
12393 goods." These are projects that have been successful in producing
12394 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
12395 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
12396 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
12397 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
12398 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
12399 that I describe in the Afterword. It included a project to develop
12400 single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs), which are thought to have
12401 great significance in biomedical research. (That nonprofit project
12402 comprised a consortium of the Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and
12403 technological companies, including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
12404 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
12405 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
12406 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
12407 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
12408 in the early
1980s. And it included "open source and free software."
12409 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)
</primary></indexterm>
12412 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
12413 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
12414 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
12415 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
12416 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
12419 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.
<footnote><para>
12420 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
12423 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
12424 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
12425 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
12426 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
12430 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
12431 about WIPO. In February
2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
12432 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
12433 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
12434 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
12435 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
12436 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
12437 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
12438 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
12439 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
12440 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
12441 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
12442 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
12443 talk about an "Information Society" unless one also talked about the
12444 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
12445 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
12446 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
12448 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
12449 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
12450 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
12451 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
12454 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
12455 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
12456 thus the meeting about "open and collaborative projects to create
12457 public goods" seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
12460 But there is one project within that list that is highly
12461 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is "open source
12462 and free software." Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
12463 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
12464 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
12465 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
12466 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
12467 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
12468 rather than "proprietary software," for their own internal uses.
12471 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
12472 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
12473 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
12474 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
12475 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
12476 operating system, the most famous bit of "free software"
—and IBM
12477 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support "open source and
12478 free software" is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
12479 to support a mode of software development that is different from
12480 Microsoft's.
<footnote><para>
12482 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
12483 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
12484 "open source" software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
12485 principal opposition is to "free software" licensed under a "copyleft"
12486 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
12487 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, "The Future
12488 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide," Government Policy
12489 Toward Open Source Software (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
12490 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
12491 Public Policy Research,
2002),
69, available at
12492 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
62</ulink>. See also
12493 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, The Commercial Software
12494 Model, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (
3
12495 May
2001), available at
12496 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
63</ulink>.
12500 More important for our purposes, to support "open source and free
12501 software" is not to oppose copyright. "Open source and free software"
12502 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
12503 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
12504 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
12506 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
12507 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
12508 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
12509 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
12510 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
12511 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
12512 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
12513 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
12514 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
12515 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
12518 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
12519 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
12520 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
12521 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
12522 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
12523 Washington Post, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
12524 States government to veto the meeting.
<footnote><para>
12526 Krim, "The Quiet War over Open-Source," available at
<ulink
12527 url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
64</ulink>.
12529 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
12532 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
12533 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
12534 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
12535 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
12536 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
12537 its lobbying efforts.
12540 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
12541 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
12542 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
12543 Office, explained that "open-source software runs counter to the
12544 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights."
12545 She is quoted as saying, "To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
12546 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
12550 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
12552 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
12554 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
12555 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
12556 right called "copyright". Without it, restrictions imposed by those
12557 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it "runs counter" to the mission
12558 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
12559 in understanding
—the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
12560 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
12561 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
12564 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to "promote"
12565 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
12566 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
12567 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
12568 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
12569 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
12570 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
12571 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
12572 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
12573 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
12574 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
12577 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
12578 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
12579 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
12580 what to do with those rights because, again, they are their rights. If
12581 they want to "waive" or "disclaim" their rights, that is, within our
12582 tradition, totally appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than
12583 $
20 billion to do good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the
12584 objectives of the property system. That is, on the contrary, just what
12585 a property system is supposed to be about: giving individuals the
12586 right to decide what to do with their property.
12587 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
12590 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
12591 "which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights," she's
12592 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
12593 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
12594 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
12595 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from "waiving" or
12596 "disclaiming" an intellectual property right. That the interest of
12597 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
12598 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
12602 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
12603 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called "feudalism." Under
12604 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
12605 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
12606 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
12607 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
12608 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
12609 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
12610 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
12613 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
12614 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John
</primary></indexterm>
12616 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
12617 choice we are now making about intellectual property.
<footnote><para>
12619 See Drahos with Braithwaite, Information Feudalism,
210–20.
12620 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
12622 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
12623 choice now is whether that information society will be free or
12624 feudal. The trend is toward the feudal.
12627 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
12628 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
12629 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
12630 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
12634 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
12635 it should be ("the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
12636 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
12637 not simply to promote intellectual property rights"), not as it is. If
12638 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
12639 say anything wrong. But in the world
12640 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
12641 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
12642 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
12646 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
12647 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
12648 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
12649 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
12650 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
12651 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
12652 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
12653 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
12656 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
12657 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
12658 "goal" of a government should be "to promote the right balance" of
12659 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
12660 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. "Typical for
12661 an academic," the poster might well have continued.
