]> pere.pagekite.me Git - text-free-culture-lessig.git/blob - freeculture.xml
Make dedication text larger, at least with dblatex.
[text-free-culture-lessig.git] / freeculture.xml
1 <?xml version='1.0' encoding='UTF-8' ?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href="docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type="text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012 with input from Martin Borg. -->
5 <!--
6 TODO
7 * indexterm primary
8 -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC "-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
11 [
12 <!ENTITY copy "©">
13 <!ENTITY translationblock "">
14 ]>
15 <book id="index" lang="en">
16 <bookinfo>
17 <title>Free Culture</title>
18
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
20
21 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
22 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY</subtitle>
23
24 <pubdate>2004-03-25</pubdate>
25
26 <releaseinfo>Version 2004-02-10</releaseinfo>
27
28 <authorgroup>
29 <author>
30 <firstname>Lawrence</firstname>
31 <surname>Lessig</surname>
32 </author>
33 <!--
34 Keep these out to avoid showing up as author in the PDF.
35
36 <editor>
37 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
38 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
39 </editor>
40
41 <othercredit role='converter'>
42 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
43 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
44 <contrib>Created this Docbook version from an earlier version</contrib>
45 </othercredit>
46 -->
47 </authorgroup>
48
49 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
50 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
51 -->
52 <subjectset scheme="libraryofcongress">
53 <subject>
54 <subjectterm>Intellectual property&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
55 </subject>
56 <subject>
57 <subjectterm>Mass media&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
58 </subject>
59 <subject>
60 <subjectterm>Technological innovations&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
61 </subject>
62 <subject>
63 <subjectterm>Art&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
64 </subject>
65 </subjectset>
66
67
68 <publisher>
69 <publishername>Petter Reinholdtsen</publishername>
70 <address><city>Oslo</city></address>
71 </publisher>
72
73 <copyright>
74 <year>2004</year>
75 <holder>Lawrence Lessig</holder>
76 </copyright>
77 <legalnotice>
78 <para>
79 <inlinemediaobject>
80 <imageobject>
81 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.png" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
82 </imageobject>
83 <imageobject>
84 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.svg" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
85 </imageobject>
86 <textobject>
87 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved</phrase>
88 </textobject>
89 </inlinemediaobject>
90 </para>
91
92 <para>
93 This version of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is licensed under
94 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
95 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
96 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
97 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/</ulink>
98 </para>
99 </legalnotice>
100
101 <abstract>
102 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR</title>
103 <para>
104 LAWRENCE LESSIG
105 (<ulink url="http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org</ulink>),
106 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
107 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
108 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
109 (<ulink url="http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org</ulink>).
110 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) and Code: And
111 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), Lessig is a member of
112 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
113 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
114 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
115 twice listed in BusinessWeek's <quote>e.biz 25,</quote> and named one of Scientific
116 American's <quote>50 visionaries.</quote> A graduate of the University of
117 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
118 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
119 Appeals.
120 </para>
121 </abstract>
122
123 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
124 <mediaobject role="cover">
125 <imageobject remap="lrg" role="front-large">
126 <imagedata fileref="images/cover.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
127 </imageobject>
128 <!--
129 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
130 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
131 </imageobject>
132 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
133 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
134 </imageobject>
135 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
136 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
137 </imageobject>
138 -->
139 </mediaobject>
140
141 <biblioid class="isbn">978-82-92812-XX-Y</biblioid>
142
143 <!-- LCCN from
144 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
145 -->
146 <biblioid class="libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
147
148 </bookinfo>
149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
150 <dedication id="alsobylessig">
151 <title>
152 Also by Lawrence Lessig
153 </title>
154 <para>
155 <!-- 2014 -->
156 The USA is lesterland: The nature of congressional corruption
157 </para>
158 <para>
159 <!-- 2011, 2012 -->
160 Republic, lost: How money corrupts Congress - and a plan to stop it
161 </para>
162 <para>
163 <!-- 2008 -->
164 Remix: Making art and commerce thrive in the hybrid economy
165 </para>
166 <para>
167 <!-- 2006 -->
168 Code: Version 2.0
169 </para>
170 <para>
171 <!-- 2001, 2002 -->
172 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
173 </para>
174 <para>
175 <!-- 1999 -->
176 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
177 </para>
178 </dedication>
179 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
180 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
182 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
183 <dedication><title></title>
184 <!-- FIXME figure out how to do this better in dblatex and docbook-xsl -->
185 <?latex {\Huge \centering ?>
186 <para>
187 To Eric Eldred &mdash; whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
188 it continues still.
189 </para>
190 <?latex } ?>
191 </dedication>
192
193 <toc id="toc"></toc>
194
195 <lot>
196 <title>List of figures</title>
197 </lot>
198
199 <!--
200 c PREFACE xiii
201 c INTRODUCTION
202 c "PIRACY"
203 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
204 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
205 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
206 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
207 2 Film
208 2 Recorded Music
209 2 Radio
210 2 Cable TV
211 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
212 2 Piracy I
213 2 Piracy II
214 c "PROPERTY"
215 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
216 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
217 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
218 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
219 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
220 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
221 2 Beginnings
222 2 Law: Duration
223 2 Law: Scope
224 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
225 2 Architecture and Law: Force
226 2 Market: Concentration
227 2 Together
228 c PUZZLES
229 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
230 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
231 2 Constraining Creators
232 2 Constraining Innovators
233 2 Corrupting Citizens
234 c BALANCES
235 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
236 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
237 c CONCLUSION
238 c AFTERWORD
239 1 Us, Now
240 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
241 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
242 1 Them, Soon
243 2 1. More Formalities
244 3 Registration and Renewal
245 3 Marking
246 2 2. Shorter Terms
247 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
248 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
249 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
250 c NOTES
251 c ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
252 c INDEX
253 -->
254
255 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
256
257 <preface id="preface">
258 <title>PREFACE</title>
259 <indexterm id='idxpoguedavid' class='startofrange'><primary>Pogue, David</primary></indexterm>
260 <para>
261 <emphasis role="bold">At the end</emphasis> of his review of my first
262 book, <citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle>, David
263 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
264 computer-related texts, wrote this:
265 </para>
266 <blockquote>
267 <para>
268 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
269 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
270 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
271 system, you can always flip off the modem.<footnote id="preface01"><para>
272 David Pogue, <quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 30 January 2000.
273 </para></footnote>
274 </para>
275 </blockquote>
276 <para>
277 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book&mdash;that
278 software, or <quote>code,</quote> functioned as a kind of law&mdash;and his review
279 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
280 could always <quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome</quote>-like simply flip a
281 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
282 any troubles that exist in <emphasis>that</emphasis> space wouldn't
283 <quote>affect</quote> us anymore.
284 </para>
285 <para>
286 Pogue might have been right in 1999&mdash;I'm skeptical, but maybe.
287 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
288 <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
289 causes even after the modem is turned
290 <!--PAGE BREAK 12-->
291 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
292 on-line have fundamentally affected <quote>people who aren't online.</quote> There
293 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
294 </para>
295 <indexterm startref='idxpoguedavid' class='endofrange'/>
296 <para>
297 But unlike <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
298 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
299 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
300 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
301 important.
302 </para>
303 <para>
304 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
305 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of <quote>free culture</quote>&mdash;not
306 <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free beer</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
307 free software movement<footnote>
308 <para>
309 Richard M. Stallman, <citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed. 2002).
310 </para></footnote>), but <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free speech,</quote> <quote>free markets,</quote>
311 <quote>free trade,</quote> <quote>free enterprise,</quote> <quote>free will,</quote> and <quote>free elections.</quote> A
312 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
313 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
314 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
315 follow-on creators and innovators remain <emphasis>as free as
316 possible</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
317 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
318 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
319 <quote>permission culture</quote>&mdash;a culture in which creators get to create
320 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
321 past.
322 </para>
323 <para>
324 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not <quote>we</quote>
325 on the Left or <quote>you</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
326 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
327 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
328 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
329 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
330 culture deem fundamental.
331 </para>
332 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
333 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
334 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
335 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted</primary></indexterm>
336 <para>
337 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
338 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
339 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
340 generated more than 700,000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
341 As William Safire described marching <quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
342 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
343 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,</quote> he formulated perhaps
344 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
345 he asked,
346 </para>
347 <blockquote>
348 <para>
349 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
350 power&mdash;political, corporate, media, cultural&mdash;should be anathema to
351 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
352 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
353 the greatest expression of democracy.<footnote><para> William Safire,
354 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 May 2003.
355 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
356 </para></footnote>
357 </para>
358 </blockquote>
359 <para>
360 This idea is an element of the argument of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle>, though my
361 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
362 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
363 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
364 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
365 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
366 you&mdash;whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
367 Safire's left or on his right.
368 </para>
369 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'/>
370 <para>
371 <emphasis role="strong">The inspiration</emphasis> for the title and for
372 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
373 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
374 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in <citetitle>Free Software, Free
375 Society</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
376 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
377 that this work is <quote>merely</quote> derivative.
378 </para>
379 <para>
380 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
381 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
382 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
383 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
384 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
385 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
386 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
387 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
388
389 <!--PAGE BREAK 14-->
390 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
391 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
392 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
393 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
394 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
395 what I advance here.
396 </para>
397 <para>
398 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
399 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
400 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
401 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
402 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
403 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
404 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
405 book is written.
406 </para>
407
408 </preface>
409 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
410
411 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
412 <chapter label="0" id="c-introduction">
413 <title>INTRODUCTION</title>
414 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
415 <para>
416 <emphasis role="strong">On December 17</emphasis>, 1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
417 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
418 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
419 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
420 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
421 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
422 </para>
423 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.</primary></indexterm>
424 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
425 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
426 <para>
427 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
428 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
429 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
430 and all the space above, to <quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.</quote><footnote><para>
431 St. George Tucker, <citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
432 Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18.
433 </para></footnote>
434 For many
435 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
436 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
437 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
438 </para>
439 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
440 <para>
441 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
442 law&mdash;deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
443 by the most important legal thinkers of our past&mdash;mattered. If
444 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
445 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
446 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
447 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
448 </para>
449 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
450 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
451 <para>
452 In 1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
453 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
454 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
455 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
456 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
457 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
458 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to <quote>an indefinite
459 extent, upwards,</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
460 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
461 </para>
462 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
463 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
464 <indexterm id='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='startofrange'><primary>Douglas, William O.</primary></indexterm>
465 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on airspace vs. land rights</secondary></indexterm>
466 <para>
467 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
468 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
469 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
470 <quote>taking</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
471 that <quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
472 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.</quote> But Justice Douglas
473 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
474 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
475 </para>
476 <blockquote>
477 <para>
478 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
479 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
480 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
481 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
482 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
483 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
484 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
485 the public has a just claim.<footnote>
486 <para>
487 United States v. Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. The Court did find
488 that there could be a <quote>taking</quote> if the government's use of its land
489 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
490 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, <quote>(Intellectual)
491 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
492 Authorship,</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review</citetitle> 48 (1996): 1293, 1333. See also Paul
493 Goldstein, <citetitle>Real Property</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press, 1984),
494 1112&ndash;13.
