]> pere.pagekite.me Git - text-free-culture-lessig.git/blob - freeculture.xml
Update with new indexes and wrap lines.
[text-free-culture-lessig.git] / freeculture.xml
1 <?xml version='1.0' encoding='UTF-8' ?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href="docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type="text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012 with input from Martin Borg. -->
5 <!--
6 TODO
7 * indexterm primary
8 -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC "-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
11 [
12 <!ENTITY copy "©">
13 <!ENTITY translationblock "">
14 ]>
15 <book id="index" lang="en">
16 <bookinfo>
17 <title>Free Culture</title>
18
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
20
21 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
22 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY</subtitle>
23
24 <pubdate>2004-03-25</pubdate>
25
26 <releaseinfo>Version 2004-02-10</releaseinfo>
27
28 <authorgroup>
29 <author>
30 <firstname>Lawrence</firstname>
31 <surname>Lessig</surname>
32 </author>
33 </authorgroup>
34
35 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
36 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
37 -->
38 <subjectset scheme="libraryofcongress">
39 <subject>
40 <subjectterm>Intellectual property&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
41 </subject>
42 <subject>
43 <subjectterm>Mass media&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
44 </subject>
45 <subject>
46 <subjectterm>Technological innovations&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
47 </subject>
48 <subject>
49 <subjectterm>Art&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
50 </subject>
51 </subjectset>
52
53
54 <publisher>
55 <publishername>The Penguin Press</publishername>
56 <address><city>New York</city></address>
57 </publisher>
58
59 <copyright>
60 <year>2004</year>
61 <holder>Lawrence Lessig</holder>
62 </copyright>
63 <legalnotice>
64 <para>
65 <inlinemediaobject>
66 <imageobject>
67 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.png" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
68 </imageobject>
69 <imageobject>
70 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.svg" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
71 </imageobject>
72 <textobject>
73 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved</phrase>
74 </textobject>
75 </inlinemediaobject>
76 </para>
77
78 <para>
79 This version of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is licensed under
80 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
81 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
82 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
83 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/</ulink>
84 </para>
85 </legalnotice>
86
87 <abstract>
88 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR</title>
89 <para>
90 LAWRENCE LESSIG
91 (<ulink url="http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org</ulink>),
92 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
93 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
94 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
95 (<ulink url="http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org</ulink>).
96 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) and Code: And
97 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), Lessig is a member of
98 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
99 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
100 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
101 twice listed in BusinessWeek's <quote>e.biz 25,</quote> and named one of Scientific
102 American's <quote>50 visionaries.</quote> A graduate of the University of
103 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
104 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
105 Appeals.
106 </para>
107 </abstract>
108
109 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
110 <mediaobject role="cover">
111 <imageobject remap="lrg" role="front-large">
112 <imagedata fileref="images/cover.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
113 </imageobject>
114 <!--
115 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
116 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
117 </imageobject>
118 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
119 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
120 </imageobject>
121 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
122 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
123 </imageobject>
124 -->
125 </mediaobject>
126
127 <biblioid class="isbn">1-59420-006-8</biblioid>
128
129 <!-- LCCN from
130 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
131 -->
132 <biblioid class="libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
133
134 </bookinfo>
135 <!--PAGE BREAK 1-->
136 <dedication id="salespoints">
137 <title></title>
138 <para>
139 You can buy a copy of this book by clicking on one of the links below:
140 </para>
141 <itemizedlist mark="number" spacing="compact">
142 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.amazon.com/">Amazon</ulink></para></listitem>
143 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.barnesandnoble.com/">B&amp;N</ulink></para></listitem>
144 <listitem><para><ulink url="http://www.penguin.com/">Penguin</ulink></para></listitem>
145 <!-- <ulink url="">Local Bookstore</ulink> -->
146 </itemizedlist>
147 </dedication>
148 <!-- PAGE BREAK 2 -->
149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
150 <dedication id="alsobylessig">
151 <title></title>
152 <para>
153 ALSO BY LAWRENCE LESSIG
154 </para>
155 <para>
156 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
157 </para>
158 <para>
159 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
160 </para>
161 </dedication>
162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
163 <dedication id="frontpublisher">
164 <title></title>
165 <para>
166 THE PENGUIN PRESS, NEW YORK
167 </para>
168 </dedication>
169 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
170 <dedication id="frontbookinfo">
171 <title></title>
172 <para>
173 FREE CULTURE
174 </para>
175
176 <para>
177 HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND
178 THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN CULTURE
179 AND CONTROL CREATIVITY
180 </para>
181
182 <para>
183 LAWRENCE LESSIG
184 </para>
185 </dedication>
186 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
187 <colophon>
188 <para>
189 THE PENGUIN PRESS, a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc. 375 Hudson Street New
190 York, New York
191 </para>
192 <para>
193 Copyright &copy; Lawrence Lessig. All rights reserved.
194 </para>
195 <para>
196 Excerpt from an editorial titled <quote>The Coming of Copyright Perpetuity,</quote>
197 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, January 16, 2003. Copyright
198 &copy; 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted with permission.
199 </para>
200 <para>
201 Cartoon in <xref linkend="fig-1711"/> by Paul Conrad, copyright Tribune
202 Media Services, Inc. All rights reserved. Reprinted with permission.
203 </para>
204 <para>
205 Diagram in <xref linkend="fig-1761"/> courtesy of the office of FCC
206 Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
207 </para>
208 <para>
209 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
210 </para>
211 <para>
212 Lessig, Lawrence.
213 Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law to lock down
214 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
215 </para>
216 <para>
217 p. cm.
218 </para>
219 <para>
220 Includes index.
221 </para>
222 <para>
223 ISBN 1-59420-006-8 (hardcover)
224 </para>
225
226 <para>
227 1. Intellectual property&mdash;United States. 2. Mass media&mdash;United States.
228 </para>
229 <para>
230 3. Technological innovations&mdash;United States. 4. Art&mdash;United States. I. Title.
231 </para>
232 <para>
233 KF2979.L47
234 </para>
235 <para>
236 343.7309'9&mdash;dc22
237 </para>
238 <para>
239 This book is printed on acid-free paper.
240 </para>
241 <para>
242 Printed in the United States of America
243 </para>
244 <para>
245 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4
246 </para>
247 <para>
248 Designed by Marysarah Quinn
249 </para>
250
251 <para>
252 &translationblock;
253 </para>
254
255 <para>
256 Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of
257 this publication may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a
258 retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means
259 (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise),
260 without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and
261 the above publisher of this book.
262 </para>
263 <para>
264 The scanning, uploading, and distribution of this book via the
265 Internet or via any other means without the permission of the
266 publisher is illegal and punishable by law. Please purchase only
267 authorized electronic editions and do not participate in or encourage
268 electronic piracy of copyrighted materials. Your support of the
269 author's rights is appreciated.
270 </para>
271 </colophon>
272
273 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
274 <dedication><title></title>
275 <para>
276 To Eric Eldred&mdash;whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
277 it continues still.
278 </para>
279 </dedication>
280
281 <toc id="toc"></toc>
282
283 <lot>
284 <title>List of figures</title>
285 </lot>
286
287 <!--
288 c PREFACE xiii
289 c INTRODUCTION
290 c "PIRACY"
291 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
292 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
293 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
294 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
295 2 Film
296 2 Recorded Music
297 2 Radio
298 2 Cable TV
299 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
300 2 Piracy I
301 2 Piracy II
302 c "PROPERTY"
303 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
304 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
305 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
306 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
307 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
308 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
309 2 Beginnings
310 2 Law: Duration
311 2 Law: Scope
312 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
313 2 Architecture and Law: Force
314 2 Market: Concentration
315 2 Together
316 c PUZZLES
317 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
318 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
319 2 Constraining Creators
320 2 Constraining Innovators
321 2 Corrupting Citizens
322 c BALANCES
323 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
324 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
325 c CONCLUSION
326 c AFTERWORD
327 1 Us, Now
328 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
329 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
330 1 Them, Soon
331 2 1. More Formalities
332 3 Registration and Renewal
333 3 Marking
334 2 2. Shorter Terms
335 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
336 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
337 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
338 c NOTES
339 c ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
340 c INDEX
341 -->
342
343 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
344
345 <preface id="preface">
346 <title>PREFACE</title>
347 <indexterm id="idxpoguedavid" class='startofrange'>
348 <primary>Pogue, David</primary>
349 </indexterm>
350 <para>
351 <emphasis role="bold">At the end</emphasis> of his review of my first
352 book, <citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle>, David
353 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
354 computer-related texts, wrote this:
355 </para>
356 <blockquote>
357 <para>
358 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
359 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
360 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
361 system, you can always flip off the modem.<footnote id="preface01"><para>
362 David Pogue, <quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 30 January 2000.
363 </para></footnote>
364 </para>
365 </blockquote>
366 <para>
367 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book&mdash;that
368 software, or <quote>code,</quote> functioned as a kind of law&mdash;and his review
369 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
370 could always <quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome</quote>-like simply flip a
371 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
372 any troubles that exist in <emphasis>that</emphasis> space wouldn't
373 <quote>affect</quote> us anymore.
374 </para>
375 <para>
376 Pogue might have been right in 1999&mdash;I'm skeptical, but maybe.
377 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
378 <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
379 causes even after the modem is turned
380 <!--PAGE BREAK 12-->
381 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
382 on-line have fundamentally affected <quote>people who aren't online.</quote> There
383 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
384 </para>
385 <indexterm startref="idxpoguedavid" class='endofrange'/>
386 <para>
387 But unlike <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
388 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
389 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
390 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
391 important.
392 </para>
393 <para>
394 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
395 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of <quote>free culture</quote>&mdash;not
396 <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free beer</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
397 free software movement<footnote>
398 <para>
399 Richard M. Stallman, <citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed. 2002).
400 </para></footnote>), but <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free speech,</quote> <quote>free markets,</quote>
401 <quote>free trade,</quote> <quote>free enterprise,</quote> <quote>free will,</quote> and <quote>free elections.</quote> A
402 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
403 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
404 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
405 follow-on creators and innovators remain <emphasis>as free as
406 possible</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
407 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
408 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
409 <quote>permission culture</quote>&mdash;a culture in which creators get to create
410 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
411 past.
412 </para>
413 <para>
414 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not <quote>we</quote>
415 on the Left or <quote>you</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
416 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
417 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
418 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
419 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
420 culture deem fundamental.
421 </para>
422 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
423 <para>
424 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
425 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
426 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
427 generated more than 700,000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
428 As William Safire described marching <quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
429 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
430 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,</quote> he formulated perhaps
431 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
432 he asked,
433 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
434 </para>
435 <blockquote>
436 <para>
437 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
438 power&mdash;political, corporate, media, cultural&mdash;should be anathema to
439 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
440 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
441 the greatest expression of democracy.<footnote><para> William Safire,
442 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 May 2003.
443 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
444 </para></footnote>
445 </para>
446 </blockquote>
447 <para>
448 This idea is an element of the argument of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle>, though my
449 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
450 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
451 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
452 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
453 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
454 you&mdash;whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
455 Safire's left or on his right. The inspiration for the title and for
456 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
457 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
458 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in <citetitle>Free Software, Free
459 Society</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
460 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
461 that this work is <quote>merely</quote> derivative.
462 </para>
463 <para>
464 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
465 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
466 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
467 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
468 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
469 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
470 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
471 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
472
473 <!--PAGE BREAK 14-->
474 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
475 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
476 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
477 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
478 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
479 what I advance here.
480 </para>
481 <para>
482 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
483 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
484 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
485 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
486 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
487 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
488 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
489 book is written.
490 </para>
491
492 </preface>
493 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
494
495 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
496 <chapter label="0" id="c-introduction">
497 <title>INTRODUCTION</title>
498 <indexterm id='idxairtraffic' class='startofrange'>
499 <primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.</primary>
500 </indexterm>
501 <indexterm id='idxlandownership' class='startofrange'>
502 <primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary>
503 </indexterm>
504 <indexterm id='idxproprigtair' class='startofrange'>
505 <primary>property rights</primary>
506 <secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary>
507 </indexterm>
508 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
509 <para>
510 On December 17, 1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
511 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
512 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
513 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
514 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
515 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
516 </para>
517 <para>
518 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
519 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
520 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
521 and all the space above, to <quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.</quote><footnote><para>
522 St. George Tucker, <citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
523 Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18.
524 </para></footnote>
525 For many
526 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
527 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
528 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
529 </para>
530 <para>
531 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
532 law&mdash;deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
533 by the most important legal thinkers of our past&mdash;mattered. If
534 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
535 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
536 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
537 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
538 </para>
539 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
540 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
541 <para>
542 In 1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
543 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
544 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
545 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
546 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
547 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
548 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to <quote>an indefinite
549 extent, upwards,</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
550 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
551 </para>
552 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
553 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
554 <para>
555 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
556 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
557 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
558 <quote>taking</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
559 that <quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
560 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.</quote> But Justice Douglas
561 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
562 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
563 </para>
564 <blockquote>
565 <para>
566 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
567 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
568 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
569 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
570 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
571 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
572 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
573 the public has a just claim.<footnote>
574 <para>
575 United States v. Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. The Court did find
576 that there could be a <quote>taking</quote> if the government's use of its land
577 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
578 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, <quote>(Intellectual)
579 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
580 Authorship,</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review</citetitle> 48 (1996): 1293, 1333. See also Paul
581 Goldstein, <citetitle>Real Property</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press, 1984),
582 1112&ndash;13.
583 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
584 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
585 </para></footnote>
586 </para>
587 </blockquote>
588 <para>
589 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.</quote>
590 </para>
591 <para>
592 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
593 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
594 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
595 <!--PAGE BREAK 18-->
596 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: <quote>Common sense revolts
597 at the idea.</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
598 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
599 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
600 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
601 </para>
602 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
603 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
604 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
605 <para>
606 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
607 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
608 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
609 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
610 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
611 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
612 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
613 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
614 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by <quote>what
615 seemed reasonable</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
616 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
617 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
618 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
619 end, the force of what seems <quote>obvious</quote> to everyone else&mdash;the power of
620 <quote>common sense</quote>&mdash;would prevail. Their <quote>private interest</quote> would not be
621 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
622 </para>
623 <indexterm startref='idxproprigtair' class='endofrange'/>
624 <indexterm startref='idxlandownership' class='endofrange'/>
625 <indexterm startref='idxairtraffic' class='endofrange'/>
626 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwin' class='startofrange'>
627 <primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary>
628 </indexterm>
629 <para>
630 <emphasis role='strong'>Edwin Howard Armstrong</emphasis> is one of America's forgotten inventor
631 geniuses. He came to the great American inventor scene just after the
632 titans Thomas Edison and Alexander Graham Bell. But his work in
633 the area of radio technology was perhaps the most important of any
634 single inventor in the first fifty years of radio. He was better educated
635 than Michael Faraday, who as a bookbinder's apprentice had discovered
636 electric induction in 1831. But he had the same intuition about
637 how the world of radio worked, and on at least three occasions,
638 Armstrong invented profoundly important technologies that advanced our
639 understanding of radio.
640 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
641 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham</primary></indexterm>
642 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
643 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael</primary></indexterm>
644 </para>
645 <para>
646 On the day after Christmas, 1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
647 for his most significant invention&mdash;FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
648 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
649 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
650 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
651 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
652 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
653 much less transmitter power and static.
654 </para>
655 <para>
656 On November 5, 1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
657 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
658 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
659 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
660 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
661 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
662 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
663 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
664 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.</quote>
665 </para>
666 <para>
667 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
668 </para>
669 <blockquote>
670 <para>
671 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
672 sounded like a glass of water being poured. &hellip; A paper was crumpled
673 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
674 fire. &hellip; Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
675 and guitar number were performed. &hellip; The music was projected with a
676 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio <quote>music
677 box.</quote><footnote><para>
678 Lawrence Lessing, <citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong</citetitle>
679 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209.
680 </para></footnote>
681 </para>
682 </blockquote>
683 <para>
684 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
685 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
686 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
687 AM radio market. By 1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
688 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
689 a handful of networks.
690 <!--PAGE BREAK 20-->
691 </para>
692 <para>
693 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
694 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
695 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
696 that removed static from <quote>radio.</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
697 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
698 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
699 </para>
700 <blockquote>
701 <para>
702 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
703 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
704 revolution&mdash; start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
705 RCA.<footnote><para> See <quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
706 Electronic Era,</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
707 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
708
709 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #1</ulink>.
710 </para></footnote>
711 </para>
712 </blockquote>
713 <para>
714 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
715 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
716 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
717 described,
718 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
719 </para>
720 <blockquote>
721 <para>
722 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
723 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
724 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
725 unrestrained, posed &hellip; a complete reordering of radio power
726 &hellip; and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
727 on which RCA had grown to power.<footnote><para>Lessing, 226.
728 </para></footnote>
729 </para>
730 </blockquote>
731 <para>
732 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
733 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
734 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
735 FM radio's deployment generally. In 1936, RCA hired the former head
736 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
737 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM&mdash;principally by moving FM
738 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
739 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
740 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
741 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
742 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
743 </para>
744 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
745 <blockquote>
746 <para>
747 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
748 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
749 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
750 deviousness.<footnote><para>
751 Lessing, 256.
752 </para></footnote>
753 </para>
754 </blockquote>
755 <indexterm><primary>AT&amp;T</primary></indexterm>
756 <para>
757 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
758 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
759 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
760 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
761 (This change was strongly supported by AT&amp;T, because the loss of
762 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
763 wired links from AT&amp;T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
764 least temporarily.
765 </para>
766 <para>
767 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
768 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
769 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
770 invalid&mdash;baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
771 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
772 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
773 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
774 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
775 now broke, in 1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
776 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
777 </para>
778 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwin' class='endofrange'/>
779 <para>
780 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
781 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
782 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
783 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
784 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
785 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
786 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
787 course always public spirited; the reality is something
788 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
789 to themselves, would crumble in
790 <!--PAGE BREAK 22-->
791 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
792 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
793 effect of technological change.
794 </para>
795 <para>
796 There's no single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
797 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
798 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
799 Internet and American Life Project, 58 percent of Americans had access
800 to the Internet in 2002, up from 49 percent two years
801 before.<footnote><para>
802 Amanda Lenhart, <quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
803 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,</quote> Pew Internet and American
804 Life Project, 15 April 2003: 6, available at
805 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #2</ulink>.
806 </para></footnote>
807 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
808 of 2004.
809 </para>
810 <para>
811 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
812 changed things. Some of these changes are technical&mdash;the Internet has
813 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
814 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
815 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
816 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
817 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
818 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
819 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
820 </para>
821 <para>
822 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
823 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
824 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
825 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
826 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
827 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
828 has introduced.
829 </para>
830 <para>
831 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
832 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
833 regulation of each. By <quote>commercial culture</quote> I mean that part of our
834 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
835 <quote>noncommercial culture</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
836 parks or on
837 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
838 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
839 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his <quote>Reader,</quote> or
840 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
841 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel</primary></indexterm>
842 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah</primary></indexterm>
843 </para>
844 <para>
845 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
846 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
847 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
848 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
849 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
850 left this culture <quote>free.</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
851 individuals shared and transformed their culture&mdash;telling
852 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
853 clubs, sharing music, making tapes&mdash;were left alone by the law.
854 </para>
855 <para>
856 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
857 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
858 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
859 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
860 marketplace.<footnote>
861 <para>
862 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
863 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
864 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
865 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
866 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
867 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
868 D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote> Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193,
869 198&ndash;200.
870 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
871 </para></footnote>
872 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
873 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
874 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
875 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
876 </para>
877 <para>
878 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
879 been erased.<footnote><para>
880 See Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
881 2001), ch. 13.
882 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
883 </para></footnote>
884 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
885 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
886 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
887 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
888 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
889 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
890 the balance of our history&mdash;between uses of our culture that were
891 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission&mdash;has
892 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
893 culture, more and more a permission culture.
894 </para>
895 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
896 <para>
897 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
898 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
899 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
900 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
901 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
902 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
903 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
904 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
905 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
906 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
907 Causbys.
908 </para>
909 <para>
910 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
911 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
912 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
913 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
914 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
915 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
916 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
917 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
918 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
919 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
920 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
921 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
922 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
923 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
924 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
925 than creators do today&mdash;all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
926 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
927 </para>
928 <para>
929 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
930 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
931 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
932 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
933 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
934 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
935 remakes them.
936 </para>
937 <para>
938 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
939 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
940 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
941 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions&mdash;whether <quote>piracy</quote> will
942 be permitted, and whether <quote>property</quote> will be protected. The <quote>war</quote> that
943 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet&mdash;what
944 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
945 calls his <quote>own terrorist war</quote><footnote><para>
946 Amy Harmon, <quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
947 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,</quote> <citetitle>New York
948 Times</citetitle>, 17 January 2002.
949 </para></footnote>&mdash;has been framed as a battle about the
950 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
951 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
952 against it.
953 </para>
954 <para>
955 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
956 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
957 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
958 <quote>creative property.</quote> I believe that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that the
959 law, properly tuned, should punish <quote>piracy,</quote> whether on or off the
960 Internet.
961 </para>
962 <para>
963 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
964 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
965 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet <quote>pirates</quote> will also rid our
966 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
967 </para>
968 <para>
969 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first 180 years of
970 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
971 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
972 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
973 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,<footnote>
974 <para>
975 Neil W. Netanel, <quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
976 Journal</citetitle> 106 (1996): 283.
977 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
978 </para></footnote>
979 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
980 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
981 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
982 could cultivate and extend our culture.
983 </para>
984 <para>
985 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
986 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
987 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
988 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist&ndash;like,
989 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
990 granted&mdash;but it is not often granted to the critical or the
991 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
992 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
993 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
994 </para>
995 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Should "Is it" be "It is" ? -->
996 <para>
997 The story that follows is about this war. Is it not about the
998 <quote>centrality of technology</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
999 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
1000 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
1001 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
1002 against an industry.
1003 </para>
1004 <para>
1005 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
1006 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
1007 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
1008 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
1009 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
1010 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
1011 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
1012 </para>
1013 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1014 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1015 <para>
1016 Like the Causbys' battle, this war is, in part, about <quote>property.</quote> The
1017 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
1018 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
1019 this <quote>property</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
1020 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
1021 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
1022 of <quote>intellectual property</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
1023 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
1024 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
1025 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
1026 <quote>trespassing</quote> upon legitimate claims of <quote>property.</quote> It is as plain to
1027 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
1028 trespass.
1029 </para>
1030 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1031 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1032 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
1033 <para>
1034 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
1035 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
1036 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
1037 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
1038 war. Unlike
1039 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
1040 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
1041 on its side.
1042 </para>
1043 <para>
1044 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
1045 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
1046 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
1047 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
1048 our <quote>culture</quote> was as <quote>owned</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
1049 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
1050 <emphasis>uses</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
1051 accepted as it is now.
1052 </para>
1053 <para>
1054 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
1055 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
1056 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
1057 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1058 </para>
1059 <para>
1060 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1061 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1062 </para>
1063 <para>
1064 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1065 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1066 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1067 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1068 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1069 </para>
1070 <para>
1071 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1072 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1073 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1074 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1075 view?
1076 </para>
1077 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1078 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1079 <para>
1080 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1081 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1082 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1083 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of <quote>intellectual
1084 property.</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1085 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1086 this silliness will be much more profound.
1087 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1088 </para>
1089 <para>
1090 The struggle that rages just now centers on two ideas: <quote>piracy</quote> and
1091 <quote>property.</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1092 ideas.
1093 </para>
1094 <para>
1095 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1096 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1097 obscure French theorists&mdash;however natural that is for the weird
1098 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1099 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1100 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1101 </para>
1102 <para>
1103 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1104 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1105 government, pushed by big media to respond to this <quote>something new,</quote> is
1106 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1107 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let <quote>common
1108 sense</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1109 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1110 law&mdash;and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1111 fundamental about who we have always been.
1112 </para>
1113 <para>
1114 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1115 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1116 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1117 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1118 of one more consequence of this form of corruption&mdash;a consequence
1119 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1120 </para>
1121 </chapter>
1122 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1123 <part id="c-piracy">
1124 <title><quote>PIRACY</quote></title>
1125 <partintro>
1126 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1127 <indexterm id="idxmansfield1" class='startofrange'>
1128 <primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary>
1129 </indexterm>
1130 <para>
1131 Since the inception of the law regulating creative property, there has
1132 been a war against <quote>piracy.</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1133 <quote>piracy,</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1134 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1135 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1136 </para>
1137 <blockquote>
1138 <para>
1139 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1140 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1141 of them for his own use.<footnote><para>
1142 <!-- f1 -->
1143 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield).
1144 </para></footnote>
1145 </para>
1146 <indexterm startref="idxmansfield1" class='endofrange'/>
1147 </blockquote>
1148 <para>
1149 Today we are in the middle of another <quote>war</quote> against <quote>piracy.</quote> The
1150 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1151 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1152 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1153 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1154 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1155 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1156 </para>
1157 <para>
1158 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1159 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1160 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1161 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1162 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will <quote>rob the author of the
1163 profit.</quote>
1164 </para>
1165 <para>
1166 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1167 increasingly to technology to defend their <quote>property</quote> against this
1168 <quote>piracy.</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1169 raised to believe that <quote>property</quote> should be <quote>free.</quote> Forget tattoos,
1170 never mind body piercing&mdash;our kids are becoming
1171 <emphasis>thieves</emphasis>!
1172 </para>
1173 <para>
1174 There's no doubt that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1175 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1176 notion of <quote>piracy</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1177 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1178 </para>
1179 <para>
1180 The idea goes something like this:
1181 </para>
1182 <blockquote>
1183 <para>
1184 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1185 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1186 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1187 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1188 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1189 piracy.
1190 </para>
1191 </blockquote>
1192 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle</primary></indexterm>
1193 <para>
1194 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1195 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1196 theory of creative property<footnote><para>
1197 <!-- f2 -->
1198 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, <quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1199 in the Pepsi Generation,</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review</citetitle> 65 (1990): 397.
1200 </para></footnote>
1201 &mdash;if there is value, then someone must have a
1202 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1203 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1204 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.<footnote><para>
1205 <!-- f3 -->
1206 Lisa Bannon, <quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1207 Up,</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 21 August 1996, available at
1208 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #3</ulink>; Jonathan
1209 Zittrain, <quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1210 Speech, No One Wins,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 24 November 2002.
1211 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
1212 </para></footnote>
1213 There was <quote>value</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1214 <quote>right</quote>&mdash;even against the Girl Scouts.
1215 </para>
1216 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP</primary></indexterm>
1217 <para>
1218 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1219 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1220 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1221 of law protecting creative property. But the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1222 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1223 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1224 </para>
1225 <para>
1226 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1227 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1228 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1229 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1230 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1231 </para>
1232 <para>
1233 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1234 takes care to draw&mdash;the distinction between republishing someone's
1235 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1236 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1237 copyright law today regulates both.
1238 </para>
1239 <para>
1240 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1241 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1242 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1243 entities could bear the burden of the law&mdash;even the burden of the
1244 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1245 more expense of doing business.
1246 </para>
1247 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1248 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1249 <para>
1250 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1251 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1252 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1253 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1254 <quote>copying,</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1255 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1256 outweighs any original benefit&mdash;certainly as it affects
1257 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1258 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1259 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1260 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1261 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1262 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1263 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1264 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1265 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1266 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the <quote>Rise of the Creative
1267 Class.</quote><footnote>
1268 <para>
1269 <!-- f4 -->
1270 In <citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class</citetitle> (New York:
1271 Basic Books, 2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1272 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1273 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1274 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1275 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1276 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1277
1278 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1279 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1280 </para></footnote>
1281 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1282 this creative class.
1283 </para>
1284 <para>
1285 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1286 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1287 context the current battles about behavior labeled <quote>piracy.</quote>
1288 </para>
1289 </partintro>
1290
1291 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1292 <chapter label="1" id="creators">
1293 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators</title>
1294 <indexterm id="idxanimadedcartoons" class='startofrange'>
1295 <primary>animated cartoons</primary>
1296 </indexterm>
1297 <para>
1298 In 1928, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1299 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called <citetitle>Plane Crazy</citetitle>.
1300 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1301 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle> brought
1302 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1303 </para>
1304 <para>
1305 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1306 movie <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1307 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1308 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1309 Disney ran a test in the summer of 1928, the results were unambiguous.
1310 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1311 </para>
1312 <blockquote>
1313 <para>
1314 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1315 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1316 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1317 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1318 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1319 </para>
1320 <para>
1321 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1322 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1323 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1324 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1325 synchronization was pretty close.
1326 </para>
1327 <para>
1328 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1329 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1330 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1331 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1332 it was something new!<footnote><para>
1333 <!-- f1 -->
1334 Leonard Maltin, <citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1335 Cartoons</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34&ndash;35.
1336 </para></footnote>
1337 </para>
1338 </blockquote>
1339 <para>
1340 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1341 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: <quote>I have never been so thrilled
1342 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.</quote>
1343 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub</primary></indexterm>
1344 </para>
1345 <para>
1346 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1347 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1348 rarely&mdash;except in Disney's hands&mdash;been anything more than
1349 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1350 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1351 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1352 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1353 </para>
1354 <para>
1355 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that 1928 also marks
1356 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1357 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1358 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>.
1359 </para>
1360 <para>
1361 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in 1895. In the era of silent
1362 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1363 uncontrollable laughter from his audience. <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1364 Jr</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1365 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton&mdash;wildly popular
1366 and among the best of its genre.
1367 </para>
1368 <para>
1369 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1370 Willie.
1371 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1372 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1373 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,<footnote><para>
1374 <!-- f2 -->
1375 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1376 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #4</ulink>.
1377 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1378 use the music for five songs in <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>: <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote> <quote>The
1379 Simpleton</quote> (Delille), <quote>Mischief Makers</quote> (Carbonara), <quote>Joyful Hurry No. 1</quote>
1380 (Baron), and <quote>Gawky Rube</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song, <quote>The Turkey in the
1381 Straw,</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1382 Harry Surden, 10 July 2003, on file with author.
1383 </para></footnote>
1384 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1385 the invention of synchronized sound in <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle> that we
1386 get <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1387 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote>
1388 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1389 Mouse.
1390 </para>
1391 <para>
1392 This <quote>borrowing</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1393 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1394 films of his day.<footnote><para>
1395 <!-- f3 -->
1396 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, <quote>The Mouse
1397 that Ate the Public Domain,</quote> Findlaw, 5 March 2002, at
1398 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #5</ulink>.
1399 </para></footnote>
1400 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1401 knockoffs&mdash;slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1402 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1403 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1404 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1405 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1406 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1407 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1408 old.
1409 </para>
1410 <para>
1411 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1412 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1413 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1414 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1415 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1416 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1417 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1418 </para>
1419 <para>
1420 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1421 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1422 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1423 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1424 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1425 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1426 work of others is astonishing when set together: <citetitle>Snow White</citetitle>
1427 (1937), <citetitle>Fantasia</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Pinocchio</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Dumbo</citetitle>
1428 (1941), <citetitle>Bambi</citetitle> (1942), <citetitle>Song of the South</citetitle> (1946),
1429 <citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle> (1950), <citetitle>Alice in Wonderland</citetitle> (1951), <citetitle>Robin
1430 Hood</citetitle> (1952), <citetitle>Peter Pan</citetitle> (1953), <citetitle>Lady and the Tramp</citetitle>
1431 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1432 (1955), <citetitle>Mulan</citetitle> (1998), <citetitle>Sleeping Beauty</citetitle> (1959), <citetitle>101
1433 Dalmatians</citetitle> (1961), <citetitle>The Sword in the Stone</citetitle> (1963), and
1434 <citetitle>The Jungle Book</citetitle> (1967)&mdash;not to mention a recent example
1435 that we should perhaps quickly forget, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>
1436 (2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1437 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1438 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1439 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1440 </para>
1441 <indexterm startref="idxanimadedcartoons" class='endofrange'/>
1442 <para>
1443 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1444 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1445 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1446 its importance. We could call this <quote>Disney creativity,</quote> though that
1447 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, <quote>Walt Disney
1448 creativity</quote>&mdash;a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1449 culture around us and makes it something different.
1450 </para>
1451 <para> In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1452 relatively fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was
1453 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1454 thirty years&mdash;for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1455 copyrighted.<footnote><para>
1456 <!-- f4 -->
1457 Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1458 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the <quote>average</quote> term by
1459 determining
1460 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1461 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in year
1462 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the
1463 average
1464 term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1465 Web site associated with this book, available at
1466 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #6</ulink>.
1467 </para></footnote>
1468 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1469 copyright holders of a creative work had an <quote>exclusive right</quote> to control
1470 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1471 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1472 </para>
1473 <para>
1474 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1475 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1476 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a <quote>lawyer-free
1477 zone.</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1478 for Disney to use and build upon in 1928. It was free for
1479 anyone&mdash; whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1480 approved or not&mdash;to use and build upon.
1481 </para>
1482 <para>
1483 This is the ways things always were&mdash;until quite recently. For most
1484 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1485 until 1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1486 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1487
1488 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1489 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1490 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s
1491 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1492 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1493 content from before the Great Depression.
1494 </para>
1495 <para>
1496 Of course, Walt Disney had no monopoly on <quote>Walt Disney creativity.</quote>
1497 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1498 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1499 universal.
1500 </para>
1501 <para>
1502 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1503 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: <citetitle>manga</citetitle>, or
1504 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of
1505 publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives
1506 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1507 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1508 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1509 </para>
1510 <para>
1511 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1512 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1513 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1514 the stories that these <quote>graphic novels</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1515 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are <quote>men in tights.</quote>
1516 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1517 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1518 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1519 interestingly different way.
1520 </para>
1521 <para>
1522 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1523 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1524 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1525 </para>
1526 <para>
1527 This is the phenomenon of <citetitle>doujinshi</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1528 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1529 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is <emphasis>just</emphasis> a
1530 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1531 transforming it either subtly or
1532 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1533 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1534 develop it differently&mdash;with a different story line. Or the comic can
1535 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1536 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently <quote>different.</quote> But they
1537 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1538 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1539 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1540 </para>
1541 <para>
1542 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1543 huge. More than 33,000 <quote>circles</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1544 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come
1545 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1546 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1547 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1548 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1549 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1550 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1551 </para>
1552 <para>
1553 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1554 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1555 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1556 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1557 one. Doujinshi are plainly <quote>derivative works.</quote> There is no general
1558 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1559 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1560 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1561 Jr</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that <quote>taking</quote> without
1562 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1563 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1564 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1565 </para>
1566 <indexterm id="idxwinickjudd" class='startofrange'>
1567 <primary>Winick, Judd</primary>
1568 </indexterm>
1569 <para>
1570 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1571 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1572 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, <quote>The
1573 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1574 in Japan now. &hellip; American comics were born out of copying each
1575 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1576 other. &hellip; That's how [the artists] learn to draw&mdash;by going into comic
1577 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them</quote>
1578 and building from them.<footnote><para>
1579 <!-- f5 -->
1580 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, <citetitle>Reinventing Comics</citetitle> (New
1581 York: Perennial, 2000).
1582 </para></footnote>
1583 </para>
1584 <para>
1585 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1586 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1587 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, <quote>there are these rules
1588 and you have to stick to them.</quote> There are things Superman <quote>cannot</quote>
1589 do. <quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1590 which are fifty years old.</quote>
1591 </para>
1592 <indexterm startref="idxwinickjudd" class='endofrange'/>
1593 <para>
1594 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1595 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1596 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1597 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1598 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1599 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1600 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.<footnote><para>
1601 <!-- f6 -->
1602 See Salil K. Mehra, <quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1603 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1604 Review</citetitle> 55 (2002): 155, 182. <quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1605 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1606 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1607 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1608 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1609 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.</quote>
1610 </para></footnote>
1611 </para>
1612 <para>
1613 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1614 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1615 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1616 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1617 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1618 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1619 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1620 a more general pattern of blocking this <quote>free taking</quote> by the doujinshi
1621 culture?
1622 </para>
1623 <para>
1624 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1625 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1626 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. <quote>We don't have enough
1627 lawyers,</quote> he told me one afternoon. There <quote>just aren't enough resources
1628 to prosecute cases like this.</quote>
1629 </para>
1630 <para>
1631 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1632 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1633 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1634 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1635 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1636 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1637 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1638 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1639 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1640 their clients or hurt them?
1641 Let's pause for a moment.
1642 </para>
1643 <para>
1644 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1645 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1646 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1647 </para>
1648 <para>
1649 We live in a world that celebrates <quote>property.</quote> I am one of those
1650 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1651 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1652 <quote>intellectual property.</quote><footnote><para>
1653 <!-- f7 -->
1654 The term <citetitle>intellectual property</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1655 Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 11 (New York: New York
1656 University Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
1657 (New York: Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately
1658 describes a set of <quote>property</quote> rights&mdash;copyright, patents,
1659 trademark, and trade-secret&mdash;but the nature of those rights is
1660 very different.
1661 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
1662 </para></footnote>
1663 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1664 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1665 property.
1666 </para>
1667 <para>
1668 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1669 plenty of value out there that <quote>property</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1670 mean <quote>money can't buy you love,</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1671 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1672 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1673 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1674 condemning that taking as wrong&mdash; even though trivial, even if
1675 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1676 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1677 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1678 Disney's use would have been considered <quote>fair.</quote> There was nothing
1679 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1680 the public domain.
1681 </para>
1682 <para>
1683 Thus, even though the things that Disney took&mdash;or more generally,
1684 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity&mdash;are
1685 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1686
1687 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1688 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1689 freedom is good.
1690 </para>
1691 <para>
1692 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1693 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1694 work&mdash;or even one copy&mdash;without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1695 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1696 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1697 form, whether large or small.
1698 </para>
1699 <para>
1700 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1701 say that the copycat comic artists are <quote>stealing.</quote> This form of Walt
1702 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1703 particular find it hard to say why.
1704 </para>
1705 <para>
1706 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1707 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1708 without asking or paying for the privilege. (<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1709 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1710 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?</quote>) Acting companies
1711 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1712 permission from anyone. (Does <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> believe
1713 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1714 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1715 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1716 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s;
1717 two volcano disaster films in 1997.
1718 </para>
1719 <para>
1720 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1721 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1722 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1723 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1724 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1725 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1726 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking&mdash;free
1727 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1728 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1729 </para>
1730 <para>
1731 The hard question is therefore not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> a
1732 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1733 question instead is <quote><emphasis>How</emphasis> free is this culture?</quote>
1734 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1735 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1736 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1737 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1738 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1739 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1740 a studio or not?
1741 </para>
1742 <para>
1743 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1744 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1745 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1746 </para>
1747
1748 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1749 </chapter>
1750 <chapter label="2" id="mere-copyists">
1751 <title>CHAPTER TWO: <quote>Mere Copyists</quote></title>
1752 <indexterm id="idxphotography" class='startofrange'>
1753 <primary>photography</primary>
1754 </indexterm>
1755 <para>
1756 In 1839, Louis Daguerre invented the first practical technology for
1757 producing what we would call <quote>photographs.</quote> Appropriately enough, they
1758 were called <quote>daguerreotypes.</quote> The process was complicated and
1759 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1760 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1761 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1762 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1763 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis</primary></indexterm>
1764 </para>
1765 <para>
1766 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1767 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1768 <quote>automatic pictures.</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1769 making <quote>negatives.</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1770 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1771 the 1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1772 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1773 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1774 amateurs.
1775 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William</primary></indexterm>
1776 </para>
1777 <indexterm id="idxeastmangeorge" class='startofrange'>
1778 <primary>Eastman, George</primary>
1779 </indexterm>
1780 <para>
1781 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1782 didn't happen until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1783 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1784 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1785 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1786 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1787 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1788 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1789 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1790 population of photographers.
1791 </para>
1792 <para>
1793 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1794 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1795 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. <quote>You press the button and we
1796 do the rest.</quote><footnote><para>
1797 <!-- f1 -->
1798 Reese V. Jenkins, <citetitle>Images and Enterprise</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975), 112.
1799 </para></footnote> As he described in <citetitle>The Kodak Primer</citetitle>:
1800 <indexterm><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)</primary></indexterm>
1801 </para>
1802 <blockquote>
1803 <para>
1804 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1805 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1806 that only an expert can do. &hellip; We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1807 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1808 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1809 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1810 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1811 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1812 chemicals.<footnote>
1813 <para>
1814 <!-- f2 -->
1815 Brian Coe, <citetitle>The Birth of Photography</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1816 1977), 53.