12664 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
12665 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
12666 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
12667 our own country's history).
12670 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
12671 government should be to "seek balance," then count me with the silly,
12672 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
12673 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
12674 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
12675 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
12676 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
12677 not lies is just na
ïve, then who have we, the most powerful
12678 democracy in the world, become?
12681 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
12682 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
12683 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
12684 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
12685 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
12686 been part of our tradition for most of our history
—free culture.
12688 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace
</primary></indexterm>
12690 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon. There are
12691 moments of hope in this struggle. And moments that surprise. When the
12692 FCC was considering relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby
12693 further increase the concentration in media ownership, an
12694 extraordinary bipartisan coalition formed to fight this change. For
12695 perhaps the first time in history, interests as diverse as the NRA,
12696 the ACLU, Moveon.org, William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women
12697 for Peace organized to oppose this change in FCC policy. An
12698 astonishing
700,
000 letters were sent to the FCC, demanding more
12699 hearings and a different result.
12700 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted
</primary></indexterm>
12701 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
12704 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
12705 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
12706 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
12707 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
12708 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
12709 concentration in the media.
12712 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
12713 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
12714 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
12715 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
12716 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
12719 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
12720 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
12721 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
12722 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
12723 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
12724 range of rights
—property rights of a historically extreme
12725 form
—that makes their bigness bad.
12727 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
12729 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
12730 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
12731 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
12732 Americans have a long history of fighting "big," wisely or not. That
12733 we could be motivated to fight "big" again is not something new.
12736 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
12737 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
12738 the idea of "intellectual property." Not because balance is alien to
12739 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
12740 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
12741 called "property" is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
12744 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
12747 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob
</primary></indexterm>
12749 As I write these final words, the news is filled with stories about
12750 the RIAA lawsuits against almost three hundred individuals.
<footnote><para>
12752 John Borland, "RIAA Sues
261 File Swappers," CNET News.com, September
12754 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
65</ulink>; Paul
12755 R. La Monica, "Music Industry Sues Swappers," CNN/Money,
8 September
12757 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
66</ulink>; Soni
12758 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, "Sued for a Song,
12759 N.Y.C.
12-Yr-Old Among
261 Cited as Sharers," New York Daily News,
9
12760 September
2003,
3; Frank Ahrens, "RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
12761 Targets; Single Mother in Calif.,
12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
12762 Defendants," Washington Post,
10 September
2003, E1; Katie Dean,
12763 "Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA," Wired News,
10 September
2003,
12765 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
67</ulink>.
12767 Eminem has just been sued for "sampling" someone else's
12768 music.
<footnote><para>
12770 Jon Wiederhorn, "Eminem Gets Sued . . . by a Little Old Lady,"
12771 mtv.com,
17 September
2003, available at
12772 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
68</ulink>.
12774 The story about Bob Dylan "stealing" from a Japanese author has just
12775 finished making the rounds.
<footnote><para>
12777 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, "Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
12778 Dylan Songs," Kansascity.com,
9 July
2003, available at
12779 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
69</ulink>.
12780 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
12782 An insider from Hollywood
—who insists he must remain
12783 anonymous
—reports "an amazing conversation with these studio
12784 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
12785 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
12786 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
12787 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first." Congressmen are
12788 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
12789 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
12790 kids who use a computer to share content.
12792 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
12793 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
12794 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons
</primary></indexterm>
12795 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto
</primary></indexterm>
12797 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
12798 that it will build a "Creative Archive," from which British citizens can
12799 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.
<footnote><para>
12800 <!-- f14. --> "BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public," BBC press release,
12801 24 August
2003, available at
12802 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
70</ulink>.
12804 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
12805 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
12806 content and free licenses in that Latin American
12807 country.
<footnote><para>
12809 "Creative Commons and Brazil," Creative Commons Weblog,
6 August
2003,
12811 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
71</ulink>.
12813 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
12814 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
12815 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
12816 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
12817 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
12818 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
12819 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
12820 day into the Causbys.
12823 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
12824 potential is ever to be realized.
12826 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
12830 <chapter id=
"c-afterword">
12831 <title>AFTERWORD
</title>
12834 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
12835 At least some who have read this far will agree with me that something
12836 must be done to change where we are heading. The balance of this book
12837 maps what might be done.