495 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
496 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
497 </para></footnote>
498 </para>
499 </blockquote>
500 <para>
501 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.</quote>
502 </para>
503 <indexterm startref='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='endofrange'/>
504 <para>
505 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
506 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
507 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
508 <!--PAGE BREAK 18-->
509 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: <quote>Common sense revolts
510 at the idea.</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
511 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
512 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
513 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
514 </para>
515 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
516 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
517 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
518 <para>
519 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
520 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
521 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
522 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
523 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
524 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
525 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
526 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
527 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by <quote>what
528 seemed reasonable</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
529 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
530 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
531 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
532 end, the force of what seems <quote>obvious</quote> to everyone else&mdash;the power of
533 <quote>common sense</quote>&mdash;would prevail. Their <quote>private interest</quote> would not be
534 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
535 </para>
536 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'/>
537 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'/>
538 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'/>
539 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='endofrange'/>
540 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
541 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham</primary></indexterm>
542 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
543 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael</primary></indexterm>
544 <indexterm id='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
545 <para>
546 <emphasis role='strong'>Edwin Howard Armstrong</emphasis> is one of
547 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
548 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
549 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
550 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
551 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
552 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in 1831. But
553 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
554 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
555 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
556 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
557 </para>
558 <para>
559 On the day after Christmas, 1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
560 for his most significant invention&mdash;FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
561 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
562 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
563 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
564 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
565 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
566 much less transmitter power and static.
567 </para>
568 <para>
569 On November 5, 1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
570 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
571 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
572 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
573 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
574 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
575 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
576 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
577 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.</quote>
578 </para>
579 <para>
580 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
581 </para>
582 <blockquote>
583 <para>
584 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
585 sounded like a glass of water being poured. &hellip; A paper was crumpled
586 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
587 fire. &hellip; Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
588 and guitar number were performed. &hellip; The music was projected with a
589 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio <quote>music
590 box.</quote><footnote><para>
591 Lawrence Lessing, <citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong</citetitle>
592 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209.
593 </para></footnote>
594 </para>
595 </blockquote>
596 <indexterm id='idxrca' class='startofrange'><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
597 <indexterm id='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
598 <para>
599 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
600 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
601 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
602 AM radio market. By 1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
603 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
604 a handful of networks.
605 <!--PAGE BREAK 20-->
606 </para>
607 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
608 <para>
609 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
610 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
611 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
612 that removed static from <quote>radio.</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
613 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
614 </para>
615 <blockquote>
616 <para>
617 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
618 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
619 revolution&mdash; start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
620 RCA.<footnote><para> See <quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
621 Electronic Era,</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
622 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
623
624 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #1</ulink>.
625 </para></footnote>
626 </para>
627 </blockquote>
628 <indexterm id='idxfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
629 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
630 <para>
631 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
632 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
633 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
634 described,
635 </para>
636 <indexterm id='idxlessinglawrence' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessing, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
637 <blockquote>
638 <para>
639 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
640 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
641 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
642 unrestrained, posed &hellip; a complete reordering of radio power
643 &hellip; and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
644 on which RCA had grown to power.<footnote><para>Lessing, 226.
645 </para></footnote>
646 </para>
647 </blockquote>
648 <indexterm id='idxfcconfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FCC</primary><secondary>on FM radio</secondary></indexterm>
649 <para>
650 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
651 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
652 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
653 FM radio's deployment generally. In 1936, RCA hired the former head
654 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
655 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM&mdash;principally by moving FM
656 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
657 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
658 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
659 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
660 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
661 </para>
662 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
663 <blockquote>
664 <para>
665 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
666 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
667 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
668 deviousness.<footnote><para>
669 Lessing, 256.
670 </para></footnote>
671 </para>
672 </blockquote>
673 <indexterm startref='idxlessinglawrence' class='endofrange'/>
674 <indexterm><primary>AT&amp;T</primary></indexterm>
675 <para>
676 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
677 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
678 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
679 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
680 (This change was strongly supported by AT&amp;T, because the loss of
681 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
682 wired links from AT&amp;T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
683 least temporarily.
684 </para>
685 <indexterm startref='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='endofrange'/>
686 <indexterm startref='idxfcconfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
687 <para>
688 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
689 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
690 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
691 invalid&mdash;baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
692 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
693 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
694 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
695 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
696 now broke, in 1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
697 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
698 </para>
699 <indexterm startref='idxfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
700 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'/>
701 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
702 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
703 <para>
704 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
705 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
706 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
707 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
708 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
709 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
710 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
711 course always public spirited; the reality is something
712 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
713 to themselves, would crumble in
714 <!--PAGE BREAK 22-->
715 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
716 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
717 effect of technological change.
718 </para>
719 <indexterm startref='idxrca' class='endofrange'/>
720 <indexterm startref='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='endofrange'/>
721 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
722 <para>
723 <emphasis role="strong">There's no</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
724 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
725 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
726 Internet and American Life Project, 58 percent of Americans had access
727 to the Internet in 2002, up from 49 percent two years
728 before.<footnote><para>
729 Amanda Lenhart, <quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
730 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,</quote> Pew Internet and American
731 Life Project, 15 April 2003: 6, available at
732 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #2</ulink>.
733 </para></footnote>
734 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
735 of 2004.
736 </para>
737 <para>
738 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
739 changed things. Some of these changes are technical&mdash;the Internet has
740 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
741 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
742 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
743 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
744 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
745 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
746 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
747 </para>
748 <para>
749 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
750 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
751 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
752 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
753 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
754 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
755 has introduced.
756 </para>
757 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
758 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel</primary></indexterm>
759 <indexterm id='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='startofrange'><primary>culture</primary><secondary>commercial vs. noncommercial</secondary></indexterm>
760 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah</primary></indexterm>
761 <para>
762 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
763 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
764 regulation of each. By <quote>commercial culture</quote> I mean that part of our
765 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
766 <quote>noncommercial culture</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
767 parks or on
768 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
769 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
770 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his <quote>Reader,</quote> or
771 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
772 </para>
773 <para>
774 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
775 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
776 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
777 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
778 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
779 left this culture <quote>free.</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
780 individuals shared and transformed their culture&mdash;telling
781 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
782 clubs, sharing music, making tapes&mdash;were left alone by the law.
783 </para>
784 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>commercial creativity as primary purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
785 <para>
786 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
787 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
788 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
789 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
790 marketplace.<footnote>
791 <para>
792 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
793 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
794 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
795 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
796 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
797 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
798 D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote> Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193,
799 198&ndash;200.
800 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
801 </para></footnote>
802 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
803 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
804 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
805 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
806 </para>
807 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
808 <indexterm><primary>permission culture</primary><secondary> free culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
809 <para>
810 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
811 been erased.<footnote><para>
812 See Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
813 2001), ch. 13.
814 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
815 </para></footnote>
816 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
817 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
818 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
819 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
820 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
821 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
822 the balance of our history&mdash;between uses of our culture that were
823 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission&mdash;has
824 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
825 culture, more and more a permission culture.
826 </para>
827 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
828 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
829 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
830 <indexterm><primary>protection of artists vs. business interests</primary></indexterm>
831 <para>
832 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
833 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
834 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
835 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
836 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
837 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
838 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
839 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
840 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
841 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
842 Causbys.
843 </para>
844 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='endofrange'/>
845 <para>
846 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
847 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
848 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
849 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
850 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
851 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
852 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
853 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
854 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
855 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
856 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
857 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
858 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
859 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
860 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
861 than creators do today&mdash;all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
862 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
863 </para>
864 <para>
865 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
866 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
867 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
868 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
869 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
870 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
871 remakes them.
872 </para>
873 <indexterm startref='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='endofrange'/>
874 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary> on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
875 <para>
876 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
877 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
878 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
879 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions&mdash;whether <quote>piracy</quote> will
880 be permitted, and whether <quote>property</quote> will be protected. The <quote>war</quote> that
881 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet&mdash;what
882 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
883 calls his <quote>own terrorist war</quote><footnote><para>
884 Amy Harmon, <quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
885 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,</quote> <citetitle>New York
886 Times</citetitle>, 17 January 2002.
887 </para></footnote>&mdash;has been framed as a battle about the
888 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
889 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
890 against it.
891 </para>
892 <para>
893 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
894 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
895 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
896 <quote>creative property.</quote> I believe that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that the
897 law, properly tuned, should punish <quote>piracy,</quote> whether on or off the
898 Internet.
899 </para>
900 <para>
901 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
902 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
903 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet <quote>pirates</quote> will also rid our
904 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
905 </para>
906 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
907 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
908 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
909 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
910 <para>
911 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first 180 years of
912 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
913 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
914 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
915 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,<footnote>
916 <para>
917 Neil W. Netanel, <quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
918 Journal</citetitle> 106 (1996): 283.
919 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
920 </para></footnote>
921 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
922 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
923 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
924 could cultivate and extend our culture.
925 </para>
926 <para>
927 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
928 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
929 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
930 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist&ndash;like,
931 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
932 granted&mdash;but it is not often granted to the critical or the
933 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
934 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
935 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
936 </para>
937 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Ask author if "Is it" should be "It is" ? -->
938 <para>
939 The story that follows is about this war. It is not about the
940 <quote>centrality of technology</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
941 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
942 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
943 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
944 against an industry.
945 </para>
946 <para>
947 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
948 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
949 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
950 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
951 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
952 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
953 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
954 </para>
955 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
956 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
957 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary></indexterm>
958 <para>
959 <emphasis role="strong">Like the Causbys'</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about <quote>property.</quote> The
960 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
961 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
962 this <quote>property</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
963 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
964 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
965 of <quote>intellectual property</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
966 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
967 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
968 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
969 <quote>trespassing</quote> upon legitimate claims of <quote>property.</quote> It is as plain to
970 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
971 trespass.
972 </para>
973 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
974 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
975 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
976 <para>
977 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
978 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
979 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
980 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
981 war. Unlike
982 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
983 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
984 on its side.
985 </para>
986 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
987 <para>
988 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
989 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
990 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
991 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
992 our <quote>culture</quote> was as <quote>owned</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
993 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
994 <emphasis>uses</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
995 accepted as it is now.
996 </para>
997 <para>
998 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
999 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
1000 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
1001 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1002 </para>
1003 <para>
1004 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1005 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1006 </para>
1007 <para>
1008 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1009 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1010 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1011 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1012 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1013 </para>
1014 <para>
1015 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1016 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1017 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1018 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1019 view?
1020 </para>
1021 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1022 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1023 <para>
1024 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1025 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1026 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1027 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of <quote>intellectual
1028 property.</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1029 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1030 this silliness will be much more profound.
1031 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1032 </para>
1033 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='endofrange'/>
1034 <para>
1035 <emphasis role="strong">The struggle</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas: <quote>piracy</quote> and
1036 <quote>property.</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1037 ideas.
1038 </para>
1039 <para>
1040 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1041 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1042 obscure French theorists&mdash;however natural that is for the weird
1043 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1044 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1045 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1046 </para>
1047 <para>
1048 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1049 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1050 government, pushed by big media to respond to this <quote>something new,</quote> is
1051 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1052 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let <quote>common
1053 sense</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1054 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1055 law&mdash;and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1056 fundamental about who we have always been.
1057 </para>
1058 <para>
1059 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1060 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1061 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1062 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1063 of one more consequence of this form of corruption&mdash;a consequence
1064 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1065 </para>
1066 </chapter>
1067 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1068 <part id="c-piracy">
1069 <title><quote>PIRACY</quote></title>
1070 <partintro>
1071 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1072 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
1073 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
1074 <indexterm><primary>music publishing</primary></indexterm>
1075 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
1076 <para>
1077 <emphasis role="strong">Since the inception</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1078 been a war against <quote>piracy.</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1079 <quote>piracy,</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1080 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1081 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1082 </para>
1083 <blockquote>
1084 <para>
1085 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1086 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1087 of them for his own use.<footnote><para>
1088 <!-- f1 -->
1089 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield).
1090 </para></footnote>
1091 </para>
1092 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='endofrange'/>
1093 </blockquote>
1094 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary> efficient content distribution on</secondary></indexterm>
1095 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='startofrange'><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>efficiency of</secondary></indexterm>
1096 <para>
1097 Today we are in the middle of another <quote>war</quote> against <quote>piracy.</quote> The
1098 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1099 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1100 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1101 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1102 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1103 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1104 </para>
1105 <para>
1106 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1107 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1108 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1109 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1110 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will <quote>rob the author of the
1111 profit.</quote>
1112 </para>
1113 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='endofrange'/>
1114 <para>
1115 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1116 increasingly to technology to defend their <quote>property</quote> against this
1117 <quote>piracy.</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1118 raised to believe that <quote>property</quote> should be <quote>free.</quote> Forget tattoos,
1119 never mind body piercing&mdash;our kids are becoming
1120 <emphasis>thieves</emphasis>!