1817 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1818 </para></footnote>
1819 </para>
1820 </blockquote>
1821 <para>
1822 For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1823 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1824 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1825 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1826 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1827 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in 1888; one
1828 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1829 From 1888 through 1909, while industrial production was rising by 4.7
1830 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by 11
1831 percent.<footnote><para>
1832 <!-- f3 -->
1833 Jenkins, 177.
1834 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1835 an average annual increase of over 17 percent.<footnote><para>
1836 <!-- f4 -->
1837 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p. 178.
1838 </para></footnote>
1839 </para>
1840 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1841 <para>
1842
1843 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1844 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1845 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1846 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1847 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1848 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, <quote>For the
1849 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1850 permanent record of his family and its activities. &hellip; For the first
1851 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1852 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1853 interpretation or bias.</quote><footnote><para>
1854 <!-- f5 -->
1855 Coe, 58.
1856 </para></footnote>
1857 </para>
1858 <para>
1859 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1860 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1861 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1862 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1863 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1864 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its <quote>quality</quote>;
1865 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1866 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1867 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1868 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1869 have before.
1870 </para>
1871 <para>
1872 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1873 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1874 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1875 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1876 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1877 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1878 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1879 he wanted. Their answer was no.<footnote><para>
1880 <!-- f6 -->
1881 For illustrative cases, see, for example, <citetitle>Pavesich</citetitle>
1882 v. <citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co</citetitle>., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905);
1883 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Chinn</citetitle>, 123090 S.W. 364, 366
1884 (Ky. 1909); <citetitle>Corliss</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Walker</citetitle>, 64 F. 280 (Mass.
1885 Dist. Ct. 1894).
1886 </para></footnote>
1887 </para>
1888 <para>
1889 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1890 familiar. The photographer was <quote>taking</quote> something from the person or
1891 building whose photograph he shot&mdash;pirating something of
1892 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1893 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1894 draw
1895 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1896 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1897 that they thought valuable.
1898 </para>
1899 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1900 <para>
1901 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1902 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1903 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1904 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1905 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.<footnote>
1906 <para>
1907 <!-- f7 -->
1908 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote>
1909 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review</citetitle> 4 (1890): 193.
1910 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1911 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.</primary></indexterm>
1912 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1913 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1914 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1915 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1916 </para>
1917 <para>
1918 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1919 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1920 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1921 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1922 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1923 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1924 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1925 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1926 clearing the rights to do the capturing.<footnote><para>
1927 <!-- f8 -->
1928 See Melville B. Nimmer, <quote>The Right of Publicity,</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
1929 Problems</citetitle> 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, <quote>Privacy,</quote> <citetitle>California Law
1930 Review</citetitle> 48 (1960) 398&ndash;407; <citetitle>White</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
1931 Inc</citetitle>., 971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951
1932 (1993).
1933 </para></footnote>)
1934 </para>
1935 <para>
1936 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1937 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1938 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1939 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1940 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1941 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1942 Kodak would be benefiting from the <quote>theft</quote> committed by the
1943 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1944 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1945 from the <quote>image-right</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
1946 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1947 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1948 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1949 </para>
1950 <para>
1951
1952 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
1953 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
1954 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
1955 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
1956 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
1957 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
1958 technology as they did&mdash;since professionals could have more
1959 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
1960 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
1961 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
1962 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
1963 realized. If you drive through San Francisco's Presidio, you might
1964 see two gaudy yellow school buses painted over with colorful and
1965 striking images, and the logo <quote>Just Think!</quote> in place of the name of a
1966 school. But there's little that's <quote>just</quote> cerebral in the projects that
1967 these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies that
1968 teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even the
1969 film of your VCR. Rather the <quote>film</quote> of digital cameras. Just Think!
1970 is a project that enables kids to make films, as a way to understand
1971 and critique the filmed culture that they find all around them. Each
1972 year, these busses travel to more than thirty schools and enable three
1973 hundred to five hundred children to learn something about media by
1974 doing something with media. By doing, they think. By tinkering, they
1975 learn.
1976 </para>
1977 <indexterm startref="idxeastmangeorge" class='endofrange'/>
1978 <indexterm startref="idxphotography" class='endofrange'/>
1979 <para>
1980 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
1981 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
1982 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, <quote>Five years ago, a good
1983 real-time digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get
1984 professional quality for $595.</quote><footnote><para>
1985 <!-- f9 -->
1986 H. Edward Goldberg, <quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
1987 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,</quote>
1988 cadalyst, February 2002, available at
1989 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #7</ulink>.
1990 </para></footnote>
1991 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
1992 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
1993 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
1994 learning more and more of something teachers call <quote>media literacy.</quote>
1995 </para>
1996 <para>
1997 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
1998 <quote>Media literacy,</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
1999 Think!, puts it, <quote>is the ability &hellip; to understand, analyze, and
2000 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2001 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2002 the way people access it.</quote>
2003 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2004 </para>
2005 <para>
2006 This may seem like an odd way to think about <quote>literacy.</quote> For most
2007 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2008 and noticing split infinitives are the things that <quote>literate</quote> people know
2009 about.
2010 </para>
2011 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2012 <para>
2013 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of
2014 television commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000
2015 commercials generally,<footnote><para>
2016 <!-- f10 -->
2017 Judith Van Evra, <citetitle>Television and Child Development</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2018 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990); <quote>Findings on Family and TV
2019 Study,</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post</citetitle>, 25 May 1997, B6.
2020 </para></footnote>
2021 it is increasingly important to understand the <quote>grammar</quote> of media. For
2022 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2023 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2024 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2025 (at least at first) terrible media.
2026 </para>
2027 <para>
2028 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2029 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2030 has written understands how difficult writing is&mdash;how difficult
2031 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2032 language to be understandable&mdash;few of us have any real sense of
2033 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2034 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2035 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2036 </para>
2037 <para>
2038 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2039 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2040 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2041 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2042 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2043 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2044 </para>
2045 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael</primary></indexterm>
2046 <para>
2047 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2048 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2049 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2050
2051 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2052 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2053 about <quote>the placement of objects, color, &hellip; rhythm, pacing, and
2054 texture.</quote><footnote>
2055 <para>
2056 <!-- f11 -->
2057 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish, 13 December
2058 2002.
2059 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2060 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2061 </para></footnote>
2062 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2063 <quote>played</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2064 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2065 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2066 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2067 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2068 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2069 to a wildly successful author.<footnote><para>
2070 <!-- f12 -->
2071 See Scott Steinberg, <quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,</quote> E!online, 4
2072 November 2000, available at
2073 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #8</ulink>; <quote>Timeline,</quote> 22 November 2000,
2074 available at
2075 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #9</ulink>.
2076 </para></footnote>
2077 </para>
2078 <indexterm><primary>computer games</primary></indexterm>
2079 <para>
2080 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2081 describes, <quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2082 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2083 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2084 led.</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2085 </para>
2086 <para>
2087 Yet the push for an expanded literacy&mdash;one that goes beyond text
2088 to include audio and visual elements&mdash;is not about making better
2089 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2090 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2091 </para>
2092 <blockquote>
2093 <para>
2094 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2095 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2096 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2097 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2098 being read-only.
2099 </para>
2100 </blockquote>
2101 <para>
2102 <quote>Read-only.</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2103 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2104 twentieth century.
2105 </para>
2106 <para>
2107 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2108 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2109 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2110 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2111 literacy,
2112 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2113 and this literacy in particular, is to <quote>empower people to choose the
2114 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2115 express.</quote><footnote>
2116 <para>
2117 <!-- f13 -->
2118 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2119 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2120 </para></footnote> It is to enable students <quote>to communicate in the
2121 language of the twenty-first century.</quote><footnote><para>
2122 <!-- f14 -->
2123 Ibid.
2124 </para></footnote>
2125 </para>
2126 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2127 <para>
2128 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2129 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2130 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2131 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2132 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2133 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2134 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2135 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2136 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2137 students know something about&mdash;gun violence.
2138 </para>
2139 <para>
2140 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2141 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2142 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2143 away. The <quote>kids were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night,</quote>
2144 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2145 what education should be about&mdash;learning how to express themselves.
2146 </para>
2147 <para>
2148 Using whatever <quote>free web stuff they could find,</quote> and relatively simple
2149 tools to enable the kids to mix <quote>image, sound, and text,</quote> Barish said
2150 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2151 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2152 close to the lives of these students. The project <quote>gave them a tool
2153 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2154 it,</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2155 expression&mdash;far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2156 been created using only text. <quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2157 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2158 gone and done something else,</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2159 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2160 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2161 <emphasis>these</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2162 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2163 </para>
2164 <para>
2165
2166 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2167 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?</quote> I asked. In part,
2168 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2169 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of <quote>constructing
2170 meaning.</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2171 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2172 part&mdash;and increasingly, not the most powerful part&mdash;of
2173 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2174 our interview,
2175 </para>
2176 <blockquote>
2177 <para>
2178 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2179 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2180 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2181 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2182 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2183 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2184 you say, <quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.</quote>
2185 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2186 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2187 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, <quote>Well, with all these things that you
2188 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2189 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2190 for me something that reflects that.</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2191 camera and &hellip; saying, <quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2192 make a little movie.</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2193 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2194 about the topic.&hellip;
2195 </para>
2196 <para>
2197 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2198 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2199 bump up against the fact, <quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2200 to write something.</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2201 they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 times, till they got it right.
2202 </para>
2203 <para>
2204 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2205 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2206 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2207 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2208 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2209 had a lot of power with this language.
2210 </para>
2211 <!-- FIXME removed a " from the end of the previous paragraph that did
2212 not match with any start quote. -->
2213 </blockquote>
2214 <para>
2215 When two planes crashed into the World Trade Center, another into the
2216 Pentagon, and a fourth into a Pennsylvania field, all media around the
2217 world shifted to this news. Every moment of just about every day for
2218 that week, and for weeks after, television in particular, and media
2219 generally, retold the story of the events we had just witnessed. The
2220 telling was a retelling, because we had seen the events that were
2221 described. The genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the
2222 delayed second attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole
2223 world would be watching.
2224 </para>
2225 <para>
2226 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2227 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2228 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was <quote>balance,</quote>
2229 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2230 increasingly come to expect it, <quote>news as entertainment,</quote> even if the
2231 entertainment is tragedy.
2232 </para>
2233 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
2234 <indexterm><primary>CBS</primary></indexterm>
2235 <para>
2236 But in addition to this produced news about the <quote>tragedy of September
2237 11,</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2238 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2239 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2240 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2241 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2242 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2243 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2244 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2245 the term in his book <citetitle>Cyber Rights</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2246 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2247 was also the Internet.
2248 </para>
2249 <para>
2250 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet&mdash;though I do think the
2251 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2252 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2253 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2254 movie
2255 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2256 by a student on the <quote>Just Think!</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2257 with sound or text.
2258 </para>
2259 <para>
2260 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2261 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2262 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2263 tradition&mdash;not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2264 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2265 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2266 spread practically instantaneously.
2267 </para>
2268 <para>
2269 September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2270 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2271 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2272 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2273 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2274 cultures, it records private facts in a public way&mdash;it's a kind
2275 of electronic <citetitle>Jerry Springer</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2276 </para>
2277 <para>
2278 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2279 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2280 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2281 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2282 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2283 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2284 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2285 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2286 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2287 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2288 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2289 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2290 </para>
2291 <para>
2292 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2293 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2294 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2295 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2296 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2297 people vote
2298 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2299 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2300 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2301 </para>
2302 <para>
2303 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2304 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2305 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2306 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2307 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2308 most important account of early <quote>Democracy in America.</quote> It wasn't
2309 popular elections that fascinated him&mdash;it was the jury, an
2310 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2311 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2312 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2313 deliberated. Members argued about the <quote>right</quote> result; they tried to
2314 persuade each other of the <quote>right</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2315 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2316 come to an end.<footnote><para>
2317 <!-- f15 -->
2318 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, <citetitle>Democracy in America</citetitle>,
2319 bk. 1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16.
2320 </para></footnote>
2321 </para>
2322 <para>
2323 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2324 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2325 are pushing to create just such an institution.<footnote><para>
2326 <!-- f16 -->
2327 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, <quote>Deliberation Day,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2328 Political Philosophy</citetitle> 10 (2) (2002): 129.
2329 </para></footnote>
2330 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2331 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2332 place for <quote>democratic deliberation</quote> to occur.
2333 </para>
2334 <para>
2335 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2336 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2337 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2338 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2339 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2340 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.<footnote><para>
2341 <!-- f17 -->
2342 Cass Sunstein, <citetitle>Republic.com</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001),
2343 65&ndash;80, 175, 182, 183, 192.
2344 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2345 little beyond what our friends say.
2346 </para>
2347 <para>
2348 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2349 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2350 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2351 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2352 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2353
2354 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2355 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2356 place.
2357 </para>
2358 <para>
2359 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2360 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2361 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2362 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2363 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2364 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2365 </para>
2366 <para>
2367 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2368 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race
2369 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2370 is having an effect.
2371 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard</primary></indexterm>
2372 </para>
2373 <para>
2374 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2375 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2376 <quote>misspoke</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2377 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2378 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2379 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2380 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2381 more instances of the same <quote>misspeaking</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2382 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2383 resign as senate majority leader.<footnote><para>
2384 <!-- f18 -->
2385 Noah Shachtman, <quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,</quote> New
2386 York Times, 16 January 2003, G5.
2387 </para></footnote>
2388 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent</primary></indexterm>
2389 </para>
2390 <para>
2391 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2392 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2393 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2394 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2395 on.
2396 </para>
2397 <para>
2398 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2399 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2400 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2401 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2402 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2403 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2404 peer-generated rankings.
2405 </para>
2406 <indexterm id="idxwinerdave" class='startofrange'>
2407 <primary>Winer, Dave</primary>
2408 </indexterm>
2409 <para>
2410 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2411 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2412 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2413 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2414 difference is the absence of a financial <quote>conflict of interest.</quote> <quote>I think you
2415 have to take the conflict of interest</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2416 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2417 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2418 get it out of the way.</quote>
2419 </para>
2420 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2421 <para>
2422 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2423 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2424 from the public than an unconcentrated media can&mdash;as CNN admitted
2425 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2426 its own employees.<footnote><para>
2427 <!-- f19 -->
2428 Telephone interview with David Winer, 16 April 2003.
2429 </para></footnote>
2430 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2431 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2432 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2433 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2434 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2435 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2436 told her that <emphasis>they</emphasis> were writing <quote>the story.</quote>)
2437 </para>
2438 <para> Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2439 debate&mdash;<quote>amateur</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced, but in the
2440 sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to give their
2441 reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a story, as
2442 reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds from across
2443 the southwest United States turned to the Internet to retell what they
2444 had seen.<footnote><para>
2445 <!-- f20 -->
2446 John Schwartz, <quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2447 Information Online,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci
2448 D. Kramer, <quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,</quote>
2449 Online Journalism Review, 2 February 2003, available at
2450 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #10</ulink>.
2451 </para></footnote>
2452 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2453 <quote>triangulate,</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2454 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2455 out of it</quote>&mdash;with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2456 </para>
2457 <para>
2458 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2459 with blogs. <quote>It's going to become an essential skill,</quote> Winer predicts,
2460 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2461 not clear that <quote>journalism</quote> is happy about this&mdash;some journalists
2462 have been told to curtail their blogging.<footnote>
2463 <para>
2464 <!-- f21 -->
2465 See Michael Falcone, <quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?</quote> <citetitle>New
2466 York Times</citetitle>, 29 September 2003, C4. (<quote>Not all news organizations have
2467 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2468 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2469 war on March 9, stopped posting 12 days later at his bosses'
2470 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a <citetitle>Houston Chronicle</citetitle> reporter, was
2471 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2472 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.</quote>)
2473 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2474 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve</primary></indexterm>
2475 </para></footnote>
2476 But it is clear that we are still in transition. <quote>A
2477
2478 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2479 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,</quote> Winer told me.
2480 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2481 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2482 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, <quote>we will
2483 be the last thing that gets shut down.</quote>
2484 </para>
2485 <para>
2486 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because <quote>you
2487 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.</quote>
2488 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2489 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2490 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2491 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2492 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2493 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2494 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2495 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2496 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2497 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2498 extraordinary to report.
2499 </para>
2500 <indexterm startref="idxwinerdave" class='endofrange'/>
2501 <indexterm id="idxbrownjohnseely" class='startofrange'>
2502 <primary>Brown, John Seely</primary>
2503 </indexterm>
2504 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'>
2505 <primary>advertising</primary>
2506 </indexterm>
2507 <para>
2508 John Seely Brown is the chief scientist of the Xerox Corporation.
2509 His work, as his Web site describes it, is <quote>human learning and &hellip; the
2510 creation of knowledge ecologies for creating &hellip; innovation.</quote>
2511 </para>
2512 <para>
2513 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2514 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2515 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2516 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2517 affect learning.
2518 </para>
2519 <para>
2520 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When <quote>a lot of us grew up,</quote>
2521 he explains, that tinkering was done <quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2522 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.</quote> But digital technologies
2523 enable a different kind of tinkering&mdash;with abstract ideas though
2524 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2525 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2526 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2527 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2528 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2529 or <quote>free collage,</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2530 the tinkering of many others.
2531 </para>
2532 <para>
2533 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2534 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2535 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2536 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2537 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2538 </para>
2539 <para>
2540 This opportunity creates a <quote>completely new kind of learning platform,</quote>
2541 as Brown describes. <quote>As soon as you start doing that, you &hellip;
2542 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2543 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2544 if they can improve it.</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2545 apprenticeship. <quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.</quote>
2546 </para>
2547 <para>
2548 In this process, <quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2549 They are code.</quote> Kids are <quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2550 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2551 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2552 platform. &hellip; You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2553 you tinker the more you improve.</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2554 learn.
2555 </para>
2556 <para>
2557 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2558 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2559 it, <quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2560 intelligence.</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2561 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2562 text. <quote>The Web &hellip; says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2563 you are visual, if you are interested in film &hellip; [then] there is a
2564 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2565 these multiple forms of intelligence.</quote>
2566 </para>
2567 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'/>
2568 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2569 <para>
2570 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2571 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2572
2573 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2574 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2575 kind of recognition.
2576 </para>
2577 <para>
2578 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2579 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2580 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2581 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2582 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2583 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2584 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2585 </para>
2586 <para>
2587 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2588 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2589 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>)
2590 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the <quote>right to
2591 tinker</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2592 general.<footnote><para>
2593 <!-- f22 -->
2594 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, <quote>Technological Access
2595 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2596 of the Association for Computer Machinery</citetitle> 43 (2000): 9.
2597 </para></footnote>
2598 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2599 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2600 </para>
2601 <para>
2602 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,</quote> Brown
2603 explains. We need to <quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2604 and want to learn.</quote>
2605 </para>
2606 <para>
2607 <quote>Yet,</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2608 evince, <quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2609 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. &hellip; We're building an
2610 architecture that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2611 system that closes down that part of the brain.</quote>
2612 </para>
2613 <indexterm startref="idxbrownjohnseely" class='endofrange'/>
2614 <para>
2615 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2616 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2617 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2618 the law to close down that technology.
2619 </para>
2620 <para>
2621 <quote>No way to run a culture,</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2622 chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="collectors"/>,
2623 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2624 </para>
2625 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2626 </chapter>
2627 <chapter label="3" id="catalogs">
2628 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs</title>
2629 <indexterm><primary>RPI</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</see></indexterm>
2630 <indexterm id="idxrensselaer" class='startofrange'>
2631 <primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary>
2632 </indexterm>
2633 <para>
2634 In the fall of 2002, Jesse Jordan of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as
2635 a freshman at Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York.
2636 His major at RPI was information technology. Though he is not a
2637 programmer, in October Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search
2638 engine technology that was available on the RPI network.
2639 </para>
2640 <para>
2641 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2642 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2643 to information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand
2644 undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school
2645 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2646 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2647 </para>
2648 <para>
2649 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2650 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2651 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2652 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2653 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2654 </para>
2655 <para>
2656 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2657 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2658 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2659 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2660 engines can do this even better. The idea of <quote>intranet</quote> search
2661 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2662 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2663 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2664 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2665 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2666 </para>
2667 <para>
2668 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2669 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2670 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2671 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2672 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2673 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2674 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2675 </para>
2676 <para>
2677 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2678 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2679 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2680 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2681 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2682 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2683 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2684 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2685 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2686 on-line.
2687 </para>
2688 <para>
2689 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2690 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2691 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2692 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2693 be on users' computers.
2694 </para>
2695 <para>
2696 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2697 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2698 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2699 might have created; university brochures&mdash;basically anything that
2700 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2701 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2702 computer.
2703 </para>
2704 <para>
2705 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2706 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2707 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and&mdash;so that this
2708 point is absolutely clear&mdash;Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2709 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2710 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2711 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2712 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2713 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2714 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2715 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2716 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2717 supposed to do.
2718 </para>
2719 <para>
2720 On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2721 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2722 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2723 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2724 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2725 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2726 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2727 </para>
2728 <para>
2729 <quote>It was absurd,</quote> he told me. <quote>I don't think I did anything
2730 wrong. &hellip; I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2731 engine that I ran or &hellip; what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2732 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2733 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2734 easier to use</quote>&mdash;again, a <emphasis>search engine</emphasis>,
2735 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2736 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2737 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2738 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2739 with music.
2740 </para>
2741 <para>
2742 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2743 network and had therefore <quote>willfully</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2744 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2745 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2746 <quote>willful infringement,</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2747 call <quote>statutory damages.</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2748 claim $150,000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2749 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2750 Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000.
2751 </para>
2752 <para>
2753 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2754 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2755 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2756 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2757 huge demands for <quote>damages</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2758 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2759 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $100
2760 <emphasis>billion</emphasis>&mdash;six times the
2761 <emphasis>total</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2762 2001.<footnote><para>
2763
2764 <!-- f1 -->
2765 Tim Goral, <quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks:
2766 Suit Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages,</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC</citetitle> 6
2767 (2003): 5, available at 2003 WL 55179443.
2768 </para></footnote>
2769 </para>
2770 <indexterm startref="idxrensselaer" class='endofrange'/>
2771 <para>
2772 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2773 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2774 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2775 $12,000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2776 $12,000 to dismiss the case.
2777 </para>
2778 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt</primary></indexterm>
2779 <para>
2780 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2781 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2782 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2783 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2784 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2785 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2786 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, <quote>You don't want to pay another
2787 visit to a dentist like me.</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2788 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2789 </para>
2790 <para>
2791 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2792 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2793 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2794 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2795 at least $250,000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2796 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2797 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2798 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2799 </para>
2800 <para>
2801 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $250,000 and a chance at winning,
2802 or $12,000 and a settlement.
2803 </para>
2804 <indexterm>
2805 <primary>artists</primary>
2806 <secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary>
2807 </indexterm>
2808 <para>
2809 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2810 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2811 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2812 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2813 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $1 million a year.
2814 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2815 artist makes $45,900.<footnote><para>
2816 <!-- f2 -->
2817 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001)
2818 (27&ndash;2042&mdash;Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2819 the Arts, <citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon</citetitle> (2000).
2820 </para></footnote>
2821 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2822 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2823 student for running a search engine?<footnote><para>
2824 <!-- f3 -->
2825 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in <quote>KaZaA and Punishment,</quote>
2826 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, A24.
2827 </para></footnote>
2828 </para>
2829 <para>
2830 On June 23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2831 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2832 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $15 million lawsuit became an
2833 activist:
2834 </para>
2835 <blockquote>
2836 <para>
2837 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2838 an activist. &hellip; [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2839 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2840 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2841 </para>
2842 </blockquote>
2843 <para>
2844 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2845 his father told me, Jesse <quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
2846 I. &hellip; He's not a tree hugger. &hellip; I think it's bizarre that they would
2847 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2848 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.</quote>
2849 </para>
2850 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
2851 </chapter>
2852 <chapter label="4" id="pirates">
2853 <title>CHAPTER FOUR: <quote>Pirates</quote></title>
2854 <para>
2855 If <quote>piracy</quote> means using the creative property of others without
2856 their permission&mdash;if <quote>if value, then right</quote> is true&mdash;then the history of
2857 the content industry is a history of piracy. Every important sector of
2858 <quote>big media</quote> today&mdash;film, records, radio, and cable TV&mdash;was born of a
2859 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last generation's
2860 pirates join this generation's country club&mdash;until now.
2861 </para>
2862 <section id="film">
2863 <title>Film</title>
2864 <para>
2865 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.<footnote><para>
2866 <!-- f1 -->
2867 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
2868 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 87&ndash;93,
2869 which details Edison's <quote>adventures</quote> with copyright and patent.
2870 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
2871 </para></footnote>
2872 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
2873 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
2874 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
2875 exercised through a monopoly <quote>trust,</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
2876 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
2877 property&mdash;patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
2878 this creative property
2879 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
2880 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
2881 </para>
2882 <para>
2883 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
2884 </para>
2885 <blockquote>
2886 <para>
2887 A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
2888 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
2889 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
2890 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
2891 summer of 1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
2892 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
2893 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
2894 </para>
2895 <para>
2896 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
2897 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
2898 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
2899 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
2900 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
2901 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
2902 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
2903 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
2904 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
2905 license was revoked.<footnote><para>
2906 <!-- f2 -->
2907 J. A. Aberdeen, <citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
2908 Picture Producers</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts
2909 posted at <quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
2910 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,</quote> available at
2911 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #11</ulink>. For a
2912 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
2913 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, <quote>From
2914 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
2915 the Propertization of Copyright</quote> (September 2002), University of
2916 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
2917 Working Paper No. 159.
2918 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
2919 </para></footnote>
2920 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William</primary></indexterm>
2921 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company</primary></indexterm>
2922 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
2923 </para>
2924 </blockquote>
2925 <para>
2926 The Napsters of those days, the <quote>independents,</quote> were companies like
2927 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
2928 resisted. <quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
2929 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
2930 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.</quote><footnote><para>
2931 <!-- f3 -->
2932 Marc Wanamaker, <quote>The First Studios,</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority</citetitle>, archived at
2933 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #12</ulink>.
2934 </para></footnote>
2935 That led the independents to flee the East
2936 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
2937 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
2938 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
2939 did just that.
2940 </para>
2941 <para>
2942 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
2943 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
2944 patent holder a truly <quote>limited</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
2945
2946 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
2947 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
2948 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
2949 Edison's creative property.
2950 </para>
2951 </section>
2952 <section id="recordedmusic">
2953 <title>Recorded Music</title>
2954 <para>
2955 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
2956 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
2957 </para>
2958 <indexterm id="idxfourneauxhenri" class='startofrange'>
2959 <primary>Fourneaux, Henri</primary>
2960 </indexterm>
2961 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil</primary></indexterm>
2962 <para>
2963 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
2964 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
2965 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
2966 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
2967 their music. In other words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
2968 1899 hit <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
2969 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
2970 right to perform it publicly.
2971 </para>
2972 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
2973 <para>
2974 But what if I wanted to record <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> using Edison's phonograph
2975 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
2976 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
2977 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
2978 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
2979 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
2980 <quote>public performance</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
2981 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
2982 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
2983 brain are not&mdash;yet&mdash; regulated by copyright law). So if I
2984 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
2985 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
2986 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
2987 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
2988 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
2989 its composer anything.
2990 </para>
2991 <indexterm startref="idxfourneauxhenri" class='endofrange'/>
2992 <para>
2993 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
2994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
2995 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
2996 put it,
2997 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
2998 </para>
2999 <blockquote>
3000 <para>
3001 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3002 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3003 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3004 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3005 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3006 rights.<footnote><para>
3007 <!-- f4 -->
3008 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3009 S. 6330 and H.R. 19853 Before the ( Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th
3010 Cong. 59, 1st sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3011 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in <citetitle>Legislative History of the
3012 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3013 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3014 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3015 </para></footnote>
3016 </para>
3017 </blockquote>
3018 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip</primary></indexterm>
3019 <para>
3020 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3021 people's works were <quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3022 genius of American composers,</quote><footnote><para>
3023 <!-- f5 -->
3024 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223
3025 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3026 </para></footnote>
3027 and the <quote>music publishing industry</quote>
3028 was thereby <quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.</quote><footnote><para>
3029 <!-- f6 -->
3030 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226
3031 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3032 </para></footnote>
3033 As John Philip
3034 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, <quote>When they make money
3035 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.</quote><footnote><para>
3036 <!-- f7 -->
3037 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23
3038 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3039 </para></footnote>
3040 </para>
3041 <para>
3042 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3043 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3044 player piano argued that <quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3045 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3046 of anything he had before their introduction.</quote> Rather, the machines
3047 increased the sales of sheet music.<footnote><para>
3048 <!-- f8 -->
3049
3050 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283&ndash;84
3051 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3052 Perforating Company of New York).
3053 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3054 Congress was <quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3055 they represent, and whose servants they are.</quote> <quote>All talk about
3056 `theft,'</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3057 wrote, <quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3058 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3059 statute.</quote><footnote><para>
3060 <!-- f9 -->
3061 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared
3062 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3063 Graphophone Company Association).
3064 </para></footnote>
3065 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company</primary></indexterm>
3066 </para>
3067 <para>
3068 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3069 <emphasis>and</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3070 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the <quote>mechanical
3071 reproductions</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3072 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3073 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3074 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3075 recorded once. This is the part of
3076
3077 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3078 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3079 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3080 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3081 </para>
3082 <para>
3083 American law ordinarily calls this a <quote>compulsory license,</quote> but I will
3084 refer to it as a <quote>statutory license.</quote> A statutory license is a license
3085 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3086 Copyright Act in 1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3087 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3088 the fee set by the statute.
3089 </para>
3090 <para>
3091 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3092 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3093 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3094 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3095 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3096 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3097 Grisham.
3098 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
3099 </para>
3100 <para>
3101 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3102 thus, in effect, the law <emphasis>subsidizes</emphasis> the recording
3103 industry through a kind of piracy&mdash;by giving recording artists a
3104 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3105 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3106 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3107 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3108 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3109 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3110 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3111 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3112 creativity.<footnote><para>
3113
3114 <!-- f10 -->
3115 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and
3116 H.R. 11794 Before the ( Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st
3117 sess., 217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3118 in <citetitle>Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3119 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3120 </para></footnote>
3121 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3122 </para>
3123 <para>
3124 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3125 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3126 records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3127 relates,
3128 </para>
3129 <blockquote>
3130 <para>
3131 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3132 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3133 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3134 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3135 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3136 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3137 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3138 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3139 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before 1909 and
3140 the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3141 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3142 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3143 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3144 choice.<footnote><para>
3145 <!-- f11 -->
3146 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee
3147 on the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8
3148 March 1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3149 this report.</para></footnote>
3150 </para>
3151 </blockquote>
3152 <para>
3153 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3154 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3155 </para>
3156 </section>
3157 <section id="radio">
3158 <title>Radio</title>
3159 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments1' class='startofrange'>
3160 <primary>artists</primary>
3161 <secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary>
3162 </indexterm>
3163 <para>
3164 Radio was also born of piracy.
3165 </para>
3166 <para>
3167 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3168 <quote>public performance</quote> of the composer's work.<footnote><para>
3169 <!-- f12 -->
3170 See 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning,
3171 record companies printed <quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast</quote> and other
3172 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3173 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3174 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3175 station. See <citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Whiteman</citetitle>, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd
3176 Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3177 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3178 Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 281.
3179 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned</primary></indexterm>
3180 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3181 </para></footnote>
3182 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3183 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3184 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3185 </para>
3186 <para>
3187 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3188 copy of the <emphasis>composer's</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3189 also performing a copy of the <emphasis>recording artist's</emphasis>
3190 work. It's one thing to have <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> sung on the radio by the
3191 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3192 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3193 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3194 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3195 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3196 music for his work.
3197 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
3198
3199 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3200 </para>
3201 <para>
3202 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3203 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3204 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3205 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3206 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3207 of playing the song.
3208 </para>
3209 <indexterm id="idxmadonna" class='startofrange'>
3210 <primary>Madonna</primary>
3211 </indexterm>
3212 <para>
3213 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3214 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3215 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3216 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3217 </para>
3218 <para>
3219 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3220 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3221 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3222 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3223 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3224 <quote>protected</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3225 <emphasis>pirate</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3226 her anything.
3227 </para>
3228 <indexterm startref="idxmadonna" class='endofrange'/>
3229 <para>
3230 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3231 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3232 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3233 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3234 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3235 to take something for nothing.
3236 </para>
3237 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments1' class='endofrange'/>
3238 </section>
3239 <section id="cabletv">
3240 <title>Cable TV</title>
3241 <para>
3242
3243 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3244 </para>
3245 <para>
3246 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3247 television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3248 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3249 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3250 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3251 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3252 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3253 did&mdash; Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3254 give away.
3255 </para>
3256 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas</primary></indexterm>
3257 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin</primary></indexterm>
3258 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3259 <para>
3260 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3261 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3262 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.</quote><footnote><para>
3263 <!-- f13 -->
3264 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the
3265 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3266 Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966)
3267 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3268 Commission).
3269 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3270 </para></footnote>
3271 There may have been a <quote>public interest</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3272 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3273 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, <quote>Does public
3274 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?</quote><footnote><para>
3275 <!-- f14 -->
3276 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3277 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3278 </para></footnote>
3279 As another broadcaster put it,
3280 </para>
3281 <blockquote>
3282 <para>
3283 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3284 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3285 paid for.<footnote><para>
3286 <!-- f15 -->
3287 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3288 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3289 </para></footnote>
3290 </para>
3291 </blockquote>
3292 <para>
3293 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3294 </para>
3295 <blockquote>
3296 <para>
3297 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3298 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3299 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3300 think there are harsher words which would fit it.<footnote><para>
3301 <!-- f16 -->
3302 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3303 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3304 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3305 </para></footnote>
3306 </para>
3307 </blockquote>
3308 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3309 <para>
3310 These were <quote>free-ride[rs],</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3311 Heston said, who were <quote>depriving actors of
3312 compensation.</quote><footnote><para>
3313 <!-- f17 -->
3314 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3315 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3316 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3317 </para>
3318 </footnote>
3319 </para>
3320 <para>
3321 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3322 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3323 </para>
3324 <blockquote>
3325 <para>
3326 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3327 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3328 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3329 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. &hellip; The
3330
3331 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3332 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3333 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.<footnote><para>
3334 <!-- f18 -->
3335 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M.
3336 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3337 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3338 </para></footnote>
3339 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3340 </para>
3341 </blockquote>
3342 <para>
3343 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3344 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3345 </para>
3346 <para>
3347 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3348 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they <quote>pirated.</quote>
3349 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3350 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3351 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3352 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3353 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3354 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3355 companies thus built their empire in part upon a <quote>piracy</quote> of the value
3356 created by broadcasters' content.
3357 </para>
3358 <para>
3359 These separate stories sing a common theme. If <quote>piracy</quote> means
3360 using value from someone else's creative property without permission
3361 from that creator&mdash;as it is increasingly described
3362 today<footnote><para>
3363 <!-- f19 -->
3364 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, <citetitle>The Engine
3365 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet&mdash;The Myth of Free
3366 Information</citetitle>, available at
3367 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #13</ulink>. <quote>The
3368 threat of piracy&mdash;the use of someone else's creative work without
3369 permission or compensation&mdash;has grown with the Internet.</quote>
3370 </para></footnote>
3371 &mdash; then <emphasis>every</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3372 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3373 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV. &hellip; The list is long and
3374 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3375 last. Every generation&mdash;until now.
3376 </para>
3377 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3378 </section>
3379 </chapter>
3380 <chapter label="5" id="piracy">
3381 <title>CHAPTER FIVE: <quote>Piracy</quote></title>
3382 <para>
3383 There is piracy of copyrighted material. Lots of it. This piracy comes
3384 in many forms. The most significant is commercial piracy, the
3385 unauthorized taking of other people's content within a commercial
3386 context. Despite the many justifications that are offered in its
3387 defense, this taking is wrong. No one should condone it, and the law
3388 should stop it.
3389 </para>
3390 <para>
3391 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of <quote>taking</quote>
3392 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3393 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3394 taking <quote>piracy,</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3395 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3396 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3397 has so often done in the past.
3398 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3399 </para>
3400 <section id="piracy-i">
3401 <title>Piracy I</title>
3402 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3403 <para>
3404 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3405 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3406 content, copy it, and sell it&mdash;all without the permission of a copyright
3407 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion
3408 every year to physical piracy<footnote><para>
3409 <!-- f1 -->
3410 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), <citetitle>The
3411 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003</citetitle>, July 2003, available
3412 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #14</ulink>. See
3413 also Ben Hunt, <quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3414 Times</citetitle>, 14 February 2003, 11.
3415 </para></footnote>
3416 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3417 estimates that it loses $3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3418 </para>
3419 <para>
3420 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3421 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3422 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3423 This piracy is wrong.
3424 </para>
3425 <para>
3426 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3427 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3428 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3429 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3430 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3431 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3432 of our existence, treated as right.
3433 </para>
3434 <para>
3435 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3436 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3437 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3438 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3439 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3440 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3441 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3442 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3443 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3444 </para>
3445 <para>
3446 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3447 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3448 <beginpage pagenum="77"/>
3449 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3450 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3451 similar childhood.
3452 </para>
3453 <para>
3454 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3455 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3456 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3457 of intellectual property law.<footnote><para>
3458 <!-- f2 -->
3459 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3460 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The
3461 New Press, 2003), 10&ndash;13, 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3462 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3463 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3464 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3465 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3466 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3467 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3468 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3469 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3470 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3471 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3472 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3473 TRIPS framework.
3474 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents</primary></indexterm>
3475 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
3476 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3477 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3478 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3479 is wrong.
3480 </para>
3481 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3482 <para>
3483 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3484 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3485 to American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3486 bought those American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any
3487 less money than they otherwise would have had.<footnote><para>
3488 <!-- f3 -->
3489 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3490 Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002),
3491 144&ndash;90. <quote>In some instances &hellip; the impact of piracy on the
3492 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3493 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3494 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3495 pirating were not an option.</quote> Ibid., 149.
3496 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3497 </para></footnote>
3498 </para>
3499 <para>
3500 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3501 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3502 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3503 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3504 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes &amp; Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3505 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?</quote>
3506 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes &amp;
3507 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3508 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3509 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3510 piracy of the tangible.
3511 </para>
3512 <para>
3513 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3514 property right of a very special sort, it <emphasis>is</emphasis> a
3515 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3516 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3517 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3518 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3519 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3520 give people the right to <quote>take</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3521 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3522
3523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3524 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3525 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3526 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3527 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3528 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what <quote>property</quote> means.
3529 </para>
3530 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3531 <para>
3532 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3533 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese <quote>steal</quote>
3534 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3535 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3536 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3537 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3538 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3539 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3540 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3541 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3542 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3543 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3544 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3545 <indexterm>
3546 <primary>Microsoft</primary>
3547 <secondary>Windows operating system of</secondary>
3548 </indexterm>
3549 <indexterm><primary>Windows</primary></indexterm>
3550 </para>
3551 <para>
3552 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3553 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3554 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3555 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3556 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3557 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3558 </para>
3559 <para>
3560 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3561 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3562 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3563 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3564 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3565 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3566 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3567 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3568 what&mdash;at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3569 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3570 violating the law is still wrong.
3571 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3572 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer</primary></indexterm>
3573 <indexterm><primary>Netscape</primary></indexterm>
3574 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3575 </para>
3576 <para>
3577 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3578 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3579 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3580 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3581 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3582 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3583 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3584 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3585 is flat out wrong.
3586 </para>
3587 <para>
3588 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3589 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is. Or
3590 at least, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3591 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of <quote>piracy</quote> are useful
3592 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3593 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3594 <quote>piracy</quote> in that sense of the term.
3595 </para>
3596 <para>
3597 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3598 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3599 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3600 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3601 </para>
3602 <para>
3603 For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3604 controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it
3605 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable
3606 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3607 </para>
3608 <para>
3609 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3610 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3611 sharing to survive.