12840 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
12841 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
12842 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
12843 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
12846 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
12847 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
12848 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists
—all to tell this
12849 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
12853 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
12854 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
12855 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
12856 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
12857 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
12859 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
12862 <title>US, NOW
</title>
12864 Common sense is with the copyright warriors because the debate so far
12865 has been framed at the extremes
—as a grand either/or: either
12866 property or anarchy, either total control or artists won't be paid. If
12867 that really is the choice, then the warriors should win.
12870 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
12871 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
12872 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright
—"All Rights
12873 Reserved"
— and those who reject copyright
—"No Rights
12874 Reserved." The "All Rights Reserved" sorts believe that you should ask
12875 permission before you "use" a copyrighted work in any way. The "No
12876 Rights Reserved" sorts believe you should be able to do with content
12877 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
12880 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
12881 tilted in the "no rights reserved" direction. Content could be copied
12882 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
12883 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
12886 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
12887 original design of the Internet was "no rights reserved." Content was
12888 "taken" regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
12892 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
12893 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
12894 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
12895 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
12896 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
12897 architecture made the effective default "no rights reserved," the
12898 future architecture will make the effective default "all rights
12899 reserved." The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
12900 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
12901 content requires permission. The "cut and paste" world that defines
12902 the Internet today will become a "get permission to cut and paste"
12903 world that is a creator's nightmare.
12906 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle
—neither
12907 "all rights reserved" nor "no rights reserved" but "some rights
12908 reserved"
— and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
12909 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
12910 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
12914 <sect2 id=
"examples">
12915 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
</title>
12917 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
12918 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
12919 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
12920 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
12921 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
12922 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
12923 to your neighbors or boss. The "privacy" of your browsing habits was
12927 What made it assured?
12929 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
12931 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
12932 10, your privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture
12933 for gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
12934 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
12935 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
12936 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
12937 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
12938 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
12939 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
12940 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
12941 (there is no law protecting "privacy" in public places), and in many
12942 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
12943 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
12945 <indexterm><primary>Amazon
</primary></indexterm>
12947 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
12948 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
12949 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
12950 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
12951 "recently viewed" pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
12952 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
12953 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any "privacy"
12954 protected by the friction disappears, too.
12957 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
12958 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
12959 people should have the "right" to browse in a library without the
12960 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
12961 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
12962 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
12963 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
12967 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define "privacy"
12968 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
12969 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
12970 friction did.
<footnote><para>
12973 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, "Fair Information Practices and the
12974 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get)," Stanford Technology
12975 Law Review
1 (
2001): par.
6–18, available at
12977 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
72</ulink>
12978 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
12979 also Jeffrey Rosen, The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
12980 in an Anxious Age (New York: Random House,
2004) (mapping tradeoffs
12981 between technology and privacy).
</para></footnote>
12982 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
12983 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
12985 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
12986 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
12987 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
12988 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
12991 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
12992 movement. When computers with software were first made available
12993 commercially, the software
—both the source code and the
12994 binaries
— was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
12995 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
12996 care much about controlling their software.
12998 <indexterm><primary>Stallman, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
13000 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
13001 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
13002 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
13003 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
13004 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
13008 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
13009 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
13010 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
13011 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
13012 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
13013 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
13014 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
13015 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
13016 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
13020 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
13021 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
13022 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
13023 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
13024 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
13025 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
13026 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
13029 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
13030 early
1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
13031 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
13032 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
13033 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
13034 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
13035 fundamentally weakened.
13038 Therefore, in
1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
13039 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
13040 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's "Linux"
13041 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
13044 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
13045 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
13046 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
13047 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
13048 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
13049 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
13050 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
13051 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
13055 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
13056 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
13057 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
13058 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
13059 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
13060 what before had been passively guaranteed.
13063 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
13064 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
13065 scientific journals are produced.
13068 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
13069 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
13070 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
13071 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
13072 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
13073 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
13074 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
13075 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
13076 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
13077 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
13078 and Westlaw are also free
13079 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
13080 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
13081 Court opinion through their respective services.
13084 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
13085 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
13086 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
13087 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
13088 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
13089 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
13090 access to material that is not in the public domain.