1121 </para>
1122 <para>
1123 There's no doubt that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1124 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1125 notion of <quote>piracy</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1126 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1127 </para>
1128 <para>
1129 The idea goes something like this:
1130 </para>
1131 <blockquote>
1132 <para>
1133 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1134 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1135 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1136 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1137 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1138 piracy.
1139 </para>
1140 </blockquote>
1141 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP</primary></indexterm>
1142 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle</primary></indexterm>
1143 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts</primary></indexterm>
1144 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory of</secondary></indexterm>
1145 <indexterm id='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
1146 <para>
1147 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1148 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1149 theory of creative property<footnote><para>
1150 <!-- f2 -->
1151 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, <quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1152 in the Pepsi Generation,</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review</citetitle> 65 (1990): 397.
1153 </para></footnote>
1154 &mdash;if there is value, then someone must have a
1155 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1156 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1157 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.<footnote><para>
1158 <!-- f3 -->
1159 Lisa Bannon, <quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1160 Up,</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 21 August 1996, available at
1161 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #3</ulink>; Jonathan
1162 Zittrain, <quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1163 Speech, No One Wins,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 24 November 2002.
1164 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
1165 </para></footnote>
1166 There was <quote>value</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1167 <quote>right</quote>&mdash;even against the Girl Scouts.
1168 </para>
1169 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='endofrange'/>
1170 <para>
1171 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1172 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1173 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1174 of law protecting creative property. But the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1175 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1176 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1177 </para>
1178 <indexterm startref='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='endofrange'/>
1179 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
1180 <indexterm id='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>legal restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
1181 <para>
1182 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1183 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1184 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1185 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1186 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1187 </para>
1188 <para>
1189 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1190 takes care to draw&mdash;the distinction between republishing someone's
1191 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1192 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1193 copyright law today regulates both.
1194 </para>
1195 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='endofrange'/>
1196 <para>
1197 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1198 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1199 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1200 entities could bear the burden of the law&mdash;even the burden of the
1201 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1202 more expense of doing business.
1203 </para>
1204 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>creativity impeded by</secondary></indexterm>
1205 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1206 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1207 <para>
1208 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1209 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1210 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1211 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1212 <quote>copying,</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1213 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1214 outweighs any original benefit&mdash;certainly as it affects
1215 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1216 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1217 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1218 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1219 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1220 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1221 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1222 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1223 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1224 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the <quote>Rise of the Creative
1225 Class.</quote><footnote>
1226 <para>
1227 <!-- f4 -->
1228 In <citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class</citetitle> (New York:
1229 Basic Books, 2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1230 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1231 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1232 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1233 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1234 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1235
1236 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1237 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1238 </para></footnote>
1239 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1240 this creative class.
1241 </para>
1242 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='endofrange'/>
1243 <para>
1244 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1245 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1246 context the current battles about behavior labeled <quote>piracy.</quote>
1247 </para>
1248 </partintro>
1249
1250 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1251 <chapter label="1" id="creators">
1252 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators</title>
1253 <indexterm id='idxanimatedcartoons' class='startofrange'><primary>animated cartoons</primary></indexterm>
1254 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'><primary>cartoon films</primary></indexterm>
1255 <indexterm id='idxfilmsanimated' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>animated</secondary></indexterm>
1256 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatwillie' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Willie</primary></indexterm>
1257 <indexterm id='idxmickeymouse' class='startofrange'><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
1258 <para>
1259 <emphasis role="strong">In 1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1260 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called <citetitle>Plane Crazy</citetitle>.
1261 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1262 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle> brought
1263 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1264 </para>
1265 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1266 <para>
1267 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1268 movie <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1269 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1270 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1271 Disney ran a test in the summer of 1928, the results were unambiguous.
1272 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1273 </para>
1274 <blockquote>
1275 <para>
1276 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1277 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1278 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1279 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1280 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1281 </para>
1282 <para>
1283 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1284 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1285 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1286 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1287 synchronization was pretty close.
1288 </para>
1289 <para>
1290 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1291 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1292 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1293 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1294 it was something new!<footnote><para>
1295 <!-- f1 -->
1296 Leonard Maltin, <citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1297 Cartoons</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34&ndash;35.
1298 </para></footnote>
1299 </para>
1300 </blockquote>
1301 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub</primary></indexterm>
1302 <para>
1303 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1304 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: <quote>I have never been so thrilled
1305 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.</quote>
1306 </para>
1307 <para>
1308 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1309 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1310 rarely&mdash;except in Disney's hands&mdash;been anything more than
1311 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1312 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1313 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1314 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1315 </para>
1316 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt' class='endofrange'/>
1317 <indexterm id='idxkeatonbuster' class='startofrange'><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1318 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1319 <para>
1320 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that 1928 also marks
1321 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1322 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1323 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>.
1324 </para>
1325 <para>
1326 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in 1895. In the era of silent
1327 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1328 uncontrollable laughter from his audience. <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1329 Jr</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1330 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton&mdash;wildly popular
1331 and among the best of its genre.
1332 </para>
1333 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1334 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1335 <para>
1336 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1337 Willie.
1338 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1339 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1340 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,<footnote><para>
1341 <!-- f2 -->
1342 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1343 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #4</ulink>.
1344 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1345 use the music for five songs in <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>: <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote> <quote>The
1346 Simpleton</quote> (Delille), <quote>Mischief Makers</quote> (Carbonara), <quote>Joyful Hurry No. 1</quote>
1347 (Baron), and <quote>Gawky Rube</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song, <quote>The Turkey in the
1348 Straw,</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1349 Harry Surden, 10 July 2003, on file with author.
1350 </para></footnote>
1351 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1352 the invention of synchronized sound in <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle> that we
1353 get <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1354 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote>
1355 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1356 Mouse.
1357 </para>
1358 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatwillie' class='endofrange'/>
1359 <indexterm startref='idxmickeymouse' class='endofrange'/>
1360 <indexterm startref='idxkeatonbuster' class='endofrange'/>
1361 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='endofrange'/>
1362 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1363 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
1364 <para>
1365 This <quote>borrowing</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1366 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1367 films of his day.<footnote><para>
1368 <!-- f3 -->
1369 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, <quote>The Mouse
1370 that Ate the Public Domain,</quote> Findlaw, 5 March 2002, at
1371 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #5</ulink>.
1372 </para></footnote>
1373 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1374 knockoffs&mdash;slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1375 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1376 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1377 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1378 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1379 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1380 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1381 old.
1382 </para>
1383 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1384 <para>
1385 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1386 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1387 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1388 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1389 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1390 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1391 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1392 </para>
1393 <para>
1394 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1395 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1396 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1397 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1398 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1399 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1400 work of others is astonishing when set together: <citetitle>Snow White</citetitle>
1401 (1937), <citetitle>Fantasia</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Pinocchio</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Dumbo</citetitle>
1402 (1941), <citetitle>Bambi</citetitle> (1942), <citetitle>Song of the South</citetitle> (1946),
1403 <citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle> (1950), <citetitle>Alice in Wonderland</citetitle> (1951), <citetitle>Robin
1404 Hood</citetitle> (1952), <citetitle>Peter Pan</citetitle> (1953), <citetitle>Lady and the Tramp</citetitle>
1405 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1406 (1955), <citetitle>Mulan</citetitle> (1998), <citetitle>Sleeping Beauty</citetitle> (1959), <citetitle>101
1407 Dalmatians</citetitle> (1961), <citetitle>The Sword in the Stone</citetitle> (1963), and
1408 <citetitle>The Jungle Book</citetitle> (1967)&mdash;not to mention a recent example
1409 that we should perhaps quickly forget, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>
1410 (2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1411 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1412 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1413 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1414 </para>
1415 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales' class='endofrange'/>
1416 <para>
1417 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1418 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1419 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1420 its importance. We could call this <quote>Disney creativity,</quote> though that
1421 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, <quote>Walt Disney
1422 creativity</quote>&mdash;a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1423 culture around us and makes it something different.
1424 </para>
1425 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='endofrange'/>
1426 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='endofrange'/>
1427 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='endofrange'/>
1428 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
1429 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>defined</secondary></indexterm>
1430 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>traditional term for conversion to</secondary></indexterm>
1431 <para> In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1432 relatively fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was
1433 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1434 thirty years&mdash;for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1435 copyrighted.<footnote><para>
1436 <!-- f4 -->
1437 Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1438 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the <quote>average</quote> term by
1439 determining
1440 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1441 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in year
1442 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the
1443 average
1444 term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1445 Web site associated with this book, available at
1446 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #6</ulink>.
1447 </para></footnote>
1448 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1449 copyright holders of a creative work had an <quote>exclusive right</quote> to control
1450 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1451 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1452 </para>
1453 <para>
1454 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1455 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1456 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a <quote>lawyer-free
1457 zone.</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1458 for Disney to use and build upon in 1928. It was free for
1459 anyone&mdash; whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1460 approved or not&mdash;to use and build upon.
1461 </para>
1462 <indexterm startref='idxanimatedcartoons' class='endofrange'/>
1463 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsanimated' class='endofrange'/>
1464 <para>
1465 This is the ways things always were&mdash;until quite recently. For most
1466 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1467 until 1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1468 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1469
1470 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1471 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1472 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s
1473 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1474 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1475 content from before the Great Depression.
1476 </para>
1477 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'/>
1478 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc' class='endofrange'/>
1479 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='endofrange'/>
1480 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='endofrange'/>
1481 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='endofrange'/>
1482 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1483 <para>
1484 <emphasis role="strong">Of course</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on <quote>Walt Disney creativity.</quote>
1485 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1486 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1487 universal.
1488 </para>
1489 <indexterm id='idxcomicsjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1490 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1491 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1492 <indexterm id='idxmanga' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1493 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1494 <para>
1495 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1496 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: <citetitle>manga</citetitle>, or
1497 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of
1498 publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives
1499 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1500 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1501 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1502 </para>
1503 <para>
1504 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1505 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1506 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1507 the stories that these <quote>graphic novels</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1508 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are <quote>men in tights.</quote>
1509 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1510 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1511 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1512 interestingly different way.