3612 </para>
3613 </section>
3614 <section id="piracy-ii">
3615 <title>Piracy II</title>
3616 <para>
3617 The key to the <quote>piracy</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that <quote>rob[s]
3618 the author of [his] profit.</quote><footnote><para>
3619 <!-- f4 -->
3620 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777).
3621 </para></footnote>
3622 This means we must determine whether
3623 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3624 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3625 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3626 author of his profit.
3627 </para>
3628 <para>
3629 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3630 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3631 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3632 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well<footnote><para>
3633 <!-- f5 -->
3634 See Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3635 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle> (New York:
3636 HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3637 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3638 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3639 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3640 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3641 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 89&ndash;92, 139.
3642
3643 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
3644 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3645 put together components that had been developed independently.
3646 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn</primary></indexterm>
3647 </para>
3648 <para>
3649 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999,
3650 Napster amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After
3651 eighteen months, there were close to 80 million registered users of the
3652 system.<footnote><para>
3653 <!-- f6 -->
3654 See Carolyn Lochhead, <quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,</quote> <citetitle>San
3655 Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24 September 2002, A1; <quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,</quote>
3656 <citetitle>New Scientist</citetitle>, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Napster Names CEO,
3657 Secures New Financing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 23 May 2003, C1;
3658 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton,
3659 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet</quote> (London) <citetitle>Times</citetitle>, 26 July 2002, 18.
3660 </para></footnote>
3661 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3662 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3663 boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3664 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3665 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3666 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend&mdash;
3667 or your 20,000 best friends.
3668 </para>
3669 <para>
3670 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3671 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3672 September 2002 estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded
3673 music&mdash;28 percent of Americans older than 12.<footnote><para>
3674
3675 <!-- f7 -->
3676 See Ipsos-Insight, <citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution</citetitle>
3677 (September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3678 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have
3679 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3680 </para></footnote>
3681 A survey by the NPD group quoted in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>
3682 estimated that 43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3683 exchange content in May 2003.<footnote><para>
3684 <!-- f8 -->
3685 Amy Harmon, <quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,</quote> <citetitle>New
3686 York Times</citetitle>, 6 June 2003, A1.
3687 </para></footnote>
3688 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3689 massive quantity of content is being <quote>taken</quote> on these networks. The
3690 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3691 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3692 </para>
3693 <para>
3694 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3695 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3696 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3697 complicated than one might think. So consider&mdash;a bit more
3698 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3699 do&mdash;the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3700 of harm it entails.
3701 </para>
3702 <para>
3703 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3704 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3705 different kinds into four types.
3706 </para>
3707 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
3708 <listitem><para>
3709 <!-- A. -->
3710 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3711 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3712 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3713 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3714 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3715 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3716 users who download instead of purchasing.
3717 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3718 </para></listitem>
3719 <listitem><para>
3720 <!-- B. -->
3721 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3722 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3723 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3724 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3725 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3726 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3727 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3728 music purchased.
3729 </para></listitem>
3730 <listitem><para>
3731 <!-- C. -->
3732 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3733 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3734 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3735 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3736 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3737 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3738 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend <quote>recalling</quote> old
3739 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3740 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3741 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3742 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero&mdash;the same
3743 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to
3744 a local collector.
3745 </para></listitem>
3746 <listitem><para>
3747 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3748 <!-- D. -->
3749 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3750 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3751 wants to give away.
3752 </para></listitem>
3753 </orderedlist>
3754 <para>
3755 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3756 </para>
3757 <para>
3758 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3759 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3760 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3761 harmful.<footnote><para>
3762 <!-- f9 -->
3763 See Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle>, 148&ndash;49.
3764 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3765 </para></footnote>
3766 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3767 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3768 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3769 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3770 answer&mdash;and certainly much more difficult than the current
3771 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3772 </para>
3773 <para>
3774 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3775 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3776 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3777 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3778 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of <quote>theft</quote> that is
3779 <quote>devastating</quote> the industry.
3780 </para>
3781 <para>
3782 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3783 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3784 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3785 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3786 &amp; Young put it, <quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3787 technology, the labels fought it.</quote><footnote><para>
3788 <!-- f10 -->
3789 See Cap Gemini Ernst &amp; Young, <citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
3790 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis</citetitle> (2003), 3. This report
3791 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3792 practice of cassette taping in the 1970s, including an advertising
3793 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption <quote>Home taping
3794 is killing music.</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3795 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3796 behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3797 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3798 Assessment, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law</citetitle>,
3799 OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3800 October 1989), 145&ndash;56. </para></footnote>
3801 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3802 when record sales fell by 11.4 percent in 1981, the industry claimed
3803 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3804 regulating technology was the answer.
3805 </para>
3806 <para>
3807 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3808 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3809 turnaround. <quote>In the end,</quote> Cap Gemini concludes, <quote>the `crisis' &hellip; was
3810 not the fault of the tapers&mdash;who did not [stop after MTV came into
3811 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
3812 being]&mdash;but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
3813 innovation at the major labels.</quote><footnote><para>
3814 <!-- f11 -->
3815 U.S. Congress, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying</citetitle>, 4.
3816 </para></footnote>
3817 </para>
3818 <para>
3819 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
3820 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
3821 the industry in particular, and society in general&mdash;or at least
3822 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
3823 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
3824 VCR&mdash;the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
3825 harmful. The question is also <emphasis>how</emphasis> harmful type A
3826 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
3827 </para>
3828 <para>
3829 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
3830 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
3831 The <quote>net harm</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
3832 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
3833 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
3834 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
3835 therefore have little <emphasis>static</emphasis> reason to resist
3836 them.
3837
3838 </para>
3839 <para>
3840 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
3841 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
3842 actually suggest it might be close.
3843 </para>
3844 <para>
3845 In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9 percent,
3846 from 882 million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7
3847 percent.<footnote><para>
3848 <!-- f12 -->
3849 See Recording Industry Association of America, <citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics</citetitle>,
3850 available at
3851 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #15</ulink>. A later
3852 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
3853 Association of America, <citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy</citetitle>, 25 June 2003,
3854 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
3855 #16</ulink>: <quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
3856 have fallen by 26 percent from 1.16 billion units in to 860 million
3857 units in 2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
3858 of sales, revenues are down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in to $12.6
3859 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
3860 industry worldwide has gone from a $39 billion industry in 2000 down
3861 to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
3862 shipments).</quote>
3863 </para></footnote>
3864 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
3865 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
3866 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
3867 than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That no
3868 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
3869 account for at least some of the loss. <quote>From 1999 to 2001, the average
3870 price of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19.</quote><footnote>
3871 <!-- f13 -->
3872 <para>
3873 Jane Black, <quote>Big Music's Broken Record,</quote> BusinessWeek online, 13
3874 February 2003, available at
3875 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #17</ulink>.
3876 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane</primary></indexterm>
3877 </para>
3878 </footnote>
3879 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
3880 the decline. As Jane Black of <citetitle>BusinessWeek</citetitle> notes, <quote>The
3881 soundtrack to the film <citetitle>High Fidelity</citetitle> has a list price of
3882 $18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
3883 $19.99.</quote><footnote><para>
3884 <!-- f14 -->
3885 Ibid.
3886 </para></footnote>
3887 </para>
3888 <para>
3889
3890 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
3891 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
3892 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
3893 that the RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
3894 estimates that 2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
3895 although 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
3896 free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 percent.
3897 </para>
3898 <para>
3899 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
3900 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
3901 The recording industry constantly asks, <quote>What's the difference between
3902 downloading a song and stealing a CD?</quote>&mdash;but their own numbers
3903 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
3904 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
3905 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
3906 downloads. If every download were a lost sale&mdash;if every use of
3907 Kazaa <quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit</quote>&mdash;then the industry
3908 would have suffered a 100 percent drop in sales last year, not a 7
3909 percent drop. If 2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
3910 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, then there is
3911 a huge difference between <quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.</quote>
3912 </para>
3913 <para>
3914 These are the harms&mdash;alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
3915 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
3916 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
3917 these costs?
3918 </para>
3919 <para>
3920 One benefit is type C sharing&mdash;making available content that
3921 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
3922 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
3923 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
3924 available.<footnote><para>
3925 <!-- f15 -->
3926 By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels
3927 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
3928 Law&mdash;Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
3929 Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April
3930 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
3931 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #18</ulink>.
3932 </para></footnote>
3933 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
3934 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
3935 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
3936 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
3937 sense <emphasis>to the company</emphasis> to make it available.
3938 </para>
3939 <para>
3940 In real space&mdash;long before the Internet&mdash;the market had a simple
3941 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
3942 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
3943 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
3944 today.<footnote><para>
3945 <!-- f16 -->
3946 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores in
3947 existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the United States,
3948 an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter Press, <citetitle>The Quiet
3949 Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book Market</citetitle> (2002), available at
3950 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #19</ulink>. Used records accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See
3951 National
3952 Association of Recording Merchandisers, <quote>2002 Annual Survey
3953 Results,</quote>
3954 available at
3955 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #20</ulink>.
3956 </para></footnote>
3957 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
3958 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
3959 content, <emphasis>even if the content is still under
3960 copyright</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
3961 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
3962 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
3963 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
3964 the content they sell.
3965 </para>
3966 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard</primary></indexterm>
3967 <para>
3968 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
3969 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
3970 the content available isn't making money from making the content
3971 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
3972 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
3973 when someone shares my 1949 recording of Bernstein's <quote>Two Love Songs,</quote>
3974 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
3975 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
3976 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
3977 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
3978 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
3979 </para>
3980 <para>
3981 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
3982 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
3983 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
3984 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
3985 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
3986 shut as well?
3987 </para>
3988 <para>
3989 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
3990 type D sharing to occur&mdash;the sharing of content that copyright owners
3991 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
3992 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
3993 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
3994 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
3995
3996 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
3997 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
3998 would be a great advertisement for the <quote>real</quote> book. People would read
3999 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4000 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4001 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4002 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4003 great book!)
4004 </para>
4005 <para>
4006 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4007 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4008 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4009 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4010 </para>
4011 <para>
4012 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4013 understandably says, <quote>This is how much we've lost,</quote> we must also ask,
4014 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4015 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4016 unavailable?</quote>
4017 </para>
4018 <para>
4019 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4020 chapter, much of the <quote>piracy</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4021 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4022 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="pirates"/>, much of
4023 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4024 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4025 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4026 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4027 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4028 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4029 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4030 found only with time.
4031 </para>
4032 <para>
4033 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4034 just what you call type A sharing?</quote>
4035 </para>
4036 <para>
4037 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The
4038 effect
4039 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4040 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4041 Napster
4042 case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4043 developed
4044 a technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of identified
4045 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4046 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4
4047 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4048 <quote>down to zero.</quote><footnote><para>
4049 <!-- f17 -->
4050 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34-
4051 35 (N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183
4052 MHP, available at
4053
4054 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #21</ulink>. For an
4055 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4056 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster</citetitle> (New
4057 York: Crown Business, 2003), 269&ndash;82.
4058 </para></footnote>
4059 </para>
4060 <para>
4061 If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4062 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4063 assure that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance
4064 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of
4065 VCRs or 100 percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns
4066 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4067 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4068 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4069 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4070 </para>
4071 <para>
4072 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4073 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4074 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4075 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4076 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4077 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4078 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4079 </para>
4080 <indexterm>
4081 <primary>artists</primary>
4082 <secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary>
4083 </indexterm>
4084 <para>
4085 So, as we've seen, when <quote>mechanical reproduction</quote> threatened the
4086 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4087 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4088 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4089 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4090 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4091 complained to Congress that their <quote>creative property</quote> was not being
4092 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4093 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4094 benefit was enough.
4095 </para>
4096 <para>
4097 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4098 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4099 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4100 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4101 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4102 price.
4103 </para>
4104 <para>
4105
4106 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4107 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4108 pianos, served two important goals&mdash;indeed, the two central goals
4109 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4110 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4111 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4112 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4113 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4114 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4115 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4116 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4117 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4118 Congress chose a path that would assure
4119 <emphasis>compensation</emphasis> without giving the past
4120 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4121 </para>
4122 <indexterm><primary>Betamax</primary></indexterm>
4123 <para>
4124 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4125 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4126 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4127 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4128 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4129 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4130 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4131 <quote>record</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4132 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4133 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4134 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4135 </para>
4136 <para>
4137 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4138 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4139 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4140 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4141 machine to copy only if there were a special <quote>copy me</quote> signal on the
4142 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4143 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4144 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4145 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4146 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4147 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4148 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4149 for the architecture it chose.
4150 </para>
4151 <para>
4152 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4153 champion. Valenti called VCRs <quote>tapeworms.</quote> He warned, <quote>When there are
4154 20, 30, 40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4155 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4156 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4157 copyright.</quote><footnote><para>
4158 <!-- f18 -->
4159 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4160 S. 1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st
4161 and 2nd sess., 459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4162 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4163 </para></footnote>
4164 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4165 creative judgment,</quote> he told Congress, <quote>to understand the devastation
4166 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4167 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4168 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4169 and plain common sense.</quote><footnote><para>
4170 <!-- f19 -->
4171 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475.
4172 </para></footnote>
4173 Indeed, as surveys would later show,
4174 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more<footnote><para>
4175 <!-- f20 -->
4176 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 480 F. Supp. 429,
4177 (C.D. Cal., 1979).
4178 </para></footnote>
4179 &mdash; a use the Court would later hold was not <quote>fair.</quote> By
4180 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4181 copyright infringementwithout creating a mechanism to compensate
4182 copyrightowners,</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would <quote>take from the
4183 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4184 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4185 profit from its reproduction.</quote><footnote><para>
4186 <!-- f21 -->
4187 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony
4188 of Jack Valenti).
4189 </para></footnote>
4190 </para>
4191 <para>
4192 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4193 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4194 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction&mdash;leading Judge Alex
4195 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the <quote>Hollywood
4196 Circuit</quote>&mdash;held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4197 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4198 rule, this totally familiar technology&mdash;which Jack Valenti had
4199 called <quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry</quote> (worse
4200 yet, it was a <emphasis>Japanese</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4201 American film industry)&mdash;was an illegal
4202 technology.<footnote><para>
4203 <!-- f22 -->
4204 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th Cir.
4205 1981).
4206 </para></footnote>
4207 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex</primary></indexterm>
4208 </para>
4209 <para>
4210 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4211
4212 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4213 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4214 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4215 Court wrote,
4216 </para>
4217 <blockquote>
4218 <para>
4219 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4220 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4221 market
4222 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4223 authority
4224 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4225 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4226 implicated
4227 by such new technology.<footnote><para>
4228 <!-- f23 -->
4229 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417, 431 (1984).
4230 </para></footnote>
4231 </para>
4232 </blockquote>
4233 <para>
4234 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4235 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4236 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4237 enough, this <quote>taking</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4238 together, a pattern is clear:
4239 </para>
4240
4241 <informaltable id="t1">
4242 <tgroup cols="4" align="char">
4243 <thead>
4244 <row>
4245 <entry>CASE</entry>
4246 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS <quote>PIRATED</quote></entry>
4247 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS</entry>
4248 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS</entry>
4249 </row>
4250 </thead>
4251 <tbody>
4252 <row>
4253 <entry>Recordings</entry>
4254 <entry>Composers</entry>
4255 <entry>No protection</entry>
4256 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4257 </row>
4258 <row>
4259 <entry>Radio</entry>
4260 <entry>Recording artists</entry>
4261 <entry>N/A</entry>
4262 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4263 </row>
4264 <row>
4265 <entry>Cable TV</entry>
4266 <entry>Broadcasters</entry>
4267 <entry>No protection</entry>
4268 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4269 </row>
4270 <row>
4271 <entry>VCR</entry>
4272 <entry>Film creators</entry>
4273 <entry>No protection</entry>
4274 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4275 </row>
4276 </tbody>
4277 </tgroup>
4278 </informaltable>
4279
4280 <para>
4281 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4282 way content was distributed.<footnote><para>
4283 <!-- f24 -->
4284 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4285 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4286 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4287 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4288 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4289 1992 (Title 17 of the <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat.
4290 4237, codified at 17 U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4291 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4292 Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 71. See also Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,</quote>
4293 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 293&ndash;96.
4294 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
4295 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
4296 </para></footnote>
4297 In each case, throughout our history,
4298 that change meant that someone got a <quote>free ride</quote> on someone else's
4299 work.
4300 </para>
4301 <para>
4302 In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4303 Congress eliminate all free riding. In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of
4304 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4305 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4306 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of <quote>piracy.</quote>
4307 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4308 the behavior of the <quote>pirates.</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4309 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4310 interests at stake.
4311 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4312 </para>
4313 <para>
4314 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4315 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4316 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4317 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4318 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4319 regulated?
4320 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4321 to $15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4322 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4323 permission to record a song?
4324 </para>
4325 <para>
4326 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4327 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4328 copyright <quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4329 over all possible uses of his work.</quote><footnote><para>
4330 <!-- f25 -->
4331 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
4332 (1984).
4333 </para></footnote>
4334 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4335 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4336 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4337 balancing has historically been done <emphasis>after</emphasis> a
4338 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4339 facilitate the distribution of content.
4340 </para>
4341 <para>
4342 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4343 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4344 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4345 should not become a tool for <quote>stealing</quote> from artists. But neither
4346 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4347 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4348 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4349 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4350 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4351 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4352 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4353 public interest that innovation continue.
4354 </para>
4355 <para>
4356
4357 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4358 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4359 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4360 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4361 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4362 efficient. Yet these <quote>potential public benefits,</quote> as John Schwartz
4363 writes in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, <quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4364 fight.</quote><footnote><para>
4365 <!-- f26 -->
4366 John Schwartz, <quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4367 Echoes Past Efforts,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 September 2003, C3.
4368 </para></footnote>
4369 Yet when anyone begins to talk about <quote>balance,</quote> the copyright warriors
4370 raise a different argument. <quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4371 incentives,</quote> they say, <quote>misses a fundamental point. Our content,</quote> the
4372 warriors insist, <quote>is our <emphasis>property</emphasis>. Why should we
4373 wait for Congress to `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to
4374 wait before calling the police when your car has been stolen? And why
4375 should Congress deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do
4376 we ask whether the car thief had a good use for the car before we
4377 arrest him?</quote>
4378 </para>
4379 <para>
4380 <quote>It is <emphasis>our property</emphasis>,</quote> the warriors
4381 insist. <quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4382 is protected.</quote>
4383 </para>
4384 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4385 </section>
4386 </chapter>
4387 </part>
4388 <part id="c-property">
4389 <title><quote>PROPERTY</quote></title>
4390 <partintro>
4391 <para>
4392
4393 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4394 The copyright warriors are right: A copyright is a kind of
4395 property. It can be owned and sold, and the law protects against its
4396 theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to hold out for any price he
4397 wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand that partially determine
4398 the price she can get.
4399 </para>
4400 <para>
4401 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a <quote>property</quote> right is a
4402 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4403 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4404 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4405 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4406 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4407 when I take the good <emphasis>idea</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4408 table in the backyard&mdash;by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4409 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4410 then?
4411 </para>
4412 <para>
4413 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4414 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4415 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4416 in the ordinary case&mdash;indeed, in practically every case except for a
4417 narrow
4418 range of exceptions&mdash;ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4419 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress&mdash;though I
4420 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4421 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4422 when I copy the way someone else dresses), <quote>He who receives an idea
4423 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4424 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.</quote><footnote><para>
4425 <!-- f1 -->
4426 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in
4427 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson</citetitle>, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4428 Ellery Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333&ndash;34.
4429 </para></footnote>
4430 </para>
4431 <para>
4432 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4433 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4434 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4435 expression
4436 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4437 property.
4438 </para>
4439 <para>
4440 But how, and to what extent, and in what form&mdash;the details,
4441 in other words&mdash;matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4442 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4443 <quote>property</quote> in its proper context.<footnote><para>
4444 <!-- f2 -->
4445 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4446 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4447 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4448 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4449 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4450 Adam Mossoff, <quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,</quote>
4451 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review</citetitle> 45 (2003): 373, 429 n. 241.
4452 </para></footnote>
4453 </para>
4454 <para>
4455 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4456 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4457 <quote>copyright material is property</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4458 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4459 these stories, the significance of this true
4460 statement&mdash;<quote>copyright material is property</quote>&mdash; will be a bit
4461 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4462 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4463 </para>
4464 </partintro>
4465
4466 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4467 <chapter label="6" id="founders">
4468 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders</title>
4469 <indexterm><primary>Henry V</primary></indexterm>
4470 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4471 <para>
4472 William Shakespeare wrote <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> in 1595. The play
4473 was first published in 1597. It was the eleventh major play that
4474 Shakespeare had written. He would continue to write plays through
4475 1613, and the plays that he wrote have continued to define
4476 Anglo-American culture ever since. So deeply have the works of a
4477 sixteenth-century writer seeped into our culture that we often don't
4478 even recognize their source. I once overheard someone commenting on
4479 Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of Henry V: <quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare
4480 is so full of clichés.</quote>
4481 </para>
4482 <para>
4483 In 1774, almost 180 years after <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> was written, the
4484 <quote>copy-right</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4485 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.<footnote><para>
4486 <!-- f1 -->
4487 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4488 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4489 handsome <quote>definitive editions</quote> of classic works. In addition to <citetitle>Romeo and
4490 Juliet</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4491 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4492 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, <quote>Jacob Tonson,
4493 Bookseller,</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar</citetitle> 61:3 (1992): 424&ndash;31.
4494 </para></footnote>
4495 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4496 the Conger<footnote><para>
4497 <!-- f2 -->
4498 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle> (Nashville:
4499 Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 151&ndash;52.
4500 </para></footnote>
4501 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4502 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the <quote>copy</quote> of
4503 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4504 that no
4505 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4506 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4507 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4508 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4509 </para>
4510 <para>
4511 Now, there's something puzzling about the year 1774 to anyone who
4512 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4513 history of copyright is 1710, the year that the British Parliament
4514 adopted the first <quote>copyright</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4515 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4516 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4517 works already published by 1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4518 additional years.<footnote><para>
4519 <!-- f3 -->
4520 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4521 <quote>copyright law.</quote> See Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 40.
4522 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4523 </para></footnote> Under this law, <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> should have been
4524 free in 1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4525 Tonson's control in 1774?
4526 </para>
4527 <para>
4528 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a <quote>copyright</quote>
4529 was&mdash;indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4530 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4531 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of 1662, had
4532 expired in 1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4533 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4534 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4535 that the publishers, or <quote>Stationers,</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4536 books.
4537 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (1662)</primary></indexterm>
4538 </para>
4539 <para>
4540 There was no <emphasis>positive</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4541 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4542 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4543 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4544 from legislatures <quote>positive law.</quote> We call the words from judges
4545 <quote>common law.</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4546 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4547 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4548 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4549 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4550 </para>
4551 <para>
4552 This question was important to the publishers, or <quote>booksellers,</quote> as
4553 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4554 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4555 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4556
4557 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4558 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4559 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4560 ultimately
4561 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4562 </para>
4563 <para>
4564 The Statute of Anne granted the author or <quote>proprietor</quote> of a book an
4565 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4566 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4567 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4568 copyright <quote>expired,</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4569 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4570 believed.
4571 </para>
4572 <para>
4573 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4574 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4575 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4576 <emphasis>at all?</emphasis>
4577 </para>
4578 <para>
4579 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4580 strong claim. Take <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> as an example: That play
4581 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4582 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4583 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4584 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4585 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4586 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4587 reason is there to allow someone else to <quote>steal</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4588 </para>
4589 <para>
4590 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4591 about the notion of <quote>copyright</quote> that existed at the time of the
4592 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4593 <quote>booksellers.</quote>
4594 </para>
4595 <para>
4596 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4597 to apply the concept of <quote>copyright</quote> ever more broadly. But in 1710, it
4598 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4599 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4600 others from reprinting a book. In 1710, the <quote>copy-right</quote> was a right
4601 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4602 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4603 generally how
4604 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4605 a work could be <emphasis>used</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4606 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4607 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4608 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4609 </para>
4610 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4611 <para>
4612 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4613 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4614 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4615 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4616 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4617 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4618 allowed to make his films. The <quote>copy-right</quote> was only an exclusive
4619 right to print&mdash;no less, of course, but also no more.
4620 </para>
4621 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England</primary></indexterm>
4622 <para>
4623 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4624 They had had a long and ugly experience with <quote>exclusive rights,</quote>
4625 especially <quote>exclusive rights</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4626 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4627 monopolies&mdash;especially monopolies for works that already
4628 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4629 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4630 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In 1656, it passed the
4631 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4632 inventions. And by 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4633 monopoly in publishing.
4634 </para>
4635 <para>
4636 Thus the <quote>copy-right,</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4637 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4638 claim that <quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,</quote> try
4639 sounding convincing when uttering, <quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4640 have it forever.</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4641 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4642 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4643 </para>
4644 <para>
4645 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4646 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4647 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4648 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4649 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4650
4651 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4652 kind&mdash;tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4653 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4654 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as <quote>old patentees
4655 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling</quote>; they were <quote>men who do
4656 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4657 indetted.</quote><footnote><para>
4658
4659 <!-- f4 -->
4660 Philip Wittenberg, <citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4661 Property</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31.
4662 </para></footnote>
4663 </para>
4664 <para>
4665 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4666 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4667 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4668 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4669 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4670 with that idea.
4671 </para>
4672 <para>
4673 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4674 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4675 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4676 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4677 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4678 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4679 compromise
4680 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4681 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4682 construction and spread of culture.
4683 </para>
4684 <para>
4685 When 1731 (1710 + 21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4686 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4687 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4688 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4689 to control publication. But in 1735 and 1737, they tried to persuade
4690 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4691 they said; they needed more time.
4692 </para>
4693 <para>
4694 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4695 words that echo today,
4696 </para>
4697 <blockquote>
4698 <para>
4699 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4700 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4701 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4702 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4703 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4704 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4705 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4706 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4707 Booksellers.<footnote><para>
4708 <!-- f5 -->
4709 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4710 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4711 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4712 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4713 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4714 mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4715 al., 8, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618).
4716 </para></footnote>
4717 </para>
4718 </blockquote>
4719 <para>
4720 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4721 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4722 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
4723 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
4724 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
4725 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
4726 creative <quote>property</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
4727 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
4728 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
4729 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
4730 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
4731 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
4732 way to protect authors.
4733 </para>
4734 <para>
4735 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
4736 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
4737 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
4738 <quote>The publishers &hellip; had as much concern for authors as a cattle
4739 rancher has for cattle.</quote><footnote><para>
4740 <!-- f6 -->
4741 Lyman Ray Patterson, <quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
4742 Law Review</citetitle> 40 (1987): 28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
4743 Vaidhyanathan, 37&ndash;48.
4744 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4745 </para></footnote>
4746 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
4747 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
4748 </para>
4749 <para>
4750 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
4751 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
4752 Donaldson.<footnote><para>
4753 <!-- f7 -->
4754 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, <citetitle>Authorship and Copyright</citetitle>
4755 (London: Routledge, 1992), 62&ndash;69.
4756 </para></footnote>
4757 </para>
4758 <para>
4759 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
4760 career in Edinburgh in 1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
4761 reprints <quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,</quote> at least
4762 under the Statute of Anne.<footnote><para>
4763 <!-- f8 -->
4764 Mark Rose, <citetitle>Authors and Owners</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
4765 1993), 92.
4766 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
4767 </para></footnote>
4768 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
4769 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
4770 and became <quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.</quote> <quote>[A]mong
4771 them,</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was <quote>the young James Boswell
4772 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
4773 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.</quote><footnote><para>
4774 <!-- f9 -->
4775 Ibid., 93.
4776 </para></footnote>
4777 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James</primary></indexterm>
4778 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew</primary></indexterm>
4779 </para>
4780 <para>
4781 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
4782 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
4783 inexpensive editions <quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
4784 of the supposed common law right of Literary
4785 Property.</quote><footnote><para>
4786 <!-- f10 -->
4787 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle>, 167 (quoting
4788 Borwell).
4789 </para></footnote>
4790 His books undercut the Conger prices by 30 to 50 percent, and he
4791 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
4792 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
4793 </para>
4794 <para>
4795 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block <quote>piracy</quote> like
4796 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the <quote>pirates,</quote>
4797 the most important early victory being <citetitle>Millar</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Taylor</citetitle>.
4798 </para>
4799 <para>
4800 Millar was a bookseller who in 1729 had purchased the rights to James
4801 Thomson's poem <quote>The Seasons.</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
4802 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
4803 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
4804 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
4805 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.<footnote><para>
4806 <!-- f11 -->
4807 Howard B. Abrams, <quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
4808 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review</citetitle> 29
4809 (1983): 1152.
4810 </para></footnote>
4811 </para>
4812 <indexterm id="idxmansfield2" class='startofrange'>
4813 <primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary>
4814 </indexterm>
4815 <para>
4816 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
4817 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
4818 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
4819 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
4820 law would protect the author against subsequent <quote>pirates.</quote>
4821 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
4822 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
4823 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
4824 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
4825 </para>
4826 <para>
4827 Considered as a matter of abstract justice&mdash;reasoning as if
4828 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
4829 principles&mdash;Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
4830 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
4831 with in 1710: How best to limit
4832 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
4833 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
4834 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in 1710, but
4835 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
4836 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
4837 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
4838 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
4839 </para>
4840 <indexterm startref="idxmansfield2" class='endofrange'/>
4841 <para>
4842 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
4843 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
4844 </para>
4845 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
4846 <para>
4847 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
4848 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
4849 Thomas Beckett.<footnote><para>
4850 <!-- f12 -->
4851 Ibid., 1156.
4852 </para></footnote>
4853 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
4854 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in <citetitle>Millar</citetitle>,
4855 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
4856 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
4857 Court. In February of 1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
4858 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
4859 </para>
4860 <para>
4861 As few legal cases ever do, <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle> drew an
4862 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
4863 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
4864 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
4865 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
4866 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
4867 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
4868 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
4869 </para>
4870 <para>
4871 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
4872 presented to the House and voted upon first by the <quote>law lords,</quote>
4873 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
4874 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
4875 House of Lords generally voted.
4876 </para>
4877 <para>
4878 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
4879 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
4880 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
4881 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
4882 (22 to 11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
4883 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
4884 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
4885 passed into the public domain.
4886 </para>
4887 <para>
4888 <quote>The public domain.</quote> Before the case of <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle>
4889 v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
4890 England. Before 1774, there was a strong argument that common law
4891 copyrights were perpetual. After 1774, the public domain was
4892 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
4893 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
4894 history&mdash;including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
4895 and Bunyan&mdash;were free of legal restraint.
4896 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis</primary></indexterm>
4897 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John</primary></indexterm>
4898 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel</primary></indexterm>
4899 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
4900 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4901 </para>
4902 <para>
4903 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
4904 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
4905 where most of the <quote>pirate publishers</quote> did their work, people
4906 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the <citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser</citetitle>
4907 reported, <quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
4908 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
4909 decision of which so many individuals were interested.</quote> <quote>Great
4910 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
4911 and illuminations.</quote><footnote><para>
4912 <!-- f13 -->
4913 Rose, 97.
4914 </para></footnote>
4915 </para>
4916 <para>
4917 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
4918 equally strong in the opposite direction. The <citetitle>Morning Chronicle</citetitle>
4919 reported:
4920 </para>
4921 <blockquote>
4922 <para>
4923 By the above decision &hellip; near 200,000 pounds worth of what was
4924 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
4925 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
4926 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
4927 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
4928 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
4929 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
4930 successors.<footnote><para>
4931 <!-- f14 -->
4932 Ibid.
4933 </para></footnote>
4934 </para>
4935 </blockquote>
4936 <para>
4937 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
4938 <quote>Ruined</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
4939 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
4940 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
4941 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
4942 <emphasis>free</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
4943 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
4944 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
4945 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
4946 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
4947 book from someone. But <emphasis>free</emphasis> in the sense that the
4948 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
4949 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
4950 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
4951 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
4952 develop&mdash; chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
4953 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a <emphasis>competitive
4954 context</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
4955 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
4956 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
4957 </para>
4958 <para>
4959 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
4960 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
4961 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
4962 protected.
4963 </para>
4964 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
4965 </chapter>
4966 <chapter label="7" id="recorders">
4967 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders</title>
4968 <para>
4969 Jon Else is a filmmaker. He is best known for his documentaries and
4970 has been very successful in spreading his art. He is also a teacher, and
4971 as a teacher myself, I envy the loyalty and admiration that his students
4972 feel for him. (I met, by accident, two of his students at a dinner party.
4973 He was their god.)
4974 </para>
4975 <para>
4976 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
4977 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
4978 today.
4979 </para>
4980 <para>
4981 In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
4982 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
4983 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
4984 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
4985 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
4986 stage.
4987 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
4988 </para>
4989 <para>
4990 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
4991 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
4992 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
4993 and the opera company played Wagner, was <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. As Else judged
4994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
4995 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
4996 about the scene.
4997 </para>
4998 <para>
4999 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5000 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>.
5001 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5002 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5003 unless <quote>fair use</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5004 </para>
5005 <para>
5006 Else called <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5007 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5008 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5009 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5010 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5011 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5012 </para>
5013 <para>
5014 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5015 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5016 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5017 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5018 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5019 <indexterm><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5020 </para>
5021 <para>
5022 Then, as Else told me, <quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5023 &hellip; that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation&mdash;or at
5024 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.</quote>
5025 And second, Fox <quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5026 to use this four-point-five seconds of &hellip; entirely unsolicited
5027 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.</quote>
5028 </para>
5029 <para>
5030 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5031 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5032 explained to her, <quote>There must be some mistake here. &hellip; We're
5033 asking for your educational rate on this.</quote> That was the educational
5034 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5035 confirm what he had been told.
5036 </para>
5037 <para>
5038 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,</quote> he told me. <quote>Yes, you
5039 have your facts straight,</quote> she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the
5040 clip of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5041 about
5042
5043 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5044 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, <quote>And
5045 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.</quote> As an assistant
5046 to Herrera told Else later on, <quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5047 the money.</quote>
5048 </para>
5049 <para>
5050 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5051 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5052 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5053 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5054 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5055 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5056 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5057 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The</primary></indexterm>
5058 </para>
5059 <para>
5060 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5061 copyright to <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5062 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5063 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5064 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5065 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5066 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5067 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5068 says the owner gets to control.
5069 </para>
5070 <para>
5071 For example, <quote>public performance</quote> is a use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> that the
5072 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5073 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see <quote>My
5074 Favorite <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>,</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5075 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5076 whatever she wants&mdash;$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set
5077 by the law.
5078 </para>
5079 <para>
5080 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5081 thought is <quote>fair use.</quote><footnote><para>
5082 <!-- f1 -->
5083 For an excellent argument that such use is <quote>fair use,</quote> but that
5084 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is <quote>fair use,</quote> see Richard
5085 A. Posner with William F. Patry, <quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5086 Wake of <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5087 Law School, 5 August 2003.
5088 </para></footnote>
5089 Else's use of just 4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>
5090 episode is clearly a fair use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>&mdash;and fair use does
5091 not require the permission of anyone.
5092 </para>
5093 <para>
5094 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5095 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon <quote>fair use.</quote> Here's his reply:
5096 </para>
5097 <blockquote>
5098 <para>
5099 The <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5100 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5101 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5102 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was <quote>clearly
5103 fair use</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5104 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5105 </para>
5106 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
5107 <listitem><para>
5108 <!-- 1. -->
5109 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5110 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5111 <quote>visual cue sheet</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5112 shot in the film. They take a dim view of <quote>fair use,</quote> and a claim of
5113 <quote>fair use</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5114 </para></listitem>
5115 <listitem>
5116 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5117 <para>
5118 <!-- 2. -->
5119 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5120 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5121 tracking down and stopping unlicensed <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> usage, just as George
5122 Lucas had a very high profile litigating <citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5123 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5124 license to four seconds of <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5125 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5126 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5127 principle.
5128 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George</primary></indexterm>
5129 </para></listitem>
5130 <listitem><para>
5131 <!-- 3. -->
5132 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5133 School &hellip; who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5134 that Fox would <quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5135 life,</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5136 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5137 pockets, me or them.
5138 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5139 </para></listitem>
5140 <listitem><para>
5141 <!-- 4. -->
5142 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5143 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5144 money.
5145 </para></listitem>
5146 </orderedlist>
5147 </blockquote>
5148 <para>
5149 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5150 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5151 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5152 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5153 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5154 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5155 </para>
5156 <para>
5157 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5158 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5159 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5160 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5161 not.
5162 </para>
5163 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5164 </chapter>
5165 <chapter label="8" id="transformers">
5166 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers</title>
5167 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul</primary></indexterm>
5168 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'>
5169 <primary>Alben, Alex</primary>
5170 </indexterm>
5171 <para>
5172 In 1993, Alex Alben was a lawyer working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave
5173 was an innovative company founded by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to
5174 develop digital entertainment. Long before the Internet became
5175 popular, Starwave began investing in new technology for delivering
5176 entertainment in anticipation of the power of networks.
5177 </para>
5178 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'>
5179 <primary>artists</primary>
5180 <secondary>retrospective compilations on</secondary>
5181 </indexterm>
5182 <para>
5183 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5184 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology&mdash;not to distribute
5185 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5186 difficult. In 1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5187 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5188 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5189 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5190 important to his career.
5191 </para>
5192 <para>
5193 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5194 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5195 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5196 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5197 </para>
5198 <para>
5199 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5200 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5201 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5202 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5203 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5204 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5205 </para>
5206 <para>
5207 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. <quote>Our
5208 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5209 Eastwood's films,</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5210 arose. <quote>No one had ever really done this before,</quote> Alben explained. <quote>No
5211 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5212 actor's career.</quote>
5213 </para>
5214 <para>
5215 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5216 Slade asked, <quote>Well, what will it take?</quote>
5217 </para>
5218 <para>
5219 Alben replied, <quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5220 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5221 else that we want to use in these film clips.</quote> Slade said, <quote>Great! Go
5222 for it.</quote><footnote>
5223 <para>
5224 <!-- f1 -->
5225 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5226 publicity&mdash;rights an artist has to control the commercial
5227 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden <quote>Rip, Mix,
5228 Burn</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5229 <indexterm>
5230 <primary>artists</primary>
5231 <secondary>publicity rights on images of</secondary>
5232 </indexterm>
5233 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5234 </para></footnote>
5235 </para>
5236 <para>
5237 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5238 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5239 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5240 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5241 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5242 </para>
5243 <para>
5244 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5245 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5246 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5247 </para>
5248 <blockquote>
5249 <para>
5250 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5251 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include&mdash;of
5252 course we were going to use the <quote>Make my day</quote> clip from <citetitle>Dirty
5253 Harry</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5254 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5255 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5256 </para>
5257 <para>
5258 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5259 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5260 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5261 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5262 rate at the time was about $600. So we had to identify the
5263 people&mdash;some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5264 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5265 glass&mdash;is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5266 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5267 started calling people.
5268 </para>
5269 </blockquote>
5270 <para>
5271 Some actors were glad to help&mdash;Donald Sutherland, for example,
5272 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5273 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5274 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5275 know, $1,200?</quote> And they would say, <quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5276 to get $1,200.</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5277 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5278 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5279 career.
5280 </para>
5281 <para>
5282 It was one <emphasis>year</emphasis> later&mdash;<quote>and even then we
5283 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.</quote>
5284 </para>
5285 <para>
5286 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5287 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5288 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5289 </para>
5290 <blockquote>
5291 <para>
5292 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5293 hands and said, <quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5294 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5295 actors.</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5296 constituent parts and said, <quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5297 directors, &hellip; this many musicians,</quote> and we just went at it very
5298 systematically and cleared the rights.
5299 </para>
5300 </blockquote>
5301 <para>
5302
5303 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5304 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5305 loved it, and it sold very well.
5306 </para>
5307 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter</primary></indexterm>
5308 <para>
5309 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5310 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5311 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, <quote>There is
5312 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5313 at all.</quote><footnote><para>
5314 <!-- f2 -->
5315 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, <citetitle>Seven
5316 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition</citetitle>, available at
5317 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #22</ulink>.
5318 </para></footnote>
5319 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5320 has to be made?
5321 </para>
5322 <para>
5323 For, as he acknowledged, <quote>very few &hellip; have the time and resources,
5324 and the will to do this,</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5325 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5326 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5327 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5328 </para>
5329 <blockquote>
5330 <para>
5331 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5332 he or she gets paid very well. &hellip; And then when 30 seconds of
5333 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5334 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person &hellip; should be
5335 compensated for that.