13093 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
13094 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
13095 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
13098 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
13099 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
13100 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
13101 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
13102 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
13103 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
13104 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
13105 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
13106 the technology of paper journals (architecture)
—namely, that it
13107 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
13110 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
13111 that libraries not give the general public access to the
13112 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
13113 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
13114 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
13118 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
13119 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
13120 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
13121 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
13122 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
13123 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
13124 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
13125 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
13126 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
13127 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
13128 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
13129 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)
</primary></indexterm>
13132 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
13133 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
13134 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
13135 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
13136 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
13137 presumptively a good
—especially when it helps spread knowledge
13142 <sect2 id=
"oneidea">
13143 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
</title>
13144 <indexterm id=
"idxcc" class='startofrange'
>
13145 <primary>Creative Commons
</primary>
13148 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
13149 increasing control effected through law and technology.
13152 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
13153 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
13154 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of reasonable
13155 copyright on top of the extremes that now reign. It does this by
13156 making it easy for people to build upon other people's work, by making
13157 it simple for creators to express the freedom for others to take and
13158 build upon their work. Simple tags, tied to human-readable
13159 descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses, make this possible.
13162 Simple
—which means without a middleman, or without a lawyer. By
13163 developing a free set of licenses that people can attach to their
13164 content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of content that can
13165 easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are then linked to
13166 machine-readable versions of the license that enable computers
13167 automatically to identify content that can easily be shared. These
13168 three expressions together
—a legal license, a human-readable
13170 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
13171 machine-readable tags
—constitute a Creative Commons license. A
13172 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
13173 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
13174 that the person associated with the license believes in something
13175 different than the "All" or "No" extremes. Content is marked with the
13176 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
13177 certain freedoms are given.
13180 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
13181 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
13182 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
13183 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
13184 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
13185 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses ("share and share
13186 alike"). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
13187 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
13188 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
13191 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
13192 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
13193 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
13194 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
13195 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
13196 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
13197 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
13198 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
13202 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
13203 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
13204 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
13205 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
13206 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
13207 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
13208 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
13209 of content ("content conducers," as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
13210 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
13211 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
13212 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia
</primary></indexterm>
13215 The aim is not to fight the "All Rights Reserved" sorts. The aim is to
13216 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
13217 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
13218 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
13219 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
13220 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
13221 the background of digital technologies. New rules
—with different
13222 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
13223 them
—are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
13224 to begin to build those rules.
13227 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
13228 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
13229 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, Down and Out in
13230 the Magic Kingdom, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
13231 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
13234 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
13235 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (
1)
13236 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
13237 and (
2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
13238 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (
1) will download
13239 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(
1)s. Some part of (
2)
13240 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
13241 them (
2)-goods. If there are more (
2)-goods than bad-(
1)s, the
13242 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably increase
13243 sales of Cory's book.
13246 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
13247 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
13248 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
13249 was a total success.
13252 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
13253 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
13254 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
13255 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled Free for All,
13256 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
13257 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
13258 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
13259 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
13263 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread
13264 proprietary content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of
13265 the Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for
13266 other reasons. Many who use the "sampling license" do so because
13267 anything else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that
13268 others are free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample
13269 content from the licensed work; they are just not free to make full
13270 copies of the licensed work available to others. This is consistent
13271 with their own art
—they, too, sample from others. Because the
13272 legal costs of sampling are so high (Walter Leaphart, manager of the
13273 rap group Public Enemy, which was born sampling the music of others,
13274 has stated that he does not "allow" Public Enemy to sample anymore,
13275 because the legal costs are so high
<footnote><para>
13278 Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
13279 Culture Wars (
2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
13280 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
13281 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
72</ulink>.
13282 </para></footnote>),
13283 these artists release into the creative environment content
13284 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
13287 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
13288 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
13289 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
13290 you are effectively saying you believe in the "All Rights Reserved"
13291 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
13292 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
13293 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
13294 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
13295 this notion of "Some Rights Reserved," and gives many the chance to
13299 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
13300 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
13301 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
13302 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
13304 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
13305 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
13306 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
13309 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
13310 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
13311 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
13312 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
13313 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
13314 steps are possible.
13317 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
13318 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
13319 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
13320 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
13321 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
13322 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
13323 creativity to spread more easily.
13325 <indexterm startref=
"idxcc" class='endofrange'
/>
13327 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
13330 <sect1 id=
"themsoon">
13331 <title>THEM, SOON
</title>
13333 We will not reclaim a free culture by individual action alone. It will
13334 also take important reforms of laws. We have a long way to go before
13335 the politicians will listen to these ideas and implement these reforms.
13336 But that also means that we have time to build awareness around the
13337 changes that we need.
13340 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
13341 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
13342 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
13346 <sect2 id=
"formalities">
13347 <title>1. More Formalities
</title>
13349 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
13350 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
13351 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
13352 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
13355 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
13356 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
13357 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
13361 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
13362 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
13363 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
13364 default is control, and "formalities" are banished.