1513 </para>
1514 <para>
1515 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1516 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1517 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1518 </para>
1519 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1520 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1521 <para>
1522 This is the phenomenon of <citetitle>doujinshi</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1523 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1524 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is <emphasis>just</emphasis> a
1525 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1526 transforming it either subtly or
1527 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1528 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1529 develop it differently&mdash;with a different story line. Or the comic can
1530 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1531 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently <quote>different.</quote> But they
1532 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1533 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1534 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1535 </para>
1536 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1537 <para>
1538 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1539 huge. More than 33,000 <quote>circles</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1540 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come
1541 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1542 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1543 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1544 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1545 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1546 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1547 </para>
1548 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1549 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1550 <para>
1551 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1552 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1553 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1554 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1555 one. Doujinshi are plainly <quote>derivative works.</quote> There is no general
1556 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1557 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1558 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1559 Jr</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that <quote>taking</quote> without
1560 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1561 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1562 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1563 </para>
1564 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt2' class='endofrange'/>
1565 <indexterm id='idxwinickjudd' class='startofrange'><primary>Winick, Judd</primary></indexterm>
1566 <para>
1567 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1568 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1569 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, <quote>The
1570 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1571 in Japan now. &hellip; American comics were born out of copying each
1572 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1573 other. &hellip; That's how [the artists] learn to draw &mdash; by going into comic
1574 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them</quote>
1575 and building from them.<footnote><para>
1576 <!-- f5 -->
1577 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, <citetitle>Reinventing Comics</citetitle> (New
1578 York: Perennial, 2000).
1579 </para></footnote>
1580 </para>
1581 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1582 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics</primary></indexterm>
1583 <para>
1584 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1585 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1586 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, <quote>there are these rules
1587 and you have to stick to them.</quote> There are things Superman <quote>cannot</quote>
1588 do. <quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1589 which are fifty years old.</quote>
1590 </para>
1591 <indexterm startref='idxwinickjudd' class='endofrange'/>
1592 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1593 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1594 <indexterm id='idxmehrasalil' class='startofrange'><primary>Mehra, Salil</primary></indexterm>
1595 <para>
1596 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1597 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1598 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1599 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1600 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1601 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1602 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.<footnote><para>
1603 <!-- f6 -->
1604 See Salil K. Mehra, <quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1605 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1606 Review</citetitle> 55 (2002): 155, 182. <quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1607 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1608 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1609 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1610 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1611 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.</quote>
1612 </para></footnote>
1613 </para>
1614 <indexterm startref='idxcomicsjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1615 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics' class='endofrange'/>
1616 <indexterm startref='idxmanga' class='endofrange'/>
1617 <para>
1618 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1619 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1620 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1621 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1622 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1623 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1624 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1625 a more general pattern of blocking this <quote>free taking</quote> by the doujinshi
1626 culture?
1627 </para>
1628 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='endofrange'/>
1629 <indexterm startref='idxmehrasalil' class='endofrange'/>
1630 <para>
1631 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1632 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1633 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. <quote>We don't have enough
1634 lawyers,</quote> he told me one afternoon. There <quote>just aren't enough resources
1635 to prosecute cases like this.</quote>
1636 </para>
1637 <para>
1638 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1639 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1640 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1641 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1642 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1643 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1644 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1645 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1646 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1647 their clients or hurt them?
1648 </para>
1649 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics' class='endofrange'/>
1650 <para>
1651 <emphasis role='strong'>Let's pause</emphasis> for a moment.
1652 </para>
1653 <para>
1654 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1655 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1656 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1657 </para>
1658 <para>
1659 We live in a world that celebrates <quote>property.</quote> I am one of those
1660 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1661 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1662 <quote>intellectual property.</quote><footnote><para>
1663 <!-- f7 -->
1664 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
1665 The term <citetitle>intellectual property</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1666 Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 11 (New York: New York
1667 University Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
1668 (New York: Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately
1669 describes a set of <quote>property</quote> rights &mdash; copyright, patents,
1670 trademark, and trade-secret &mdash; but the nature of those rights is
1671 very different.
1672 </para></footnote>
1673 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1674 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1675 property.
1676 </para>
1677 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt3' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1678 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1679 <indexterm><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1680 <para>
1681 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1682 plenty of value out there that <quote>property</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1683 mean <quote>money can't buy you love,</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1684 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1685 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1686 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1687 condemning that taking as wrong&mdash; even though trivial, even if
1688 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1689 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1690 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1691 Disney's use would have been considered <quote>fair.</quote> There was nothing
1692 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1693 the public domain.
1694 </para>
1695 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>derivative works based on</secondary></indexterm>
1696 <para>
1697 Thus, even though the things that Disney took&mdash;or more generally,
1698 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity&mdash;are
1699 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1700
1701 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1702 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1703 freedom is good.
1704 </para>
1705 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='endofrange'/>
1706 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1707 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1708 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1709 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1710 <indexterm id='idxmanga2' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1711 <para>
1712 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1713 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1714 work&mdash;or even one copy&mdash;without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1715 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1716 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1717 form, whether large or small.
1718 </para>
1719 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='endofrange'/>
1720 <para>
1721 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1722 say that the copycat comic artists are <quote>stealing.</quote> This form of Walt
1723 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1724 particular find it hard to say why.
1725 </para>
1726 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1727 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1728 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='endofrange'/>
1729 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1730 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1731 <indexterm startref='idxmanga2' class='endofrange'/>
1732 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
1733 <para>
1734 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1735 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1736 without asking or paying for the privilege. (<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1737 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1738 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?</quote>) Acting companies
1739 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1740 permission from anyone. (Does <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> believe
1741 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1742 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1743 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1744 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s;
1745 two volcano disaster films in 1997.
1746 </para>
1747 <para>
1748 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1749 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1750 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1751 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1752 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1753 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1754 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking&mdash;free
1755 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1756 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1757 </para>
1758 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt3' class='endofrange'/>
1759 <para>
1760 The hard question is therefore not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> a
1761 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1762 question instead is <quote><emphasis>How</emphasis> free is this culture?</quote>
1763 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1764 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1765 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1766 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1767 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1768 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1769 a studio or not?
1770 </para>
1771 <para>
1772 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1773 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1774 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1775 </para>
1776 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='endofrange'/>
1777
1778 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1779 </chapter>
1780 <chapter label="2" id="mere-copyists">
1781 <title>CHAPTER TWO: <quote>Mere Copyists</quote></title>
1782 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis</primary></indexterm>
1783 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1784 <indexterm id='idxphotography' class='startofrange'><primary>photography</primary></indexterm>
1785 <para>
1786 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1787 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1788 <quote>photographs.</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1789 <quote>daguerreotypes.</quote> The process was complicated and
1790 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1791 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1792 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1793 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1794 </para>
1795 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William</primary></indexterm>
1796 <para>
1797 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1798 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1799 <quote>automatic pictures.</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1800 making <quote>negatives.</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1801 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1802 the 1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1803 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1804 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1805 amateurs.
1806 </para>
1807 <indexterm id='idxeastmangeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Eastman, George</primary></indexterm>
1808 <para>
1809 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1810 didn't happen until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1811 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1812 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1813 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1814 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1815 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1816 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1817 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1818 population of photographers.
1819 </para>
1820 <indexterm id='idxkodakcameras' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1821 <indexterm id='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)</primary></indexterm>
1822 <para>
1823 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1824 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1825 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. <quote>You press the button and we
1826 do the rest.</quote><footnote><para>
1827 <!-- f1 -->
1828 Reese V. Jenkins, <citetitle>Images and Enterprise</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975), 112.
1829 </para></footnote> As he described in <citetitle>The Kodak Primer</citetitle>:
1830 </para>
1831 <blockquote>
1832 <para>
1833 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1834 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1835 that only an expert can do. &hellip; We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1836 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1837 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1838 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1839 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1840 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1841 chemicals.<footnote>
1842 <para>
1843 <!-- f2 -->
1844 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1845 Brian Coe, <citetitle>The Birth of Photography</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1846 1977), 53.
1847 </para></footnote>
1848 </para>
1849 </blockquote>
1850 <indexterm startref='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='endofrange'/>
1851 <para>
1852 For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1853 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1854 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1855 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1856 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1857 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in 1888; one
1858 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1859 From 1888 through 1909, while industrial production was rising by 4.7
1860 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by 11
1861 percent.<footnote><para>
1862 <!-- f3 -->
1863 Jenkins, 177.
1864 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1865 an average annual increase of over 17 percent.<footnote><para>
1866 <!-- f4 -->
1867 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p. 178.
1868 </para></footnote>
1869 </para>
1870 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1871 <para>
1872
1873 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1874 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1875 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1876 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1877 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1878 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, <quote>For the
1879 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1880 permanent record of his family and its activities. &hellip; For the first
1881 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1882 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1883 interpretation or bias.</quote><footnote><para>
1884 <!-- f5 -->
1885 Coe, 58.
1886 </para></footnote>
1887 </para>
1888 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
1889 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
1890 <para>
1891 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1892 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1893 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1894 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1895 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1896 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its <quote>quality</quote>;
1897 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1898 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1899 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1900 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1901 have before.
1902 </para>
1903 <indexterm startref='idxkodakcameras' class='endofrange'/>
1904 <indexterm id='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>permissions</primary><secondary>photography exempted from</secondary></indexterm>
1905 <para>
1906 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1907 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1908 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1909 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1910 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1911 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1912 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1913 he wanted. Their answer was no.<footnote><para>
1914 <!-- f6 -->
1915 For illustrative cases, see, for example, <citetitle>Pavesich</citetitle>
1916 v. <citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co</citetitle>., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905);
1917 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Chinn</citetitle>, 123090 S.W. 364, 366
1918 (Ky. 1909); <citetitle>Corliss</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Walker</citetitle>, 64 F. 280 (Mass.
1919 Dist. Ct. 1894).
1920 </para></footnote>
1921 </para>
1922 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology' class='endofrange'/>
1923 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt4' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1924 <indexterm id='idximagesownershipof' class='startofrange'><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
1925 <para>
1926 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1927 familiar. The photographer was <quote>taking</quote> something from the person or
1928 building whose photograph he shot&mdash;pirating something of
1929 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1930 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1931 draw
1932 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1933 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1934 that they thought valuable.
1935 </para>
1936 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1937 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1938 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology2' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1939 <para>
1940 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1941 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1942 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1943 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1944 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.<footnote>
1945 <para>
1946 <!-- f7 -->
1947 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote>
1948 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review</citetitle> 4 (1890): 193.
1949 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1950 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.</primary></indexterm>
1951 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1952 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1953 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1954 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1955 </para>
1956 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt4' class='endofrange'/>
1957 <para>
1958 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1959 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1960 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1961 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1962 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1963 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1964 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1965 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1966 clearing the rights to do the capturing.<footnote><para>
1967 <!-- f8 -->
1968 See Melville B. Nimmer, <quote>The Right of Publicity,</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
1969 Problems</citetitle> 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, <quote>Privacy,</quote> <citetitle>California Law
1970 Review</citetitle> 48 (1960) 398&ndash;407; <citetitle>White</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
1971 Inc</citetitle>., 971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951
1972 (1993).
1973 </para></footnote>)
1974 </para>
1975 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1976 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
1977 <para>
1978 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1979 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1980 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1981 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1982 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1983 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1984 Kodak would be benefiting from the <quote>theft</quote> committed by the
1985 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1986 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1987 from the <quote>image-right</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
1988 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1989 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1990 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1991 </para>
1992 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology2' class='endofrange'/>
1993 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology3' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1994 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
1995 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
1996 <para>
1997
1998 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
1999 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
2000 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
2001 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
2002 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
2003 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
2004 technology as they did&mdash;since professionals could have more
2005 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
2006 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
2007 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
2008 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
2009 realized.
2010 </para>
2011 <indexterm startref='idxphotography' class='endofrange'/>
2012 <indexterm startref='idxeastmangeorge' class='endofrange'/>
2013 <indexterm startref='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
2014 <indexterm startref='idximagesownershipof' class='endofrange'/>
2015 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
2016 <indexterm id='idxjustthink' class='startofrange'><primary>Just Think!</primary></indexterm>
2017 <para>
2018 <emphasis role='strong'>If you drive</emphasis> through San
2019 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
2020 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
2021 <quote>Just Think!</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
2022 there's little that's <quote>just</quote> cerebral in the projects
2023 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
2024 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
2025 the film of your VCR. Rather the <quote>film</quote> of digital
2026 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
2027 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
2028 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
2029 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
2030 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
2031 think. By tinkering, they learn.
2032 </para>
2033 <indexterm id='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>education</primary><secondary>in media literacy</secondary></indexterm>
2034 <indexterm id='idxmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>media literacy</primary></indexterm>
2035 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>media literacy and</secondary></indexterm>
2036 <para>
2037 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
2038 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
2039 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, <quote>Five years ago, a good
2040 real-time digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get
2041 professional quality for $595.</quote><footnote><para>
2042 <!-- f9 -->
2043 H. Edward Goldberg, <quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
2044 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,</quote>
2045 cadalyst, February 2002, available at
2046 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #7</ulink>.