5336 </para>
5337 </blockquote>
5338 <para>
5339 Or at least, is this <emphasis>how</emphasis> the artist should be
5340 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5341 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5342 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5343 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5344 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5345 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5346 made to be more clean?
5347 </para>
5348 <blockquote>
5349 <para>
5350 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5351 mechanism&mdash;where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5352 subject to estranged former spouses&mdash;you'd see a lot more of this
5353 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5354 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5355 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5356 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5357 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5358 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5359 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5360 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5361 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5362 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5363 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, <quote>Oh, I
5364 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5365 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5366 money,</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5367 </para>
5368 </blockquote>
5369 <para>
5370 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5371 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5372 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5373 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5374 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5375 </para>
5376 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'/>
5377 <para>
5378 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5379 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5380 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5381 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5382 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5383 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5384 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5385 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5386 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5387 <quote>Does this still make sense?</quote>
5388 </para>
5389 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'/>
5390 <para>
5391 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5392 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5393 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5394 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5395
5396 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5397 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5398 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5399 </para>
5400 <para>
5401 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5402 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode.
5403 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5404 judges loved every minute of it.
5405 </para>
5406 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David</primary></indexterm>
5407 <para>
5408 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5409 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5410 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5411 room of over 250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5412 began his talk with a question: <quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5413 were just violated in this room?</quote>
5414 </para>
5415 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David</primary></indexterm>
5416 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5417 <para>
5418 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5419 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5420 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5421 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5422 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle
5423 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5424 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5425 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5426 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5427 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5428 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5429 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5430 couldn't easily do them legally.
5431 </para>
5432 <para>
5433 We live in a <quote>cut and paste</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5434 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5435 and paste architecture of the Internet created&mdash;in a second you can
5436 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5437 planted in your presentation.
5438 </para>
5439 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos</primary></indexterm>
5440 <para>
5441 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5442 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5443 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5444 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5445 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5446 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5447 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5448 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5449 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5450 </para>
5451 <para>
5452 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5453 wanted to be <quote>legal,</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5454 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5455 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5456 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5457 </para>
5458 <para>
5459 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5460 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5461 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5462 necessarily requiring that the <quote>free</quote> use be free as in <quote>free beer.</quote>
5463 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5464 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5465 along: a rule, for example, that says <quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5466 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5467 will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5468 copyright owner.</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5469 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5470 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5471 registers the work.
5472 </para>
5473 <para>
5474 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5475 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5476 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5477 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5478 </para>
5479 <para>
5480 In February 2003, DreamWorks studios announced an agreement with Mike
5481 Myers, the comic genius of <citetitle>Saturday Night Live</citetitle> and
5482 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5483 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5484 would work together to form a <quote>unique filmmaking pact.</quote> Under the
5485 agreement, DreamWorks <quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5486 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and&mdash;with the use
5487 of stateof-the-art digital technology&mdash;insert Myers and other
5488 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5489 entertainment.</quote>
5490 </para>
5491 <para>
5492 The announcement called this <quote>film sampling.</quote> As Myers explained,
5493 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5494 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5495 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5496 to take that same concept and apply it to film.</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5497 quoted as saying, <quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5498 new audiences, it is Mike.</quote>
5499 </para>
5500 <para>
5501 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5502 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5503 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5504 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5505 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5506 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5507 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5508 privilege reserved for the funny and famous&mdash;and presumably rich.
5509 </para>
5510 <para>
5511 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5512 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of <quote>fair use.</quote>
5513 Much of <quote>sampling</quote> should be considered <quote>fair use.</quote> But few would
5514 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5515 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5516 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5517 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5518 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5519 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5520 process is a process of paying lawyers&mdash;again a privilege, or perhaps a
5521 curse, reserved for the few.
5522 </para>
5523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5524 </chapter>
5525 <chapter label="9" id="collectors">
5526 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors</title>
5527 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'>
5528 <primary>archives, digital</primary>
5529 </indexterm>
5530 <para>
5531 In April 1996, millions of <quote>bots</quote>&mdash;computer codes designed to
5532 <quote>spider,</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy content&mdash;began
5533 running across the Net. Page by page, these bots copied Internet-based
5534 information onto a small set of computers located in a basement in San
5535 Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots finished the whole of the Internet,
5536 they started again. Over and over again, once every two months, these
5537 bits of code took copies of the Internet and stored them.
5538 </para>
5539 <para>
5540 By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5541 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5542 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5543 the world. Using a technology called <quote>the Way Back Machine,</quote> you could
5544 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to 1996, as
5545 well as when those pages changed.
5546 </para>
5547 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'>
5548 <primary>Orwell, George</primary>
5549 </indexterm>
5550 <para>
5551 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5552 appreciated. In the dystopia described in <citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5553 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5554 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5555 reports.
5556 </para>
5557 <para>
5558 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5559 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5560 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5561 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5562 </para>
5563 <para>
5564 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5565 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5566 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5567 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5568 library&mdash;constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5569 </para>
5570 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'/>
5571 <para>
5572 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5573 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5574 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5575 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5576 what others might prefer you forget.<footnote><para>
5577 <!-- f1 -->
5578 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5579 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003,
5580 press release stated, <quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.</quote> That was
5581 later changed, without notice, to <quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5582 Have Ended.</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003.
5583 </para></footnote>
5584 </para>
5585 <para>
5586 We take it for granted that we can go back to see what we remember
5587 reading. Think about newspapers. If you wanted to study the reaction
5588 of your hometown newspaper to the race riots in Watts in 1965, or to
5589 Bull Connor's water cannon in 1963, you could go to your public
5590 library and look at the newspapers. Those papers probably exist on
5591 microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in paper, too. Either way, you
5592 are free, using a library, to go back and remember&mdash;not just what
5593 it is convenient to remember, but remember something close to the
5594 truth.
5595 </para>
5596 <para>
5597 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5598 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We <emphasis>all</emphasis>
5599 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
5600 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
5601 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
5602 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
5603 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
5604 </para>
5605 <para>
5606 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5607 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5608 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5609 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5610 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5611 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5612 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5613 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet&mdash;the
5614 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5615 </para>
5616 <para>
5617 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5618 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5619 researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5620 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5621 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5622 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5623 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10
5624 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5625 </para>
5626 <para>
5627 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
5628 human history. At the end of 2002, it held <quote>two hundred and thirty
5629 terabytes of material</quote>&mdash;and was <quote>ten times larger than the
5630 Library of Congress.</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
5631 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
5632 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
5633 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
5634 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
5635 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
5636 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University&mdash;thanks to a
5637 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
5638 is available to scholars for a very low fee. <quote>But other than that,
5639 [television] is almost unavailable,</quote> Kahle told me. <quote>If you were
5640 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
5641 just a graduate student?</quote> As Kahle put it,
5642 </para>
5643 <blockquote>
5644 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan</primary></indexterm>
5645 <para>
5646 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
5647 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
5648 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
5649 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
5650 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
5651
5652 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
5653 <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode that came out after it &hellip; it would be almost
5654 impossible. &hellip; Those materials are almost unfindable. &hellip;
5655 </para>
5656 </blockquote>
5657 <para>
5658 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
5659 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
5660 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
5661 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
5662 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
5663 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
5664 </para>
5665 <para>
5666 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
5667 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
5668 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
5669 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
5670 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
5671 work.
5672 </para>
5673 <para>
5674 These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library
5675 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
5676 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
5677 borrow back the deposits&mdash;for an unlimited time at no cost. In
5678 1915 alone, there were more than 5,475 films deposited and <quote>borrowed
5679 back.</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
5680 held by any library. The copy exists&mdash;if it exists at
5681 all&mdash;in the library archive of the film company.<footnote><para>
5682 <!-- f2 -->
5683 Doug Herrick, <quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
5684 the Library of Congress,</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly</citetitle> 13 nos. 2&ndash;3
5685 (1980): 5; Anthony Slide, <citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
5686 Preservation in the United States</citetitle> ( Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland &amp;
5687 Co., 1992), 36.
5688 </para></footnote>
5689 </para>
5690 <para>
5691 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
5692 were originally not copyrighted&mdash;there was no way to capture the
5693 broadcasts, so there was no fear of <quote>theft.</quote> But as technology enabled
5694 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
5695 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
5696 <quote>copyrighted.</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
5697 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
5698 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
5699 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
5700 </para>
5701 <para>
5702 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and
5703 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
5704 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
5705 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
5706 September 11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
5707 stations from around the world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made
5708 their coverage during the week of September 11 available free on-line.
5709 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
5710 events of that day.
5711 </para>
5712 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive</primary></indexterm>
5713 <indexterm>
5714 <primary>archive.org</primary>
5715 <seealso>Internet Archive</seealso>
5716 </indexterm>
5717 <para>
5718 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
5719 archive of film includes close to 45,000 <quote>ephemeral films</quote> (meaning
5720 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
5721 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
5722 1,300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
5723 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
5724 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
5725 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
5726 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
5727 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
5728 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
5729 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
5730 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the <quote>Duck and Cover</quote> film
5731 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
5732 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
5733 few minutes&mdash;for free.
5734 </para>
5735 <para>
5736 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
5737 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
5738 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
5739 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
5740 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
5741 to find them.
5742 </para>
5743 <para>
5744 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
5745 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
5746 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
5747 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
5748 property, but during a second life that all creative property
5749 has&mdash;a noncommercial life.
5750 </para>
5751 <para>
5752 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
5753 of creative property goes through different <quote>lives.</quote> In its first
5754 life, if the
5755
5756 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
5757 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
5758 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
5759 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
5760 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
5761 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
5762 </para>
5763 <para>
5764 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
5765 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
5766 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
5767 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
5768 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
5769 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
5770 longer sold.
5771 </para>
5772 <para>
5773 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
5774 very quickly (the average today is after about a year<footnote><para>
5775 <!-- f3 -->
5776 Dave Barns, <quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
5777 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>,
5778 5 September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927
5779 and 1946, only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese,
5780 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,</quote> <citetitle>Boston
5781 College Law Review</citetitle> 44 (2003): 593 n. 51.
5782 </para></footnote>). After
5783 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
5784 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
5785 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
5786 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
5787 important to the spread and stability of culture.
5788 </para>
5789 <para>
5790 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
5791 creative property does not hold true with the most important
5792 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
5793 centuries. For these&mdash;television, movies, music, radio, the
5794 Internet&mdash;there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
5795 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes &amp;
5796 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
5797 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
5798 disappears.
5799 </para>
5800 <para>
5801 For most of the twentieth century, it was economics that made this
5802 so. It would have been insanely expensive to collect and make
5803 accessible all television and film and music: The cost of analog
5804 copies is extraordinarily high. So even though the law in principle
5805 would have restricted the ability of a Brewster Kahle to copy culture
5806 generally, the
5807 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
5808 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
5809 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
5810 little practical effect.
5811 </para>
5812 <para>
5813 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
5814 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
5815 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
5816 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
5817 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
5818 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
5819 </para>
5820 <para>
5821 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
5822 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
5823 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
5824 Kahle describes,
5825 </para>
5826 <blockquote>
5827 <indexterm>
5828 <primary>books</primary>
5829 <secondary>total number of</secondary>
5830 </indexterm>
5831 <para>
5832 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
5833 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
5834 movies, &hellip; and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
5835 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
5836 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
5837 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
5838 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
5839 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
5840 &hellip; thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
5841 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
5842 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
5843 </para>
5844 </blockquote>
5845 <para>
5846 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
5847 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
5848 libraries or archives could be. <emphasis>When</emphasis> the
5849 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
5850 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
5851 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
5852 will draw upon it to understand it;
5853 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
5854 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
5855 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
5856 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past&mdash;a
5857 future <emphasis>for</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
5858 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
5859 </para>
5860 <para>
5861 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
5862 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
5863 call these <quote>archives,</quote> as warm as the idea of a <quote>library</quote> might seem,
5864 the <quote>content</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
5865 someone's <quote>property.</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
5866 that Kahle and others would exercise.
5867 </para>
5868 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'/>
5869 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
5870 </chapter>
5871 <chapter label="10" id="property-i">
5872 <title>CHAPTER TEN: <quote>Property</quote></title>
5873 <para>
5874 Jack Valenti has been the president of the Motion Picture Association
5875 of America since 1966. He first came to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon
5876 Johnson's administration&mdash;literally. The famous picture of
5877 Johnson's swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of
5878 President Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty
5879 years of running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps
5880 the most prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
5881 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon</primary></indexterm>
5882 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
5883 </para>
5884 <para>
5885 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
5886 Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal
5887 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
5888 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
5889 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
5890 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
5891 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
5892 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
5893 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
5894 Warner Brothers.
5895 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
5896 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment</primary></indexterm>
5897 <indexterm><primary>MGM</primary></indexterm>
5898 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures</primary></indexterm>
5899 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox</primary></indexterm>
5900 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures</primary></indexterm>
5901 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
5902 </para>
5903 <para>
5904 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
5905 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
5906 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
5907 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
5908 political skill of a Southerner&mdash;the ability to appear simple and
5909 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
5910 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
5911 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
5912 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
5913 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
5914 Washingtonian way.
5915 </para>
5916 <para>
5917 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
5918 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
5919 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
5920 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
5921 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
5922 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
5923 redefine the meaning of <quote>creative property.</quote>
5924 </para>
5925 <para>
5926 In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
5927 perfectly:
5928 </para>
5929 <blockquote>
5930 <para>
5931 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
5932 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
5933 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
5934 theme which animates this entire debate: <emphasis>Creative property
5935 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
5936 other property owners in the nation</emphasis>. That is the issue.
5937 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
5938 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.<footnote><para>
5939 <!-- f1 -->
5940 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R.
5941 4794, H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the
5942 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
5943 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
5944 Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack
5945 Valenti).
5946 </para></footnote>
5947 </para>
5948 </blockquote>
5949 <para>
5950 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
5951 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
5952 <quote>central theme</quote> to which <quote>reasonable men and women</quote> will return is
5953 this:
5954 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
5955 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
5956 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.</quote>
5957 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
5958 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
5959 </para>
5960 <para>
5961 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
5962 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
5963 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
5964 extreme a claim made by <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> who is serious in
5965 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
5966 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
5967 it comes to the nature and scope of <quote>creative property.</quote> His views
5968 have <emphasis>no</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
5969 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
5970 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
5971 </para>
5972 <para>
5973 While <quote>creative property</quote> is certainly <quote>property</quote> in a nerdy and
5974 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,<footnote><para>
5975 <!-- f2 -->
5976 Lawyers speak of <quote>property</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
5977 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
5978 object. Thus, my <quote>property right</quote> to my car gives me the right to
5979 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For
5980 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of <quote>property</quote> to
5981 <quote>lawyer talk,</quote> see Bruce Ackerman, <citetitle>Private Property and the
5982 Constitution</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 26&ndash;27.
5983 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
5984 <quote>creative property owners</quote> have been <quote>accorded the same rights and
5985 protection resident in all other property owners.</quote> Indeed, if creative
5986 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
5987 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
5988 in our tradition.
5989 </para>
5990 <para>
5991 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
5992 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
5993 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
5994 overturned in 1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
5995 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
5996 culture would develop.
5997 </para>
5998 <para>
5999 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6000 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6001 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6002 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6003 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6004 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6005 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6006 the same would be to
6007
6008 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6009 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6010 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6011 perfect control.
6012 </para>
6013 <para>
6014 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6015 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6016 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6017 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6018 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6019 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6020 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old. To
6021 get just a hint that there is something fundamentally wrong in
6022 Valenti's argument, we need look no further than the United States
6023 Constitution itself.
6024 </para>
6025 <para>
6026 The framers of our Constitution loved <quote>property.</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6027 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6028 important requirement. If the government takes your property&mdash;if
6029 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6030 farm&mdash;it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's <quote>Takings
6031 Clause,</quote> to pay you <quote>just compensation</quote> for that taking. The
6032 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6033 sacred. It cannot <emphasis>ever</emphasis> be taken from the property
6034 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6035 </para>
6036 <para>
6037 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6038 Valenti calls <quote>creative property.</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6039 power to create <quote>creative property,</quote> the Constitution
6040 <emphasis>requires</emphasis> that after a <quote>limited time,</quote> Congress
6041 take back the rights that it has granted and set the <quote>creative
6042 property</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6043 the expiration of a copyright term <quote>takes</quote> your copyright and turns it
6044 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6045 pay <quote>just compensation</quote> for this <quote>taking.</quote> Instead, the same
6046 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6047 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6048 requires that you lose your <quote>creative property</quote> right without any
6049 compensation at all.
6050 </para>
6051 <para>
6052 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6053 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6054 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6055 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6056 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6057 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6058 itself.
6059 </para>
6060 <para>
6061 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6062 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6063 The Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6064 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6065 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6066 president (as it did in 1800). The framers were no doubt
6067 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6068 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6069 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6070 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6071 </para>
6072 <para>
6073 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6074 least try to understand <emphasis>why</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6075 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6076 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6077 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6078 domain?
6079 </para>
6080 <para>
6081 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6082 history of these <quote>creative property</quote> rights, and the control that they
6083 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6084 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6085 should be at the core of this war: Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis>
6086 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6087 <emphasis>whether</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6088 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6089 ought to be. Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6090 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6091 also control how culture develops.
6092 </para>
6093 <para>
6094
6095 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6096 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6097 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6098 than the narrow language of the law allows. In <citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6099 Cyberspace</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6100 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6101 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6102 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6103 </para>
6104 <figure id="fig-1331">
6105 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.</title>
6106 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6107 </figure>
6108 <para>
6109 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6110 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6111 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6112 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6113 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6114 be regulated&mdash; either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6115 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6116 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6117 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6118 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6119 Web, you can be punished
6120 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6121 with a $150,000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6122 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6123 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6124 </para>
6125 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6126 <para>
6127 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6128 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6129 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6130 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6131 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6132 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6133 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6134 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6135 the source of the enforcement.
6136 </para>
6137 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6138 <para>
6139 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6140 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6141 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6142 norms&mdash;it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6143 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6144 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6145 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6146 individual or group might behave.
6147 </para>
6148 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6149 <para>
6150 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6151 <quote>architecture</quote>&mdash;the physical world as one finds it&mdash;is a
6152 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6153 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6154 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6155 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6156 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6157 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6158 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6159 theft, but by nature, by <quote>architecture.</quote> If a 500-pound boulder
6160 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6161 constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6162 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6163 </para>
6164 <para>
6165
6166 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6167 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6168 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6169 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6170 undermined by another.
6171 </para>
6172 <para>
6173 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6174 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6175 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6176 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6177 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6178 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6179 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6180 </para>
6181 <indexterm id="idxdrivespeed" class='startofrange'>
6182 <primary>driving speed, constraints on</primary>
6183 </indexterm>
6184 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6185 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6186 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6187 <para>
6188 So, for example, consider the <quote>freedom</quote> to drive a car at a high
6189 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6190 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6191 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6192 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6193 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6194 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6195 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6196 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6197 the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own
6198 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6199 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6200 </para>
6201 <para>
6202 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6203 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6204 special role in affecting the three.<footnote><para>
6205 <!-- f3 -->
6206 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6207 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6208 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6209 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6210 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Code: And
6211 Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90&ndash;95;
6212 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>The New Chicago School,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies</citetitle>,
6213 June 1998.
6214 </para></footnote>
6215 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6216 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6217 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6218 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6219 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6220 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6221 used to require that other laws be more
6222 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6223 strict&mdash;a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6224 limit, for example&mdash;so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6225 driving.
6226 </para>
6227 <indexterm startref="idxdrivespeed" class='endofrange'/>
6228
6229 <figure id="fig-1361">
6230 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.</title>
6231 <graphic fileref="images/1361.png"></graphic>
6232 </figure>
6233 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6234 <para>
6235 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6236 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6237 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6238 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6239 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6240 another.<footnote>
6241 <para>
6242 <!-- f4 -->
6243 Some people object to this way of talking about <quote>liberty.</quote> They object
6244 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6245 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6246 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6247 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6248 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6249 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6250 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6251 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6252 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6253 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6254 of liberty. As I argued in <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, we come from a
6255 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6256 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6257 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6258 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6259 <citetitle>On Liberty</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6260 1978), 19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6261 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons, <quote>The
6262 Right to Work,</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6263 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays</citetitle> (London:
6264 Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6265 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6266 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6267 places easier; 42 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
6268 12101 (2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6269 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6270 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6271 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6272 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (1990)</primary></indexterm>
6273 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.</primary></indexterm>
6274 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6275 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6276 </para></footnote>
6277 </para>
6278 <section id="hollywood">
6279 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right</title>
6280 <para>
6281 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6282 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6283 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6284 rallying makes sense.
6285 </para>
6286 <para>
6287 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6288 Internet:
6289 </para>
6290 <figure id="fig-1371">
6291 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6292 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6293 </figure>
6294 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6295 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6296 <para>
6297 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6298 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6299 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6300 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6301 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6302 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6303 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6304 recognize&mdash;kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6305 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6306 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6307 this form of infringement.
6308 </para>
6309 <para>
6310 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6311 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6312 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6313 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6314 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6315 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6316 </para>
6317 <para>
6318 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6319 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6320 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6321 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6322 Iraq
6323 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6324 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6325 looting that results.
6326 </para>
6327 <figure id="fig-1381">
6328 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.</title>
6329 <graphic fileref="images/1381.png"></graphic>
6330 </figure>
6331 <para>
6332 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6333 warriors. Indeed, in a <quote>White Paper</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6334 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995,
6335 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6336 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6337 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should
6338 strengthen intellectual property law, (2) businesses should adopt
6339 innovative marketing techniques, (3) technologists should push to
6340 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (4) educators should
6341 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6342 </para>
6343 <para>
6344 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed&mdash;if it was to
6345 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6346 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6347 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6348 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6349 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6350 life. Homeowners living in a
6351
6352 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6353 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6354 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6355 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6356 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6357 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6358 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6359 </para>
6360 <para>
6361 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6362 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6363 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6364 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6365 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6366 Brown describes it, its <quote>architecture of revenue.</quote>
6367 </para>
6368 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry</primary></indexterm>
6369 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
6370 <para>
6371 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6372 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6373 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6374 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6375 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20
6376 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6377 of digital cameras.<footnote><para>
6378 <!-- f5 -->
6379 See Geoffrey Smith, <quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?</quote>
6380 BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at
6381 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #23</ulink>. For a more
6382 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6383 R. Schoenberger, <quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?</quote> Forbes.com, 6
6384 October 2003, available at
6385 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #24</ulink>.
6386 </para></footnote>
6387
6388 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6389 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6390 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6391 <emphasis>for the purpose of</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6392 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6393 weakened the <quote>stickiness</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6394 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf ), and it
6395 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6396 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6397 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6398 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6399 </para>
6400 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
6401 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
6402 <para>
6403 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6404 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6405 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6406 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6407 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6408 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6409 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6410 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, <quote>established companies
6411 have an interest in excluding future competitors.</quote><footnote><para>
6412 <!-- f6 -->
6413 Fred Warshofsky, <citetitle>The Patent Wars</citetitle> (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170&ndash;71.
6414 </para></footnote>
6415 And relative to a
6416 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6417 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6418 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6419 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6420 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6421 Brezhnev.
6422 </para>
6423 <para>
6424 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6425 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6426 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6427 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6428 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6429 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6430 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6431 opportunities for innovation and change.
6432 </para>
6433 <para>
6434 In the context of laws regulating speech&mdash;which include,
6435 obviously, copyright law&mdash;that duty is even stronger. When the
6436 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6437 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6438 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6439 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6440 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6441 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: <quote>Congress
6442 shall make no law &hellip; abridging the freedom of speech.</quote> So when
6443 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would <quote>abridge</quote> the freedom
6444 of speech, it should ask&mdash; carefully&mdash;whether such
6445 regulation is justified.
6446 </para>
6447 <para>
6448 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6449 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6450 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6451 <quote>justified.</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6452 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6453 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6454 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6455 </para>
6456 <para>
6457 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6458 </para>
6459 <indexterm id="idxddt" class='startofrange'>
6460 <primary>DDT</primary>
6461 </indexterm>
6462 <para>
6463 In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss
6464 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6465 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the
6466 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6467 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6468 <indexterm><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann</primary></indexterm>
6469 </para>
6470 <para>
6471 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6472 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6473 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6474 </para>
6475 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6476 <indexterm><primary>Silent Sprint (Carson)</primary></indexterm>
6477 <para>
6478 But in 1962, Rachel Carson published <citetitle>Silent Spring</citetitle>, which argued that
6479 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6480 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6481 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6482 </para>
6483 <para>
6484 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6485 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6486 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6487 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6488 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6489 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6490 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6491 </para>
6492 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James</primary></indexterm>
6493 <para>
6494 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6495 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an <quote>environmentalism</quote> for
6496 culture.<footnote><para>
6497 <!-- f7 -->
6498 See, for example, James Boyle, <quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6499 Environmentalism for the Net?</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal</citetitle> 47 (1997): 87.
6500 </para></footnote>
6501 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6502 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6503 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6504 <quote>for free.</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6505 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6506 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6507 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6508 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6509 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6510 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6511 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6512 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6513 </para>
6514 <para>
6515 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6516 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6517 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6518 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6519 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6520 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6521 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6522 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6523 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6524 </para>
6525 <para>
6526 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6527 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6528 be lost.
6529 </para>
6530 <indexterm startref="idxddt" class='endofrange'/>
6531 </section>
6532 <section id="beginnings">
6533 <title>Beginnings</title>
6534 <para>
6535 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6536 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of <quote>creative
6537 property</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6538 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6539 </para>
6540 <para>
6541 The power to establish <quote>creative property</quote> rights is granted to
6542 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6543 odd. Article I, section 8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that:
6544 </para>
6545 <para>
6546 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6547 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6548 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
6549
6550 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
6551 We can call this the <quote>Progress Clause,</quote> for notice what this clause
6552 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
6553 <quote>creative property rights.</quote> It says that Congress has the power
6554 <emphasis>to promote progress</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
6555 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
6556 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
6557 </para>
6558 <para>
6559 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
6560 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="founders"/>,
6561 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
6562 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
6563 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
6564 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
6565 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
6566 copyrights extend <quote>to Authors</quote> only.
6567 </para>
6568 <para>
6569 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
6570 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
6571 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
6572 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
6573 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
6574 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
6575 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
6576 to reinforce the power of the states&mdash;including the Senate, whose
6577 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
6578 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
6579 case, a <emphasis>structure</emphasis> built checks and balances into
6580 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
6581 concentrations of power.
6582 </para>
6583 <para>
6584 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call <quote>copyright</quote>
6585 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
6586 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
6587 <quote>copyright</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210
6588 years since they first struck its design.
6589 </para>
6590 <para>
6591 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
6592 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
6593 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
6594 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
6595 started here:
6596 </para>
6597 <figure id="fig-1441">
6598 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6599 <graphic fileref="images/1331.png"></graphic>
6600 </figure>
6601 <para>
6602 We will end here:
6603 </para>
6604 <figure id="fig-1442">
6605 <title><quote>Copyright</quote> today.</title>
6606 <graphic fileref="images/1442.png"></graphic>
6607 </figure>
6608 <para>
6609 Let me explain how.
6610 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
6611 </para>
6612 </section>
6613 <section id="lawduration">
6614 <title>Law: Duration</title>
6615 <para>
6616 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
6617 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
6618 the English had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws
6619 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
6620 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
6621 authorship.<footnote>
6622 <para>
6623 <!-- f8 -->
6624 William W. Crosskey, <citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
6625 the United States</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press, 1953), vol. 1,
6626 485&ndash;86: <quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
6627 Law of the Land,' <emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
6628 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law</emphasis></quote>
6629 (emphasis added).
6630 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.</primary></indexterm>
6631 </para></footnote>
6632 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
6633 States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
6634 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
6635 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
6636 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
6637 domain to reprint and distribute works.
6638 </para>
6639 <para>
6640 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
6641 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
6642 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
6643 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
6644 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
6645 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
6646 </para>
6647 <para>
6648 In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
6649 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
6650 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
6651 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
6652 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
6653 </para>
6654 <para>
6655 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
6656 ten years of the Republic, only 5 percent of the works were actually
6657 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
6658 in the United States both before 1790 and from 1790 through 1800, 95
6659 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
6660 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
6661 likely within fourteen years.<footnote><para>
6662 <!-- f9 -->
6663 Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790
6664 to 1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, <citetitle>A
6665 History of Book Publishing in the United States</citetitle>, vol. 1, <citetitle>The Creation
6666 of an Industry, 1630&ndash;1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000
6667 imprints recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
6668 1790 act; William J. Maher, <citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
6669 and the Copyright Law of 1790 in Historical Context</citetitle>, 7&ndash;10 (2002),
6670 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
6671 #25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
6672 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
6673 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
6674 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
6675 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
6676 Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124. </para></footnote>
6677 </para>
6678 <para>
6679 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
6680 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
6681 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
6682 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
6683 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
6684 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
6685 copyright, either.
6686 </para>
6687 <para>
6688 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
6689 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
6690 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
6691 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
6692 domain.<footnote><para>
6693 <!-- f10 -->
6694 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
6695 instance, of the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were
6696 renewed in 1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
6697 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, <quote>Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright,</quote>
6698 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright</citetitle>, vol. 1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
6699 1963), 618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
6700 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote>
6701 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 471, 498&ndash;501, and
6702 accompanying figures. </para></footnote>
6703 </para>
6704 <para>
6705 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
6706 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
6707 out of print after one year.<footnote><para>
6708 <!-- f11 -->
6709 See Ringer, ch. 9, n. 2. </para></footnote> When that happens, the
6710 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
6711 no longer <emphasis>effectively</emphasis> controlled by
6712 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
6713 is to sell the books as used books; that use&mdash;because it does not
6714 involve publication&mdash;is effectively free.
6715 </para>
6716 <para>
6717 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
6718 changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28
6719 years to a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
6720 from 14 years to 28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
6721 the term increased once again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal
6722 term of 14 years to 28 years, setting a maximum term of 56 years.
6723 </para>
6724 <para>
6725 Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
6726 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
6727 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
6728 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
6729 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
6730 In 1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
6731 And in 1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
6732 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
6733 </para>
6734 <para>
6735 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
6736 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
6737 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
6738 years, or 70 percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years
6739
6740 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
6741 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
6742 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
6743 of the expiration of a copyright term.
6744 </para>
6745 <para>
6746 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
6747 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
6748 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
6749 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
6750 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
6751 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
6752 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
6753 value.
6754 </para>
6755 <para>
6756 The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For
6757 all works created after 1978, there was only one copyright term&mdash;the
6758 maximum term. For <quote>natural</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
6759 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992,
6760 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
6761 before 1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
6762 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
6763 was ninety-five years.
6764 </para>
6765 <para>
6766 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
6767 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
6768 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
6769 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
6770 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
6771 that terms be <quote>limited,</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
6772 them.
6773 </para>
6774 <para>
6775 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
6776 dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to
6777 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
6778 in 1973 was just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
6779 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
6780 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95
6781 years.<footnote><para>
6782 <!-- f12 -->
6783 These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the
6784 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
6785 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
6786 Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote> loc. cit.
6787 </para></footnote>
6788 </para>
6789 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
6790 </section>
6791 <section id="lawscope">
6792 <title>Law: Scope</title>
6793 <para>
6794 The <quote>scope</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
6795 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
6796 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
6797 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
6798 </para>
6799 <para>
6800 In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only <quote>maps,
6801 charts, and books.</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
6802 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
6803 the author the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> copyrighted works. That
6804 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
6805 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
6806 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
6807 did not extend to what lawyers call <quote>derivative works.</quote> It would not,
6808 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
6809 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
6810 (such as a drama based on a published book).
6811 </para>
6812 <para>
6813 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
6814 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
6815 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
6816 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
6817 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
6818 work not only the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> the work, but also the
6819 exclusive right of control over any <quote>copies</quote> of that work. And most
6820 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
6821 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
6822 <quote>derivative work</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
6823 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
6824 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
6825 on the initial creative work.
6826 </para>
6827 <para>
6828 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
6829 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
6830 complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition
6831 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
6832 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
6833 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
6834 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
6835 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
6836 famous &copy; or the word <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>. And for most
6837 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
6838 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
6839 secured.
6840 </para>
6841 <para>
6842 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
6843 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
6844 in the first ten years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible
6845 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
6846 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
6847 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
6848 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
6849 copyrighted&mdash;that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
6850 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
6851 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
6852 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
6853 original author.
6854 </para>
6855 <para>
6856 All of these <quote>formalities</quote> were abolished in the American system when
6857 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
6858 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
6859 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
6860 a &copy;; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
6861 copy available for others to copy.
6862 </para>
6863 <para>
6864 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
6865 differences.
6866 </para>
6867 <para>
6868 If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who
6869 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
6870 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
6871 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
6872 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were
6873 174 publishers in the United States.<footnote><para>
6874 <!-- f13 -->
6875 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, <quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
6876 Creation of American Literature,</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
6877 International Law and Politics</citetitle> 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
6878 Federal Copyright Records, 1790&ndash;1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987).
6879
6880 </para></footnote>
6881 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
6882 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
6883 the United States&mdash;publishers.
6884 </para>
6885 <para>
6886 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
6887 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
6888 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
6889 was totally unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and made
6890 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
6891 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
6892 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
6893 were restrained.
6894 </para>
6895 <para>
6896 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
6897 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
6898 every note to your spouse, every doodle, <emphasis>every</emphasis>
6899 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form&mdash;all of this is
6900 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
6901 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
6902 protect it.
6903 </para>
6904 <para>
6905 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
6906 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
6907 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
6908 </para>
6909 <para>
6910 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
6911 control
6912 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
6913 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of <quote>derivative
6914 rights.</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
6915 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
6916 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
6917 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
6918 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
6919 exclusive
6920 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
6921 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
6922 </para>
6923 <para>
6924 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
6925 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
6926 expansion
6927 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
6928 copyright.
6929 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
6930 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
6931 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
6932 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
6933 </para>
6934 <para>
6935 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
6936 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
6937 within a free culture&mdash;at least, it's astonishing when you
6938 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
6939 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
6940 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
6941 <emphasis>that</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
6942 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
6943 all&mdash;they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
6944 not protect derivative rights at all.<footnote><para>
6945 <!-- f14 -->
6946 Jonathan Zittrain, <quote>The Copyright Cage,</quote> <citetitle>Legal
6947 Affairs</citetitle>, July/August 2003, available at
6948 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #26</ulink>.
6949 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
6950 </para></footnote>
6951 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
6952 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
6953 the wrong of direct piracy.
6954 </para>
6955 <para>
6956 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
6957 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
6958 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
6959 of my book.<footnote><para>
6960 <!-- f15 -->
6961 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
6962 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
6963 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere <quote>copies</quote> and
6964 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld, <quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
6965 Copyright's Constitutionality,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
6966 Journal</citetitle> 112 (2002): 1&ndash;60 (see especially
6967 pp. 53&ndash;59).
6968 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb</primary></indexterm>
6969 </para></footnote>
6970 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
6971 </para>
6972 <para>
6973 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
6974 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
6975 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
6976 called <quote>Mickey Mouse,</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
6977 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
6978 created?
6979 </para>
6980 <para>
6981 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
6982 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
6983 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
6984 the rights originally granted.
6985 </para>
6986 </section>
6987 <section id="lawreach">
6988 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach</title>
6989 <para>
6990 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
6991 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
6992 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
6993 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.<footnote><para>
6994 <!-- f16 -->
6995 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
6996 certainly regulates more than <quote>copies</quote>&mdash;a public performance of a
6997 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
6998 per se doesn't make a copy; 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
6999 106(4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a <quote>copy</quote>; 17
7000 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section 112(a). But the presumption under the
7001 existing law (which regulates <quote>copies;</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7002 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7003 </para></footnote>
7004 </para>
7005 <para>
7006 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7007 <quote>Copies.</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7008 <emphasis>copy</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7009 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that <quote>creative
7010 property</quote> deserves the <quote>same rights</quote> as all other property, it is the
7011 <emphasis>obvious</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7012 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7013 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7014 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7015 copies should <emphasis>not</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7016 law. More precisely, they should not <emphasis>always</emphasis> be
7017 the trigger for copyright law.
7018 </para>
7019 <para>
7020 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7021 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7022 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7023 the law of copyright automatically applies,<footnote><para>
7024 <!-- f17 -->
7025 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7026 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7027 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7028 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7029 technology.
7030 </para></footnote>
7031 because it is clear that the
7032 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7033 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7034 </para>
7035 <para>
7036 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7037 empty circle.
7038 </para>
7039 <figure id="fig-1521">
7040 <title>All potential uses of a book.</title>
7041 <graphic fileref="images/1521.png"></graphic>
7042 </figure>
7043 <para>
7044 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7045 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7046 all its potential <emphasis>uses</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7047 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7048 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7049 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7050 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7051 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7052 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7053 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7054 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7055 acts do not make a copy.
7056 </para>
7057 <figure id="fig-1531">
7058 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.</title>
7059 <graphic fileref="images/1531.png"></graphic>
7060 </figure>
7061 <para>
7062 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7063 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7064 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7065 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7066 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see first
7067 diagram on next page).
7068 </para>
7069 <para>
7070 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7071 that remain unregulated because the law considers these <quote>fair uses.</quote>
7072 </para>
7073 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7074 <figure id="fig-1541">
7075 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.</title>
7076 <graphic fileref="images/1541.png"></graphic>
7077 </figure>
7078 <para>
7079 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7080 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7081 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7082 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7083 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7084 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7085 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such <quote>fair uses</quote>
7086 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7087 </para>
7088 <figure id="fig-1542">
7089 <title>Unregulated copying considered <quote>fair uses.</quote></title>
7090 <graphic fileref="images/1542.png"></graphic>
7091 </figure>
7092 <para> </para>
7093 <figure id="fig-1551">
7094 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.</title>
7095 <graphic fileref="images/1551.png"></graphic>
7096 </figure>
7097 <para>
7098 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7099 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7100 sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that
7101 are nonetheless deemed <quote>fair</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7102 </para>
7103 <para>
7104 Enter the Internet&mdash;a distributed, digital network where every use
7105 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.<footnote><para>
7106 <!-- f18 -->
7107 I don't mean <quote>nature</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7108 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7109 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7110 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7111 of copies remain.
7112 </para></footnote>
7113 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7114 digital network, the scope of category 1 changes dramatically. Uses
7115 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7116 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7117 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7118 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7119 a copy&mdash;category 1 gets sucked into category 2. And those who
7120 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7121 exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7122 shift.
7123 </para>
7124 <para>
7125 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7126 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7127 be no plausible <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>-related argument that
7128 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7129 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7130 the book once, ten times, or every
7131 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7132 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7133 use&mdash;reading&mdash; could be regulated by copyright law because
7134 none of those uses produced a copy.
7135 </para>
7136 <para>
7137 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7138 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7139 only once or only once a month, then <emphasis>copyright
7140 law</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7141 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7142 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7143 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7144 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7145 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7146 copyright owner's wish.
7147 </para>
7148 <para>
7149 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7150 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7151 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7152 points also become clear:
7153 </para>
7154 <para>
7155 First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7156 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7157 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7158 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7159 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7160 part of free culture before the Internet.
7161 </para>
7162 <para>
7163 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7164 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7165 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7166 <emphasis>any</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7167 using a machine. <quote>Copy and paste</quote> and <quote>cut and paste</quote> become
7168 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7169 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7170 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7171 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7172 creative work.
7173 </para>
7174 <para>
7175 Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary
7176
7177 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7178 burden on category 3 (<quote>fair use</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7179 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7180 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7181 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7182 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7183 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7184 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7185 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7186 regulated.
7187 </para>
7188 <para>
7189 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7190 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7191 depend upon fair use&mdash;never even addressing the earlier question
7192 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7193 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7194 <emphasis>unregulated</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7195 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7196 enough.