13370 As I suggested in chapter
10, the motivation to abolish formalities
13371 was a good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
13372 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
13373 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
13374 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
13375 formalities were getting in the way.
13378 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
13379 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
13380 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
13381 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
13382 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
13383 trace
— there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
13384 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
13385 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
13386 past. And thus, the lack of formalities forces many into silence where
13387 they otherwise could speak.
13390 The law should therefore change this requirement
<footnote><para>
13392 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
13393 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
13394 adopted by other countries as well.
</para></footnote>—but it
13395 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
13396 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
13397 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
13400 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
13401 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
13402 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
13403 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
13404 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
13405 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
13406 developed by others.
13409 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
13411 <sect3 id=
"registration">
13412 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL
</title>
13414 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
13415 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
13416 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
13417 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
13418 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
13419 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
13420 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
13421 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
13422 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
13423 panic
—nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
13424 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
13427 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
13428 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
13429 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
13430 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
13431 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
13432 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
13433 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
13436 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
13437 There are at least
32 million Web sites registered around the world.
13438 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
13439 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
13440 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
13441 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
13442 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
13443 with which registration occurs up.
13446 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
13447 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
13448 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
13449 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
13450 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
13451 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
13452 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
13453 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
13454 formality
—while producing a database
13455 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
13456 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
13460 <sect3 id=
"marking">
13461 <title>MARKING
</title>
13463 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
13464 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
13465 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule
—akin to
13466 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
13467 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
13468 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
13469 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
13470 uniformly across all media.
13473 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
13474 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
13475 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
13479 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
13480 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
13481 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
13482 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
13483 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
13484 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
13485 signal from the failure to mark
—not the loss of the copyright, but the
13486 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
13489 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
13490 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
13491 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
13492 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
13493 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
13494 doesn't give permission.
<footnote><para>
13496 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
13497 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
13498 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
13500 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be "use unless someone
13501 complains." If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
13502 stop using the work in any new
13503 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
13504 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
13505 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
13509 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
13510 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
13511 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
13512 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
13513 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
13516 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
13517 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
13518 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
13519 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
13520 judged preferable, and it would base that choice solely upon the
13521 consideration of which method could best be integrated into the
13522 registration and renewal system. We would not count on the government
13523 to innovate; but we would count on the government to keep the product
13524 of innovation in line with its other important functions.
13527 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
13528 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
13529 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
13530 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
13531 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
13532 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
13535 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
13536 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
13537 make things unclear.
13540 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
13541 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
13542 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
13543 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
13544 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
13545 that assertion at the appropriate time.
13548 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
13551 <sect2 id=
"shortterms">
13552 <title>2. Shorter Terms
</title>
13554 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
13555 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
13559 In The Future of Ideas, I proposed a seventy-five-year term, granted
13560 in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every five
13561 years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
13562 Eldred v. Ashcroft, the proposals became even more radical. The
13563 Economist endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year copyright
13564 term.
<footnote><para>
13566 "A Radical Rethink," Economist,
366:
8308 (
25 January
2003):
15,
13568 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
74</ulink>.
13570 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
13573 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
13574 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
13575 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
13578 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
13581 Keep it short: The term should be as long as necessary to give
13582 incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied to very strong
13583 protections for authors (so authors were able to reclaim rights from
13584 publishers), rights to the same work (not derivative works) might be
13585 extended further. The key is not to tie the work up with legal
13586 regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
</para></listitem>
13589 Keep it simple: The line between the public domain and protected
13590 content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the fuzziness of "fair use,"
13591 and the distinction between "ideas" and "expression." That kind of
13592 law gives them lots of work. But our framers had a simpler idea in
13593 mind: protected versus unprotected. The value of short terms is that
13594 there is little need to build exceptions into copyright when the term
13595 itself is kept short. A clear and active "lawyer-free zone" makes the
13596 complexities of "fair use" and "idea/expression" less necessary to
13598 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
13602 Keep it alive: Copyright should have to be renewed. Especially if the
13603 maximum term is long, the copyright owner should be required to signal
13604 periodically that he wants the protection continued. This need not be
13605 an onerous burden, but there is no reason this monopoly protection has
13606 to be granted for free. On average, it takes ninety minutes for a
13607 veteran to apply for a pension.
<footnote><para>
13609 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
13610 and/or Pension, VA Form
21-
526 (OMB Approved No.
2900-
0001),
13612 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
75</ulink>.