2047 </para></footnote>
2048 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
2049 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
2050 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
2051 learning more and more of something teachers call <quote>media literacy.</quote>
2052 </para>
2053 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2054 <para>
2055 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
2056 <quote>Media literacy,</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
2057 Think!, puts it, <quote>is the ability &hellip; to understand, analyze, and
2058 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2059 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2060 the way people access it.</quote>
2061 </para>
2062 <indexterm startref='idxjustthink' class='endofrange'/>
2063 <para>
2064 This may seem like an odd way to think about <quote>literacy.</quote> For most
2065 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2066 and noticing split infinitives are the things that <quote>literate</quote> people know
2067 about.
2068 </para>
2069 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2070 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
2071 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
2072 <para>
2073 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of
2074 television commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000
2075 commercials generally,<footnote><para>
2076 <!-- f10 -->
2077 Judith Van Evra, <citetitle>Television and Child Development</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2078 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990); <quote>Findings on Family and TV
2079 Study,</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post</citetitle>, 25 May 1997, B6.
2080 </para></footnote>
2081 it is increasingly important to understand the <quote>grammar</quote> of media. For
2082 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2083 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2084 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2085 (at least at first) terrible media.
2086 </para>
2087 <para>
2088 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2089 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2090 has written understands how difficult writing is&mdash;how difficult
2091 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2092 language to be understandable&mdash;few of us have any real sense of
2093 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2094 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2095 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2096 </para>
2097 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology3' class='endofrange'/>
2098 <para>
2099 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2100 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2101 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2102 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2103 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2104 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2105 </para>
2106 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2107 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael</primary></indexterm>
2108 <para>
2109 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2110 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2111 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2112
2113 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2114 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2115 about <quote>the placement of objects, color, &hellip; rhythm, pacing, and
2116 texture.</quote><footnote>
2117 <para>
2118 <!-- f11 -->
2119 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish, 13 December
2120 2002.
2121 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2122 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2123 </para></footnote>
2124 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2125 <quote>played</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2126 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2127 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2128 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2129 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2130 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2131 to a wildly successful author.<footnote><para>
2132 <!-- f12 -->
2133 See Scott Steinberg, <quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,</quote> E!online, 4
2134 November 2000, available at
2135 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #8</ulink>; <quote>Timeline,</quote> 22 November 2000,
2136 available at
2137 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #9</ulink>.
2138 </para></footnote>
2139 </para>
2140 <indexterm><primary>computer games</primary></indexterm>
2141 <para>
2142 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2143 describes, <quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2144 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2145 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2146 led.</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2147 </para>
2148 <para>
2149 Yet the push for an expanded literacy&mdash;one that goes beyond text
2150 to include audio and visual elements&mdash;is not about making better
2151 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2152 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2153 </para>
2154 <blockquote>
2155 <para>
2156 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2157 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2158 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2159 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2160 being read-only.
2161 </para>
2162 </blockquote>
2163 <para>
2164 <quote>Read-only.</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2165 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2166 twentieth century.
2167 </para>
2168 <para>
2169 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2170 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2171 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2172 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2173 literacy,
2174 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2175 and this literacy in particular, is to <quote>empower people to choose the
2176 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2177 express.</quote><footnote>
2178 <para>
2179 <!-- f13 -->
2180 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2181 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2182 </para></footnote> It is to enable students <quote>to communicate in the
2183 language of the twenty-first century.</quote><footnote><para>
2184 <!-- f14 -->
2185 Ibid.
2186 </para></footnote>
2187 </para>
2188 <indexterm id='idxbarishstephanie' class='startofrange'><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2189 <para>
2190 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2191 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2192 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2193 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2194 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2195 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2196 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2197 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2198 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2199 students know something about&mdash;gun violence.
2200 </para>
2201 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='endofrange'/>
2202 <para>
2203 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2204 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2205 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2206 away. The <quote>kids were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night,</quote>
2207 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2208 what education should be about&mdash;learning how to express themselves.
2209 </para>
2210 <para>
2211 Using whatever <quote>free web stuff they could find,</quote> and relatively simple
2212 tools to enable the kids to mix <quote>image, sound, and text,</quote> Barish said
2213 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2214 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2215 close to the lives of these students. The project <quote>gave them a tool
2216 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2217 it,</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2218 expression&mdash;far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2219 been created using only text. <quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2220 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2221 gone and done something else,</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2222 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2223 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2224 <emphasis>these</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2225 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2226 </para>
2227 <indexterm startref='idxbarishstephanie' class='endofrange'/>
2228 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2229 <para>
2230
2231 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2232 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?</quote> I asked. In part,
2233 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2234 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of <quote>constructing
2235 meaning.</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2236 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2237 part&mdash;and increasingly, not the most powerful part&mdash;of
2238 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2239 our interview,
2240 </para>
2241 <blockquote>
2242 <para>
2243 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2244 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2245 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2246 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2247 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2248 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2249 you say, <quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.</quote>
2250 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2251 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2252 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, <quote>Well, with all these things that you
2253 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2254 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2255 for me something that reflects that.</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2256 camera and &hellip; saying, <quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2257 make a little movie.</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2258 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2259 about the topic.&hellip;
2260 </para>
2261 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2262 <para>
2263 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2264 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2265 bump up against the fact, <quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2266 to write something.</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2267 they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 times, till they got it right.
2268 </para>
2269 <para>
2270 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2271 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2272 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2273 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2274 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2275 had a lot of power with this language.
2276 </para>
2277 <!-- FIXME removed a " from the end of the previous paragraph that did
2278 not match with any start quote. -->
2279 </blockquote>
2280 <indexterm startref='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2281 <indexterm startref='idxmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2282 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='endofrange'/>
2283 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='endofrange'/>
2284 <indexterm id='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='startofrange'><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2285 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center</primary></indexterm>
2286 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
2287 <para>
2288 <emphasis role='strong'>When two planes</emphasis> crashed into the
2289 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2290 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2291 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2292 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2293 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2294 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2295 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2296 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2297 watching.
2298 </para>
2299 <para>
2300 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2301 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2302 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was <quote>balance,</quote>
2303 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2304 increasingly come to expect it, <quote>news as entertainment,</quote> even if the
2305 entertainment is tragedy.
2306 </para>
2307 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
2308 <indexterm><primary>CBS</primary></indexterm>
2309 <para>
2310 But in addition to this produced news about the <quote>tragedy of September
2311 11,</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2312 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2313 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2314 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2315 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2316 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2317 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2318 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2319 the term in his book <citetitle>Cyber Rights</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2320 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2321 was also the Internet.
2322 </para>
2323 <indexterm startref='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='endofrange'/>
2324 <para>
2325 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet&mdash;though I do think the
2326 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2327 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2328 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2329 movie
2330 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2331 by a student on the <quote>Just Think!</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2332 with sound or text.
2333 </para>
2334 <para>
2335 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2336 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2337 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2338 tradition&mdash;not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2339 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2340 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2341 spread practically instantaneously.
2342 </para>
2343 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2344 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2345 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2346 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2347 <para>
2348 September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2349 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2350 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2351 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2352 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2353 cultures, it records private facts in a public way&mdash;it's a kind
2354 of electronic <citetitle>Jerry Springer</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2355 </para>
2356 <indexterm><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2357 <indexterm id='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>public discourse conducted on</secondary></indexterm>
2358 <para>
2359 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2360 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2361 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2362 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2363 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2364 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2365 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2366 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2367 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2368 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2369 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2370 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2371 </para>
2372 <indexterm id='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
2373 <indexterm id='idxelections' class='startofrange'><primary>elections</primary></indexterm>
2374 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
2375 <para>
2376 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2377 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2378 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2379 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2380 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2381 people vote
2382 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2383 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2384 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2385 </para>
2386 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2387 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson' class='endofrange'/>
2388 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2389 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de</primary></indexterm>
2390 <indexterm id='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>public discourse in</secondary></indexterm>
2391 <indexterm><primary>jury system</primary></indexterm>
2392 <para>
2393 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2394 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2395 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2396 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2397 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2398 most important account of early <quote>Democracy in America.</quote> It wasn't
2399 popular elections that fascinated him&mdash;it was the jury, an
2400 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2401 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2402 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2403 deliberated. Members argued about the <quote>right</quote> result; they tried to
2404 persuade each other of the <quote>right</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2405 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2406 come to an end.<footnote><para>
2407 <!-- f15 -->
2408 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, <citetitle>Democracy in America</citetitle>,
2409 bk. 1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16.
2410 </para></footnote>
2411 </para>
2412 <indexterm startref='idxelections' class='endofrange'/>
2413 <para>
2414 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2415 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2416 are pushing to create just such an institution.<footnote><para>
2417 <!-- f16 -->
2418 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, <quote>Deliberation Day,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2419 Political Philosophy</citetitle> 10 (2) (2002): 129.
2420 </para></footnote>
2421 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2422 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2423 place for <quote>democratic deliberation</quote> to occur.
2424 </para>
2425 <indexterm id='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='startofrange'><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2426 <para>
2427 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2428 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2429 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2430 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2431 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2432 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.<footnote><para>
2433 <!-- f17 -->
2434 Cass Sunstein, <citetitle>Republic.com</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001),
2435 65&ndash;80, 175, 182, 183, 192.
2436 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2437 little beyond what our friends say.
2438 </para>
2439 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2440 <indexterm><primary>e-mail</primary></indexterm>
2441 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2442 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2443 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='endofrange'/>
2444 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='endofrange'/>
2445 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='endofrange'/>
2446 <para>
2447 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2448 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2449 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2450 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2451 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2452
2453 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2454 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2455 place.
2456 </para>
2457 <para>
2458 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2459 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2460 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2461 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2462 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2463 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2464 </para>
2465 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard</primary></indexterm>
2466 <para>
2467 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2468 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race
2469 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2470 is having an effect.
2471 </para>
2472 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent</primary></indexterm>
2473 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom</primary></indexterm>
2474 <indexterm id='idxmediablogpressureon' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>blog pressure on</secondary></indexterm>
2475 <indexterm id='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>news events on</secondary></indexterm>
2476 <para>
2477 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2478 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2479 <quote>misspoke</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2480 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2481 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2482 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2483 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2484 more instances of the same <quote>misspeaking</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2485 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2486 resign as senate majority leader.<footnote><para>
2487 <!-- f18 -->
2488 Noah Shachtman, <quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,</quote> New
2489 York Times, 16 January 2003, G5.
2490 </para></footnote>
2491 </para>
2492 <indexterm id='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2493 <para>
2494 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2495 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2496 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2497 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2498 on.
2499 </para>
2500 <indexterm startref='idxmediablogpressureon' class='endofrange'/>
2501 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>peer-generated rankings on</secondary></indexterm>
2502 <para>
2503 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2504 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2505 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2506 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2507 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2508 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2509 peer-generated rankings.
2510 </para>
2511 <indexterm startref='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='endofrange'/>
2512 <indexterm id='idxjournalism' class='startofrange'><primary>journalism</primary></indexterm>
2513 <indexterm id='idxwinerdave' class='startofrange'><primary>Winer, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2514 <para>
2515 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2516 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2517 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2518 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2519 difference is the absence of a financial <quote>conflict of interest.</quote> <quote>I think you
2520 have to take the conflict of interest</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2521 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2522 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2523 get it out of the way.</quote>
2524 </para>
2525 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2526 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2527 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2528 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
2529 <para>
2530 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2531 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2532 from the public than an unconcentrated media can&mdash;as CNN admitted
2533 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2534 its own employees.<footnote><para>
2535 <!-- f19 -->
2536 Telephone interview with David Winer, 16 April 2003.
2537 </para></footnote>
2538 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2539 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2540 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2541 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2542 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2543 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2544 told her that <emphasis>they</emphasis> were writing <quote>the story.</quote>)
2545 </para>
2546 <indexterm startref='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='endofrange'/>
2547 <para>
2548 Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2549 debate&mdash;<quote>amateur</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced,
2550 but in the sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to
2551 give their reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a
2552 story, as reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds
2553 from across the southwest United States turned to the Internet to
2554 retell what they had seen.<footnote><para>
2555 <!-- f20 -->
2556 John Schwartz, <quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2557 Information Online,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci
2558 D. Kramer, <quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,</quote>
2559 Online Journalism Review, 2 February 2003, available at
2560 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #10</ulink>.