7197 </para>
7198 <indexterm id='idxadvertising2' class='startofrange'>
7199 <primary>advertising</primary>
7200 </indexterm>
7201 <para>
7202 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7203 in the business of making <quote>trailer</quote> advertisements for movies available
7204 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7205 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7206 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7207 </para>
7208 <para>
7209 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it began
7210 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7211 previews. The idea was to expand their <quote>selling by sampling</quote>
7212 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7213 <quote>browsing.</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7214 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7215 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7216 </para>
7217 <para>
7218 In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7219 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7220 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7221 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7222 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7223 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter&mdash;he had built a
7224 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7225 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7226 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7227 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7228 <quote>fair use</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7229 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7230 their rights.
7231 </para>
7232 <para>
7233 Disney countersued&mdash;for $100 million in damages. Those damages
7234 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had <quote>willfully
7235 infringed</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7236 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7237 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7238 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7239 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7240 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $100 million.
7241 </para>
7242 <para>
7243 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7244 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7245 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7246 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7247 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7248 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7249 Disney's permission.
7250 </para>
7251 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising2' class='endofrange'/>
7252 <para>
7253 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7254 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7255 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7256 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7257 was in the marketplace, the <quote>first-sale doctrine</quote> would free the
7258 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7259 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7260 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7261 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7262 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7263 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7264 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7265 </para>
7266 <indexterm><primary>Barnes &amp; Noble</primary></indexterm>
7267 <para>
7268 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7269 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7270 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes &amp; Noble has the
7271 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7272 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7273 abuse. If Barnes &amp; Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7274 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7275 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7276 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7277 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7278 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7279 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7280 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7281 happening are quite slight.
7282 </para>
7283 <para>
7284 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7285 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7286 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7287 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7288 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7289 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7290 </para>
7291 </section>
7292 <section id="lawforce">
7293 <title>Architecture and Law: Force</title>
7294 <para>
7295 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7296 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7297 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7298 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7299 </para>
7300 <para>
7301 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7302 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7303 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7304 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7305 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7306 your freedom.
7307 </para>
7308 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca</primary></indexterm>
7309 <indexterm id="idxmarxbrothers" class='startofrange'>
7310 <primary>Marx Brothers</primary>
7311 </indexterm>
7312 <indexterm id="idxwarnerbrothers" class='startofrange'>
7313 <primary>Warner Brothers</primary>
7314 </indexterm>
7315 <para>
7316 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7317 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7318 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7319 <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7320 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7321 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7322 plan.<footnote><para>
7323 <!-- f19 -->
7324 See David Lange, <quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7325 Contemporary Problems</citetitle> 44 (1981): 172&ndash;73.
7326 </para></footnote>
7327 </para>
7328 <para>
7329 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7330 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers <quote>were brothers long before
7331 you were.</quote><footnote><para>
7332 <!-- f20 -->
7333 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and
7334 Copywrongs</citetitle>, 1&ndash;3.
7335 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
7336 </para></footnote>
7337 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7338 <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7339 trying to control <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>, then the Marx
7340 Brothers would insist on control over <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>.
7341 </para>
7342 <para>
7343 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7344 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7345 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7346 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7347 </para>
7348 <para>
7349 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7350 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7351 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7352 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7353 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7354 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7355 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7356 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7357 </para>
7358 <indexterm startref="idxwarnerbrothers" class='endofrange'/>
7359 <indexterm startref="idxmarxbrothers" class='endofrange'/>
7360
7361 <indexterm id="idxadobeebookreader" class='startofrange'>
7362 <primary>Adobe eBook Reader</primary>
7363 </indexterm>
7364 <para>
7365 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7366 </para>
7367 <para>
7368 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7369 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7370 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7371 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7372 technology.
7373 </para>
7374 <para>
7375 On the next page is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook
7376 Reader.
7377 </para>
7378 <para>
7379 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7380 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7381 public domain: <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, for example, is in
7382 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7383 public domain: My own book <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
7384 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7385 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7386 copy of
7387 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7388 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7389 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
7390 </para>
7391 <figure id="fig-1611">
7392 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader</title>
7393 <graphic fileref="images/1611.png"></graphic>
7394 </figure>
7395 <para>
7396 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7397 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7398 </para>
7399 <figure id="fig-1612">
7400 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.</title>
7401 <graphic fileref="images/1612.png"></graphic>
7402 </figure>
7403 <para>
7404 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7405 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
7406 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
7407 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
7408 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
7409 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>
7410 read aloud through the computer.
7411 </para>
7412 <para>
7413 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7414 translation): Aristotle's <citetitle>Politics</citetitle>.
7415 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle</primary></indexterm>
7416 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics</citetitle>, (Aristotle)</primary></indexterm>
7417 </para>
7418 <figure id="fig-1621">
7419 <title>E-book of Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote></title>
7420 <graphic fileref="images/1621.png"></graphic>
7421 </figure>
7422 <para>
7423 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7424 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
7425 the book.
7426 </para>
7427 <figure id="fig-1622">
7428 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle;s <quote>Politics</quote>.</title>
7429 <graphic fileref="images/1622.png"></graphic>
7430 </figure>
7431 <para>
7432 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
7433 original e-book version of my last book, <citetitle>The Future of
7434 Ideas</citetitle>:
7435 </para>
7436 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
7437 <figure id="fig-1631">
7438 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>The Future of Ideas</quote>.</title>
7439 <graphic fileref="images/1631.png"></graphic>
7440 </figure>
7441 <para>
7442 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
7443 </para>
7444 <para>
7445 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
7446 <quote>permissions</quote>&mdash; as if the publisher has the power to control how
7447 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
7448 certainly does have the power&mdash;up to the limits of the copyright
7449 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
7450 power.<footnote><para>
7451 <!-- f21 -->
7452 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
7453 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
7454 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
7455 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
7456 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
7457 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
7458 subsequently acquired the book.
7459 </para></footnote>
7460 When my e-book of <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> says I have the
7461 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
7462 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
7463 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
7464 control that the law would enable.
7465 </para>
7466 <para>
7467 The control comes instead from the code&mdash;from the technology
7468 within which the e-book <quote>lives.</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
7469 permissions, they are not the sort of <quote>permissions</quote> that most of us
7470 deal with. When a teenager gets <quote>permission</quote> to stay out till
7471 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
7472 till 2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
7473 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
7474 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
7475 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
7476 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
7477 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
7478 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
7479 aloud&mdash;it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
7480 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
7481 won't read aloud.
7482 </para>
7483 <para>
7484 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
7485 These are <emphasis>controls</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
7486 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
7487 you tried to type <quote>Warner Brothers,</quote> erased <quote>Brothers</quote> from the
7488 sentence.
7489 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7490 </para>
7491 <para>
7492 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
7493 <emphasis>law</emphasis> as copyright <emphasis>code</emphasis>. The
7494 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
7495 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
7496 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
7497 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
7498 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
7499 </para>
7500 <para>
7501 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
7502 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
7503 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
7504 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
7505 to defeat these protections as well?
7506 </para>
7507 <para>
7508 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
7509 eBook Reader.
7510 </para>
7511 <para>
7512 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
7513 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
7514 on the Adobe site was a copy of <citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
7515 Wonderland</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
7516 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
7517 following report:
7518 <indexterm><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)</primary></indexterm>
7519 </para>
7520 <figure id="fig-1641">
7521 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>Alice's Adventures in
7522 Wonderland</quote>.</title>
7523 <graphic fileref="images/1641.png"></graphic>
7524 </figure>
7525 <beginpage pagenum="164"/>
7526 <para>
7527 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
7528 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
7529 <quote>permissions</quote> indicated, not allowed to <quote>read aloud</quote>!
7530 </para>
7531 <para>
7532 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
7533 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
7534 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
7535 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
7536 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
7537 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
7538 </para>
7539 <para>
7540 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
7541 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
7542 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
7543 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
7544 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
7545 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
7546 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
7547 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
7548 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
7549 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
7550 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
7551 </para>
7552 <para>
7553 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
7554 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
7555 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
7556 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
7557 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
7558 often crazy.
7559 </para>
7560 <indexterm startref="idxadobeebookreader" class='endofrange'/>
7561 <para>
7562 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
7563 story of mine that makes the same point.
7564 </para>
7565 <indexterm id="idxaibo1" class='startofrange'>
7566 <primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary>
7567 </indexterm>
7568 <indexterm id="idxroboticdog1" class='startofrange'>
7569 <primary>robotic dog</primary>
7570 </indexterm>
7571 <indexterm id="idxsonyaibo1" class='startofrange'>
7572 <primary>Sony</primary>
7573 <secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary>
7574 </indexterm>
7575 <para>
7576 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named <quote>Aibo.</quote> The Aibo
7577 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
7578 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
7579 </para>
7580 <para>
7581 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
7582 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
7583 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
7584 <beginpage pagenum="165"/>
7585 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
7586 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
7587 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
7588 </para>
7589 <para>
7590 <quote>Teach</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
7591 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
7592 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
7593 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
7594 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
7595 their computer <quote>dog</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
7596 </para>
7597 <para>
7598 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
7599 <citetitle>hack</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
7600 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
7601 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
7602 them, <citetitle>hack</citetitle> is a much more positive
7603 term. <citetitle>Hack</citetitle> just means code that enables the
7604 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
7605 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
7606 old computer doesn't run, or <quote>drive,</quote> the printer. If you discovered
7607 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
7608 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
7609 you just bought.
7610 </para>
7611 <para>
7612 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
7613 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
7614 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
7615 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
7616 ethically.
7617 </para>
7618 <para>
7619 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
7620 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
7621 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
7622 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
7623 than Sony had built.
7624 </para>
7625 <indexterm startref="idxsonyaibo1" class='endofrange'/>
7626 <indexterm startref="idxroboticdog1" class='endofrange'/>
7627 <indexterm startref="idxaibo1" class='endofrange'/>
7628 <para>
7629 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
7630 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
7631 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
7632 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
7633 the
7634
7635 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
7636 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
7637 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
7638 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
7639 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
7640 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
7641 thought, <emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
7642 a robot dog to dance?</emphasis>
7643 </para>
7644 <para>
7645 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show&mdash;
7646 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
7647 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
7648 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
7649 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
7650 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
7651 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
7652 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
7653 into being silent about something he knew very well.
7654 </para>
7655 <para>
7656 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.<footnote><para>
7657 <!-- f22 -->
7658 See Pamela Samuelson, <quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,</quote>
7659 <citetitle>Science</citetitle> 293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, <quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
7660 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect</citetitle>,
7661 January 2002; <quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
7662 DMCA,</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter</citetitle>, 11 December 2001; Bill
7663 Holland, <quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,</quote> <citetitle>Billboard</citetitle>,
7664 May 2001; Janelle Brown, <quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?</quote> Salon.com,
7665 April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, <quote>Frequently Asked
7666 Questions about <citetitle>Felten and USENIX</citetitle> v. <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> Legal Case,</quote> available at
7667 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #27</ulink>.
7668 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
7669 </para></footnote>
7670 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
7671 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
7672 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
7673 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
7674 </para>
7675 <para>
7676 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
7677 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
7678 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
7679 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
7680 <quote>this music cannot be copied,</quote> and have a computer respect that
7681 command. The technology was to be part of a <quote>trusted system</quote> of
7682 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
7683 Internet much more.
7684 </para>
7685 <para>
7686 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
7687 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
7688 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
7689 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
7690 </para>
7691 <para>
7692 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
7693 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
7694 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
7695 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
7696 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
7697 </para>
7698 <para>
7699 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
7700 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
7701 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
7702 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
7703 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
7704 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
7705 </para>
7706 <para>
7707 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
7708 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
7709 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
7710 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
7711 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
7712 constituted, succeed.
7713 </para>
7714 <indexterm id="idxaibo2" class='startofrange'>
7715 <primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary>
7716 </indexterm>
7717 <indexterm id="idxroboticdog2" class='startofrange'>
7718 <primary>robotic dog</primary>
7719 </indexterm>
7720 <indexterm id="idxsonyaibo2" class='startofrange'>
7721 <primary>Sony</primary>
7722 <secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary>
7723 </indexterm>
7724 <para>
7725 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
7726 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
7727 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
7728 wrote:
7729 </para>
7730 <blockquote>
7731 <para>
7732 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
7733 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
7734 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
7735 </para>
7736 </blockquote>
7737 <indexterm startref="idxsonyaibo2" class='endofrange'/>
7738 <indexterm startref="idxroboticdog2" class='endofrange'/>
7739 <indexterm startref="idxaibo2" class='endofrange'/>
7740 <para>
7741 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
7742 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
7743 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
7744 </para>
7745 <blockquote>
7746 <para>
7747 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
7748 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
7749 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
7750 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
7751 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (<quote>DMCA</quote>).
7752 </para>
7753 </blockquote>
7754 <para>
7755 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
7756 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
7757 spreading such information an offense.
7758 </para>
7759 <para>
7760 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
7761 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
7762 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
7763 These new technologies would be copyright protection
7764 technologies&mdash; technologies to control the replication and
7765 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
7766 <emphasis>code</emphasis> to modify the original
7767 <emphasis>code</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
7768 protection for copyright owners.
7769 </para>
7770 <para>
7771 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
7772 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
7773 <emphasis>legal code</emphasis> intended to buttress
7774 <emphasis>software code</emphasis> which itself was intended to
7775 support the <emphasis>legal code of copyright</emphasis>.
7776 </para>
7777 <para>
7778 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
7779 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
7780 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
7781 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
7782 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
7783 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
7784 have been a copyright violation.
7785 </para>
7786 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7787 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7788 <indexterm>
7789 <primary>Sony</primary>
7790 <secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary>
7791 </indexterm>
7792 <para>
7793 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
7794 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
7795 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
7796 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
7797 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
7798 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
7799 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
7800 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
7801 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
7802 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
7803 </para>
7804 <para>
7805 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
7806 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
7807 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
7808 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
7809 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
7810 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
7811 </para>
7812 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
7813 <para>
7814 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
7815 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
7816 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
7817 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
7818 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
7819 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka <quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers</citetitle>,</quote>
7820 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
7821 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
7822 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
7823 </para>
7824 <blockquote>
7825 <para>
7826 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
7827 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
7828 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
7829 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
7830 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
7831 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the <quote>Neighborhood</quote>
7832 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
7833 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
7834 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
7835 broadcasting has always been <quote>You are an important person just the way
7836 you are. You can make healthy decisions.</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
7837 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
7838 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
7839 important.<footnote><para>
7840 <!-- f23 -->
7841 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
7842 455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
7843 James Lardner, <citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
7844 the VCR</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270&ndash;71.
7845 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
7846 </para></footnote>
7847 </para>
7848 </blockquote>
7849 <para>
7850 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
7851 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
7852 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
7853 the VCR responsible.
7854 </para>
7855 <para>
7856 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
7857 the DMCA.
7858 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
7859 </para>
7860 <para>
7861 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
7862 </para>
7863 <para>
7864 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
7865 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
7866 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
7867 pirating of copyrighted material&mdash;a bad end. Or they can be used
7868 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
7869 would be considered fair use&mdash;a good end.
7870 </para>
7871 <para>
7872 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
7873 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
7874 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
7875 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
7876 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
7877 and bad uses.
7878 </para>
7879 <figure id="fig-1711">
7880 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.</title>
7881 <graphic fileref="images/1711.png"></graphic>
7882 </figure>
7883 <para>
7884 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
7885 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
7886 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: <emphasis>No one ever
7887 died from copyright circumvention</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
7888 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
7889 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
7890 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
7891 </para>
7892 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7893 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
7894 <indexterm>
7895 <primary>Sony</primary>
7896 <secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary>
7897 </indexterm>
7898 <para>
7899 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
7900 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
7901 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
7902 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
7903 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
7904 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
7905 </para>
7906 <para>
7907 This is how <emphasis>code</emphasis> becomes
7908 <emphasis>law</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
7909 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
7910 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
7911 law&mdash;increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
7912 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
7913 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
7914 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect&mdash;at
7915 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
7916 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
7917 </para>
7918 <para>
7919 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
7920 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
7921 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
7922 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
7923 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
7924 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
7925 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
7926 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
7927 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
7928 </para>
7929 <para>
7930
7931 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
7932 For example, imagine you were part of a <citetitle>Star Trek</citetitle> fan club. You
7933 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
7934 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
7935 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
7936 simply continue it.<footnote><para>
7937 <!-- f24 -->
7938 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, <quote>Legal Fictions,
7939 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
7940 Entertainment Law Journal</citetitle> 17 (1997): 651.
7941 </para></footnote>
7942 </para>
7943 <para>
7944 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
7945 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
7946 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
7947 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
7948 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
7949 </para>
7950 <para>
7951 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
7952 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
7953 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
7954 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
7955 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
7956 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
7957 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
7958 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
7959 </para>
7960 <para>
7961 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
7962 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
7963 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
7964 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
7965 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
7966 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
7967 </para>
7968 </section>
7969 <section id="marketconcentration">
7970 <title>Market: Concentration</title>
7971 <para>
7972 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically&mdash;tripled in
7973 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
7974 well&mdash;from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
7975 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
7976 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
7977 find better ways
7978 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
7979 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
7980 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
7981 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
7982 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
7983 market for creative work, has become the single most important
7984 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
7985 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
7986 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
7987 control.
7988 </para>
7989 <para>
7990 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
7991 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
7992 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
7993 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
7994 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
7995 </para>
7996 <para>
7997 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
7998 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
7999 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8000 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8001 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8002 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8003 announced in June 2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8004 live in a world where just three companies control more than percent
8005 of the media.
8006 </para>
8007 <para>
8008 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8009 nature.
8010 </para>
8011 <para>
8012 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8013 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8014 ownership, <quote>five companies control 85 percent of our media sources.</quote><footnote><para>
8015 <!-- f25 -->
8016 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8017 Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003)
8018 (statement of Senator John McCain). </para></footnote>
8019 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8020 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 percent of the
8021 U.S. music market.<footnote><para>
8022 <!-- f26 -->
8023 Lynette Holloway, <quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8024 Slide,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 23 December 2002.
8025 </para></footnote>
8026 The <quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8027 programming to 74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.</quote><footnote><para>
8028 <!-- f27 -->
8029 Molly Ivins, <quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette</citetitle>,
8030 31 May 2003.
8031 </para></footnote>
8032 <indexterm><primary>BMG</primary></indexterm>
8033 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
8034 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John</primary></indexterm>
8035 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8036 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8037 </para>
8038 <para>
8039 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8040 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8042 seventy-five stations. Today <emphasis>one</emphasis> company owns
8043 more than 1,200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8044 total number of radio owners dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most
8045 markets, the two largest broadcasters control 74 percent of that
8046 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control 90 percent of
8047 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8048 </para>
8049 <para>
8050 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8051 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8052 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8053 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8054 the United States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all
8055 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent
8056 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8057 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8058 protected&mdash; by the market.
8059 </para>
8060 <para>
8061 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8062 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8063 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8064 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8065 </para>
8066 <blockquote>
8067 <para>
8068 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8069 unmatched in its integration. They supply content&mdash;Fox movies
8070 &hellip; Fox TV shows &hellip; Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8071 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8072 advertisers&mdash;in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8073 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8074 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8075 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8076 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8077 the same function in the United States.<footnote><para>
8078 <!-- f28 -->
8079 James Fallows, <quote>The Age of Murdoch,</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly</citetitle> (September
8080 2003): 89.
8081 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8082 </para></footnote>
8083 </para>
8084 </blockquote>
8085 <para>
8086 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8087 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8088 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8089 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8090 </para>
8091 <figure id="fig-1761">
8092 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.</title>
8093 <graphic fileref="images/1761.png"></graphic>
8094 </figure>
8095 <para>
8096 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8097 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8098 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8099 distribute content?
8100 </para>
8101 <para>
8102 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8103 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8104 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8105 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8106 </para>
8107 <para>
8108 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8109 integration may matter.
8110 </para>
8111 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman</primary></indexterm>
8112 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8113 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8114 <para>
8115 In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle>. He took
8116 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8117 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8118 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8119 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8120 </para>
8121 <para>
8122 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8123 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8124 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8125 control.<footnote><para>
8126 <!-- f29 -->
8127 Leonard Hill, <quote>The Axis of Access,</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8128 Forum, <quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,</quote> St. Louis,
8129 Missouri, 3 April 2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8130 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #28</ulink>;
8131 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8132 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #29</ulink>).
8133 </para></footnote>
8134 </para>
8135 <para>
8136
8137 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8138 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8139 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8140 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8141 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992,
8142 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8143 television&mdash;75 percent of it&mdash;was <quote>independent</quote> of the
8144 networks.
8145 </para>
8146 <para>
8147 In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8148 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985,
8149 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8150 2002, only five independent television studios remained. <quote>In 1992,
8151 only 15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8152 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8153 controlled companies more than quintupled to 77 percent.</quote> <quote>In 1992, 16
8154 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8155 year there was one.</quote><footnote><para>
8156 <!-- f30 -->
8157 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8158 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st
8159 sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8160 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8161 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8162 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8163 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February
8164 2003.
8165 </para></footnote>
8166 In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8167 that ran it. <quote>In the ten-year period between 1992 and 2002, the number
8168 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8169 increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8170 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8171 63%.</quote><footnote><para>
8172 <!-- f31 -->
8173 Ibid.
8174 </para></footnote>
8175 </para>
8176 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8177 <para>
8178 Today, another Norman Lear with another <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle> would
8179 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8180 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8181 owned by the network.
8182 </para>
8183 <para>
8184 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8185 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8186 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8187 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry</primary></indexterm>
8188 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill</primary></indexterm>
8189 </para>
8190 <blockquote>
8191 <para>
8192 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8193 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8194 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8195 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8196 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8197 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8198 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8199 handful.<footnote><para>
8200 <!-- f32 -->
8201 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers</citetitle>, Bill
8202 Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at
8203 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #31</ulink>.
8204 </para></footnote>
8205 </para>
8206 </blockquote>
8207 <para>
8208 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8209 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8210 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8211 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8212 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8213 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8214 question without risk of consequence&mdash;not necessarily banishment
8215 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8216 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8217 democracy.
8218 </para>
8219 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.</primary></indexterm>
8220 <para>
8221 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8222 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the <quote>Innovator's
8223 Dilemma</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8224 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8225 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8226 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.<footnote><para>
8227 <!-- f33 -->
8228 Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8229 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle>
8230 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press, 1997). Christensen
8231 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8232 Kim B. Clark, <quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8233 Concepts in Technological Evolution,</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy</citetitle> 14 (1985):
8234 235&ndash;51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8235 Kaplan, <citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8236 Underperform the Market&mdash;and How to Successfully Transform Them</citetitle>
8237 (New York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001). </para></footnote>
8238
8239 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8240 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8241 sprinting.
8242 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
8243 </para>
8244 <para>
8245 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8246 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8247 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8248 measure.
8249 </para>
8250 <para>
8251 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8252 suggest the concern.
8253 </para>
8254 <para>
8255 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8256 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8257 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8258 </para>
8259 <para>
8260 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8261 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8262 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8263
8264 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8265 wrecked by drugs&mdash;though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8266 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8267 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8268 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8269 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8270 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8271 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8272 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8273 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8274 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8275 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8276 outweigh these costs.
8277 </para>
8278 <para>
8279 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8280 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8281 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8282 these issues.
8283 </para>
8284 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'>
8285 <primary>advertising</primary>
8286 </indexterm>
8287 <para>
8288 Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8289 a media campaign as part of the <quote>war on drugs.</quote> The campaign produced
8290 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8291 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8292 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8293 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8294 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8295 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8296 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8297 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8298 </para>
8299 <para>
8300 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8301 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8302 </para>
8303 <para>
8304 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8305 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8306 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8307 war. Can you do it?
8308 </para>
8309 <para>
8310 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8311 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8312 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8313 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8314 message will be heard then?
8315 </para>
8316 <para>
8317 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8318 <quote>controversial</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8319 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8320 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8321 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8322 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8323 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8324 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8325 rights of the stations to be this biased.<footnote><para>
8326 <!-- f34 -->
8327 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads
8328 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8329 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as <quote>against
8330 [their] policy.</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8331 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8332 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8333 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8334 Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8335 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, <quote>On the Issue of
8336 an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV Networks,</quote> <citetitle>New
8337 York Times</citetitle>, 13 March 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time
8338 there is very little that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to
8339 even the playing field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, <quote>Ad
8340 Hoc Access: The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8341 Radio,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review</citetitle> 6 (1988): 449&ndash;79, and for a
8342 more recent summary of the stance of the FCC and the courts, see
8343 <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors Association</citetitle> v. <citetitle>FCC</citetitle>, 184 F. 3d 872
8344 (D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8345 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8346 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8347 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, <quote>Antidiesel Group Fuming
8348 After Muni Rejects Ad,</quote> SFGate.com, 16 June 2003, available at
8349 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #32</ulink>. The ground
8350 was that the criticism was <quote>too controversial.</quote>
8351 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8352 <indexterm><primary>Comcast</primary></indexterm>
8353 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project</primary></indexterm>
8354 <indexterm><primary>NBC</primary></indexterm>
8355 <indexterm><primary>WJOA</primary></indexterm>
8356 <indexterm><primary>WRC</primary></indexterm>
8357 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8358 </para></footnote>
8359 </para>
8360 <para>
8361 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well&mdash;if we lived
8362 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8363 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8364 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8365 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8366 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8367 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8368 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8369 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8370 </para>
8371 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'/>
8372 </section>
8373 <section id="together">
8374 <title>Together</title>
8375 <para>
8376 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8377 copyright warriors that the government should <quote>protect my property.</quote>
8378 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8379 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8380 </para>
8381 <para>
8382 But when we see how dramatically this <quote>property</quote> has changed&mdash;
8383 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8384 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8385 cultivate our culture is dramatically different&mdash;the claim begins
8386 to seem
8387
8388 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8389 less innocent and obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to
8390 supplement the law's control, and (2) the power of concentrated
8391 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8392 the massively expanded <quote>property</quote> rights granted by copyright
8393 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8394 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8395 be redefined.
8396 </para>
8397 <para>
8398 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8399 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8400 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8401 our culture today.
8402 </para>
8403 <para>
8404 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8405 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8406 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8407 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8408 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8409 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8410 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8411 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8412 traditionally defined copyright's regulation&mdash;a weakening of that
8413 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
8414 </para>
8415 <para>
8416 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
8417 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
8418 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
8419 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
8420 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
8421 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
8422 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
8423 future. And these changes have to be <emphasis>reductions</emphasis>
8424 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
8425 in control that technology and the market enable.
8426 </para>
8427 <para>
8428 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
8429 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
8430 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
8431 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
8432 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
8433 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
8434 more of the development of our culture than now</emphasis>.
8435 </para>
8436 <para>
8437 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
8438 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
8439 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
8440 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
8441 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
8442 were independent of the networks. <emphasis>Never</emphasis> has
8443 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
8444 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
8445 regulation&mdash;a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
8446 energy of a nation at the founding&mdash;is now a massive regulation
8447 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
8448 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
8449 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
8450 known.<footnote><para>
8451 <!-- f35 -->
8452 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his <quote>four surrenders</quote> of
8453 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan, 159&ndash;60.
8454 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
8455 </para></footnote>
8456 </para>
8457 <para>
8458 This has been a long chapter. Its point can now be briefly stated.
8459 </para>
8460 <para>
8461 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
8462 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
8463 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
8464 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
8465 that copyright law has undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this:
8466 </para>
8467
8468 <informaltable id="t2">
8469 <tgroup cols="3" align="char">
8470 <thead>
8471 <row>
8472 <entry></entry>
8473 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
8474 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8475 </row>
8476 </thead>
8477 <tbody>
8478 <row>
8479 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8480 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8481 <entry>Free</entry>
8482 </row>
8483 <row>
8484 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8485 <entry>Free</entry>
8486 <entry>Free</entry>
8487 </row>
8488 </tbody>
8489 </tgroup>
8490 </informaltable>
8491
8492 <para>
8493 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
8494 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
8495 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
8496
8497 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
8498 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
8499 noncommercial work was also free.
8500 </para>
8501 <para>
8502 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
8503 </para>
8504
8505 <informaltable id="t3">
8506 <tgroup cols="3" align="char">
8507 <thead>
8508 <row>
8509 <entry></entry>
8510 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
8511 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8512 </row>
8513 </thead>
8514 <tbody>
8515 <row>
8516 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8517 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8518 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8519 </row>
8520 <row>
8521 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8522 <entry>Free</entry>
8523 <entry>Free</entry>
8524 </row>
8525 </tbody>
8526 </tgroup>
8527 </informaltable>
8528
8529 <para>
8530 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law&mdash;if
8531 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
8532 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
8533 transformation were still essentially free.
8534 </para>
8535 <para>
8536 In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
8537 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
8538 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
8539 expanded. Thus by 1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
8540 we could say the law began to look like this:
8541 </para>
8542
8543 <informaltable id="t4">
8544 <tgroup cols="3" align="char">
8545 <thead>
8546 <row>
8547 <entry></entry>
8548 <entry>COPY</entry>
8549 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8550 </row>
8551 </thead>
8552 <tbody>
8553 <row>
8554 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8555 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8556 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8557 </row>
8558 <row>
8559 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8560 <entry>&copy;/Free</entry>
8561 <entry>Free</entry>
8562 </row>
8563 </tbody>
8564 </tgroup>
8565 </informaltable>
8566
8567 <para>
8568 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
8569 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
8570 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
8571 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
8572 that the law now looks like this:
8573 </para>
8574
8575 <informaltable id="t5">
8576 <tgroup cols="3" align="char">
8577 <thead>
8578 <row>
8579 <entry></entry>
8580 <entry>COPY</entry>
8581 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
8582 </row>
8583 </thead>
8584 <tbody>
8585 <row>
8586 <entry>Commercial</entry>
8587 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8588 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8589 </row>
8590 <row>
8591 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
8592 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8593 <entry>&copy;</entry>
8594 </row>
8595 </tbody>
8596 </tgroup>
8597 </informaltable>
8598
8599 <para>
8600 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
8601 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
8602 creativity&mdash;
8603 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
8604 commercial or not, transformative or not&mdash;with the same rules
8605 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
8606 </para>
8607 <para>
8608 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
8609 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
8610 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
8611 these domains actually does any good.
8612 </para>
8613 <para>
8614 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
8615 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
8616 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
8617 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
8618 reasons sketched especially in chapters
8619 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/> and
8620 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>, one
8621 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
8622 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
8623 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
8624 </para>
8625 <para>
8626 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
8627 course copyright is a kind of <quote>property,</quote> and of course, as with any
8628 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
8629 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
8630 property rights<footnote><para>
8631 <!-- f36 -->
8632 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
8633 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
8634 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, <quote>The
8635 Disintegration of Property,</quote> in <citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property</citetitle>, J. Roland
8636 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
8637 Press, 1980).
8638 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement</primary></indexterm>
8639 </para></footnote>)
8640 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
8641 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
8642 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
8643 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the <quote>copyright</quote>
8644 did not control <emphasis>at all</emphasis> the freedom of others to
8645 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
8646 free, and for almost 180 years our country consistently protected a
8647 vibrant and rich free culture.
8648 </para>
8649 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
8650 <para>
8651 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
8652 limits on the scope of the interests protected by <quote>property.</quote> The very
8653 birth of <quote>copyright</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
8654 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
8655 story of chapter 6). The tradition of <quote>fair use</quote> is animated by a
8656 similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the costs of
8657 exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the story of
8658 chapter 7). Adding
8659 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
8660 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
8661 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter
8662 8). And granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect,
8663 claims of property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing
8664 the soul of a culture (chapter 9). Free cultures, like free markets,
8665 are built with property. But the nature of the property that builds a
8666 free culture is very different from the extremist vision that
8667 dominates the debate today.
8668 </para>
8669 <para>
8670 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
8671 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
8672 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
8673 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
8674 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
8675 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
8676 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
8677 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
8678 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
8679 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
8680 lawyer.
8681 </para>
8682 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
8683 </section>
8684 </chapter>
8685 </part>
8686 <part id="c-puzzles">
8687 <title>PUZZLES</title>
8688
8689 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
8690 <chapter label="11" id="chimera">
8691 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera</title>
8692 <indexterm id="idxchimera" class='startofrange'>
8693 <primary>chimeras</primary>
8694 </indexterm>
8695 <indexterm id="idxwells" class='startofrange'>
8696 <primary>Wells, H. G.</primary>
8697 </indexterm>
8698 <indexterm id="idxtcotb" class='startofrange'>
8699 <primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The</quote> (Wells)</primary>
8700 </indexterm>
8701
8702 <para>
8703 In a well-known short story by H. G. Wells, a mountain climber
8704 named Nunez trips (literally, down an ice slope) into an unknown and
8705 isolated valley in the Peruvian Andes.<footnote><para>
8706 <!-- f1. -->
8707 H. G. Wells, <quote>The Country of the Blind</quote> (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells,
8708 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
8709 York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
8710 </para></footnote>
8711 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with <quote>sweet water, pasture,
8712 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
8713 that bore an excellent fruit.</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
8714 takes this as an opportunity. <quote>In the Country of the Blind,</quote> he tells
8715 himself, <quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.</quote> So he resolves to live with the
8716 villagers to explore life as a king.
8717 </para>
8718 <para>
8719 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
8720 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
8721 <quote>blind.</quote> They don't have the word <citetitle>blind</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
8722 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
8723 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
8724 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. <quote>`You
8725 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
8726 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
8727 alone!'</quote>
8728 </para>
8729 <para>
8730 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
8731 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
8732 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
8733 affection, a young woman who to him seems <quote>the most beautiful thing in
8734 the whole of creation,</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
8735 description of what he sees <quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
8736 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
8737 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
8738 indulgence.</quote> <quote>She did not believe,</quote> Wells tells us, and <quote>she could
8739 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.</quote>
8740 </para>
8741 <para>
8742 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his <quote>mysteriously delighted</quote>
8743 love, the father and the village object. <quote>You see, my dear,</quote> her
8744 father instructs, <quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
8745 anything right.</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
8746 </para>
8747 <para>
8748 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. <quote>His brain
8749 is affected,</quote> he reports.
8750 </para>
8751 <para>
8752 <quote>What affects it?</quote> the father asks. <quote>Those queer things that are
8753 called the eyes &hellip; are diseased &hellip; in such a way as to affect
8754 his brain.</quote>
8755 </para>
8756 <para>
8757 The doctor continues: <quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
8758 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
8759 simple and easy surgical operation&mdash;namely, to remove these
8760 irritant bodies [the eyes].</quote>
8761 </para>
8762 <para>
8763 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
8764 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
8765 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
8766 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
8767 It sometimes happens that the eggs of twins fuse in the mother's
8768 womb. That fusion produces a <quote>chimera.</quote> A chimera is a single creature
8769 with two sets of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be
8770 different from the DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
8771
8772 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
8773 plot for murder mysteries. <quote>But the DNA shows with 100 percent
8774 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
8775 scene. &hellip;</quote>
8776 </para>
8777 <indexterm startref="idxtcotb" class='endofrange'/>
8778 <indexterm startref="idxwells" class="endofrange"/>
8779 <para>
8780 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
8781 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
8782 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
8783 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
8784 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
8785 understanding of a <quote>person</quote> should reflect this reality.
8786 </para>
8787 <para>
8788 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
8789 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
8790 unfairly enough, <quote>the copyright wars,</quote> the more I think we're dealing
8791 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question <quote>What is
8792 p2p file sharing?</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
8793 wrong. One side says, <quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
8794 others' records&mdash;the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
8795 thirty years without any question at all.</quote> That's true, at least in
8796 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
8797 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
8798 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
8799 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
8800 </para>
8801 <para>
8802 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
8803 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
8804 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
8805 <quote>friends</quote> beyond recognition to say <quote>my ten thousand best friends</quote> can
8806 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
8807 what <quote>we have always been allowed to do,</quote> we have not always been
8808 allowed to share music with <quote>our ten thousand best friends.</quote>
8809 </para>
8810 <para>
8811 Likewise, when the other side says, <quote>File sharing is just like walking
8812 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
8813 with it,</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
8814 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
8815 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
8816 from Tower.
8817 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
8818 </para>
8819 <para>
8820
8821 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
8822 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
8823 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
8824 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
8825 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
8826 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
8827 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
8828 $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
8829 CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.)
8830 </para>
8831 <para>
8832 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
8833 that it is both&mdash;both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
8834 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
8835 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
8836 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
8837 </para>
8838 <para>
8839 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
8840 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
8841 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
8842 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
8843 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
8844 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
8845 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
8846 implemented.<footnote><para>
8847 <!-- f2. -->
8848 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
8849 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
8850 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003,
8851 available at
8852 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
8853 #33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
8854 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
8855 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
8856 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, <quote>House Bill Aims to Up
8857 Stakes on Piracy,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 17 July 2003, available at
8858 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #34</ulink>. Civil
8859 penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied song. For a recent
8860 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
8861 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 songs
8862 through a family computer, see <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
8863 re. Verizon Internet Services)</citetitle>, 240 F. Supp. 2d 24
8864 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $90
8865 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
8866 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
8867 $12,000 to $17,500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
8868 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $98
8869 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
8870 Elizabeth Young, <quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,</quote> redandblack.com,
8871 August 2003, available at
8872 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #35</ulink>. For an
8873 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
8874 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
8875 identities, see James Collins, <quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
8876 Name Students,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 8 August 2003, D3, available at
8877 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #36</ulink>.
8878 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
8879 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
8880 </para></footnote>
8881
8882 </para>
8883 <indexterm startref="idxchimera" class='endofrange'/>
8884 <para>
8885 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
8886 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
8887 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
8888 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
8889 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
8890 </para>
8891 <para>
8892 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
8893 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
8894 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
8895 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
8896 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
8897 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe <emphasis>either</emphasis> extreme
8898 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
8899 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
8900 </para>
8901 <para>
8902
8903 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
8904 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
8905 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
8906 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
8907 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
8908 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
8909 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
8910 </para>
8911 <para>
8912 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to <quote>steal</quote> music. My
8913 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
8914 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
8915 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
8916 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
8917 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
8918 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
8919 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
8920 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
8921 protection for copyrighted material,
8922 </para>
8923 <blockquote>
8924 <para>
8925 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
8926 material, and we want to protect those rights.
8927 </para>
8928 <para>
8929 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
8930 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
8931 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
8932 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
8933 produce a totally different industry model.
8934 </para>
8935 <para>
8936 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
8937 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
8938 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
8939 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
8940 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
8941 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
8942 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
8943 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
8944 interests.<footnote><para>
8945 <!-- f3. -->
8946 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
8947 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
8948 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
8949 House Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement of Peter
8950 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
8951 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
8952 Congressional Testimony File. </para></footnote>
8953 </para>
8954 </blockquote>
8955 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
8956 <para>
8957 In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
8958 one of <quote>the major labels.</quote> Its position on these matters has now
8959 changed.
8960 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
8961 </para>
8962 <para>
8963 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
8964 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
8965 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
8966 </para>
8967
8968 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
8969 </chapter>
8970 <chapter label="12" id="harms">
8971 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms</title>
8972 <para>
8973 To fight <quote>piracy,</quote> to protect <quote>property,</quote> the content industry has
8974 launched a war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now
8975 brought the government into this war. As with any war, this one will
8976 have both direct and collateral damage. As with any war of
8977 prohibition, these damages will be suffered most by our own people.
8978 </para>
8979 <para>
8980 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
8981 particular, the consequences for <quote>free culture.</quote> But my aim now is to
8982 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
8983 justified?
8984 </para>
8985 <para>
8986 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
8987 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
8988 power of the property called <quote>intellectual property</quote> is at its greatest in
8989 our history.
8990 </para>
8991 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
8992 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
8993 <para>
8994 Yet <quote>common sense</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
8995 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
8996 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
8997 rejection of <quote>piracy</quote> still has play.
8998 </para>
8999 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9000 <para>
9001 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9002 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9003 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9004 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9005 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9006 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9007 </para>
9008 <section id="constrain">
9009 <title>Constraining Creators</title>
9010 <para>
9011 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9012 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9013 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9014 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9015 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9016 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9017 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9018 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9019 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9020 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9021 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9022 weave together a string&mdash;a mash-up&mdash; of songs from your
9023 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9024 </para>
9025 <para>
9026 This digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> is in part an extension of the
9027 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9028 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9029 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9030 of digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9031 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9032 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9033 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9034 the culture all around.
9035 </para>
9036 <para>
9037 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9038 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9039
9040 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9041
9042 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9043 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9044 storytelling extended across the globe.