13614 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
13615 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
13620 Keep it prospective: Whatever the term of copyright should be, the
13621 clearest lesson that economists teach is that a term once given should
13622 not be extended. It might have been a mistake in
1923 for the law to
13623 offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I don't think so, but it's
13624 possible. If it was a mistake, then the consequence was that we got
13625 fewer authors to create in
1923 than we otherwise would have. But we
13626 can't correct that mistake today by increasing the term. No matter
13627 what we do today, we will not increase the number of authors who wrote
13628 in
1923. Of course, we can increase the reward that those who write
13629 now get (or alternatively, increase the copyright burden that smothers
13630 many works that are today invisible). But increasing their reward will
13631 not increase their creativity in
1923. What's not done is not done,
13632 and there's nothing we can do about that now.
</para></listitem>
13635 These changes together should produce an average copyright term
13636 that is much shorter than the current term. Until
1976, the average
13637 term was just
32.2 years. We should be aiming for the same.
13640 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas "radical." (After all, I
13641 call them "extremists.") But again, the term I recommended was longer
13642 than the term under Richard Nixon. How "radical" can it be to ask for
13643 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
13646 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
13649 <sect2 id=
"freefairuse">
13650 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
</title>
13652 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
13653 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
13654 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
13655 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
13656 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
13657 the emergence of that new technology.
13660 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors "exclusive
13661 right" to "their writings." Congress has given authors an exclusive
13662 right to "their writings" plus any derivative writings (made by
13663 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
13664 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
13665 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
13666 though that movie is not "my writing."
13669 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in
1870, when it
13670 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
13671 control translations and dramatizations of a work.
<footnote><para>
13673 Benjamin Kaplan, An Unhurried View of Copyright (New York: Columbia
13674 University Press,
1967),
32.
13676 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
13677 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
13678 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
13682 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
13683 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
13684 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
13685 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.
<footnote><para>
13686 <!-- f6. --> Ibid.,
56.
13691 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
13692 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
13693 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
13694 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
13695 Consider each limitation in turn.
13698 Term: If Congress wants to grant a derivative right, then that right
13699 should be for a much shorter term. It makes sense to protect John
13701 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
13702 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
13703 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
13704 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
13705 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
13706 after the creative work is done.
13707 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John
</primary></indexterm>
13710 Scope: Likewise should the scope of derivative rights be narrowed.
13711 Again, there are some cases in which derivative rights are important.
13712 Those should be specified. But the law should draw clear lines around
13713 regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted material. When all
13714 "reuse" of creative material was within the control of businesses,
13715 perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate the lines. It no
13716 longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the lines. Think about all
13717 the creative possibilities that digital technologies enable; now
13718 imagine pouring molasses into the machines. That's what this general
13719 requirement of permission does to the creative process. Smothers it.
13722 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
13723 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
13724 foreseeable derivative rights
—turning a book into a movie, or a
13725 poem into a musical score
—it doesn't make sense to require
13726 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
13730 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
13731 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
13732 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
13733 Paul Goldstein.
<footnote>
13736 Paul Goldstein, Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
13737 Jukebox (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
2003),
187–216.
13738 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
13740 His view is that the law should be written so that
13741 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
13744 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
13745 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
13746 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
13747 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
13748 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
13751 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
13752 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
13753 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
13754 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
13755 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
13756 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
13760 <sect2 id=
"liberatemusic">
13761 <title>4. Liberate the Music
—Again
</title>
13763 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
13764 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
13765 is, to most people, most pressing
—music. There is no other
13766 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
13767 battles around the sharing of music.
13770 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
13771 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
13772 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
13773 killer app
—possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
13774 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
13775 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
13776 innovation on the network.
13779 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
13780 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
13781 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
13782 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
13783 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
13786 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the
13787 spread of content for which the performer has not been paid. But of
13788 course, that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in
13789 chapter
5, they enable four different kinds of sharing:
13791 <orderedlist numeration=
"upperalpha">
13794 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
13795 for purchasing CDs.
13799 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
13800 on the way to purchasing CDs.
13803 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
13805 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
13806 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
13807 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
13811 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
13812 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
13813 owner plainly endorses.
13817 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
13818 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
13819 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
13820 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
13821 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
13822 significantly weakened.