2561 </para></footnote>
2562 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2563 <quote>triangulate,</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2564 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2565 out of it</quote>&mdash;with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2566 </para>
2567 <para>
2568 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2569 with blogs. <quote>It's going to become an essential skill,</quote> Winer predicts,
2570 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2571 not clear that <quote>journalism</quote> is happy about this&mdash;some journalists
2572 have been told to curtail their blogging.<footnote>
2573 <para>
2574 <!-- f21 -->
2575 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2576 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2577 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve</primary></indexterm>
2578 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2579 See Michael Falcone, <quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?</quote> <citetitle>New
2580 York Times</citetitle>, 29 September 2003, C4. (<quote>Not all news organizations have
2581 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2582 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2583 war on March 9, stopped posting 12 days later at his bosses'
2584 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a <citetitle>Houston Chronicle</citetitle> reporter, was
2585 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2586 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.</quote>)
2587 </para></footnote>
2588 But it is clear that we are still in transition. <quote>A
2589
2590 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2591 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,</quote> Winer told me.
2592 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2593 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2594 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, <quote>we will
2595 be the last thing that gets shut down.</quote>
2596 </para>
2597 <indexterm startref='idxjournalism' class='endofrange'/>
2598 <para>
2599 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because <quote>you
2600 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.</quote>
2601 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2602 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2603 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2604 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2605 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2606 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2607 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2608 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2609 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2610 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2611 extraordinary to report.
2612 </para>
2613 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage' class='endofrange'/>
2614 <indexterm startref='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='endofrange'/>
2615 <indexterm startref='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='endofrange'/>
2616 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2617 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson2' class='endofrange'/>
2618 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2619 <indexterm startref='idxwinerdave' class='endofrange'/>
2620 <indexterm id='idxbrownjohnseely' class='startofrange'><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
2621 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2622 <para>
2623 <emphasis role='strong'>John Seely Brown</emphasis> is the chief
2624 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2625 describes it, is <quote>human learning and &hellip; the creation of
2626 knowledge ecologies for creating &hellip; innovation.</quote>
2627 </para>
2628 <para>
2629 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2630 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2631 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2632 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2633 affect learning.
2634 </para>
2635 <para>
2636 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When <quote>a lot of us grew up,</quote>
2637 he explains, that tinkering was done <quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2638 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.</quote> But digital technologies
2639 enable a different kind of tinkering&mdash;with abstract ideas though
2640 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2641 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2642 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2643 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2644 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2645 or <quote>free collage,</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2646 the tinkering of many others.
2647 </para>
2648 <para>
2649 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2650 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2651 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2652 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2653 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2654 </para>
2655 <para>
2656 This opportunity creates a <quote>completely new kind of learning platform,</quote>
2657 as Brown describes. <quote>As soon as you start doing that, you &hellip;
2658 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2659 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2660 if they can improve it.</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2661 apprenticeship. <quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.</quote>
2662 </para>
2663 <para>
2664 In this process, <quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2665 They are code.</quote> Kids are <quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2666 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2667 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2668 platform. &hellip; You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2669 you tinker the more you improve.</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2670 learn.
2671 </para>
2672 <para>
2673 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2674 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2675 it, <quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2676 intelligence.</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2677 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2678 text. <quote>The Web &hellip; says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2679 you are visual, if you are interested in film &hellip; [then] there is a
2680 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2681 these multiple forms of intelligence.</quote>
2682 </para>
2683 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'/>
2684 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2685 <para>
2686 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2687 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2688
2689 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2690 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2691 kind of recognition.
2692 </para>
2693 <para>
2694 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2695 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2696 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2697 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2698 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2699 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2700 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2701 </para>
2702 <para>
2703 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2704 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2705 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>)
2706 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the <quote>right to
2707 tinker</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2708 general.<footnote><para>
2709 <!-- f22 -->
2710 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, <quote>Technological Access
2711 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2712 of the Association for Computer Machinery</citetitle> 43 (2000): 9.
2713 </para></footnote>
2714 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2715 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2716 </para>
2717 <para>
2718 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,</quote> Brown
2719 explains. We need to <quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2720 and want to learn.</quote>
2721 </para>
2722 <para>
2723 <quote>Yet,</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2724 evince, <quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2725 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. &hellip; We're building an
2726 architecture that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2727 system that closes down that part of the brain.</quote>
2728 </para>
2729 <indexterm startref='idxbrownjohnseely' class='endofrange'/>
2730 <para>
2731 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2732 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2733 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2734 the law to close down that technology.
2735 </para>
2736 <para>
2737 <quote>No way to run a culture,</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2738 chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="collectors"/>,
2739 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2740 </para>
2741 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2742 </chapter>
2743 <chapter label="3" id="catalogs">
2744 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs</title>
2745 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2746 <indexterm><primary>RPI</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</see></indexterm>
2747 <indexterm id='idxrensselaer' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary></indexterm>
2748 <indexterm id='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary><secondary>computer network search engine of</secondary></indexterm>
2749 <indexterm id='idxsearchengines' class='startofrange'><primary>search engines</primary></indexterm>
2750 <indexterm id='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='startofrange'><primary>university computer networks, p2p sharing on</primary></indexterm>
2751 <indexterm id='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>search engines used on</secondary></indexterm>
2752 <para>
2753 <emphasis role='strong'>In the fall</emphasis> of 2002, Jesse Jordan
2754 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2755 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2756 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2757 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2758 was available on the RPI network.
2759 </para>
2760 <para>
2761 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2762 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2763 to information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand
2764 undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school
2765 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2766 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2767 </para>
2768 <para>
2769 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2770 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2771 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2772 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2773 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2774 </para>
2775 <indexterm id='idxgoogle' class='startofrange'><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2776 <para>
2777 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2778 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2779 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2780 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2781 engines can do this even better. The idea of <quote>intranet</quote> search
2782 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2783 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2784 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2785 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2786 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2787 </para>
2788 <indexterm id='idxjordanjesse' class='startofrange'><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2789 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>network file system of</secondary></indexterm>
2790 <para>
2791 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2792 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2793 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2794 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2795 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2796 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2797 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2798 </para>
2799 <indexterm startref='idxgoogle' class='endofrange'/>
2800 <para>
2801 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2802 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2803 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2804 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2805 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2806 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2807 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2808 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2809 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2810 on-line.
2811 </para>
2812 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='endofrange'/>
2813 <para>
2814 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2815 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2816 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2817 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2818 be on users' computers.
2819 </para>
2820 <indexterm startref='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='endofrange'/>
2821 <para>
2822 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2823 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2824 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2825 might have created; university brochures&mdash;basically anything that
2826 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2827 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2828 computer.
2829 </para>
2830 <indexterm><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2831 <indexterm><primary>education</primary><secondary>tinkering as means of</secondary></indexterm>
2832 <para>
2833 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2834 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2835 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and&mdash;so that this
2836 point is absolutely clear&mdash;Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2837 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2838 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2839 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2840 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2841 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2842 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2843 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2844 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2845 supposed to do.
2846 </para>
2847 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
2848 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>against student file sharing</secondary></indexterm>
2849 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
2850 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
2851 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='endofrange'/>
2852 <para>
2853 On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2854 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2855 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2856 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2857 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2858 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2859 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2860 </para>
2861 <para>
2862 <quote>It was absurd,</quote> he told me. <quote>I don't think I did anything
2863 wrong. &hellip; I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2864 engine that I ran or &hellip; what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2865 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2866 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2867 easier to use</quote>&mdash;again, a <emphasis>search engine</emphasis>,
2868 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2869 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2870 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2871 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2872 with music.
2873 </para>
2874 <indexterm startref='idxsearchengines' class='endofrange'/>
2875 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
2876 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>statutory damages of</secondary></indexterm>
2877 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>individual defendants intimidated by</secondary></indexterm>
2878 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages</primary></indexterm>
2879 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>intimidation tactics of</secondary></indexterm>
2880 <para>
2881 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2882 network and had therefore <quote>willfully</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2883 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2884 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2885 <quote>willful infringement,</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2886 call <quote>statutory damages.</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2887 claim $150,000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2888 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2889 Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000.
2890 </para>
2891 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University</primary></indexterm>
2892 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University</primary></indexterm>
2893 <para>
2894 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2895 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2896 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2897 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2898 huge demands for <quote>damages</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2899 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2900 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $100
2901 <emphasis>billion</emphasis>&mdash;six times the
2902 <emphasis>total</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2903 2001.<footnote><para>
2904
2905 <!-- f1 -->
2906 Tim Goral, <quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks:
2907 Suit Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages,</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC</citetitle> 6
2908 (2003): 5, available at 2003 WL 55179443.
2909 </para></footnote>
2910 </para>
2911 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaer' class='endofrange'/>
2912 <para>
2913 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2914 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2915 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2916 $12,000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2917 $12,000 to dismiss the case.
2918 </para>
2919 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt</primary></indexterm>
2920 <para>
2921 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2922 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2923 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2924 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2925 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2926 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2927 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, <quote>You don't want to pay another
2928 visit to a dentist like me.</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2929 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2930 </para>
2931 <indexterm><primary>legal system, attorney costs in</primary></indexterm>
2932 <para>
2933 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2934 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2935 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2936 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2937 at least $250,000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2938 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2939 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2940 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2941 </para>
2942 <para>
2943 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $250,000 and a chance at winning,
2944 or $12,000 and a settlement.
2945 </para>
2946 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
2947 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
2948 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
2949 <para>
2950 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2951 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2952 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2953 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2954 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $1 million a year.
2955 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2956 artist makes $45,900.<footnote><para>
2957 <!-- f2 -->
2958 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001)
2959 (27&ndash;2042&mdash;Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2960 the Arts, <citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon</citetitle> (2000).
2961 </para></footnote>
2962 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2963 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2964 student for running a search engine?<footnote><para>
2965 <!-- f3 -->
2966 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in <quote>KaZaA and Punishment,</quote>
2967 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, A24.
2968 </para></footnote>
2969 </para>
2970 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='endofrange'/>
2971 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='endofrange'/>
2972 <para>
2973 On June 23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2974 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2975 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $15 million lawsuit became an
2976 activist:
2977 </para>
2978 <blockquote>
2979 <para>
2980 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2981 an activist. &hellip; [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2982 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2983 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2984 </para>
2985 </blockquote>
2986 <para>
2987 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2988 his father told me, Jesse <quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
2989 I. &hellip; He's not a tree hugger. &hellip; I think it's bizarre that they would
2990 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2991 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.</quote>
2992 </para>
2993 <indexterm startref='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='endofrange'/>
2994 <indexterm startref='idxjordanjesse' class='endofrange'/>
2995 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
2996 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='endofrange'/>
2997 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='endofrange'/>
2998 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='endofrange'/>
2999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
3000 </chapter>
3001 <chapter label="4" id="pirates">
3002 <title>CHAPTER FOUR: <quote>Pirates</quote></title>
3003 <indexterm id='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in development of content industry</secondary></indexterm>
3004 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
3005 <para>
3006 <emphasis role='strong'>If <quote>piracy</quote> means</emphasis>
3007 using the creative property of others without their
3008 permission&mdash;if <quote>if value, then right</quote> is
3009 true&mdash;then the history of the content industry is a history of
3010 piracy. Every important sector of <quote>big media</quote>
3011 today&mdash;film, records, radio, and cable TV&mdash;was born of a
3012 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
3013 generation's pirates join this generation's country club&mdash;until
3014 now.