9045 </para>
9046 <para>
9047 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9048 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9049 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9050 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9051 that catalog cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9052 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9053 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9054 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9055 work is presumptively illegal.
9056 </para>
9057 <para>
9058 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9059 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9060 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9061 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9062 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9063 by the RIAA ( Jesse Jordan of chapter 3 was just one) were threatened
9064 with a $98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted
9065 songs to be copied. Yet World-Com&mdash;which defrauded investors of
9066 $11 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization
9067 of over $200 billion&mdash;received a fine of a mere $750
9068 million.<footnote><para>
9069 <!-- f1. -->
9070 See Lynne W. Jeter, <citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom</citetitle>
9071 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley &amp; Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of
9072 the settlement, see MCI press release, <quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9073 Approval for SEC Settlement</quote> (7 July 2003), available at
9074 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #37</ulink>.
9075 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom</primary></indexterm>
9076 </para></footnote>
9077 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9078 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9079 no more than $250,000 in damages for pain and
9080 suffering.<footnote>
9081 <para>
9082 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9083 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For
9084 an overview, see Tanya Albert, <quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9085 Say Tort Reformers,</quote> amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at
9086 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #38</ulink>,
9087 and <quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,</quote> CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003,
9088 available at
9089 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9090 recent months.
9091 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.</primary></indexterm>
9092 </para></footnote>
9093 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9094 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9095 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9096 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom</primary></indexterm>
9097 </para>
9098 <indexterm><primary>art, underground</primary></indexterm>
9099 <para>
9100 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9101 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9102 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9103 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9104 Disneys <quote>pirates.</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9105 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9106 designed to
9107
9108 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9109 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9110 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9111 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9112 we will begin to see a world of underground art&mdash;not because the
9113 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9114 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9115 fraught. Already, exhibits of <quote>illegal art</quote> tour the United
9116 States.<footnote><para>
9117 <!-- f3. -->
9118
9119 See Danit Lidor, <quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,</quote> <citetitle>Wired</citetitle>, 7 July
9120 2003, available at
9121 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9122 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #41</ulink>.
9123 </para></footnote>
9124 In what does their <quote>illegality</quote> consist?
9125 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9126 critical or reflective.
9127 </para>
9128 <para>
9129 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9130 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9131 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. But an
9132 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9133 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9134 discovered in 2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9135 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9136 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9137 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9138 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9139 </para>
9140 <para>
9141 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9142 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9143 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9144 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9145 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9146 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9147 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9148 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9149 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9150 </para>
9151 <para>
9152 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9153 described in chapter
9154 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/>, in
9155 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9156 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9157 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9158 use.
9159 </para>
9160 <para>
9161
9162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9163 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9164 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9165 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad&mdash;in
9166 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9167 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9168 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9169 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9170 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9171 </para>
9172 <para>
9173 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9174 <quote>breathing room</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9175 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9176 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9177 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9178 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9179 journalists&mdash; these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9180 these rules have little relationship to the <quote>law</quote> with which judges
9181 comfort themselves.
9182 </para>
9183 <para>
9184 For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful
9185 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9186 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9187 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9188 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak&mdash;in that
9189 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9190 <quote>copyright</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9191 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9192 culture that is free.
9193 </para>
9194 <para>
9195 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9196 </para>
9197 <blockquote>
9198 <para>
9199 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9200 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9201 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9202 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made &hellip; you're not
9203 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9204 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9205 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, <quote>This has been
9206 cleared.</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9207 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9208 </para>
9209 </blockquote>
9210 </section>
9211 <section id="innovators">
9212 <title>Constraining Innovators</title>
9213 <para>
9214 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9215 story&mdash;creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9216 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9217 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9218 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9219 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9220 </para>
9221 <para>
9222 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9223 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9224 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9225 one at that, 188 pages into a book like this), then you can see this
9226 other aspect by substituting <quote>free market</quote> every place I've spoken of
9227 <quote>free culture.</quote> The point is the same, even if the interests
9228 affecting culture are more fundamental.
9229 </para>
9230 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9231 <para>
9232 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9233 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9234 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary&mdash;at
9235 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9236 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9237 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9238 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9239 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9240 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9241 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9242 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9243 </para>
9244 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9245 <para>
9246 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9247 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9248 strategy that I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9249 labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9250 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9251 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9252 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9253 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9254 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9255 lesson. That lesson&mdash;what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9256 <quote>nuclear pall</quote> that has fallen over the Valley&mdash;has been learned.
9257 </para>
9258 <para>
9259 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9260 I told in <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9261 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9262 </para>
9263 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael</primary></indexterm>
9264 <para>
9265 In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9266 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9267 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9268 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9269 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9270 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9271 </para>
9272 <para>
9273 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9274 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9275 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9276 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9277 Raitt. And so on.
9278 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9279 </para>
9280 <para>
9281 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9282 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9283 preference data. In January 2000, the company launched a service
9284 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9285 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9286 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9287 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9288 wherever you were&mdash;at work or at home&mdash;you could get access
9289 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9290 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9291 </para>
9292 <para>
9293 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9294 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9295
9296 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9297 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9298 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9299 the kind of content the users liked.
9300 </para>
9301 <para>
9302 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000
9303 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9304 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9305 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9306 therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9307 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9308 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9309 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was 50,000
9310 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers something
9311 they had already bought.
9312 </para>
9313 <indexterm id="idxvivendiuniversal" class='startofrange'>
9314 <primary>Vivendi Universal</primary>
9315 </indexterm>
9316 <para>
9317 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9318 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9319 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9320 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9321 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9322 MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9323 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $54 million. Vivendi
9324 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9325 </para>
9326 <para>
9327 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9328 </para>
9329 <para>
9330 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9331 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9332 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9333 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9334 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9335 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9336 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9337 demanded.
9338 </para>
9339 <para>
9340 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9341 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9342 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9343 clients in this
9344 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9345 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9346 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9347 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9348 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9349 </para>
9350 <indexterm startref="idxvivendiuniversal" class='endofrange'/>
9351 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John</primary></indexterm>
9352 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9353 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad</primary></indexterm>
9354 <para>
9355 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003,
9356 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9357 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9358 its development, its cofounder ( John Hummer), and general partner
9359 (Hank Barry).<footnote><para>
9360 <!-- f4. -->
9361 See Joseph Menn, <quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9362 Times</citetitle>, 23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9363 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, <quote>The Music
9364 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,</quote> Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available
9365 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #42</ulink>.
9366 See also Jon Healey, <quote>Online Music Services Besieged,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9367 Times</citetitle>, 28 May 2001.
9368 </para></footnote>
9369 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
9370 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
9371 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
9372 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
9373 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
9374 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
9375 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
9376 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
9377 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
9378 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
9379 <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
9380 discussion with BMW:
9381 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
9382 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
9383 </para>
9384 <blockquote>
9385 <indexterm><primary>BMW</primary></indexterm>
9386 <para>
9387 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
9388 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
9389 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
9390 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
9391 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
9392 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
9393 United States with bona fide MP3 players. &hellip; <footnote>
9394 <para>
9395 <!-- f5. -->
9396 Rafe Needleman, <quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,</quote> <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, 16 June
9397 2003, available at
9398 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #43</ulink>. I am grateful
9399 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
9400 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
9401 </para></footnote>
9402 </para>
9403 </blockquote>
9404 <para>
9405 This is the world of the mafia&mdash;filled with <quote>your money or your
9406 life</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
9407 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
9408 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
9409 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
9410 constantly threatened by litigation.
9411 </para>
9412 <para>
9413
9414 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
9415 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
9416 enterprises. The point is the definition of <quote>illegal.</quote> The law is a
9417 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
9418 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
9419 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
9420 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
9421 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
9422 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
9423 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
9424 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
9425 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
9426 much less creativity.
9427 </para>
9428 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9429 <para>
9430 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
9431 use. Whatever the <quote>real</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
9432 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
9433 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
9434 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
9435 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
9436 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
9437 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
9438 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
9439 produce an overregulatedregulated market.
9440 </para>
9441 <para>
9442 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
9443 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
9444 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
9445 culture&mdash;a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
9446 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
9447 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
9448 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
9449 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
9450 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
9451 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
9452 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
9453 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
9454 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
9455 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
9456 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
9457 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
9458 result. The uncertainty of the law is one burden on innovation. There
9459 is a second burden that operates more directly. This is the effort by
9460 many in the content industry to use the law to directly regulate the
9461 technology of the Internet so that it better protects their content.
9462 </para>
9463 <para>
9464 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
9465 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
9466 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
9467 this feature is a <quote>bug.</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
9468 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
9469 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
9470 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables <quote>piracy,</quote> then,
9471 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
9472 </para>
9473 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
9474 <para>
9475 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
9476 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
9477 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
9478 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.<footnote><para>
9479 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> GartnerG2 and
9480 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
9481 (2003), 33&ndash;35, available at
9482 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
9483 </para></footnote>
9484 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
9485 <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
9486 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
9487 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
9488 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
9489 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
9490 copyright violators and disable their machines.<footnote><para>
9491 <!-- f7. -->
9492 GartnerG2, 26&ndash;27.
9493 </para></footnote>
9494 </para>
9495 <para>
9496 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
9497 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
9498 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
9499 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
9500 and costs on
9501 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
9502 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
9503 those requirements.
9504 </para>
9505 <para>
9506 In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
9507 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
9508 would impose.<footnote><para>
9509 <!-- f8. -->
9510 See David McGuire, <quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,</quote> Newsbytes,
9511 February 2002 (Entertainment).
9512 </para></footnote>
9513 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
9514 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
9515 harm than good.
9516 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
9517 </para>
9518 <para>
9519 There is one more obvious way in which this war has harmed
9520 innovation&mdash;again, a story that will be quite familiar to the
9521 free market crowd.
9522 </para>
9523 <para>
9524 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
9525 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
9526 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
9527 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
9528 </para>
9529 <para>
9530 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9531 linkend="property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
9532 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
9533 Jessica Litman in her book <citetitle>Digital
9534 Copyright</citetitle>,<footnote><para>
9535 <!-- f9. -->
9536 Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (Amherst,
9537 N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 2001).
9538 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
9539 </para></footnote>
9540 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter 10 details,
9541 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
9542 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
9543 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
9544 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
9545 </para>
9546 <para>
9547 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
9548 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
9549 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
9550 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
9551 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
9552 </para>
9553 <para>
9554 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.<footnote><para>
9555 <!-- f10. -->
9556 The only circuit court exception is found in <citetitle>Recording Industry
9557 Association of America (RIAA)</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems</citetitle>, 180 F. 3d
9558 1072 (9th Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
9559 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
9560 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
9561 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
9562 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
9563 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
9564 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Grokster, Ltd</citetitle>., 259 F. Supp. 2d
9565 1029 (C.D. Cal., 2003), where the court found the link between the
9566 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
9567 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
9568 liability.
9569 </para></footnote>
9570 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
9571 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
9572 here.<footnote><para>
9573 <!-- f11. -->
9574 For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
9575 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize
9576 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
9577 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
9578 August 2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
9579 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
9580 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that
9581 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
9582 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
9583 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
9584 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, <quote>Copyright and
9585 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003, 33&ndash;34,
9586 available at
9587 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
9588 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
9589 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz</primary></indexterm>
9590 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
9591 </para></footnote>
9592 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
9593 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
9594 </para>
9595 <indexterm>
9596 <primary>artists</primary>
9597 <secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary>
9598 </indexterm>
9599 <para>
9600
9601 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
9602 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9603 linkend="pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
9604 artist doesn't get paid for that <quote>radio performance</quote> unless he or she
9605 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
9606 version of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote>&mdash;to memorialize her famous
9607 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden&mdash;
9608 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
9609 copyright owners of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> would get some money, whereas
9610 Marilyn Monroe would not.
9611 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
9612 </para>
9613 <para>
9614 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
9615 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
9616 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
9617 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
9618 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
9619 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
9620 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
9621 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
9622 recording artists.
9623 </para>
9624 <para>
9625 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
9626 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
9627 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
9628 spectrum. Thus, I can <quote>tune in</quote> to an Internet radio station in
9629 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
9630 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
9631 metropolitan area.
9632 </para>
9633 <para>
9634 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
9635 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
9636 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
9637 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
9638 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
9639 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
9640 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
9641 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
9642 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
9643 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
9644 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
9645 </para>
9646 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9647 <para>
9648
9649 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
9650 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
9651 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
9652 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
9653 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
9654 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
9655 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
9656 FM radio,
9657 </para>
9658 <blockquote>
9659 <para>
9660 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
9661 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
9662 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
9663 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
9664 than by technical restrictions. &hellip; Armstrong likened the situation
9665 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
9666 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
9667 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
9668 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
9669 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
9670 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
9671 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
9672 shackles.<footnote><para>
9673 <!-- f12. -->
9674 Lessing, 239.
9675 </para></footnote>
9676 </para>
9677 </blockquote>
9678 <para>
9679 This potential for FM radio was never realized&mdash;not
9680 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
9681 underestimated the power of <quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
9682 legislation</quote><footnote><para>
9683 <!-- f13. -->
9684 Ibid., 229.
9685 </para></footnote>
9686 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
9687 </para>
9688 <para>
9689 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
9690 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
9691 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
9692 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
9693 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
9694 radio?
9695 </para>
9696 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments2' class='startofrange'>
9697 <primary>artists</primary>
9698 <secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary>
9699 </indexterm>
9700 <para>
9701 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
9702 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
9703
9704 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
9705 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
9706 of Internet radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
9707 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
9708 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
9709 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
9710 of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> on the air, <emphasis>Internet radio
9711 does</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
9712 radio&mdash;the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
9713 burdens terrestrial radio.
9714 </para>
9715 <para>
9716 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
9717 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
9718 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
9719 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
9720 over $1 million a year.<footnote>
9721 <para>
9722 <!-- f14. -->
9723 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
9724 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
9725 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
9726 iLaw (Stanford), 3 July 2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
9727 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
9728 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
9729 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP
9730 DTRA 1 and 2, available at
9731 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #45</ulink>.
9732 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
9733 C. Picker, <quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
9734 Distribution,</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin</citetitle> (Summer/Fall 2002): 461: <quote>This was
9735 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
9736 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
9737 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
9738 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
9739 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.</quote>
9740 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)</primary></indexterm>
9741 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
9742 </para></footnote>
9743 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
9744 equivalent fee.
9745 </para>
9746 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments2' class='endofrange'/>
9747 <para>
9748 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
9749 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
9750 station) would have to collect the following data from <emphasis>every
9751 listening transaction</emphasis>:
9752 </para>
9753 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
9754 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
9755 <listitem><para>
9756 name of the service;
9757 </para></listitem>
9758 <listitem><para>
9759 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
9760 </para></listitem>
9761 <listitem><para>
9762 type of program (archived/looped/live);
9763 </para></listitem>
9764 <listitem><para>
9765 date of transmission;
9766 </para></listitem>
9767 <listitem><para>
9768 time of transmission;
9769 </para></listitem>
9770 <listitem><para>
9771 time zone of origination of transmission;
9772 </para></listitem>
9773 <listitem><para>
9774 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
9775 </para></listitem>
9776 <listitem><para>
9777 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
9778 </para></listitem>
9779 <listitem><para>
9780 sound recording title;
9781 </para></listitem>
9782 <listitem><para>
9783 ISRC code of the recording;
9784 </para></listitem>
9785 <listitem><para>
9786 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
9787 </para></listitem>
9788 <listitem><para>
9789 featured recording artist;
9790 </para></listitem>
9791 <listitem><para>
9792 retail album title;
9793 </para></listitem>
9794 <listitem><para>
9795 recording label;
9796 </para></listitem>
9797 <listitem><para>
9798 UPC code of the retail album;
9799 </para></listitem>
9800 <listitem><para>
9801 catalog number;
9802 </para></listitem>
9803 <listitem><para>
9804 copyright owner information;
9805 </para></listitem>
9806 <listitem><para>
9807 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
9808 </para></listitem>
9809 <listitem><para>
9810 name of the service or entity;
9811 </para></listitem>
9812 <listitem><para>
9813 channel or program;
9814 </para></listitem>
9815 <listitem><para>
9816 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
9817 </para></listitem>
9818 <listitem><para>
9819 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
9820 </para></listitem>
9821 <listitem><para>
9822 time zone where the signal was received (user);
9823 </para></listitem>
9824 <listitem><para>
9825 unique user identifier;
9826 </para></listitem>
9827 <listitem><para>
9828 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
9829 </para></listitem>
9830 </orderedlist>
9831
9832 <para>
9833 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
9834 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
9835 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
9836 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
9837 Internet radio has to pay a <emphasis>type of copyright fee</emphasis>
9838 that terrestrial radio does not.
9839 </para>
9840 <para>
9841 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
9842 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
9843 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
9844 </para>
9845 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
9846 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'>
9847 <primary>Alben, Alex</primary>
9848 </indexterm>
9849 <para>
9850 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
9851 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
9852 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
9853 </para>
9854 <blockquote>
9855 <para>
9856 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
9857 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
9858 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
9859 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
9860 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
9861 webcasters asked the RIAA, &hellip; <quote>How do you come up with a
9862
9863 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
9864 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
9865 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
9866 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
9867 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
9868 business. &hellip;</quote>
9869 </para>
9870 <indexterm>
9871 <primary>artists</primary>
9872 <secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary>
9873 </indexterm>
9874 <para>
9875 And the RIAA experts said, <quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
9876 industry with thousands of webcasters, <emphasis>we think it should be
9877 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
9878 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market</emphasis>.</quote> (Emphasis
9879 added.)
9880 </para>
9881 </blockquote>
9882 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'/>
9883 <para>
9884 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
9885 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
9886 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
9887 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
9888 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
9889 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
9890 effective to prevent it.
9891 </para>
9892 </section>
9893 <section id="corruptingcitizens">
9894 <title>Corrupting Citizens</title>
9895 <para>
9896 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
9897 dinosaurs
9898 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
9899 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
9900 </para>
9901 <para>
9902 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
9903 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
9904 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
9905 </para>
9906 <para>
9907 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
9908 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
9909 large number of citizens. According to <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, 43 million
9910 Americans downloaded music in May 2002.<footnote><para>
9911 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, <quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,</quote> Pew
9912 Internet and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at
9913 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #46</ulink>.
9914 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that 37 million
9915 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early 2001.
9916 </para></footnote>
9917 According to the RIAA,
9918 the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
9919 set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As the
9920
9921 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
9922 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
9923 the world, but against students building search engines, and
9924 increasingly
9925 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
9926 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
9927 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
9928 extreme
9929 response by the other.
9930 </para>
9931 <para>
9932 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
9933 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
9934 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
9935 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
9936 ($15,000,000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
9937 paying all the money in the world in damages ($250,000 in legal fees)
9938 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
9939 ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
9940 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September 2003, the RIAA
9941 sued 261 individuals&mdash;including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
9942 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
9943 was.<footnote><para>
9944 <!-- f16. -->
9945 Alex Pham, <quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,</quote> <citetitle>Los
9946 Angeles Times</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, Business.
9947 </para></footnote>
9948 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
9949 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
9950 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000
9951 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
9952 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
9953 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
9954 they oppose.
9955 </para>
9956 <para>
9957 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
9958 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
9959 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
9960 consumption of alcohol was 1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
9961 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just 30 percent
9962 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
9963 consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition
9964 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
9965 number were criminals.<footnote><para>
9966 <!-- f17. -->
9967 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, <quote>Alcohol Consumption During
9968 Prohibition,</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review</citetitle> 81, no. 2 (1991): 242.
9969 </para></footnote>
9970 We have
9971 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
9972 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
9973 narcotics that 7 percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.<footnote><para>
9974 <!-- f18. -->
9975 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
9976 Reform Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of
9977 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
9978 </para></footnote>
9979 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of
9980 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
9981 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
9982 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
9983 cheat.<footnote><para>
9984 <!-- f19. -->
9985 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, <quote>Tax
9986 Compliance,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature</citetitle> 36 (1998): 818 (survey of
9987 compliance literature).
9988 </para></footnote>
9989 We pride ourselves on our <quote>free society,</quote> but an endless array of
9990 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
9991 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
9992 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition</primary></indexterm>
9993 </para>
9994 <para>
9995 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
9996 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
9997 students about the importance of <quote>ethics.</quote> As my colleague Charlie
9998 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
9999 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10000 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10001 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10002 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10003 teach them how to behave ethically&mdash;how to say no to bribes, or
10004 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10005 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10006 Americans&mdash;more significantly in some parts of America than in
10007 others, but still, everywhere in America today&mdash;can't live their
10008 lives both normally and legally, since <quote>normally</quote> entails a certain
10009 degree of illegality.
10010 <indexterm><primary>law schools</primary></indexterm>
10011 </para>
10012 <para>
10013 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10014 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10015 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10016 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10017 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10018 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10019 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10020 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10021 to consider the alternative.
10022 </para>
10023 <para>
10024
10025 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10026 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10027 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10028 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10029 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10030 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10031 </para>
10032 <para>
10033 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10034 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10035 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10036 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10037 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10038 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10039 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10040 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10041 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10042 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10043 introduced this different idea of <quote>sharing.</quote> We need to be able to
10044 call these twenty million Americans <quote>citizens,</quote> not <quote>felons.</quote>
10045 </para>
10046 <para>
10047 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10048 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10049 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10050 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10051 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10052 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10053 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10054 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10055 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10056 a nation of felons?
10057 </para>
10058 <para>
10059 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10060 </para>
10061 <para>
10062 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10063 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10064 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10065 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10066 used
10067
10068 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10069 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That <quote>use</quote> of the
10070 recordings is free.
10071 </para>
10072 <para>
10073 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10074 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10075 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am <quote>free</quote> to copy,
10076 or <quote>rip,</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10077 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that <quote>freedom</quote> was a
10078 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the <quote>Rip, Mix, Burn</quote>
10079 capacities of digital technologies.
10080 </para>
10081 <indexterm><primary>Adromeda</primary></indexterm>
10082 <para>
10083 This <quote>use</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10084 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10085 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10086 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10087 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10088 Others&mdash;the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10089 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10090 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10091 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10092 </para>
10093 <para>
10094 This use is enabled by unprotected media&mdash;either CDs or records.
10095 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10096 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10097 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10098 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10099 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10100 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10101 on people's machines.
10102 </para>
10103 <para>
10104 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10105 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10106 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10107 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10108 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10109 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10110
10111 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10112 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10113 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10114 plastic or were part of a massively complex <quote>digital rights
10115 management</quote> system.
10116 </para>
10117 <para>
10118 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10119 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10120 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10121 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10122 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10123 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10124 freedom to move content easily?
10125 </para>
10126 <para>
10127 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10128 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10129 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10130 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10131 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10132 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10133 alternative&mdash;namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10134 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10135 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10136 </para>
10137 <para>
10138 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10139 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10140 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10141 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10142 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10143 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10144 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10145 </para>
10146 <para>
10147 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10148 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10149 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10150 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10151 </para>
10152 <para>
10153 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10154 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10155
10156 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10157
10158 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10159 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10160 There's one more aspect to this corruption that is particularly
10161 important to civil liberties, and follows directly from any war of
10162 prohibition. As Electronic Frontier Foundation attorney Fred von
10163 Lohmann describes, this is the <quote>collateral damage</quote> that <quote>arises
10164 whenever you turn a very large percentage of the population into
10165 criminals.</quote> This is the collateral damage to civil liberties
10166 generally.
10167 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
10168 </para>
10169 <para>
10170 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,</quote> von Lohmann
10171 explains,
10172 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10173 </para>
10174 <blockquote>
10175 <para>
10176 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10177 evaporate to one degree or another. &hellip; If you're a copyright
10178 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10179 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10180 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10181 access? &hellip; Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, <quote>Oh, well,
10182 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.</quote> Well, what this campaign
10183 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10184 American Internet-using population into <quote>lawbreakers.</quote>
10185 </para>
10186 </blockquote>
10187 <para>
10188 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10189 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10190 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10191 </para>
10192 <para>
10193 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA
10194 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10195 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10196 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10197 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10198 an Internet user is revealed.
10199 </para>
10200 <para>
10201 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10202 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10203 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10204 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10205 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10206 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10207 the family could be liable for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10208 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10209 Jesse Jordan.<footnote><para>
10210 <!-- f20. -->
10211 See Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10212 Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,</quote>
10213 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, <quote>Worried Parents
10214 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10215 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10216 Being Sued,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson
10217 Graham, <quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 15 September
10218 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, <quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10219 Fan, Either,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 25 September 2003, C1; Margo Varadi, <quote>Is
10220 Brianna a Criminal?</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star</citetitle>, 18 September 2003, P7.
10221 </para></footnote>
10222
10223 </para>
10224 <para>
10225 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10226 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10227 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.<footnote><para>
10228 <!-- f21. -->
10229 See <quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10230 Some Methods Used,</quote> CNN.com, available at
10231 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #47</ulink>.
10232 </para></footnote>
10233 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10234 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10235 one of those MP3s will have the same <quote>fingerprint.</quote>
10236 </para>
10237 <para>
10238 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10239 friend gives a CD to your daughter&mdash;a collection of songs just
10240 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10241 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10242 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10243 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10244 network is <quote>cooperating</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10245 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10246 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10247 as a <quote>criminal.</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10248 to deploy,<footnote><para>
10249 <!-- f22. -->
10250 See Jeff Adler, <quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,</quote>
10251 <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, <quote>Four
10252 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10253 Colleges,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10254 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10255 Monitor</citetitle>, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, <quote>Music
10256 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10257 Lawsuit Possible,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 16 July 2003, 1C; Beth Cox, <quote>RIAA
10258 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,</quote> <citetitle>Internet News</citetitle>, 30 January
10259 2003, available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10260 #48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Download Warning 101: Freshman
10261 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10262 Sharing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 11 August 2003, E11; <quote>Raid, Letters
10263 Are Weapons at Universities,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 26 September 2000, 3D.
10264 </para></footnote>
10265 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10266 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10267 </para>
10268 <para>
10269 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10270 a lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10271 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10272 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10273 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10274 this <quote>contraband</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10275 college students
10276
10277 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10278 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10279 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10280 Says von Lohmann,
10281 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10282 </para>
10283 <blockquote>
10284 <para>
10285 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10286 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10287 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10288 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10289 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10290 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10291 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10292 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10293 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10294 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10295 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10296 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10297 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10298 larger number of Americans than drug use. &hellip; If forty to sixty
10299 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10300 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10301 million of them.
10302 </para>
10303 </blockquote>
10304 <para>
10305 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered <quote>criminals</quote> under
10306 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective&mdash;
10307 securing rights to authors&mdash;without these millions being
10308 considered <quote>criminals,</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10309 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10310 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10311 </para>
10312
10313 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10314 </section>
10315 </chapter>
10316 </part>
10317 <part id="c-balances">
10318 <title>BALANCES</title>
10319 <partintro>
10320
10321 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10322 <para>
10323 So here's the picture: You're standing at the side of the road. Your
10324 car is on fire. You are angry and upset because in part you helped start
10325 the fire. Now you don't know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket,
10326 filled with gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10327 </para>
10328 <para>
10329 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10330 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10331 stop&mdash;or before she understands just why she should
10332 stop&mdash;the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10333 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10334 everything around.
10335 </para>
10336 <para>
10337 A war about copyright rages all around&mdash;and we're all focusing on
10338 the wrong thing. No doubt, current technologies threaten existing
10339 businesses. No doubt they may threaten artists. But technologies
10340 change. The industry and technologists have plenty of ways to use
10341 technology to protect themselves against the current threats of the
10342 Internet. This is a fire that if let alone would burn itself out.
10343 </para>
10344 <para>
10345 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
10346 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
10347 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
10348 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
10349 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
10350 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
10351 made that is happening all around.
10352 </para>
10353 <para>
10354 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
10355 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
10356 gasoline onto this fire.
10357 </para>
10358 <para>
10359 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
10360 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
10361 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
10362 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
10363 </para>
10364 <para>
10365 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
10366 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
10367 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
10368 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
10369 success will require.
10370 </para>
10371 </partintro>
10372
10373 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
10374 <chapter label="13" id="eldred">
10375 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred</title>
10376 <indexterm id="idxhawthornenathaniel" class='startofrange'>
10377 <primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel</primary>
10378 </indexterm>
10379 <para>
10380 In 1995, a father was frustrated that his daughters didn't seem to
10381 like Hawthorne. No doubt there was more than one such father, but at
10382 least one did something about it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer
10383 programmer living in New Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the
10384 Web. An electronic version, Eldred thought, with links to pictures and
10385 explanatory text, would make this nineteenth-century author's work
10386 come alive.
10387 </para>
10388 <para>
10389 It didn't work&mdash;at least for his daughters. They didn't find
10390 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
10391 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
10392 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
10393 them available for free.
10394 </para>
10395 <para>
10396 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
10397 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
10398 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
10399 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
10400 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
10401 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
10402 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
10403 many others, into a form more accessible&mdash;technically
10404 accessible&mdash;today.
10405 </para>
10406 <para>
10407 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
10408 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's <citetitle>Scarlet Letter</citetitle> had passed into the
10409 public domain in 1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
10410 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
10411 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
10412 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
10413 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
10414 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (<citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle>), sometimes not
10415 (<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame</citetitle>, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>). These are all
10416 commercial publications of public domain works.
10417 </para>
10418 <indexterm startref="idxhawthornenathaniel" class='endofrange'/>
10419 <para>
10420 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
10421 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
10422 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
10423 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
10424 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
10425 call the <quote>noncommercial publishing industry,</quote> which before the
10426 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
10427 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
10428 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
10429 generally.<footnote><para>
10430 <!-- f1. -->
10431 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
10432 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
10433 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers&mdash;people who
10434 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
10435 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
10436 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
10437 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
10438 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
10439 Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on
10440 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
10441 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
10442 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
10443 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
10444 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
10445 protect noncommercial pornographers.</para></footnote>
10446 </para>
10447 <para>
10448 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's
10449 collection of poems <citetitle>New Hampshire</citetitle> was slated to
10450 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
10451 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
10452 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10453 linkend="property-i"/>, in 1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
10454 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights&mdash;this time by
10455 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
10456 than 1923 to his collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
10457 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
10458 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
10459 more than 1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
10460 </para>
10461 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
10462 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
10463 <para>
10464
10465 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
10466 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
10467 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
10468 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
10469 <quote>copyrights should be forever.</quote><footnote><para>
10470 <!-- f2. -->
10471 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
10472 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
10473 The full text is: <quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
10474 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
10475 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
10476 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
10477 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
10478 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
10479 Congress,</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998).
10480 </para></footnote>
10481
10482 </para>
10483 <para>
10484 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
10485 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
10486 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
10487 second law passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
10488 of publishing would make Eldred a felon&mdash;whether or not anyone
10489 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
10490 to undertake.
10491 </para>
10492 <para>
10493 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
10494 constitutional
10495 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
10496 interpretation.
10497 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
10498 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
10499 importantly
10500 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
10501 </para>
10502 <blockquote>
10503 <para>
10504 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science &hellip;
10505 by securing for limited Times to Authors &hellip; exclusive Right to
10506 their &hellip; Writings. &hellip;
10507 </para>
10508 </blockquote>
10509 <para>
10510 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
10511 clause of Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
10512 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
10513 something&mdash;for example, to regulate <quote>commerce among the several
10514 states</quote> or <quote>declare War.</quote> But here, the <quote>something</quote> is something quite
10515 specific&mdash;to <quote>promote &hellip; Progress</quote>&mdash;through means that
10516 are also specific&mdash; by <quote>securing</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights</quote> (i.e.,
10517 copyrights) <quote>for limited Times.</quote>
10518 </para>
10519 <para>
10520 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
10521 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
10522 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
10523 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be <quote>limited</quote> will have
10524 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
10525 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
10526 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
10527 what the Constitution plainly forbids&mdash;perpetual terms <quote>on the
10528 installment plan,</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
10529 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
10530 </para>
10531 <para>
10532 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
10533 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
10534 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
10535 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
10536 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
10537 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
10538 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
10539 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
10540 this gravy train going.
10541 </para>
10542 <para>
10543 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
10544 government. <quote>Corruption</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
10545 bribed. Rather, <quote>corruption</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
10546 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
10547 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
10548 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
10549 do&mdash;and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
10550 </para>
10551 <para>
10552 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
10553 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
10554 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
10555 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry
10556 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
10557 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
10558 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
10559 published by anyone for free.
10560 </para>
10561 <para>
10562 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from
10563 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
10564 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
10565 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
10566 report:
10567 </para>
10568 <para>
10569 <quote>Next year,</quote> the adviser announces, <quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
10570
10571 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
10572 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
10573 receiving the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of
10574 those works.</quote>
10575 </para>
10576 <para>
10577 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,</quote> she continues, <quote>that
10578 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
10579 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
10580 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.</quote>
10581 </para>
10582 <para>
10583 <quote>Hope?</quote> a fellow board member says. <quote>Can't we be doing something
10584 about it?</quote>
10585 </para>
10586 <para>
10587 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>We could contribute
10588 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
10589 they support the bill.</quote>
10590 </para>
10591 <para>
10592 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
10593 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. <quote>How much
10594 would we get if this extension were passed?</quote> you ask the adviser. <quote>How
10595 much is it worth?</quote>
10596 </para>
10597 <para>
10598 <quote>Well,</quote> the adviser says, <quote>if you're confident that you will continue
10599 to get at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
10600 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent),
10601 then this law would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate.</quote>
10602 </para>
10603 <para>
10604 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
10605 correct conclusion:
10606 </para>
10607 <para>
10608 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
10609 $1,000,000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
10610 contributions
10611 would assure that the bill was passed?</quote>
10612 </para>
10613 <para>
10614 <quote>Absolutely,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>It is worth it to you to
10615 contribute
10616 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
10617 copyrights. Which for us means over $1,000,000.</quote>
10618 </para>
10619 <para>
10620 You quickly get the point&mdash;you as the member of the board and, I
10621 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
10622 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
10623 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
10624 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
10625 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
10626 copyrights
10627 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
10628 the copyright term extended.
10629 </para>
10630 <para>
10631 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
10632 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
10633 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
10634 </para>
10635 <para>
10636 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
10637 Copyright
10638 Term Extension Act, this <quote>theory</quote> about incentives was proved
10639 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
10640 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
10641 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
10642 contributions.<footnote><para>
10643 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, <quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
10644 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years,</quote>
10645 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 17 October 1998, 22.
10646 </para></footnote>
10647 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
10648 $1.5 million lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more
10649 than $200,000 in campaign contributions.<footnote><para>
10650 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, <quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
10651 Age,</quote> available at
10652 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #49</ulink>.
10653 </para></footnote>
10654 Disney is estimated to have
10655 contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in the
10656 cycle.<footnote><para>
10657 <!-- f5. -->
10658 Alan K. Ota, <quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,</quote>
10659 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week</citetitle>, 8 August 1990, available at
10660 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #50</ulink>.
10661 </para></footnote>
10662
10663 </para>
10664 <para>
10665 Constitutional law is not oblivious to the obvious. Or at least,
10666 it need not be. So when I was considering Eldred's complaint, this
10667 reality
10668 about the never-ending incentives to increase the copyright term
10669 was central to my thinking. In my view, a pragmatic court committed
10670 to interpreting and applying the Constitution of our framers would see
10671 that if Congress has the power to extend existing terms, then there
10672 would be no effective constitutional requirement that terms be
10673 <quote>limited.</quote>
10674 If they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again
10675 and again.
10676 </para>
10677 <para>
10678 It was also my judgment that <emphasis>this</emphasis> Supreme Court
10679 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
10680 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
10681 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
10682 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
10683 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
10684 Supreme Court's
10685
10686 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
10687 decision in 1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
10688 guns near schools.
10689 </para>
10690 <para>
10691 Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
10692 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
10693 power to regulate only <quote>commerce among the several states</quote> (aka
10694 <quote>interstate
10695 commerce</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
10696 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
10697 interstate
10698 commerce.
10699 </para>
10700 <para>
10701 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
10702 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
10703 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
10704 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
10705 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
10706 </para>
10707 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
10708 <para>
10709 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
10710 that in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The government had
10711 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
10712 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
10713 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
10714 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
10715 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
10716 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
10717 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
10718 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
10719 position to second-guess Congress.
10720 </para>
10721 <para>
10722 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,</quote>
10723 the Chief Justice wrote.<footnote><para>
10724 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995).
10725 </para></footnote>
10726 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
10727 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
10728 Congress's power. The decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
10729 later in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>.<footnote><para>
10730 <!-- f7. -->
10731 <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>, 529 U.S. 598 (2000).
10732 </para></footnote>
10733 </para>
10734 <para>
10735 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
10736 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.<footnote><para>
10737 <!-- f8. -->
10738 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
10739 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
10740 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
10741 by the government would allow the government unending power to
10742 regulate commerce&mdash;the limitation to interstate commerce
10743 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
10744 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
10745 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights&mdash;the
10746 limitation to <quote>limited times</quote> notwithstanding.
10747 </para></footnote>
10748 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
10749 yield the conclusion that Congress
10750 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
10751 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
10752 term, then there would be no <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power over
10753 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
10754 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
10755 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
10756 term of existing copyrights.
10757 </para>
10758 <para>
10759 <emphasis>If</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
10760 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> stood for
10761 politics&mdash;a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
10762 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
10763 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
10764 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
10765 demonstrating the <quote>fidelity</quote> in such an interpretation of the
10766 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
10767 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
10768 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
10769 were going to be petty politicians.
10770 </para>
10771 <para>
10772 Now let's pause for a moment to make sure we understand what the
10773 argument in <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
10774 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
10775 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
10776 piracy&mdash;piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
10777 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
10778 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
10779 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
10780 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
10781 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
10782 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
10783 power&mdash;expressed through the power of lobbyists' money&mdash;to
10784 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
10785 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
10786 piracy that affects us all.
10787 </para>
10788 <para>
10789 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
10790
10791 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
10792 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
10793 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than <quote>legal piracy.</quote><footnote><para>
10794 <!-- f9. -->
10795 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
10796 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available
10797 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #51</ulink>.
10798 </para></footnote>
10799 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
10800 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
10801 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
10802 charter.
10803 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association</primary></indexterm>
10804 </para>
10805 <para>
10806 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
10807 copyright
10808 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
10809 influence
10810 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
10811 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
10812 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
10813 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
10814 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
10815 bought to extend them again.
10816 </para>
10817 <para>
10818 It is valuable copyrights that are responsible for terms being
10819 extended.
10820 Mickey Mouse and <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.</quote> These works are too
10821 valuable for copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our
10822 society
10823 from copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains
10824 Disney's.
10825 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works
10826 from the 1920s and 1930s that have continuing commercial value. The
10827 real harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The
10828 real harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially
10829 exploited,
10830 and no longer available as a result.
10831 </para>
10832 <para>
10833 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to
10834 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
10835 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
10836 copyright holders for that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
10837 But the law and its effect were not limited to that 2 percent. The law
10838 extended the terms of copyright generally.<footnote><para>
10839 <!-- f10. --> The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
10840 Congressional
10841 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
10842 of Petitioners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 7, available at
10843 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #52</ulink>.
10844 </para></footnote>
10845
10846 </para>
10847 <para>
10848 Think practically about the consequence of this
10849 extension&mdash;practically,
10850 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
10851
10852 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
10853 work. In 1930, 10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those
10854 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
10855 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
10856 remaining
10857 9,873. What would you have to do?
10858 </para>
10859 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
10860 <para>
10861 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were
10862 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
10863 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
10864 titles and authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration
10865 and renewal records for works published in 1930. That will produce a
10866 list of books still under copyright.
10867 </para>
10868 <para>
10869 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
10870 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
10871 </para>
10872 <para>
10873 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
10874 owners
10875 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
10876 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
10877 being at least a list?
10878 </para>
10879 <para>
10880 But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in
10881 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
10882 practically
10883 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
10884 thousands
10885 of such records&mdash;especially since the person who registered is
10886 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930!
10887 </para>
10888 <para>
10889 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,</quote> the
10890 apologists for the system respond. <quote>Why should there be a list of
10891 copyright owners?</quote>
10892 </para>
10893 <para>
10894 Well, actually, if you think about it, there <emphasis>are</emphasis>
10895 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
10896 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
10897 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
10898 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
10899 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
10900 what tangible property.