13825 As I said in chapter
5, the actual harm caused by sharing is
13826 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
13827 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
13828 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
13832 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
13833 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
13837 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
13838 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
13839 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
13840 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
13841 is cumbersome and slow
—we in the United States are lucky to have
13842 broadband service at
1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
13843 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
13844 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
13845 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
13846 Internet is mainly just an idea.
13849 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
13850 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
13851 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
13852 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
13853 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
13854 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
13855 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
13856 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
13857 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
13858 where everywhere you are
—except maybe the desert or the
13859 Rockies
—you can instantaneously be connected to the
13860 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
13861 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
13864 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services
13865 that give you access to content on the fly
—such as Internet
13866 radio, content that is streamed to the user when the user
13867 demands. Here, then, is the critical point: When it is extremely easy
13868 to connect to services that give access to content, it will be easier
13869 to connect to services that give you access to content than it will be
13870 to download and store content on the many devices you will have for
13871 playing content. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe than
13872 it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
13873 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
13874 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
13875 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
13876 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
13877 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
13878 paying for this content even though "free" content is available in the
13879 form of MP3s across the Web.
<footnote><para>
13881 See, for example, "Music Media Watch," The J@pan Inc. Newsletter,
3
13882 April
2002, available at
13883 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
76</ulink>.
13888 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
13889 present: It is emphatically temporary. The "problem" with file
13890 sharing
—to the extent there is a real problem
—is a problem
13891 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
13892 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
13893 makers today to be "solving" this problem in light of a technology
13894 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
13895 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
13896 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
13897 artists get paid, during
13899 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
13900 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
13901 and twenty-first-century technologies.
13904 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different "problems"
13905 here to solve. Let's start with type D content
—uncopyrighted
13906 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
13907 "problem" with this content is to make sure that the technology that
13908 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
13909 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
13910 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
13911 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
13912 order to eliminate kidnapping.
13915 Type C content raises a different "problem." This is content that was,
13916 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
13917 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
13918 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
13919 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
13920 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
13921 way that returns something to the artist.
13924 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
13925 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
13926 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
13927 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
13928 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
13929 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
13930 from the author's perspective, this "sharing" of his content without
13931 his being compensated is less than ideal.
13934 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
13935 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
13936 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
13937 providers would be free, under this rule, to "share" that content,
13938 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
13939 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
13940 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
13944 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
13945 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
13946 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
13947 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
13948 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
13949 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
13950 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
13951 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
13955 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
13956 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
13957 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
13958 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
13959 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
13960 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
13961 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
13962 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
13965 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
13966 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
13967 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
13968 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
13969 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
13970 delivering and accessing content.
13973 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
13974 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
13977 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
13978 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
13979 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
13980 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
13981 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
13982 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
13983 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
13984 harmed the interests of the content industry.
13987 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
13988 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
13989 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
13990 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
13991 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
13992 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
13993 way to compensate those who are harmed.
13996 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
13997 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.
<footnote>
13999 <!-- f9. --> William Fisher, Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities (last revised:
14000 10 October
2000), available at
14001 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
77</ulink>; William Fisher, Promises to Keep:
14002 Technology, Law, and the Future of Entertainment (forthcoming) (Stanford:
14003 Stanford University Press,
2004), ch.
6, available at
14004 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
78</ulink>. Professor
14005 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
14006 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
14007 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, "Impose a
14008 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing," available at
14009 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, "Who's Holding Back
14010 Broadband?" Washington Post,
8 January
2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
14011 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
14012 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee,
26 February
2002,
14014 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
14015 Use Fee (IPUF),
3 March
2002, available at
14016 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
14017 "Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly," USA Today,
13 May
14019 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, "Getting Copyright Right,"
14020 IEEE Spectrum Online,
1 July
2002, available at
14021 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
83</ulink>; Declan
14022 McCullagh, "Verizon's Copyright Campaign," CNET News.com,
27 August
14024 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
84</ulink>.
14025 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
14026 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
14027 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
14028 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
14029 debate by about a decade. See
14030 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
85</ulink>.
14031 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
14032 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William
</primary></indexterm>
14034 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
14035 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
14036 would (
1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
14037 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
14038 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
14039 develop (
2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
14040 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (
3) artists would be
14041 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (
4) an appropriate
14045 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
14046 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
14047 Promises to Keep. The modification that I would make is relatively
14048 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
14049 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
14050 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
14051 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
14052 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
14053 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
14054 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
14055 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
14056 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
14057 controlling access.
14060 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
14061 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
14062 the system supports the widest range of "semiotic democracy"
14063 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
14064 other changes I described were accomplished
—in particular, the
14065 limits on derivative
14067 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
14068 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
14069 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
14070 allowed to do with the content itself.