3015 </para>
3016 <section id="film">
3017 <title>Film</title>
3018 <para>
3019 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.<footnote><para>
3020 <!-- f1 -->
3021 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
3022 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
3023 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 87&ndash;93,
3024 which details Edison's <quote>adventures</quote> with copyright and patent.
3025 </para></footnote>
3026 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
3027 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
3028 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
3029 exercised through a monopoly <quote>trust,</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
3030 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
3031 property&mdash;patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
3032 this creative property
3033 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
3034 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
3035 </para>
3036 <para>
3037 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
3038 </para>
3039 <blockquote>
3040 <para>
3041 A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
3042 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
3043 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
3044 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
3045 summer of 1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
3046 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
3047 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
3048 </para>
3049 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William</primary></indexterm>
3050 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company</primary></indexterm>
3051 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3052 <para>
3053 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
3054 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
3055 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
3056 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
3057 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
3058 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
3059 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
3060 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
3061 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
3062 license was revoked.<footnote><para>
3063 <!-- f2 -->
3064 J. A. Aberdeen, <citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
3065 Picture Producers</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts
3066 posted at <quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
3067 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,</quote> available at
3068 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #11</ulink>. For a
3069 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
3070 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, <quote>From
3071 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
3072 the Propertization of Copyright</quote> (September 2002), University of
3073 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
3074 Working Paper No. 159.
3075 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
3076 </para></footnote>
3077 </para>
3078 </blockquote>
3079 <para>
3080 The Napsters of those days, the <quote>independents,</quote> were companies like
3081 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
3082 resisted. <quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
3083 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
3084 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.</quote><footnote><para>
3085 <!-- f3 -->
3086 Marc Wanamaker, <quote>The First Studios,</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority</citetitle>, archived at
3087 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #12</ulink>.
3088 </para></footnote>
3089 That led the independents to flee the East
3090 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
3091 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
3092 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
3093 did just that.
3094 </para>
3095 <para>
3096 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
3097 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
3098 patent holder a truly <quote>limited</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
3099
3100 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
3101 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
3102 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
3103 Edison's creative property.
3104 </para>
3105 </section>
3106 <section id="recordedmusic">
3107 <title>Recorded Music</title>
3108 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
3109 <para>
3110 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
3111 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
3112 </para>
3113 <indexterm id='idxfourneauxhenri' class='startofrange'><primary>Fourneaux, Henri</primary></indexterm>
3114 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil</primary></indexterm>
3115 <para>
3116 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
3117 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
3118 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
3119 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
3120 their music. In other words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
3121 1899 hit <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
3122 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
3123 right to perform it publicly.
3124 </para>
3125 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3126 <para>
3127 But what if I wanted to record <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> using Edison's phonograph
3128 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
3129 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
3130 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
3131 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
3132 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
3133 <quote>public performance</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
3134 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
3135 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
3136 brain are not&mdash;yet&mdash; regulated by copyright law). So if I
3137 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
3138 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
3139 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
3140 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
3141 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
3142 its composer anything.
3143 </para>
3144 <indexterm startref='idxfourneauxhenri' class='endofrange'/>
3145 <para>
3146 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
3147 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
3148 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
3149 put it,
3150 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3151 </para>
3152 <blockquote>
3153 <para>
3154 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3155 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3156 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3157 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3158 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3159 rights.<footnote><para>
3160 <!-- f4 -->
3161 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3162 S. 6330 and H.R. 19853 Before the (Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th
3163 Cong. 59, 1st sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3164 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in <citetitle>Legislative History of the
3165 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3166 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3167 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3168 </para></footnote>
3169 </para>
3170 </blockquote>
3171 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip</primary></indexterm>
3172 <para>
3173 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3174 people's works were <quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3175 genius of American composers,</quote><footnote><para>
3176 <!-- f5 -->
3177 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223
3178 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3179 </para></footnote>
3180 and the <quote>music publishing industry</quote>
3181 was thereby <quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.</quote><footnote><para>
3182 <!-- f6 -->
3183 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226
3184 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3185 </para></footnote>
3186 As John Philip
3187 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, <quote>When they make money
3188 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.</quote><footnote><para>
3189 <!-- f7 -->
3190 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23
3191 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3192 </para></footnote>
3193 </para>
3194 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company</primary></indexterm>
3195 <indexterm><primary>player pianos</primary></indexterm>
3196 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
3197 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
3198 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
3199 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
3200 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>statutory license system in</secondary></indexterm>
3201 <para>
3202 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3203 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3204 player piano argued that <quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3205 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3206 of anything he had before their introduction.</quote> Rather, the machines
3207 increased the sales of sheet music.<footnote><para>
3208 <!-- f8 -->
3209
3210 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283&ndash;84
3211 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3212 Perforating Company of New York).
3213 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3214 Congress was <quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3215 they represent, and whose servants they are.</quote> <quote>All talk about
3216 `theft,'</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3217 wrote, <quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3218 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3219 statute.</quote><footnote><para>
3220 <!-- f9 -->
3221 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared
3222 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3223 Graphophone Company Association).
3224 </para></footnote>
3225 </para>
3226 <indexterm><primary>cover songs</primary></indexterm>
3227 <para>
3228 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3229 <emphasis>and</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3230 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the <quote>mechanical
3231 reproductions</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3232 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3233 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3234 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3235 recorded once. This is the part of
3236
3237 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3238 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3239 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3240 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3241 </para>
3242 <indexterm id='idxcompulsorylicense' class='startofrange'><primary>compulsory license</primary></indexterm>
3243 <indexterm id='idxstatutorylicenses' class='startofrange'><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
3244 <para>
3245 American law ordinarily calls this a <quote>compulsory license,</quote> but I will
3246 refer to it as a <quote>statutory license.</quote> A statutory license is a license
3247 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3248 Copyright Act in 1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3249 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3250 the fee set by the statute.
3251 </para>
3252 <indexterm id='idxgrishamjohn' class='startofrange'><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
3253 <para>
3254 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3255 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3256 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3257 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3258 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3259 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3260 Grisham.
3261 </para>
3262 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='endofrange'/>
3263 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3264 <para>
3265 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3266 thus, in effect, the law <emphasis>subsidizes</emphasis> the recording
3267 industry through a kind of piracy&mdash;by giving recording artists a
3268 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3269 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3270 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3271 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3272 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3273 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3274 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3275 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3276 creativity.<footnote><para>
3277
3278 <!-- f10 -->
3279 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and
3280 H.R. 11794 Before the (Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st
3281 sess., 217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3282 in <citetitle>Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3283 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3284 </para></footnote>
3285 </para>
3286 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='endofrange'/>
3287 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3288 <indexterm startref='idxgrishamjohn' class='endofrange'/>
3289 <para>
3290 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3291 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3292 records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3293 relates,
3294 </para>
3295 <blockquote>
3296 <para>
3297 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3298 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3299 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3300 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3301 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3302 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3303 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3304 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3305 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before 1909 and
3306 the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3307 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3308 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3309 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3310 choice.<footnote><para>
3311 <!-- f11 -->
3312 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee
3313 on the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8
3314 March 1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3315 this report.</para></footnote>
3316 </para>
3317 </blockquote>
3318 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='endofrange'/>
3319 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='endofrange'/>
3320 <indexterm startref='idxcompulsorylicense' class='endofrange'/>
3321 <indexterm startref='idxstatutorylicenses' class='endofrange'/>
3322 <para>
3323 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3324 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3325 </para>
3326 </section>
3327 <section id="radio">
3328 <title>Radio</title>
3329 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
3330 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
3331 <para>
3332 Radio was also born of piracy.
3333 </para>
3334 <para>
3335 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3336 <quote>public performance</quote> of the composer's work.<footnote><para>
3337 <!-- f12 -->
3338 See 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning,
3339 record companies printed <quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast</quote> and other
3340 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3341 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3342 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3343 station. See <citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Whiteman</citetitle>, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd
3344 Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3345 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3346 Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 281.
3347 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned</primary></indexterm>
3348 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3349 </para></footnote>
3350 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3351 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3352 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3353 </para>
3354 <para>
3355 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3356 copy of the <emphasis>composer's</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3357 also performing a copy of the <emphasis>recording artist's</emphasis>
3358 work. It's one thing to have <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> sung on the radio by the
3359 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3360 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3361 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3362 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3363 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3364 music for his work.
3365 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
3366
3367 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3368 </para>
3369 <para>
3370 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3371 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3372 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3373 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3374 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3375 of playing the song.
3376 </para>
3377 <indexterm id='idxmadonna' class='startofrange'><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3378 <para>
3379 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3380 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3381 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3382 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3383 </para>
3384 <para>
3385 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3386 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3387 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3388 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3389 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3390 <quote>protected</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3391 <emphasis>pirate</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3392 her anything.
3393 </para>
3394 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='endofrange'/>
3395 <indexterm startref='idxmadonna' class='endofrange'/>
3396 <para>
3397 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3398 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3399 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3400 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3401 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3402 to take something for nothing.
3403 </para>
3404 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='endofrange'/>
3405 </section>
3406 <section id="cabletv">
3407 <title>Cable TV</title>
3408 <indexterm id='idxcabletelevision' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
3409 <para>
3410 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3411 </para>
3412 <para>
3413 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3414 television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3415 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3416 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3417 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3418 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3419 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3420 did&mdash; Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3421 give away.
3422 </para>
3423 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas</primary></indexterm>
3424 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin</primary></indexterm>
3425 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3426 <para>
3427 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3428 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3429 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.</quote><footnote><para>
3430 <!-- f13 -->
3431 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the
3432 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3433 Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966)
3434 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3435 Commission).
3436 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3437 </para></footnote>
3438 There may have been a <quote>public interest</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3439 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3440 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, <quote>Does public
3441 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?</quote><footnote><para>
3442 <!-- f14 -->
3443 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3444 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3445 </para></footnote>
3446 As another broadcaster put it,
3447 </para>
3448 <blockquote>
3449 <para>
3450 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3451 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3452 paid for.<footnote><para>
3453 <!-- f15 -->
3454 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3455 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3456 </para></footnote>
3457 </para>
3458 </blockquote>
3459 <para>
3460 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3461 </para>
3462 <blockquote>
3463 <para>
3464 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3465 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3466 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3467 think there are harsher words which would fit it.<footnote><para>
3468 <!-- f16 -->
3469 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3470 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3471 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3472 </para></footnote>
3473 </para>
3474 </blockquote>
3475 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3476 <para>
3477 These were <quote>free-ride[rs],</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3478 Heston said, who were <quote>depriving actors of
3479 compensation.</quote><footnote><para>
3480 <!-- f17 -->
3481 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3482 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3483 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3484 </para>
3485 </footnote>
3486 </para>
3487 <para>
3488 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3489 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3490 </para>
3491 <blockquote>
3492 <para>
3493 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3494 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3495 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3496 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. &hellip; The
3497
3498 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3499 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3500 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.<footnote><para>
3501 <!-- f18 -->
3502 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M.
3503 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3504 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3505 </para></footnote>
3506 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3507 </para>
3508 </blockquote>
3509 <para>
3510 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3511 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3512 </para>
3513 <para>
3514 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3515 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they <quote>pirated.</quote>
3516 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3517 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3518 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3519 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3520 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3521 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3522 companies thus built their empire in part upon a <quote>piracy</quote> of the value
3523 created by broadcasters' content.