10901 </para>
10902 <para>
10903 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
10904 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
10905 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
10906
10907 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
10908 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
10909 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
10910 happen
10911 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
10912 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
10913 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
10914 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
10915 know quite well who owns what property.
10916 </para>
10917 <para>
10918 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
10919 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
10920 already
10921 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
10922 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
10923 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
10924 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
10925 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
10926 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
10927 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
10928 </para>
10929 <para>
10930 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
10931 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
10932 consequence
10933 for other creative works is much more dire.
10934 </para>
10935 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'>
10936 <primary>Agee, Michael</primary>
10937 </indexterm>
10938 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
10939 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films</primary></indexterm>
10940 <para>
10941 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
10942 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
10943 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
10944 made between 1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, <citetitle>The Lucky Dog</citetitle>, is
10945 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923
10946 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
10947 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
10948 money. According to one estimate, <quote>Roach has sold about 60,000
10949 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's silent
10950 films.</quote><footnote><para>
10951 <!-- f11. -->
10952 See David G. Savage, <quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,</quote>
10953 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, <quote>Classic Movies,
10954 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
10955 Down Copyright Extension,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 9 October 2002.
10956 </para></footnote>
10957
10958 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The</primary></indexterm>
10959 </para>
10960 <para>
10961 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
10962 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
10963 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
10964 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
10965 </para>
10966 <para>
10967 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
10968
10969 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
10970 any continuing commercial value. The rest&mdash;to the extent it
10971 survives at all&mdash;sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
10972 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
10973 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
10974 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
10975 work available for distribution.
10976 </para>
10977 <para>
10978 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
10979 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
10980 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
10981 it cost more than $10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
10982 film in 1993, it can now cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of
10983 mm film.<footnote><para>
10984 <!-- f12. -->
10985 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
10986 Supporting the Petitoners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
10987 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01- 618), 12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
10988 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
10989 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, available at
10990 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #53</ulink>.
10991 </para></footnote>
10992
10993 </para>
10994 <para>
10995 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
10996 important.
10997 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
10998 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
10999 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11000 locate the copyright owner.
11001 </para>
11002 <para>
11003 Or more accurately, <emphasis>owners</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11004 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11005 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11006 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11007 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11008 to these films is exceptionally high.
11009 </para>
11010 <para>
11011 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11012 copyright owner when she shows up?</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11013 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11014 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11015 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11016 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11017 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11018 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11019 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11020 </para>
11021 <para>
11022 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11023
11024 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11025 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11026 benefit
11027 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11028 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11029 the copyright expires.
11030 </para>
11031 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'/>
11032 <para>
11033 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11034 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11035 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11036 canisters
11037 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11038 than dust.
11039 </para>
11040 <para>
11041 Of all the creative work produced by humans anywhere, a tiny
11042 fraction has continuing commercial value. For that tiny fraction, the
11043 copyright is a crucially important legal device. For that tiny fraction,
11044 the copyright creates incentives to produce and distribute the
11045 creative
11046 work. For that tiny fraction, the copyright acts as an <quote>engine of
11047 free expression.</quote>
11048 </para>
11049 <para>
11050 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11051 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11052 indicated,
11053 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11054 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11055 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11056 distributors,
11057 the commercial life ends.
11058 </para>
11059 <para>
11060 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11061 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes &amp; Noble, and
11062 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11063 between
11064 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11065 Friday
11066 night watching a 1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11067 of culture is important and valuable&mdash;for entertainment but also, and
11068 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11069 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11070 have, we need to have access to this history.
11071 </para>
11072 <para>
11073 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11074
11075 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11076 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11077 this context do no good.
11078 </para>
11079 <para>
11080 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11081 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11082 <emphasis>copyright-related use</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11083 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11084 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11085 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11086 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11087 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11088 was independent of copyright law.
11089 </para>
11090 <para>
11091 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11092 a film&mdash;the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs&mdash;were
11093 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11094 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11095 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11096 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11097 market didn't have more to offer.
11098 </para>
11099 <para>
11100 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11101 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11102 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11103 would not have interfered with anything.
11104 </para>
11105 <para>
11106 But this situation has now changed.
11107 </para>
11108 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'>
11109 <primary>archives, digital</primary>
11110 </indexterm>
11111 <para>
11112 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11113 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11114 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11115 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11116 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11117 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11118 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11119 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11120 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11121 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11122 </para>
11123 <para>
11124 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11125 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11126 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11127 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11128 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11129 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11130 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11131 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11132 written for a radically different context.
11133 </para>
11134 <para>
11135 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11136 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11137 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11138 <emphasis>copyright</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11139 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11140 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11141 context, copyright is serving no purpose <emphasis>at all</emphasis>
11142 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11143 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11144 </para>
11145 <para>
11146 You may well ask, <quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11147 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11148 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11149 culture widely?</quote>
11150 </para>
11151 <para>
11152 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11153 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes &amp; Noble
11154 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11155 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11156 of a library is to serve what <quote>the market</quote> would demand. But if you
11157 think the role of a library is bigger than this&mdash;if you think its
11158 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11159 particular bit of that culture or not&mdash;then we can't count on the
11160 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11161 </para>
11162 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'/>
11163 <para>
11164 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11165 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11166 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11167 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11168
11169 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11170 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11171 culture, 94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11172 and 1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11173 commercial market, if access is a value, then 6 percent is a failure
11174 to provide that value.<footnote><para>
11175 <!-- f13. -->
11176 Jason Schultz, <quote>The Myth of the 1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,</quote> 20
11177 December 2002, available at
11178 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #54</ulink>.
11179 </para></footnote>
11180
11181 </para>
11182 <para>
11183 In January 1999, we filed a lawsuit on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal
11184 district court in Washington, D.C., asking the court to declare the
11185 Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act unconstitutional. The two
11186 central claims that we made were (1) that extending existing terms
11187 violated the Constitution's <quote>limited Times</quote> requirement, and (2) that
11188 extending terms by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11189 </para>
11190 <para>
11191 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11192 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11193 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11194 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11195 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11196 </para>
11197 <para>
11198 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11199 copyrights be for <quote>limited Times</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11200 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11201 <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11202 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11203 terms that are <quote>limited.</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11204 to interpret the term <quote>limited Times</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11205 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11206 power to extend existing terms.
11207 </para>
11208 <para>
11209 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11210 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11211 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11212 whole, where the court will sit <quote>en banc</quote> to hear the case.
11213 </para>
11214 <para>
11215 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11216 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11217
11218 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11219 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11220 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11221 overstepped its bounds.
11222 </para>
11223 <para>
11224 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11225 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11226 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11227 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11228 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11229 </para>
11230 <para>
11231 But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11232 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11233 was set for October of 2002. The summer would be spent writing
11234 briefs and preparing for argument.
11235 </para>
11236 <para>
11237 It is over a year later as I write these words. It is still
11238 astonishingly hard. If you know anything at all about this story, you
11239 know that we lost the appeal. And if you know something more than just
11240 the minimum, you probably think there was no way this case could have
11241 been won. After our defeat, I received literally thousands of missives
11242 by well-wishers and supporters, thanking me for my work on behalf of
11243 this noble but doomed cause. And none from this pile was more
11244 significant to me than the e-mail from my client, Eric Eldred.
11245 </para>
11246 <para>
11247 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11248 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11249 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11250 mistake lost it.
11251 </para>
11252 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11253 <para>
11254 The mistake was made early, though it became obvious only at the very
11255 end. Our case had been supported from the very beginning by an
11256 extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart, and by the law firm he had
11257 moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of
11258 heat
11259 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11260 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11261 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11262 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11263 </para>
11264 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11265 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan</primary></indexterm>
11266 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11267 <para>
11268 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11269 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11270 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11271 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11272 told me, if we could make the issue seem <quote>important</quote> to the Supreme
11273 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11274 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against <quote>the
11275 most powerful media companies in the world.</quote>
11276 </para>
11277 <para>
11278 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
11279 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
11280 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
11281 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
11282 <quote>right</quote> as in <quote>true,</quote> I thought, but it is <quote>wrong</quote> as in <quote>it just shouldn't be
11283 that way.</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
11284 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
11285 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
11286 interpretation
11287 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
11288 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
11289 unconstitutional,
11290 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
11291 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
11292 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
11293 Constitution,
11294 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
11295 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
11296 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
11297 </para>
11298 <para>
11299 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
11300 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
11301 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
11302 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
11303 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
11304 why it was unconstitutional.
11305 </para>
11306 <para>
11307 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
11308
11309 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
11310 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
11311 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
11312 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
11313 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
11314 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
11315 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
11316 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
11317 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
11318 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
11319 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
11320 <emphasis>law</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
11321 the widest range of credible critics&mdash;credible not because they
11322 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
11323 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
11324 </para>
11325 <para>
11326 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
11327 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
11328 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
11329 Congress. In November 1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
11330 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
11331 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
11332 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
11333 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
11334 to get bogged down?</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
11335 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
11336 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
11337 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
11338 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11339 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis</primary></indexterm>
11340 </para>
11341 <para>
11342 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
11343 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
11344 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
11345 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
11346 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
11347 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
11348 </para>
11349 <para>
11350 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
11351 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
11352
11353 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
11354 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/ Linux
11355 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
11356 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
11357 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
11358 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
11359 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
11360 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
11361 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
11362 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
11363 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
11364 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
11365 </para>
11366 <para>
11367 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
11368 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
11369 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
11370 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
11371 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries</primary></indexterm>
11372 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union</primary></indexterm>
11373 </para>
11374 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
11375 <para>
11376 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
11377 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
11378 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
11379 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
11380 clear.
11381 </para>
11382 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George</primary></indexterm>
11383 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
11384 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James</primary></indexterm>
11385 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11386 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton</primary></indexterm>
11387 <para>
11388 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
11389 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
11390 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
11391 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
11392 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
11393 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
11394 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
11395 nothing more than <quote>rent-seeking</quote>&mdash;the fancy term economists use
11396 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
11397 </para>
11398 <para>
11399 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
11400 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
11401 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
11402 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
11403 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
11404 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
11405 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
11406 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
11407
11408 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
11409 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
11410 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
11411 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11412 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan</primary></indexterm>
11413 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen</primary></indexterm>
11414 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11415 </para>
11416 <para>
11417 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
11418 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
11419 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
11420 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
11421 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
11422 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
11423 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
11424 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
11425 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
11426 confidence in our argument.
11427 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11428 </para>
11429 <para>
11430 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
11431 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these <quote>friends</quote> included
11432 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
11433 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
11434 copyright holders.
11435 </para>
11436 <para>
11437 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
11438 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either&mdash;they
11439 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
11440 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
11441 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
11442 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
11443 wanted to control.
11444 </para>
11445 <para>
11446 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
11447 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
11448 Dr. Seuss's work&mdash; better than allowing it to fall into the
11449 public domain&mdash;because if this creativity were in the public
11450 domain, then people could use it to <quote>glorify drugs or to create
11451 pornography.</quote><footnote><para>
11452 <!-- f14. -->
11453 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11454 U.S. (2003) (No. 01-618), 19.
11455 </para></footnote>
11456 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
11457 <quote>protection</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
11458 to license <citetitle>Porgy and Bess</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
11459 Americans in the cast.<footnote><para>
11460 <!-- f15. -->
11461 Dinitia Smith, <quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
11462 Mouse Joins the Fray,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 28 March 1998, B7.
11463 </para></footnote>
11464 That's
11465 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
11466 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
11467 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
11468 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George</primary></indexterm>
11469 </para>
11470 <para>
11471 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
11472 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
11473 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
11474 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
11475 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, <quote>Give us twenty years
11476 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
11477 better with them than anyone else.</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
11478 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
11479 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
11480 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
11481 </para>
11482 <para>
11483 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
11484 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
11485 copyrights&mdash;extensions that would further concentrate the market;
11486 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
11487 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
11488 Between February and October, there was little I did beyond preparing
11489 for this case. Early on, as I said, I set the strategy.
11490 </para>
11491 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
11492 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
11493 <para>
11494 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
11495 called <quote>the Conservatives.</quote> The other we called <quote>the Rest.</quote> The
11496 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
11497 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
11498 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
11499 five who had supported the <citetitle>Lopez/Morrison</citetitle> line
11500 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
11501 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
11502 </para>
11503 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11504 <para>
11505 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
11506 Congress's power. These four&mdash;Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
11507 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer&mdash;had repeatedly argued that
11508 the Constitution
11509 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
11510 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
11511 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
11512 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
11513 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
11514 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
11515 </para>
11516 <para>
11517 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
11518 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
11519 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
11520 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
11521 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
11522 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
11523 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
11524 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
11525 sense.
11526 </para>
11527 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11528 <para>
11529 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
11530 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
11531 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
11532 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
11533 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
11534 these retrospective extensions.
11535 </para>
11536 <para>
11537 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
11538 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
11539 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
11540 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
11541 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
11542 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
11543 </para>
11544 <para>
11545 This analysis of <quote>the Rest</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
11546 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
11547 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
11548 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
11549 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation&mdash;the
11550 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
11551 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
11552 powers have limits.
11553 </para>
11554 <para>
11555 This then was the core of our strategy&mdash;a strategy for which I am
11556 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
11557 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
11558 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
11559 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
11560 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
11561 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
11562 supposed to be <quote>limited.</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
11563 reconcile <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> with
11564 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
11565 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
11566 be limited.
11567 </para>
11568 <para>
11569 The argument on the government's side came down to this: Congress has
11570 done it before. It should be allowed to do it again. The government
11571 claimed that from the very beginning, Congress has been extending the
11572 term of existing copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court
11573 should not now say that practice is unconstitutional.
11574 </para>
11575 <para>
11576 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
11577 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in 1831
11578 and in 1909. And of course, in 1962, Congress began extending
11579 existing
11580 terms regularly&mdash;eleven times in forty years.
11581 </para>
11582 <para>
11583 But this <quote>consistency</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
11584 extended
11585 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
11586 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
11587 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
11588 existing
11589 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
11590 restraint
11591 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
11592 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
11593 hesitated
11594 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
11595 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
11596 Oral argument was scheduled for the first week in October. I
11597 arrived
11598 in D.C. two weeks before the argument. During those two
11599 weeks, I was repeatedly <quote>mooted</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
11600
11601 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
11602 help in the case. Such <quote>moots</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
11603 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
11604 </para>
11605 <para>
11606 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
11607 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
11608 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
11609 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
11610 Congress
11611 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
11612 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
11613 this central idea.
11614 </para>
11615 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11616 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
11617 <para>
11618 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
11619 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
11620 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
11621 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
11622 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11623 </para>
11624 <para>
11625 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
11626 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
11627 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
11628 the harm&mdash;passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
11629 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.</quote>
11630 </para>
11631 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11632 <para>
11633 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
11634 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
11635 right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
11636 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
11637 does the right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it is right. As
11638 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
11639 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
11640 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
11641 The night before the argument, a line of people began to form
11642 in front of the Supreme Court. The case had become a focus of the
11643 press and of the movement to free culture. Hundreds stood in line
11644
11645 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
11646 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
11647 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
11648 </para>
11649 <para>
11650 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
11651 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
11652 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
11653 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
11654 congressmen
11655 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
11656 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
11657 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
11658 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
11659 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
11660 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
11661 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
11662 family of the Justices.
11663 </para>
11664 <para>
11665 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
11666 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
11667 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
11668 those enumerated powers had any limit.
11669 </para>
11670 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
11671 <para>
11672 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
11673 The history was bothering her.
11674 </para>
11675 <blockquote>
11676 <para>
11677 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
11678 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
11679 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
11680 practice that began with the very first act.
11681 </para>
11682 </blockquote>
11683 <para>
11684 She was quite willing to concede <quote>that this flies directly in the face
11685 of what the framers had in mind.</quote> But my response again and again
11686 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
11687 </para>
11688 <blockquote>
11689 <para>
11690 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
11691 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
11692 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
11693 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
11694 is yes.
11695 </para>
11696 </blockquote>
11697 <para>
11698 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
11699 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
11700 Kennedy, who observed,
11701 </para>
11702 <blockquote>
11703 <para>
11704 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
11705 the '76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
11706 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
11707 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
11708 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
11709 </para>
11710 </blockquote>
11711 <para>
11712 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
11713 student,
11714 I answered,
11715 </para>
11716 <blockquote>
11717 <para>
11718 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
11719 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
11720 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
11721 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
11722 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
11723 </para>
11724 </blockquote>
11725 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11726 <para>
11727 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
11728 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
11729 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
11730 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
11731 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
11732 </para>
11733 <para>
11734 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
11735 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> ruling,
11736 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
11737 </para>
11738 <para>
11739 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
11740 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
11741
11742 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
11743 </para>
11744 <blockquote>
11745 <para>
11746 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
11747 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
11748 </para>
11749 <para>
11750 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
11751 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
11752 domain
11753 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
11754 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
11755 into the Copyright Clause.
11756 </para>
11757 </blockquote>
11758 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.</primary></indexterm>
11759 <para>
11760 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
11761 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
11762 asked Solicitor General Olson,
11763 </para>
11764 <blockquote>
11765 <para>
11766 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11767 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
11768 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
11769 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
11770 time.
11771 </para>
11772 </blockquote>
11773 <para>
11774 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
11775 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
11776 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
11777 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
11778 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
11779 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
11780 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
11781 Patent Clause&mdash; indeed, the very first case striking a law of
11782 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
11783 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
11784 Court to my side.
11785 </para>
11786 <para>
11787 As I left the court that day, I knew there were a hundred points I
11788 wished I could remake. There were a hundred questions I wished I had
11789
11790 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
11791 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
11792 optimistic.
11793 </para>
11794 <para>
11795 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
11796 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
11797 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
11798 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
11799 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
11800 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
11801 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
11802 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
11803 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
11804 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
11805 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court&mdash;in particular,
11806 the Conservatives&mdash;would feel itself constrained by the rule of
11807 law that it had established elsewhere.
11808 </para>
11809 <para>
11810 The morning of January 15, 2003, I was five minutes late to the office
11811 and missed the 7:00 A.M. call from the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to
11812 the message, I could tell in an instant that she had bad news to report.The
11813 Supreme Court had affirmed the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven
11814 justices had voted in the majority. There were two dissents.
11815 </para>
11816 <para>
11817 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
11818 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
11819 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
11820 </para>
11821 <para>
11822 My <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
11823 money in the world against <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. And here
11824 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
11825 reasoning.
11826 </para>
11827 <para>
11828 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
11829 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
11830 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
11831 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
11832 even appear in the Court's opinion.
11833 </para>
11834 <para>
11835
11836 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
11837 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
11838 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
11839 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
11840 </para>
11841 <para>
11842 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable&mdash;for her, and for Justice
11843 Souter. Neither believes in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
11844 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
11845 they had worked so hard to defeat.
11846 </para>
11847 <para>
11848 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
11849 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
11850 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
11851 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
11852 reconcile the two simply <emphasis>by not addressing the
11853 argument</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
11854 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
11855 followed from the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
11856 be limited, but in this context it would not.
11857 </para>
11858 <para>
11859 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
11860 they would respect? By what right did they&mdash;the silent
11861 five&mdash;get to select the part of the Constitution they would
11862 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
11863 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
11864 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
11865 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
11866 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
11867 the system we have.
11868 </para>
11869 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11870 <para>
11871 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
11872 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
11873 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
11874 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
11875 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
11876 the Court discounted the parallel&mdash;without explaining how the
11877 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
11878 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
11879 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
11880 </para>
11881 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
11882 <para>
11883 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
11884 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
11885 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
11886 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
11887 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8
11888 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
11889 that the actual number was 99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
11890 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
11891 <quote>limited,</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
11892 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
11893 </para>
11894 <para>
11895 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
11896 because neither believed in the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
11897 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
11898 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
11899 Sentelle. It was <citetitle>Hamlet</citetitle> without the Prince.
11900 </para>
11901 <para>
11902 Defeat brings depression. They say it is a sign of health when
11903 depression gives way to anger. My anger came quickly, but it didn't cure
11904 the depression. This anger was of two sorts.
11905 </para>
11906 <indexterm><primary>originalism</primary></indexterm>
11907 <para>
11908 It was first anger with the five <quote>Conservatives.</quote> It would have been
11909 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> didn't
11910 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
11911 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
11912 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
11913 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
11914 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is <quote>originalism</quote>&mdash;to
11915 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
11916 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
11917 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> and many other <quote>originalist</quote> rulings. Where was their
11918 <quote>originalism</quote> now?
11919 </para>
11920 <para>
11921 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
11922 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
11923 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
11924 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
11925
11926 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
11927 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
11928 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
11929 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
11930 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
11931 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
11932 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
11933 own principles.
11934 </para>
11935 <para>
11936 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
11937 myself.
11938 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
11939 the law as it is.
11940 </para>
11941 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11942 <para>
11943 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
11944 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
11945 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
11946 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
11947 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
11948 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
11949 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
11950 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
11951 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
11952 </para>
11953 <para>
11954 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
11955 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
11956 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
11957 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
11958 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
11959 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
11960 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
11961 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
11962 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
11963 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
11964 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
11965 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
11966 effort to persuade; but I
11967 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
11968 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
11969 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
11970 should decide the issue.
11971 </para>
11972 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11973 <para>
11974 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
11975 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
11976 Kathleen Sullivan?
11977 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
11978 </para>
11979 <para>
11980 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
11981 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
11982 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
11983 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
11984 </para>
11985 <para>
11986 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
11987 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
11988 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
11989 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
11990 have persuaded.
11991 </para>
11992 <para>
11993 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
11994 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
11995 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
11996 case was a mistake. <quote>The Court is not ready,</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
11997 issue should not be raised until it is.
11998 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
11999 </para>
12000 <para>
12001 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12002 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12003 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12004 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12005 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12006 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12007 this case&mdash;a decision I had made four years before&mdash;was wrong.
12008 While the reaction to the Sonny Bono Act itself was almost
12009 unanimously negative, the reaction to the Court's decision was mixed.
12010 No one, at least in the press, tried to say that extending the term of
12011 copyright was a good idea. We had won that battle over ideas. Where
12012
12013 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12014 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12015 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12016 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12017 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12018 harmful law. <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12019 </para>
12020 <blockquote>
12021 <para>
12022 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12023 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12024 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12025 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12026 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12027 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12028 </para>
12029 </blockquote>
12030 <para>
12031 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12032 hilarious images&mdash;of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12033 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced on the next page
12034 (<xref linkend="fig-18"/>). The <quote>powerful and wealthy</quote> line is a bit
12035 unfair. But the punch in the face felt exactly like that.
12036 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12037 </para>
12038 <figure id="fig-18">
12039 <title>Tom the Dancing Bug cartoon</title>
12040 <graphic fileref="images/18.png"></graphic>
12041 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12042 </figure>
12043 <para>
12044 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12045 quote from <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>. That <quote>grand experiment</quote> we call the
12046 <quote>public domain</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think, <quote>Honey,
12047 I shrunk the Constitution.</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12048 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12049 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12050 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12051 </para>
12052 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12053 </chapter>
12054 <chapter label="14" id="eldred-ii">
12055 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II</title>
12056 <para>
12057 The day <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I was to travel to
12058 Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was
12059 denied&mdash;meaning the case was really finally over&mdash;fate would
12060 have it that I was giving a speech to technologists at Disney World.)
12061 This was a particularly long flight to my least favorite city. The
12062 drive into the city from Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I
12063 opened up my computer and wrote an op-ed piece.
12064 </para>
12065 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12066 <para>
12067 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12068 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12069 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12070 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12071 Justice Kennedy: <quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12072 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12073 that.</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12074 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12075 </para>
12076 <para>
12077 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12078 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12079 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12080 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12081 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12082 the work passed into the public domain.
12083 </para>
12084 <para>
12085 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12086 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12087 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12088 </para>
12089 <para>
12090 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12091 is either the <quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act</quote> or the <quote>Copyright
12092 Term Deregulation Act.</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12093 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12094 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12095 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $1. But for
12096 everything else, let the content go.
12097 </para>
12098 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12099 <para>
12100 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12101 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12102 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12103 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12104 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12105 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12106 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12107 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12108 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12109 the stupid harm of the present system.
12110 </para>
12111 <para>
12112 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12113 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12114 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12115 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12116 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12117 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12118 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12119 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12120 where copyright owners could be identified.
12121 </para>
12122 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12123 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12124 <para>
12125 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12126 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
12127 linkend="property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12128 removed in 1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12129 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.<footnote><para>
12130 <!-- f1. -->
12131 Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12132 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12133 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12134 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act,
12135 every text of the Convention has provided that <quote>the enjoyment and the
12136 exercise</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention <quote>shall not be subject
12137 to any formality.</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12138 embodied in Article 5(2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12139 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12140 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12141 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12142 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12143 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12144 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12145 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12146 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>International
12147 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12148 Press, 2001), 153&ndash;54. </para></footnote>
12149 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a <quote>natural right.</quote> Natural
12150 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12151 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12152 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12153 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12154 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12155 </para>
12156 <para>
12157 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12158 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12159 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12160 <quote>Walt Disney creativity</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12161 know what's protected and what's not.
12162 </para>
12163 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12164 <para>
12165 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12166 Berlin in 1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12167 Convention in 1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12168 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12169 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12170 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12171 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an <citetitle>i</citetitle> or cross a
12172 <citetitle>t</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12173 </para>
12174 <para>
12175 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12176 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12177 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12178 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12179 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12180 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12181 </para>
12182 <para>
12183 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12184 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12185 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12186 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12187 burden
12188 imposed upon creators.
12189 </para>
12190 <para>
12191 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was
12192 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12193
12194 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12195 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12196 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12197 the government. He has a property right over the table <quote>naturally,</quote>
12198 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12199 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12200 table.
12201 </para>
12202 <para>
12203 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12204 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12205 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12206 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12207 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12208 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12209 spread.
12210 </para>
12211 <para>
12212 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12213 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12214 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12215 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12216 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12217 important reason to secure registration&mdash;both because it makes
12218 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12219 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12220 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12221 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12222 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12223 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12224 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12225 system of protection for property generally.
12226 </para>
12227 <para>
12228 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12229 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12230 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12231 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12232 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12233 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12234 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12235 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12236
12237 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12238 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12239 <emphasis>lawyer</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12240 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
12241 </para>
12242 <para>
12243 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12244 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12245 didn't <quote>get.</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
12246 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
12247 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, <quote>short,</quote> then this
12248 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
12249 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
12250 be presumptively uncontrolled.
12251 </para>
12252 <para>
12253 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
12254 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
12255 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
12256 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
12257 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
12258 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
12259 seen before <emphasis>because there are no formalities</emphasis>.
12260 </para>
12261 <para>
12262 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
12263 it is worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
12264 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
12265 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
12266 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
12267 </para>
12268 <para>
12269 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
12270 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
12271 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
12272 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
12273 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you.
12274 </para>
12275 <para>
12276 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
12277 registering the work mean that the $1 is really misleading? Isn't the
12278 hassle worth more than $1? Isn't that the real problem with
12279 registration?
12280 </para>
12281 <para>
12282 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
12283 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
12284 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
12285
12286 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
12287 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
12288 address the real problem of <emphasis>governments</emphasis> standing
12289 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
12290 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
12291 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
12292 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
12293 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
12294 upon historical data, that system would move up to 98 percent of
12295 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
12296 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
12297 </para>
12298 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12299 <para>
12300 When Steve Forbes endorsed the idea, some in Washington began to pay
12301 attention. Many people contacted me pointing to representatives who
12302 might be willing to introduce the Eldred Act. And I had a few who
12303 directly suggested that they might be willing to take the first step.
12304 </para>
12305 <para>
12306 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
12307 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
12308 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
12309 possible. In May 2003, it looked as if the bill would be
12310 introduced. On May 16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, <quote>we are
12311 close.</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
12312 something good might happen here.
12313 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe</primary></indexterm>
12314 </para>
12315 <para>
12316 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
12317 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
12318 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
12319 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
12320 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
12321 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
12322 </para>
12323 <para>
12324 The MPAA argued first that Congress had <quote>firmly rejected the central
12325 concept in the proposed bill</quote>&mdash;that copyrights be renewed. That
12326 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's <quote>firm rejection</quote> had occurred
12327 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
12328 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
12329 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
12330 owners&mdash;apparently those who could not afford the $1 fee. Third,
12331 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
12332 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
12333 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
12334 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
12335 off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
12336 argued that the bill would impose <quote>enormous</quote> costs, since a
12337 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
12338 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
12339 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
12340 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
12341 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
12342 film is a valid derivative use.
12343 </para>
12344 <para>
12345 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
12346 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
12347 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
12348 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
12349 or not&mdash;a controversial claim in any case&mdash;unless they know
12350 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
12351 </para>
12352 <para>
12353 At the beginning of this book, I told two stories about the law
12354 reacting to changes in technology. In the one, common sense prevailed.
12355 In the other, common sense was delayed. The difference between the two
12356 stories was the power of the opposition&mdash;the power of the side
12357 that fought to defend the status quo. In both cases, a new technology
12358 threatened old interests. But in only one case did those interest's
12359 have the power to protect themselves against this new competitive
12360 threat.
12361 </para>
12362 <para>
12363 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
12364 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
12365 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
12366 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
12367 sense?
12368 </para>
12369 <para>
12370
12371 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
12372 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
12373 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
12374 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
12375 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
12376 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
12377 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
12378 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
12379 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
12380 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
12381 </para>
12382 <para>
12383 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
12384 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
12385 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
12386 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
12387 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
12388 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the <quote>Dark
12389 Content</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
12390 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
12391 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin</primary></indexterm>
12392 </para>
12393 <para>
12394 What does this industry really want?
12395 </para>
12396 <para>
12397 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
12398 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
12399 protecting <emphasis>their</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
12400 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
12401 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
12402 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
12403 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
12404 content that doesn't require <emphasis>their</emphasis> permission
12405 first.
12406 </para>
12407 <para>
12408 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
12409 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
12410 its aim not the protection of <quote>property</quote> but the rejection of a
12411 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
12412 theirs. <emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
12413 theirs</emphasis>.
12414 </para>
12415 <para>
12416 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
12417 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
12418
12419 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
12420 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
12421 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
12422 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
12423 and to share its own creation.
12424 </para>
12425 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
12426 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
12427 <para>
12428 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
12429 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
12430 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
12431 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
12432 block the progress of others.
12433 </para>
12434 <para>
12435 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
12436 <quote>property</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
12437 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
12438 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing <quote>permission
12439 society.</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
12440 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
12441 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
12442 </para>
12443 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
12444 </chapter>
12445 </part>
12446 <chapter label="15" id="c-conclusion">
12447 <title>CONCLUSION</title>
12448 <indexterm id="idxantiretroviraldrugs" class='startofrange'>
12449 <primary>antiretroviral drugs</primary>
12450 </indexterm>
12451 <indexterm id="idxhivaidstherapies" class='startofrange'>
12452 <primary>HIV/AIDS therapies</primary>
12453 </indexterm>
12454 <indexterm id="idxafricahivmed" class='startofrange'>
12455 <primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in</primary>
12456 </indexterm>
12457 <para>
12458 There are more than 35 million people with the AIDS virus
12459 worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live in sub-Saharan Africa.
12460 Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen million Africans
12461 is proportional percentage-wise to seven million Americans. More
12462 importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
12463 </para>
12464 <para>
12465 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
12466 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
12467 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
12468 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
12469 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
12470 the disease almost invisible.
12471 </para>
12472 <para>
12473 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
12474 United States, they cost between $10,000 and $15,000 per person per
12475 year. Today, some cost $25,000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
12476 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
12477 population:
12478 $15,000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
12479 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.<footnote><para>
12480 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, <quote>Final Report: Integrating
12481 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy</quote> (London, 2002),
12482 available at
12483 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
12484 release
12485 issued 9 July 2002, only 230,000 of the 6 million who need drugs in
12486 the developing world receive them&mdash;and half of them are in Brazil.
12487 </para></footnote>
12488 </para>
12489 <para>
12490 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
12491 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
12492 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
12493 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
12494 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
12495 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
12496 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
12497 </para>
12498 <para>
12499 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
12500 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
12501 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
12502 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
12503 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
12504 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
12505 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
12506 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
12507 changes.
12508 </para>
12509 <para>
12510 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
12511 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
12512 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
12513 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
12514 costs significantly below the market price.
12515 </para>
12516 <para>
12517 In 1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
12518 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
12519 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
12520 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
12521 Africa from India. This is called <quote>parallel importation,</quote> and it is
12522 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
12523 permitted within the European Union.<footnote>
12524 <para>
12525 <!-- f2. -->
12526 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
12527 Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37.
12528 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
12529 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12530 </para></footnote>
12531 </para>
12532 <para>
12533 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
12534 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
12535 characterized it, <quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa &hellip;
12536 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
12537 imports.</quote><footnote><para>
12538 <!-- f3. -->
12539 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
12540 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12541 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12542 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 14, available at
12543 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #56</ulink>. For a
12544 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
12545 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
12546 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess.,
12547 Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150&ndash;57 (statement of James
12548 Love).
12549 </para></footnote>
12550 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
12551 government asked South Africa to change the law&mdash;and to add
12552 pressure to that request, in 1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
12553 possible trade sanctions.
12554 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
12555 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
12556 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
12557 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
12558 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
12559 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
12560 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
12561 patent&mdash; pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
12562 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
12563 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
12564 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.<footnote><para>
12565 <!-- f4. -->
12566 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
12567 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
12568 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
12569 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 15. </para></footnote>
12570 </para>
12571 <para>
12572 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
12573 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
12574 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
12575 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
12576 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
12577 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
12578 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
12579 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
12580 </para>
12581 <para>
12582 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
12583 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
12584 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
12585 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
12586 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
12587 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save 15 to 30 million lives.
12588 </para>
12589 <para>
12590 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
12591 profits of United States drug companies&mdash;at least, not substantially. It
12592 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
12593 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
12594 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
12595 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
12596 by U.S. companies.
12597 </para>
12598 <para>
12599 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
12600 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
12601 argument
12602 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
12603 about the sanctity of property.<footnote><para>
12604 <!-- f5. -->
12605 See Sabin Russell, <quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
12606 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24
12607 May 1999, A1, available at
12608 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #57</ulink>
12609 (<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
12610 system of intellectual property protection</quote>); Robert Weissman, <quote>AIDS
12611 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
12612 Medicines,</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus</citetitle> 4:23 (August 1999), available at
12613 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #58</ulink>
12614 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, <quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
12615 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
12616 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
12617 Symposium Journal</citetitle> (Spring 2001): 175.
12618 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
12619 </para></footnote>
12620 It was because <quote>intellectual property</quote> would be violated that these
12621 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
12622 importance of <quote>intellectual property</quote> that led these government actors
12623 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
12624 </para>
12625 <para>
12626 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
12627 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
12628 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
12629 direct cost would be to speed the death of 15 to 30 million Africans,
12630 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the <quote>sanctity</quote> of an
12631 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
12632 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
12633 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
12634 </para>
12635 <para>
12636 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
12637 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
12638 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
12639 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
12640 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system&mdash;
12641 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
12642 </para>
12643 <para>
12644 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
12645 drug companies would love&mdash;they say, and I believe them&mdash;to
12646 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
12647 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
12648 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
12649 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
12650 </para>
12651 <para>
12652 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
12653 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
12654 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, <quote>How
12655 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $1 a pill, but the same
12656 drug would cost an American $1,500?</quote> Because there is no <quote>sound
12657 bite</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
12658 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
12659 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
12660 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
12661 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
12662 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
12663 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal&mdash;the sanctity of an
12664 idea called <quote>intellectual property.</quote>
12665 </para>
12666 <para>
12667 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
12668 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
12669 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
12670 What is the argument?
12671 </para>
12672 <para>
12673 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
12674 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
12675 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
12676 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
12677 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
12678 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
12679 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
12680 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
12681 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
12682 were balanced in just this sense.
12683 </para>
12684 <para>
12685 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
12686 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
12687 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
12688 our tradition, now reigns in this culture&mdash;bizarrely, and with
12689 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
12690 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
12691 </para>
12692 <indexterm startref="idxafricahivmed" class='endofrange'/>
12693 <indexterm startref="idxhivaidstherapies" class='endofrange'/>
12694 <indexterm startref="idxantiretroviraldrugs" class='endofrange'/>
12695 <para>
12696 A simple idea blinds us, and under the cover of darkness, much happens
12697 that most of us would reject if any of us looked. So uncritically do
12698 we accept the idea of property in ideas that we don't even notice how
12699 monstrous it is to deny ideas to a people who are dying without
12700 them. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in culture
12701 that we don't even question when the control of that property removes
12702 our
12703 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
12704 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
12705 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
12706 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
12707 this common sense open its eyes.
12708 </para>
12709 <para>
12710 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
12711 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
12712 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
12713 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
12714 to fight <quote>piracy,</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
12715 the idea of <quote>creative property,</quote> while transforming real creators into
12716 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
12717 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
12718 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
12719 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
12720 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
12721 produce the <quote>perfect storm</quote> for free culture.
12722 </para>
12723 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12724 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'>
12725 <primary>biomedical research</primary>
12726 </indexterm>
12727 <para>
12728 In August 2003, a fight broke out in the United States about a
12729 decision by the World Intellectual Property Organization to cancel a
12730 meeting.<footnote><para>
12731 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>,
12732 August 2003, E1, available at
12733 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #59</ulink>; William New, <quote>Global Group's
12734 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
12735 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
12736 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #60</ulink>; William New, <quote>U.S. Official
12737 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
12738 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
12739 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #61</ulink>.
12740 </para></footnote>
12741 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
12742 a meeting to discuss <quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
12743 goods.</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
12744 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
12745 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
12746 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
12747 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
12748 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
12749 that I describe in the Afterword. It included a project to develop
12750 single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs), which are thought to have
12751 great significance in biomedical research. (That nonprofit project
12752 comprised a consortium of the Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and
12753 technological companies, including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
12754 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
12755 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
12756 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
12757 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
12758 in the early 1980s. And it included <quote>open source and free software.</quote>
12759 <indexterm><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
12760 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
12761 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
12762 </para>
12763 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'/>
12764 <para>
12765 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
12766 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
12767 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
12768 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
12769 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
12770 </para>
12771 <para>
12772 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.<footnote><para>
12773 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
12774 meeting.
12775 </para></footnote>
12776 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
12777 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
12778 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
12779 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
12780 property issues.
12781 </para>
12782 <para>
12783 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
12784 about WIPO. In February 2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
12785 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
12786 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
12787 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
12788 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
12789 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
12790 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
12791 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
12792 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
12793 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
12794 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
12795 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
12796 talk about an <quote>Information Society</quote> unless one also talked about the
12797 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
12798 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
12799 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
12800 stuff of
12801 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
12802 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
12803 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
12804 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
12805 </para>
12806 <para>
12807 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
12808 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
12809 thus the meeting about <quote>open and collaborative projects to create
12810 public goods</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
12811 </para>
12812 <para>
12813 But there is one project within that list that is highly
12814 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is <quote>open source
12815 and free software.</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
12816 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
12817 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
12818 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
12819 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
12820 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
12821 rather than <quote>proprietary software,</quote> for their own internal uses.
12822 </para>
12823 <para>
12824 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
12825 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
12826 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
12827 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
12828 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
12829 operating system, the most famous bit of <quote>free software</quote>&mdash;and IBM
12830 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support <quote>open source and
12831 free software</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
12832 to support a mode of software development that is different from
12833 Microsoft's.<footnote><para>
12834 <!-- f8. -->
12835 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
12836 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
12837 <quote>open source</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
12838 principal opposition is to <quote>free software</quote> licensed under a <quote>copyleft</quote>
12839 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
12840 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, <quote>The Future
12841 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
12842 Toward Open Source Software</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
12843 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
12844 Public Policy Research, 2002), 69, available at
12845 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #62</ulink>. See also
12846 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, <citetitle>The Commercial Software
12847 Model</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (3
12848 May 2001), available at
12849 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #63</ulink>.
12850 </para></footnote>
12851 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
12852 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft</quote> licenses</primary></indexterm>
12853 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12854 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12855 </para>
12856 <para>
12857 More important for our purposes, to support <quote>open source and free
12858 software</quote> is not to oppose copyright. <quote>Open source and free software</quote>
12859 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
12860 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
12861 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
12862 by
12863 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
12864 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
12865 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
12866 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
12867 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
12868 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
12869 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
12870 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
12871 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
12872 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
12873 </para>
12874 <para>
12875 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
12876 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
12877 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
12878 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
12879 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
12880 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
12881 States government to veto the meeting.<footnote><para>
12882 <!-- f9. -->
12883 Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> available at <ulink
12884 url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #64</ulink>.