14073 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
14074 "harm" to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
14075 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
14076 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
14077 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
14078 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat "free" by being
14079 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
14080 of songs at even the very high price of
99 cents a song. (At
99 cents,
14081 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
14082 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
14083 Real Networks, offering music at just
79 cents a song. And no doubt
14084 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
14088 This competition has already occurred against the background of "free"
14089 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
14090 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
14091 that, there is nothing impossible at all about "competing with free."
14092 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
14093 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
14094 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
14095 theaters are often luxurious
—with "first class" seats, and meals
14096 served while you watch a movie
—as they struggle and succeed in
14097 finding ways to compete with "free."
14100 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
14101 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
14102 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
14103 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
14104 innovators
—ones who would have a right to the content, and would
14105 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
14109 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
14113 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
14114 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
14115 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
14116 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
14117 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
14121 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
14124 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
14127 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
14131 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
14132 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
14137 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
14138 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
14142 But what if "piracy" doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
14143 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
14144 consumers continue to "take" content for nothing? Should the law do
14148 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
14149 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
14150 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
14151 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
14152 technology that is
95 percent secure and produces a market of size x,
14153 or (b) to have a technology that is
50 percent secure but produces a
14154 market of five times x? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
14155 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
14156 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
14157 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
14158 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
14162 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
14163 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
14164 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
14166 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
14167 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
14168 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
14172 <sect2 id=
"firelawyers">
14173 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers
</title>
14175 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
14176 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
14177 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
14178 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
14181 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
14182 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
14183 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
14184 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
14185 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
14186 strong view queers the law.
14189 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
14190 "radical" by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
14191 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
14192 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
14193 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
14194 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
14195 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
14196 Nimmer, thought it obvious.
<footnote><para>
14198 Lawrence Lessig, "Copyright's First Amendment" (Melville B. Nimmer
14199 Memorial Lecture), UCLA Law Review
48 (
2001):
1057,
1069–70.
14204 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
14205 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
14206 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
14209 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
14210 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
14211 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
14212 the legal system are slight.
<footnote><para>
14214 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
14215 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
14216 leading him to question his own publicly stated
14217 position
—twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
14218 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
14219 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
14220 J. Liebowitz, Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
14221 Drive the Digital Marketplace (New York: Amacom,
2002), (reviewing his
14222 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
14223 "Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?" working paper, June
2003,
14225 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
86</ulink>.
14226 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
14227 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
14228 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
14229 Rethinking,
174–76.
14230 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
14232 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
14233 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
14237 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
14238 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
14239 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
14240 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
14241 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
14242 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
14243 practically never be done.
14246 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
14247 billed at the largest firms at more than $
400 per hour. How much time
14248 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
14249 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
14250 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
14251 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
14252 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
14253 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
14256 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
14257 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
14258 their duty to change the way the law works
—or better, to change the
14259 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
14260 top
1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
14261 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
14264 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
14265 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
14266 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
14270 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
14271 technology
—the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
14272 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
14273 technology
—a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
14274 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
14275 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
14276 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
14279 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture
—but it should
14280 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
14282 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311 -->
14283 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
14284 simple pragmatic question: "Will it do good?" When challenged about
14285 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, "Why not?"
14288 We should ask, "Why?" Show me why your regulation of culture is
14289 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
14290 keep your lawyers away.
14292 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
14296 <chapter id=
"c-notes">
14297 <title>NOTES
</title>
14299 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
14300 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
14301 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
14302 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
14303 this book. For each link below, you can go to
14304 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
14305 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
14306 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
14307 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
14310 <!-- PAGE BREAK 336 -->
14313 <chapter id=
"c-acknowledgments">
14314 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
</title>
14316 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
14317 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
14318 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
14319 to him that this book is dedicated.
14322 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
14323 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
14324 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
14325 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
14326 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
14327 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
14328 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
14329 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
14330 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
14331 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
14332 critical eye on much of this.
14335 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
14336 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
14337 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
14338 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
14339 <!-- PAGE BREAK 337 -->
14340 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
14341 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
14342 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
14343 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
14346 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
14347 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
14348 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
14349 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
14350 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
14351 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
14352 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
14353 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
14354 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
14355 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
14356 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
14357 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
14358 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
14359 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
14360 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, "Wink," Roger Wood, "Ximmbo da Jazz,"
14361 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
14362 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
14363 a bunch of great replies.)
14366 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
14367 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
14368 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
14369 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
14370 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
14371 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
14372 throughout this book.
14375 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
14376 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
14377 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
14378 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
14380 <!-- PAGE BREAK 338 -->