12885 </para></footnote>
12886 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
12887 <indexterm><primary>Krim, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
12888 </para>
12889 <para>
12890 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
12891 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
12892 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
12893 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
12894 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
12895 its lobbying efforts.
12896 </para>
12897 <para>
12898 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
12899 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
12900 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
12901 Office, explained that <quote>open-source software runs counter to the
12902 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.</quote>
12903 She is quoted as saying, <quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
12904 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
12905 goals of WIPO.</quote>
12906 </para>
12907 <para>
12908 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
12909 </para>
12910 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
12911 <para>
12912 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
12913 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
12914 right called <quote>copyright</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
12915 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it <quote>runs counter</quote> to the mission
12916 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
12917 in understanding&mdash;the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
12918 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
12919 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
12920 </para>
12921 <para>
12922 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to <quote>promote</quote>
12923 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
12924 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
12925 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
12926 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
12927 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
12928 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
12929 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
12930 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
12931 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
12932 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
12933 </para>
12934 <para>
12935 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
12936 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
12937 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
12938 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
12939 <emphasis>their</emphasis> rights. If they want to <quote>waive</quote> or
12940 <quote>disclaim</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
12941 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $20 billion to do
12942 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
12943 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
12944 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
12945 to do with <emphasis>their</emphasis> property.
12946 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
12947 </para>
12948 <para>
12949 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
12950 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,</quote> she's
12951 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
12952 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
12953 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
12954 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from <quote>waiving</quote> or
12955 <quote>disclaiming</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
12956 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
12957 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
12958 way possible.
12959 </para>
12960 <para>
12961 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
12962 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called <quote>feudalism.</quote> Under
12963 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
12964 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
12965 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
12966 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
12967 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
12968 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
12969 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
12970 that control.
12971 </para>
12972 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12973 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
12974 <para>
12975 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
12976 choice we are now making about intellectual property.<footnote><para>
12977 <!-- f10. -->
12978 See Drahos with Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism</citetitle>, 210&ndash;20.
12979 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12980 </para></footnote>
12981 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
12982 choice now is whether that information society will be
12983 <emphasis>free</emphasis> or <emphasis>feudal</emphasis>. The trend is
12984 toward the feudal.
12985 </para>
12986 <para>
12987 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
12988 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
12989 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
12990 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
12991 </para>
12992 <blockquote>
12993 <para>
12994 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
12995 it should be (<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
12996 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
12997 not simply to promote intellectual property rights</quote>), not as it is. If
12998 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
12999 say anything wrong. But in the world
13000 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13001 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13002 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13003 </para>
13004 </blockquote>
13005 <para>
13006 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13007 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13008 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13009 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13010 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13011 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13012 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13013 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13014 </para>
13015 <para>
13016 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13017 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13018 <quote>goal</quote> of a government should be <quote>to promote the right balance</quote> of
13019 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13020 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. <quote>Typical for
13021 an academic,</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13022 </para>
13023 <para>
13024 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13025 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13026 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13027 our own country's history).
13028 </para>
13029 <para>
13030 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13031 government should be to <quote>seek balance,</quote> then count me with the silly,
13032 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13033 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13034 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13035 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13036 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13037 not lies is just na&iuml;ve, then who have we, the most powerful
13038 democracy in the world, become?
13039 </para>
13040 <para>
13041 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13042 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13043 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13044 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13045 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13046 been part of our tradition for most of our history&mdash;free culture.
13047 </para>
13048 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
13049 <para>
13050 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon. There are
13051 moments of hope in this struggle. And moments that surprise. When the
13052 FCC was considering relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby
13053 further increase the concentration in media ownership, an
13054 extraordinary bipartisan coalition formed to fight this change. For
13055 perhaps the first time in history, interests as diverse as the NRA,
13056 the ACLU, Moveon.org, William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women
13057 for Peace organized to oppose this change in FCC policy. An
13058 astonishing 700,000 letters were sent to the FCC, demanding more
13059 hearings and a different result.
13060 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted</primary></indexterm>
13061 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
13062 </para>
13063 <para>
13064 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13065 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13066 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13067 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13068 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13069 concentration in the media.
13070 </para>
13071 <para>
13072 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13073 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13074 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13075 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13076 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13077 </para>
13078 <para>
13079 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13080 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13081 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13082 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13083 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13084 range of rights&mdash;property rights of a historically extreme
13085 form&mdash;that makes their bigness bad.
13086 </para>
13087 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13088 <para>
13089 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13090 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13091 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13092 Americans have a long history of fighting <quote>big,</quote> wisely or not. That
13093 we could be motivated to fight <quote>big</quote> again is not something new.
13094 </para>
13095 <para>
13096 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13097 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13098 the idea of <quote>intellectual property.</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13099 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13100 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13101 called <quote>property</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13102 </para>
13103 <para>
13104 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13105 of our tragedy.
13106 </para>
13107 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob</primary></indexterm>
13108 <para>
13109 As I write these final words, the news is filled with stories about
13110 the RIAA lawsuits against almost three hundred individuals.<footnote><para>
13111 <!-- f11. -->
13112 John Borland, <quote>RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers,</quote> CNET News.com, September
13113 2003, available at
13114 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #65</ulink>; Paul
13115 R. La Monica, <quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,</quote> CNN/Money, 8 September
13116 2003, available at
13117 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #66</ulink>; Soni
13118 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, <quote>Sued for a Song,
13119 N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among 261 Cited as Sharers,</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News</citetitle>, 9
13120 September 2003, 3; Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13121 Targets; Single Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13122 Defendants,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13123 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,</quote> <citetitle>Wired News</citetitle>, 10 September 2003,
13124 available at
13125 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #67</ulink>.
13126 </para></footnote>
13127 Eminem has just been sued for <quote>sampling</quote> someone else's
13128 music.<footnote><para>
13129 <!-- f12. -->
13130 Jon Wiederhorn, <quote>Eminem Gets Sued &hellip; by a Little Old Lady,</quote>
13131 mtv.com, 17 September 2003, available at
13132 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #68</ulink>.
13133 </para></footnote>
13134 The story about Bob Dylan <quote>stealing</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13135 finished making the rounds.<footnote><para>
13136 <!-- f13. -->
13137 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, <quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13138 Dylan Songs,</quote> Kansascity.com, 9 July 2003, available at
13139 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #69</ulink>.
13140 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13141 </para></footnote>
13142 An insider from Hollywood&mdash;who insists he must remain
13143 anonymous&mdash;reports <quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13144 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13145 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13146 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13147 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.</quote> Congressmen are
13148 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13149 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13150 kids who use a computer to share content.
13151 </para>
13152 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13153 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13154 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
13155 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto</primary></indexterm>
13156 <indexterm><primary>BBC</primary></indexterm>
13157 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in</primary></indexterm>
13158 <para>
13159 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13160 that it will build a <quote>Creative Archive,</quote> from which British citizens can
13161 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.<footnote><para>
13162 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,</quote> BBC press release,
13163 24 August 2003, available at
13164 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #70</ulink>.
13165 </para></footnote>
13166 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13167 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13168 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13169 country.<footnote><para>
13170 <!-- f15. -->
13171 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,</quote> Creative Commons Weblog, 6 August 2003,
13172 available at
13173 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #71</ulink>.
13174 </para></footnote>
13175 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13176 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13177 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13178 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13179 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13180 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13181 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13182 day into the Causbys.
13183 </para>
13184 <para>
13185 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
13186 potential is ever to be realized.
13187
13188 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
13189
13190 </para>
13191 </chapter>
13192 <chapter label="16" id="c-afterword">
13193 <title>AFTERWORD</title>
13194 <para>
13195
13196 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
13197 At least some who have read this far will agree with me that something
13198 must be done to change where we are heading. The balance of this book
13199 maps what might be done.
13200 </para>
13201 <para>
13202 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
13203 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
13204 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
13205 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
13206 </para>
13207 <para>
13208 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
13209 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
13210 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists&mdash;all to tell this
13211 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
13212 is so important.
13213 </para>
13214 <para>
13215 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
13216 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
13217 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
13218 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
13219 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
13220 </para>
13221 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
13222
13223 <section id="usnow">
13224 <title>US, NOW</title>
13225 <para>
13226 Common sense is with the copyright warriors because the debate so far
13227 has been framed at the extremes&mdash;as a grand either/or: either
13228 property or anarchy, either total control or artists won't be paid. If
13229 that really is the choice, then the warriors should win.
13230 </para>
13231 <para>
13232 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
13233 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
13234 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright&mdash;<quote>All Rights
13235 Reserved</quote>&mdash; and those who reject copyright&mdash;<quote>No Rights
13236 Reserved.</quote> The <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
13237 permission before you <quote>use</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The <quote>No
13238 Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
13239 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
13240 </para>
13241 <para>
13242 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
13243 tilted in the <quote>no rights reserved</quote> direction. Content could be copied
13244 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
13245 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
13246 the
13247
13248 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
13249 original design of the Internet was <quote>no rights reserved.</quote> Content was
13250 <quote>taken</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
13251 unprotected.
13252 </para>
13253 <para>
13254 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
13255 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
13256 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
13257 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
13258 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
13259 architecture made the effective default <quote>no rights reserved,</quote> the
13260 future architecture will make the effective default <quote>all rights
13261 reserved.</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
13262 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
13263 content requires permission. The <quote>cut and paste</quote> world that defines
13264 the Internet today will become a <quote>get permission to cut and paste</quote>
13265 world that is a creator's nightmare.
13266 </para>
13267 <para>
13268 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle&mdash;neither
13269 <quote>all rights reserved</quote> nor <quote>no rights reserved</quote> but <quote>some rights
13270 reserved</quote>&mdash; and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
13271 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
13272 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
13273 before.
13274 </para>
13275
13276 <section id="examples">
13277 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples</title>
13278 <para>
13279 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
13280 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
13281 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
13282 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
13283 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
13284 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
13285 to your neighbors or boss. The <quote>privacy</quote> of your browsing habits was
13286 assured.
13287 </para>
13288 <para>
13289 What made it assured?
13290 </para>
13291 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
13292 <para>
13293 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
13294 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>, your
13295 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
13296 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
13297 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
13298 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
13299 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
13300 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
13301 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
13302 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
13303 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
13304 (there is no law protecting <quote>privacy</quote> in public places), and in many
13305 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
13306 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
13307 </para>
13308 <indexterm><primary>Amazon</primary></indexterm>
13309 <para>
13310 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
13311 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
13312 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
13313 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
13314 <quote>recently viewed</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
13315 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
13316 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any <quote>privacy</quote>
13317 protected by the friction disappears, too.
13318 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet</primary></indexterm>
13319 </para>
13320 <para>
13321 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
13322 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
13323 people should have the <quote>right</quote> to browse in a library without the
13324 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
13325 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
13326 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
13327 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
13328 disappears.
13329 </para>
13330 <para>
13331 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define <quote>privacy</quote>
13332 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
13333 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
13334 friction did.<footnote><para>
13335 <!-- f1. -->
13336
13337 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, <quote>Fair Information Practices and the
13338 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
13339 Law Review</citetitle> 1 (2001): par. 6&ndash;18, available at
13340
13341 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>
13342 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
13343 also Jeffrey Rosen, <citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
13344 in an Anxious Age</citetitle> (New York: Random House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs
13345 between technology and privacy).</para></footnote>
13346 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
13347 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
13348
13349 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
13350 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
13351 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
13352 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
13353 </para>
13354 <para>
13355 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
13356 movement. When computers with software were first made available
13357 commercially, the software&mdash;both the source code and the
13358 binaries&mdash; was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
13359 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
13360 care much about controlling their software.
13361 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13362 </para>
13363 <indexterm><primary>Stallman, Richard</primary></indexterm>
13364 <para>
13365 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
13366 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
13367 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
13368 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
13369 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
13370 people's work.
13371 </para>
13372 <para>
13373 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
13374 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
13375 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
13376 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
13377 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
13378 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
13379 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
13380 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
13381 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
13382 anything else?
13383 </para>
13384 <para>
13385 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
13386 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
13387 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
13388 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
13389 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
13390 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
13391 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
13392 </para>
13393 <para>
13394 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
13395 early 1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
13396 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
13397 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
13398 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
13399 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
13400 fundamentally weakened.
13401 </para>
13402 <para>
13403 Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
13404 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
13405 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's <quote>Linux</quote>
13406 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
13407 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13408 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13409 </para>
13410 <para>
13411 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
13412 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
13413 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
13414 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
13415 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
13416 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
13417 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
13418 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
13419 byproduct.
13420 </para>
13421 <para>
13422 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
13423 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
13424 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
13425 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
13426 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
13427 what before had been passively guaranteed.
13428 </para>
13429 <para>
13430 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
13431 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
13432 scientific journals are produced.
13433 </para>
13434 <indexterm id="idxacademocjournals" class='startofrange'>
13435 <primary>academic journals</primary>
13436 </indexterm>
13437 <para>
13438 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
13439 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
13440 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
13441 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
13442 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
13443 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
13444 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
13445 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
13446 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
13447 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
13448 and Westlaw are also free
13449 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
13450 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
13451 Court opinion through their respective services.
13452 </para>
13453 <para>
13454 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
13455 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
13456 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
13457 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
13458 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
13459 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
13460 access to material that is not in the public domain.
13461 </para>
13462 <para>
13463 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
13464 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
13465 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
13466 </para>
13467 <para>
13468 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
13469 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
13470 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
13471 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
13472 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
13473 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
13474 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
13475 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
13476 the technology of paper journals (architecture)&mdash;namely, that it
13477 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
13478 </para>
13479 <para>
13480 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
13481 that libraries not give the general public access to the
13482 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
13483 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
13484 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
13485 granted before.
13486 </para>
13487 <para>
13488 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
13489 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
13490 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
13491 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
13492 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
13493 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
13494 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
13495 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
13496 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
13497 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
13498 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
13499 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
13500 </para>
13501 <para>
13502 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
13503 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
13504 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
13505 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
13506 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
13507 presumptively a good&mdash;especially when it helps spread knowledge
13508 and science.
13509 </para>
13510 <indexterm startref="idxacademocjournals" class='endofrange'/>
13511
13512 </section>
13513 <section id="oneidea">
13514 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea</title>
13515 <indexterm id="idxcc" class='startofrange'>
13516 <primary>Creative Commons</primary>
13517 </indexterm>
13518 <para>
13519 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
13520 increasing control effected through law and technology.
13521 </para>
13522 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University</primary></indexterm>
13523 <para>
13524 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
13525 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
13526 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
13527 <emphasis>reasonable</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
13528 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
13529 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
13530 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
13531 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
13532 make this possible.
13533 </para>
13534 <para>
13535 <emphasis>Simple</emphasis>&mdash;which means without a middleman, or
13536 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
13537 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
13538 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
13539 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
13540 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
13541 shared. These three expressions together&mdash;a legal license, a
13542 human-readable description, and
13543 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
13544 machine-readable tags&mdash;constitute a Creative Commons license. A
13545 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
13546 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
13547 that the person associated with the license believes in something
13548 different than the <quote>All</quote> or <quote>No</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
13549 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
13550 certain freedoms are given.
13551 </para>
13552 <para>
13553 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
13554 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
13555 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
13556 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
13557 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
13558 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (<quote>share and share
13559 alike</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
13560 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
13561 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
13562 </para>
13563 <para>
13564 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
13565 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
13566 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
13567 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
13568 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
13569 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
13570 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
13571 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
13572 a public domain.
13573 </para>
13574 <para>
13575 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
13576 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
13577 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
13578 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
13579 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
13580 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
13581 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
13582 of content (<quote>content conducers,</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
13583 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
13584 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
13585 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia</primary></indexterm>
13586 </para>
13587 <para>
13588 The aim is not to fight the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts. The aim is to
13589 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
13590 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
13591 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
13592 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
13593 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
13594 the background of digital technologies. New rules&mdash;with different
13595 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
13596 them&mdash;are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
13597 to begin to build those rules.
13598 </para>
13599 <para>
13600 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
13601 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
13602 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
13603 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
13604 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
13605 </para>
13606 <para>
13607 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
13608 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1)
13609 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
13610 and (2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
13611 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (1) will download
13612 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2)
13613 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
13614 them (2)-goods. If there are more (2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the
13615 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
13616 <emphasis>increase</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
13617 </para>
13618 <para>
13619 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
13620 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
13621 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
13622 was a total success.
13623 </para>
13624 <para>
13625 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
13626 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
13627 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
13628 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled <citetitle>Free for All</citetitle>,
13629 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
13630 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
13631 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
13632 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
13633 well.
13634 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)</primary></indexterm>
13635 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13636 </para>
13637 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy</primary></indexterm>
13638 <indexterm><primary>rap music</primary></indexterm>
13639 <para>
13640 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
13641 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
13642 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
13643 reasons. Many who use the <quote>sampling license</quote> do so because anything
13644 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
13645 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
13646 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
13647 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
13648 art&mdash;they, too, sample from others. Because the
13649 <emphasis>legal</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
13650 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
13651 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not <quote>allow</quote>
13652 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
13653 high<footnote><para>
13654 <!-- f2. -->
13655 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
13656 Culture Wars</citetitle> (2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
13657 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
13658 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>.
13659 </para></footnote>),
13660 these artists release into the creative environment content
13661 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
13662 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter</primary></indexterm>
13663 </para>
13664 <para>
13665 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
13666 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
13667 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
13668 you are effectively saying you believe in the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote>
13669 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
13670 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
13671 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
13672 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
13673 this notion of <quote>Some Rights Reserved,</quote> and gives many the chance to
13674 say it to others.
13675 </para>
13676 <para>
13677 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
13678 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
13679 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
13680 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
13681
13682 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
13683 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
13684 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
13685 </para>
13686 <para>
13687 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
13688 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
13689 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
13690 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
13691 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
13692 steps are possible.
13693 </para>
13694 <para>
13695 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
13696 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
13697 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
13698 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
13699 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
13700 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
13701 creativity to spread more easily.
13702 </para>
13703 <indexterm startref="idxcc" class='endofrange'/>
13704
13705 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
13706 </section>
13707 </section>
13708 <section id="themsoon">
13709 <title>THEM, SOON</title>
13710 <para>
13711 We will not reclaim a free culture by individual action alone. It will
13712 also take important reforms of laws. We have a long way to go before
13713 the politicians will listen to these ideas and implement these reforms.
13714 But that also means that we have time to build awareness around the
13715 changes that we need.
13716 </para>
13717 <para>
13718 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
13719 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
13720 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
13721 to our end.
13722 </para>
13723
13724 <section id="formalities">
13725 <title>1. More Formalities</title>
13726 <para>
13727 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
13728 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
13729 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
13730 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
13731 </para>
13732 <para>
13733 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
13734 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
13735 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
13736 protected.
13737 </para>
13738 <para>
13739 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
13740 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
13741 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
13742 default is control, and <quote>formalities</quote> are banished.
13743 </para>
13744 <para>
13745 Why?
13746 </para>
13747 <para>
13748 As I suggested in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
13749 linkend="property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
13750 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
13751 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
13752 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
13753 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
13754 formalities were getting in the way.
13755 </para>
13756 <para>
13757 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
13758 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
13759 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
13760 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
13761 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
13762 trace&mdash; there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
13763 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
13764 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
13765 past. And thus, the <emphasis>lack</emphasis> of formalities forces
13766 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
13767 </para>
13768 <para>
13769 The law should therefore change this requirement<footnote><para>
13770 <!-- f1. -->
13771 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
13772 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
13773 adopted by other countries as well.</para></footnote>&mdash;but it
13774 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
13775 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
13776 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
13777 </para>
13778 <para>
13779 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
13780 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
13781 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
13782 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
13783 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
13784 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
13785 developed by others.
13786 </para>
13787
13788 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
13789
13790 <section id="registration">
13791 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL</title>
13792 <para>
13793 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
13794 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
13795 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
13796 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
13797 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
13798 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
13799 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
13800 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
13801 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
13802 panic&mdash;nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
13803 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
13804 </para>
13805 <para>
13806 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
13807 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
13808 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
13809 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
13810 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
13811 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
13812 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
13813 </para>
13814 <para>
13815 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
13816 There are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world.
13817 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
13818 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
13819 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
13820 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
13821 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
13822 with which registration occurs up.
13823 </para>
13824 <para>
13825 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
13826 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
13827 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
13828 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
13829 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
13830 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
13831 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
13832 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
13833 formality&mdash;while producing a database
13834 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
13835 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
13836 </para>
13837
13838 </section>
13839 <section id="marking">
13840 <title>MARKING</title>
13841 <para>
13842 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
13843 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
13844 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule&mdash;akin to
13845 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
13846 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
13847 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
13848 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
13849 uniformly across all media.
13850 </para>
13851 <para>
13852 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
13853 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
13854 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
13855 use the work.
13856 </para>
13857 <para>
13858 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
13859 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
13860 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
13861 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
13862 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
13863 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
13864 signal from the failure to mark&mdash;not the loss of the copyright, but the
13865 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
13866 </para>
13867 <para>
13868 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
13869 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
13870 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
13871 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
13872 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
13873 doesn't give permission.<footnote><para>
13874 <!-- f2. -->
13875 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
13876 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
13877 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
13878 </para></footnote>
13879 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be <quote>use unless someone
13880 complains.</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
13881 stop using the work in any new
13882 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
13883 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
13884 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
13885 their work.
13886 </para>
13887 <para>
13888 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
13889 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
13890 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
13891 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
13892 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
13893 </para>
13894 <para>
13895 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
13896 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
13897 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
13898 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
13899 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
13900 <emphasis>solely</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
13901 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
13902 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
13903 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
13904 other important functions.
13905 </para>
13906 <para>
13907 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
13908 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
13909 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
13910 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
13911 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
13912 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
13913 </para>
13914 <para>
13915 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
13916 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
13917 make things unclear.
13918 </para>
13919 <para>
13920 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
13921 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
13922 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
13923 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
13924 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
13925 that assertion at the appropriate time.
13926 </para>
13927
13928 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
13929 </section>
13930 </section>
13931 <section id="shortterms">
13932 <title>2. Shorter Terms</title>
13933 <para>
13934 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
13935 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
13936 natural authors.
13937 </para>
13938 <para>
13939 In <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
13940 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
13941 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
13942 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
13943 radical. <citetitle>The Economist</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
13944 copyright term.<footnote><para>
13945
13946 <!-- f3. -->
13947 <quote>A Radical Rethink,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 366:8308 (25 January 2003): 15,
13948 available at
13949 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #74</ulink>.
13950 </para></footnote>
13951 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
13952 </para>
13953 <para>
13954 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
13955 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
13956 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
13957 terms.
13958 </para>
13959 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
13960 <listitem><para>
13961 <!-- (1) -->
13962 <emphasis>Keep it short:</emphasis> The term should be as long as
13963 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
13964 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
13965 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
13966 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
13967 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
13968 </para></listitem>
13969 <listitem><para>
13970 <!-- (2) -->
13971 <emphasis>Keep it simple:</emphasis> The line between the public
13972 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
13973 fuzziness of <quote>fair use,</quote> and the distinction between <quote>ideas</quote> and
13974 <quote>expression.</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
13975 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
13976 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
13977 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
13978 <quote>lawyer-free zone</quote> makes the complexities of <quote>fair use</quote> and
13979 <quote>idea/expression</quote> less necessary to navigate.
13980 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
13981 </para></listitem>
13982 <listitem><para>
13983 <!-- (3) -->
13984 <emphasis>Keep it alive:</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
13985 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
13986 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
13987 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
13988 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
13989 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
13990 pension.<footnote><para>
13991 <!-- f4. -->
13992 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
13993 and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001),
13994 available at
13995 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #75</ulink>.
13996 </para></footnote>
13997 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
13998 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
13999 single form.
14000 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions</primary></indexterm>
14001 </para></listitem>
14002 <listitem><para>
14003 <!-- (4) -->
14004 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14005 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14006 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14007 in 1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14008 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14009 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in 1923 than we
14010 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14011 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14012 the number of authors who wrote in 1923. Of course, we can increase
14013 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14014 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14015 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14016 creativity in 1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14017 we can do about that now. </para></listitem>
14018 </orderedlist>
14019 <para>
14020 These changes together should produce an <emphasis>average</emphasis>
14021 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until 1976,
14022 the average term was just 32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14023 same.
14024 </para>
14025 <para>
14026 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas <quote>radical.</quote> (After all, I
14027 call them <quote>extremists.</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14028 than the term under Richard Nixon. How <quote>radical</quote> can it be to ask for
14029 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14030 </para>
14031
14032 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14033
14034 </section>
14035 <section id="freefairuse">
14036 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use</title>
14037 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
14038 <indexterm>
14039 <primary>property rights</primary>
14040 <secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary>
14041 </indexterm>
14042 <para>
14043 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14044 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14045 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14046 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14047 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14048 the emergence of that new technology.
14049 </para>
14050 <para>
14051 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors <quote>exclusive
14052 right</quote> to <quote>their writings.</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14053 right to <quote>their writings</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14054 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14055 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14056 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14057 though that movie is not <quote>my writing.</quote>
14058 </para>
14059 <para>
14060 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it
14061 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14062 control translations and dramatizations of a work.<footnote><para>
14063 <!-- f5. -->
14064 Benjamin Kaplan, <citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14065 University Press, 1967), 32.
14066 </para></footnote>
14067 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14068 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14069 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14070 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin</primary></indexterm>
14071 </para>
14072 <blockquote>
14073 <para>
14074 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14075 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14076 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14077 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.<footnote><para>
14078 <!-- f6. --> Ibid., 56.
14079 </para></footnote>
14080 </para>
14081 </blockquote>
14082 <para>
14083 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14084 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14085 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14086 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14087 Consider each limitation in turn.
14088 </para>
14089 <para>
14090 <emphasis>Term:</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14091 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14092 sense to protect John
14093
14094 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14095 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14096 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14097 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14098 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14099 after the creative work is done.
14100 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
14101 </para>
14102 <para>
14103 <emphasis>Scope:</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14104 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14105 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14106 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14107 material. When all <quote>reuse</quote> of creative material was within the control
14108 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14109 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14110 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14111 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14112 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14113 the creative process. Smothers it.
14114 </para>
14115 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
14116 <para>
14117 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14118 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14119 foreseeable derivative rights&mdash;turning a book into a movie, or a
14120 poem into a musical score&mdash;it doesn't make sense to require
14121 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14122 much more sense.
14123 </para>
14124 <para>
14125 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14126 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14127 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14128 Paul Goldstein.<footnote>
14129 <para>
14130 <!-- f7. -->
14131 Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14132 Jukebox</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187&ndash;216.
14133 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul</primary></indexterm>
14134 </para></footnote>
14135 His view is that the law should be written so that
14136 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14137 </para>
14138 <para>
14139 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14140 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14141 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14142 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14143 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14144 </para>
14145 <para>
14146 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14147 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
14148 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
14149 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
14150 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
14151 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
14152 </para>
14153 </section>
14154
14155 <section id="liberatemusic">
14156 <title>4. Liberate the Music&mdash;Again</title>
14157 <para>
14158 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
14159 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
14160 is, to most people, most pressing&mdash;music. There is no other
14161 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
14162 battles around the sharing of music.
14163 </para>
14164 <para>
14165 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
14166 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
14167 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
14168 killer app&mdash;possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
14169 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
14170 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
14171 innovation on the network.
14172 </para>
14173 <para>
14174 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
14175 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
14176 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
14177 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
14178 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
14179 </para>
14180 <para>
14181 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
14182 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
14183 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
14184 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="piracy"/>, they enable
14185 four different kinds of sharing:
14186 </para>
14187 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
14188 <listitem><para>
14189 <!-- A. -->
14190 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
14191 for purchasing CDs.
14192 </para></listitem>
14193 <listitem><para>
14194 <!-- B. -->
14195 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
14196 on the way to purchasing CDs.
14197 </para></listitem>
14198 <listitem><para>
14199 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
14200 <!-- C. -->
14201 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14202 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
14203 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
14204 </para></listitem>
14205 <listitem><para>
14206 <!-- D. -->
14207 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14208 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
14209 owner plainly endorses.
14210 </para></listitem>
14211 </orderedlist>
14212 <para>
14213 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
14214 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
14215 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
14216 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
14217 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
14218 significantly weakened.
14219 </para>
14220 <para>
14221 As I said in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
14222 linkend="piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
14223 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
14224 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
14225 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
14226 networks.
14227 </para>
14228 <para>
14229 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
14230 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
14231 should respond.
14232 </para>
14233 <para>
14234 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
14235 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
14236 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
14237 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
14238 is cumbersome and slow&mdash;we in the United States are lucky to have
14239 broadband service at 1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
14240 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
14241 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
14242 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
14243 Internet is mainly just an idea.
14244 </para>
14245 <para>
14246 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
14247 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
14248 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
14249 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
14250 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
14251 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
14252 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
14253 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
14254 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
14255 where everywhere you are&mdash;except maybe the desert or the
14256 Rockies&mdash;you can instantaneously be connected to the
14257 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
14258 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
14259 </para>
14260 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over</primary></indexterm>
14261 <para>
14262 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
14263 give you access to content on the fly&mdash;such as Internet radio,
14264 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
14265 then, is the critical point: When it is <emphasis>extremely</emphasis>
14266 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
14267 <emphasis>easier</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
14268 access to content than it will be to download and store content
14269 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
14270 content</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
14271 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
14272 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
14273 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
14274 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
14275 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
14276 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
14277 paying for this content even though <quote>free</quote> content is available in the
14278 form of MP3s across the Web.<footnote><para>
14279 <!-- f8. -->
14280 See, for example, <quote>Music Media Watch,</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3
14281 April 2002, available at
14282 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #76</ulink>.
14283 </para></footnote>
14284
14285 </para>
14286 <para>
14287 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
14288 present: It is emphatically temporary. The <quote>problem</quote> with file
14289 sharing&mdash;to the extent there is a real problem&mdash;is a problem
14290 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
14291 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
14292 makers today to be <quote>solving</quote> this problem in light of a technology
14293 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
14294 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
14295 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
14296 artists get paid, during
14297
14298 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
14299 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
14300 and twenty-first-century technologies.
14301 </para>
14302 <para>
14303 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different <quote>problems</quote>
14304 here to solve. Let's start with type D content&mdash;uncopyrighted
14305 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
14306 <quote>problem</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
14307 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
14308 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
14309 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
14310 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
14311 order to eliminate kidnapping.
14312 </para>
14313 <para>
14314 Type C content raises a different <quote>problem.</quote> This is content that was,
14315 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
14316 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
14317 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
14318 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
14319 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
14320 way that returns something to the artist.
14321 </para>
14322 <para>
14323 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
14324 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
14325 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
14326 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
14327 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
14328 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
14329 from the author's perspective, this <quote>sharing</quote> of his content without
14330 his being compensated is less than ideal.
14331 </para>
14332 <para>
14333 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
14334 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
14335 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
14336 providers would be free, under this rule, to <quote>share</quote> that content,
14337 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
14338 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
14339 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
14340 </para>
14341 <para>
14342
14343 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
14344 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
14345 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
14346 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
14347 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
14348 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
14349 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
14350 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
14351 trade.
14352 </para>
14353 <para>
14354 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
14355 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
14356 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
14357 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
14358 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
14359 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
14360 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
14361 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
14362 </para>
14363 <para>
14364 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
14365 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
14366 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
14367 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
14368 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
14369 delivering and accessing content.
14370 </para>
14371 <para>
14372 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
14373 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
14374 </para>
14375 <para>
14376 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
14377 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
14378 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
14379 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
14380 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
14381 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
14382 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
14383 harmed the interests of the content industry.
14384 </para>
14385 <para>
14386 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
14387 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
14388 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
14389 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
14390 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
14391 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
14392 way to compensate those who are harmed.
14393 </para>
14394 <para>
14395 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
14396 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.<footnote>
14397 <para>
14398 <!-- f9. -->
14399 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'>
14400 <primary>artists</primary>
14401 <secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary>
14402 </indexterm>
14403 William Fisher, <citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities</citetitle> (last
14404 revised: 10 October 2000), available at
14405 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #77</ulink>; William
14406 Fisher, <citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
14407 Entertainment</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
14408 2004), ch. 6, available at
14409 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #78</ulink>. Professor
14410 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
14411 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
14412 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, <quote>Impose a
14413 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,</quote> available at
14414 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Who's Holding Back
14415 Broadband?</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
14416 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
14417 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, 26 February 2002,
14418 available at
14419 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, <citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
14420 Use Fee (IPUF)</citetitle>, 3 March 2002, available at
14421 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
14422 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 13 May
14423 2002, available at
14424 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, <quote>Getting Copyright Right,</quote>
14425 IEEE Spectrum Online, 1 July 2002, available at
14426 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #83</ulink>; Declan
14427 McCullagh, <quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,</quote> CNET News.com, 27 August
14428 2002, available at
14429 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #84</ulink>.
14430 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
14431 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
14432 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
14433 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
14434 debate by about a decade. See
14435 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #85</ulink>.
14436 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William</primary></indexterm>
14437 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
14438 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
14439 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'/>
14440 </para></footnote>
14441 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
14442 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
14443 would (1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
14444 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
14445 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
14446 develop (2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
14447 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (3) artists would be
14448 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (4) an appropriate
14449 tax.
14450 </para>
14451 <para>
14452 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
14453 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
14454 <citetitle>Promises to Keep</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
14455 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
14456 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
14457 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
14458 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
14459 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
14460 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
14461 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
14462 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
14463 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
14464 controlling access.
14465 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
14466 </para>
14467 <indexterm>
14468 <primary>artists</primary>
14469 <secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary>
14470 </indexterm>
14471 <para>
14472 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
14473 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
14474 the system supports the widest range of <quote>semiotic democracy</quote>
14475 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
14476 other changes I described were accomplished&mdash;in particular, the
14477 limits on derivative
14478
14479 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
14480 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
14481 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
14482 allowed to do with the content itself.
14483 </para>
14484 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
14485 <para>
14486 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
14487 <quote>harm</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
14488 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
14489 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
14490 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
14491 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat <quote>free</quote> by being
14492 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
14493 of songs at even the very high price of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents,
14494 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
14495 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
14496 Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a song. And no doubt
14497 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
14498 on-line.
14499 </para>
14500 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
14501 <para>
14502 This competition has already occurred against the background of <quote>free</quote>
14503 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
14504 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
14505 that, there is nothing impossible at all about <quote>competing with free.</quote>
14506 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
14507 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
14508 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
14509 theaters are often luxurious&mdash;with <quote>first class</quote> seats, and meals
14510 served while you watch a movie&mdash;as they struggle and succeed in
14511 finding ways to compete with <quote>free.</quote>
14512 </para>
14513 <para>
14514 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
14515 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
14516 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
14517 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
14518 innovators&mdash;ones who would have a right to the content, and would
14519 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
14520 the law.
14521 </para>
14522 <para>
14523 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
14524 </para>
14525 <para>
14526
14527 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
14528 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
14529 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
14530 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
14531 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
14532 create.
14533 </para>
14534 <para>
14535 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
14536 by
14537 </para>
14538 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14539 <listitem><para>
14540 <!-- 1. -->
14541 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
14542 </para></listitem>
14543 <listitem><para>
14544 <!-- 2. -->
14545 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
14546 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
14547 statute;
14548 </para></listitem>
14549 <listitem><para>
14550 <!-- 3. -->
14551 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
14552 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
14553 </para></listitem>
14554 </orderedlist>
14555 <para>
14556 But what if <quote>piracy</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
14557 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
14558 consumers continue to <quote>take</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
14559 something then?
14560 </para>
14561 <para>
14562 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
14563 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
14564 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
14565 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
14566 technology that is 95 percent secure and produces a market of size <citetitle>x</citetitle>,
14567 or (b) to have a technology that is 50 percent secure but produces a
14568 market of five times <citetitle>x</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
14569 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
14570 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
14571 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
14572 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
14573 pirates.
14574 </para>
14575 <para>
14576 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
14577 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
14578 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
14579
14580 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
14581 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
14582 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
14583 </para>
14584 </section>
14585
14586 <section id="firelawyers">
14587 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers</title>
14588 <para>
14589 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
14590 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
14591 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
14592 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
14593 </para>
14594 <para>
14595 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
14596 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
14597 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
14598 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
14599 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
14600 strong view queers the law.
14601 </para>
14602 <para>
14603 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
14604 <quote>radical</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
14605 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
14606 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
14607 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
14608 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
14609 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
14610 Nimmer, thought it obvious.<footnote><para>
14611 <!-- f10. -->
14612 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Copyright's First Amendment</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
14613 Memorial Lecture), <citetitle>UCLA Law Review</citetitle> 48 (2001): 1057, 1069&ndash;70.
14614 </para></footnote>
14615
14616 </para>
14617 <para>
14618 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
14619 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
14620 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
14621 </para>
14622 <para>
14623 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
14624 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
14625 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
14626 the legal system are slight.<footnote><para>
14627 <!-- f11. -->
14628 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
14629 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
14630 leading him to question his own publicly stated
14631 position&mdash;twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
14632 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
14633 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
14634 J. Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
14635 Drive the Digital Marketplace</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002), (reviewing his
14636 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
14637 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?</quote> working paper, June 2003,
14638 available at
14639 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #86</ulink>.
14640 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
14641 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
14642 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
14643 <citetitle>Rethinking</citetitle>, 174&ndash;76.
14644 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
14645 </para></footnote>
14646 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
14647 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
14648 them it works.
14649 </para>
14650 <para>
14651 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
14652 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
14653 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
14654 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
14655 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
14656 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
14657 practically never be done.
14658 </para>
14659 <para>
14660 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
14661 billed at the largest firms at more than $400 per hour. How much time
14662 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
14663 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
14664 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
14665 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
14666 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
14667 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
14668 </para>
14669 <para>
14670 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
14671 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
14672 their duty to change the way the law works&mdash;or better, to change the
14673 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
14674 top 1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
14675 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
14676 </para>
14677 <para>
14678 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
14679 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
14680 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
14681 its review.
14682 </para>
14683 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
14684 <para>
14685 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
14686 technology&mdash;the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
14687 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
14688 technology&mdash;a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
14689 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
14690 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
14691 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
14692 </para>
14693 <para>
14694 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture&mdash;but it should
14695 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
14696
14697 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311 -->
14698 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
14699 simple pragmatic question: <quote>Will it do good?</quote> When challenged about
14700 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, <quote>Why not?</quote>
14701 </para>
14702 <para>
14703 We should ask, <quote>Why?</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
14704 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
14705 keep your lawyers away.
14706 </para>
14707 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
14708 </section>
14709 </section>
14710 </chapter>
14711 <chapter label="17" id="c-notes">
14712 <title>NOTES</title>
14713 <para>
14714 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
14715 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
14716 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
14717 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
14718 this book. For each link below, you can go to
14719 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
14720 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
14721 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
14722 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
14723 the material.
14724 </para>
14725 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
14726
14727 </chapter>
14728 <chapter label="18" id="c-acknowledgments">
14729 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS</title>
14730 <para>
14731 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
14732 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
14733 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
14734 to him that this book is dedicated.
14735 </para>
14736 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
14737 <para>
14738 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
14739 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
14740 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
14741 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
14742 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
14743 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
14744 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
14745 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
14746 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
14747 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
14748 critical eye on much of this.
14749 </para>
14750 <para>
14751 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
14752 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
14753 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
14754 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
14755 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
14756 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
14757 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
14758 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
14759 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
14760 </para>
14761 <para>
14762 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
14763 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
14764 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
14765 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
14766 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
14767 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
14768 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
14769 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
14770 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
14771 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
14772 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
14773 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
14774 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
14775 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
14776 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, <quote>Wink,</quote> Roger Wood, <quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,</quote>
14777 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
14778 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
14779 a bunch of great replies.)
14780 </para>
14781 <para>
14782 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
14783 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
14784 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
14785 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
14786 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
14787 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
14788 throughout this book.
14789 </para>
14790 <para>
14791 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
14792 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
14793 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
14794 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
14795 </para>
14796 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->
14797
14798 </chapter>
14799 <index></index>
14800 </book>