3524 </para>
3525 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3526 <indexterm startref='idxcabletelevision' class='endofrange'/>
3527 <para>
3528 <emphasis role='strong'>These separate stories</emphasis> sing a
3529 common theme. If <quote>piracy</quote> means using value from someone
3530 else's creative property without permission from that creator&mdash;as
3531 it is increasingly described today<footnote><para>
3532 <!-- f19 -->
3533 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, <citetitle>The Engine
3534 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet&mdash;The Myth of Free
3535 Information</citetitle>, available at
3536 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #13</ulink>. <quote>The
3537 threat of piracy&mdash;the use of someone else's creative work without
3538 permission or compensation&mdash;has grown with the Internet.</quote>
3539 </para></footnote>
3540 &mdash; then <emphasis>every</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3541 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3542 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV. &hellip; The list is long and
3543 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3544 last. Every generation&mdash;until now.
3545 </para>
3546 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3547 </section>
3548 </chapter>
3549 <chapter label="5" id="piracy">
3550 <title>CHAPTER FIVE: <quote>Piracy</quote></title>
3551 <para>
3552 <emphasis role='strong'>There is piracy</emphasis> of copyrighted
3553 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3554 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3555 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3556 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3557 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3558 </para>
3559 <para>
3560 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of <quote>taking</quote>
3561 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3562 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3563 taking <quote>piracy,</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3564 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3565 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3566 has so often done in the past.
3567 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3568 </para>
3569 <section id="piracy-i">
3570 <title>Piracy I</title>
3571 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3572 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3573 <para>
3574 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3575 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3576 content, copy it, and sell it&mdash;all without the permission of a copyright
3577 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion
3578 every year to physical piracy<footnote><para>
3579 <!-- f1 -->
3580 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), <citetitle>The
3581 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003</citetitle>, July 2003, available
3582 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #14</ulink>. See
3583 also Ben Hunt, <quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3584 Times</citetitle>, 14 February 2003, 11.
3585 </para></footnote>
3586 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3587 estimates that it loses $3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3588 </para>
3589 <para>
3590 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3591 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3592 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3593 This piracy is wrong.
3594 </para>
3595 <para>
3596 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3597 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3598 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3599 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3600 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3601 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3602 of our existence, treated as right.
3603 </para>
3604 <para>
3605 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3606 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3607 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3608 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3609 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3610 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3611 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3612 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3613 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3614 </para>
3615 <para>
3616 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3617 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3618 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3619 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3620 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3621 similar childhood.
3622 </para>
3623 <para>
3624 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3625 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3626 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3627 of intellectual property law.<footnote><para>
3628 <!-- f2 -->
3629 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3630 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The
3631 New Press, 2003), 10&ndash;13, 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3632 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3633 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3634 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3635 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3636 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3637 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3638 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3639 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3640 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3641 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3642 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3643 TRIPS framework.
3644 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents</primary></indexterm>
3645 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
3646 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3647 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3648 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3649 is wrong.
3650 </para>
3651 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3652 <para>
3653 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3654 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3655 to American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3656 bought those American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any
3657 less money than they otherwise would have had.<footnote><para>
3658 <!-- f3 -->
3659 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3660 Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002),
3661 144&ndash;90. <quote>In some instances &hellip; the impact of piracy on the
3662 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3663 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3664 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3665 pirating were not an option.</quote> Ibid., 149.
3666 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3667 </para></footnote>
3668 </para>
3669 <para>
3670 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3671 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3672 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3673 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3674 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes &amp; Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3675 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?</quote>
3676 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes &amp;
3677 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3678 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3679 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3680 piracy of the tangible.
3681 </para>
3682 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'/>
3683 <para>
3684 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3685 property right of a very special sort, it <emphasis>is</emphasis> a
3686 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3687 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3688 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3689 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3690 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3691 give people the right to <quote>take</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3692 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3693
3694 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3695 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3696 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3697 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3698 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3699 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what <quote>property</quote> means.
3700 </para>
3701 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3702 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
3703 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
3704 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3705 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3706 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of</secondary></indexterm>
3707 <indexterm><primary>Windows</primary></indexterm>
3708 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>international software piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3709 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of</secondary></indexterm>
3710 <para>
3711 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3712 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese <quote>steal</quote>
3713 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3714 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3715 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3716 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3717 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3718 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3719 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3720 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3721 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3722 </para>
3723 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
3724 <para>
3725 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3726 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3727 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3728 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3729 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3730 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3731 </para>
3732 <indexterm><primary>Netscape</primary></indexterm>
3733 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer</primary></indexterm>
3734 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3735 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3736 <para>
3737 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3738 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3739 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3740 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3741 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3742 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3743 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3744 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3745 what&mdash;at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3746 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3747 violating the law is still wrong.
3748 </para>
3749 <para>
3750 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3751 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3752 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3753 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3754 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3755 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3756 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3757 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3758 is flat out wrong.
3759 </para>
3760 <para>
3761 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3762 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is. Or
3763 at least, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3764 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of <quote>piracy</quote> are useful
3765 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3766 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3767 <quote>piracy</quote> in that sense of the term.
3768 </para>
3769 <para>
3770 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3771 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3772 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3773 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3774 </para>
3775 <para>
3776 For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3777 controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it
3778 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable
3779 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3780 </para>
3781 <para>
3782 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3783 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3784 sharing to survive.
3785 </para>
3786 </section>
3787 <section id="piracy-ii">
3788 <title>Piracy II</title>
3789 <para>
3790 The key to the <quote>piracy</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that <quote>rob[s]
3791 the author of [his] profit.</quote><footnote><para>
3792 <!-- f4 -->
3793 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777).
3794 </para></footnote>
3795 This means we must determine whether
3796 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3797 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3798 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3799 author of his profit.
3800 </para>
3801 <para>
3802 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn</primary></indexterm>
3803 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3804 <indexterm id='idxnapster' class='startofrange'><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
3805 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3806 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3807 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3808 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well<footnote><para>
3809 <!-- f5 -->
3810 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3811 See Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3812 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle> (New York:
3813 HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3814 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3815 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3816 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3817 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3818 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 89&ndash;92, 139.
3819
3820 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
3821 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3822 put together components that had been developed independently.
3823 </para>
3824 <para>
3825 <indexterm><primary>Kazaa</primary></indexterm>
3826 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>number of registrations on</secondary></indexterm>
3827 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>replacement of</secondary></indexterm>
3828 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999,
3829 Napster amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After
3830 eighteen months, there were close to 80 million registered users of the
3831 system.<footnote><para>
3832 <!-- f6 -->
3833 See Carolyn Lochhead, <quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,</quote> <citetitle>San
3834 Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24 September 2002, A1; <quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,</quote>
3835 <citetitle>New Scientist</citetitle>, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Napster Names CEO,
3836 Secures New Financing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 23 May 2003, C1;
3837 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton,
3838 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet</quote> (London) <citetitle>Times</citetitle>, 26 July 2002, 18.
3839 </para></footnote>
3840 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3841 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3842 boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3843 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3844 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3845 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend&mdash;
3846 or your 20,000 best friends.
3847 </para>
3848 <indexterm startref='idxnapster' class='endofrange'/>
3849 <para>
3850 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3851 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3852 September 2002 estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded
3853 music&mdash;28 percent of Americans older than 12.<footnote><para>
3854
3855 <!-- f7 -->
3856 See Ipsos-Insight, <citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution</citetitle>
3857 (September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3858 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have
3859 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3860 </para></footnote>
3861 A survey by the NPD group quoted in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>
3862 estimated that 43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3863 exchange content in May 2003.<footnote><para>
3864 <!-- f8 -->
3865 Amy Harmon, <quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,</quote> <citetitle>New
3866 York Times</citetitle>, 6 June 2003, A1.
3867 </para></footnote>
3868 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3869 massive quantity of content is being <quote>taken</quote> on these networks. The
3870 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3871 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3872 </para>
3873 <para>
3874 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3875 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3876 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3877 complicated than one might think. So consider&mdash;a bit more
3878 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3879 do&mdash;the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3880 of harm it entails.
3881 </para>
3882 <para>
3883 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3884 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3885 different kinds into four types.
3886 </para>
3887 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
3888 <listitem>
3889 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3890 <para>
3891 <!-- A. -->
3892 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3893 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3894 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3895 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3896 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3897 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3898 users who download instead of purchasing.
3899 </para></listitem>
3900 <listitem><para>
3901 <!-- B. -->
3902 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3903 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3904 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3905 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3906 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3907 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3908 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3909 music purchased.
3910 </para></listitem>
3911 <listitem><para>
3912 <!-- C. -->
3913 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3914 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3915 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3916 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3917 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3918 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3919 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend <quote>recalling</quote> old
3920 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3921 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3922 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3923 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero&mdash;the same
3924 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to
3925 a local collector.
3926 </para></listitem>
3927 <listitem><para>
3928 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3929 <!-- D. -->
3930 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3931 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3932 wants to give away.
3933 </para></listitem>
3934 </orderedlist>
3935 <para>
3936 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3937 </para>
3938 <para>
3939 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3940 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3941 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3942 harmful.<footnote><para>
3943 <!-- f9 -->
3944 See Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle>, 148&ndash;49.
3945 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3946 </para></footnote>
3947 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3948 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3949 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3950 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3951 answer&mdash;and certainly much more difficult than the current
3952 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3953 </para>
3954 <para>
3955 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3956 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3957 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3958 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3959 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of <quote>theft</quote> that is
3960 <quote>devastating</quote> the industry.
3961 </para>
3962 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
3963 <para>
3964 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3965 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3966 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3967 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3968 &amp; Young put it, <quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3969 technology, the labels fought it.</quote><footnote><para>
3970 <!-- f10 -->
3971 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary></indexterm>
3972 See Cap Gemini Ernst &amp; Young, <citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
3973 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis</citetitle> (2003), 3. This report
3974 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3975 practice of cassette taping in the 1970s, including an advertising
3976 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption <quote>Home taping
3977 is killing music.</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3978 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3979 behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3980 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3981 Assessment, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law</citetitle>,
3982 OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3983 October 1989), 145&ndash;56. </para></footnote>
3984 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3985 when record sales fell by 11.4 percent in 1981, the industry claimed
3986 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3987 regulating technology was the answer.
3988 </para>
3989 <indexterm><primary>MTV</primary></indexterm>
3990 <para>
3991 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3992 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3993 turnaround. <quote>In the end,</quote> Cap Gemini concludes, <quote>the `crisis' &hellip; was
3994 not the fault of the tapers&mdash;who did not [stop after MTV came into
3995 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
3996 being]&mdash;but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
3997 innovation at the major labels.</quote><footnote><para>
3998 <!-- f11 -->
3999 U.S. Congress, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying</citetitle>, 4.
4000 </para></footnote>
4001 </para>
4002 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'/>
4003 <para>
4004 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
4005 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
4006 the industry in particular, and society in general&mdash;or at least
4007 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
4008 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
4009 VCR&mdash;the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
4010 harmful. The question is also <emphasis>how</emphasis> harmful type A
4011 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
4012 </para>
4013 <para>
4014 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
4015 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
4016 The <quote>net harm</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
4017 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
4018 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
4019 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
4020 therefore have little <emphasis>static</emphasis> reason to resist
4021 them.
4022
4023 </para>
4024 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>sales levels of</secondary></indexterm>
4025 <para>
4026 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
4027 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
4028 actually suggest it might be close.
4029 </para>
4030 <para>
4031 In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9 percent,
4032 from 882 million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7
4033 percent.<footnote><para>
4034 <!-- f12 -->
4035 See Recording Industry Association of America, <citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics</citetitle>,
4036 available at
4037 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #15</ulink>. A later
4038 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
4039 Association of America, <citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy</citetitle>, 25 June 2003,
4040 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
4041 #16</ulink>: <quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
4042 have fallen by 26 percent from 1.16 billion units in to 860 million
4043 units in 2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
4044 of sales, revenues are down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in to $12.6
4045 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
4046 industry worldwide has gone from a $39 billion industry in 2000 down
4047 to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
4048 shipments).</quote>
4049 </para></footnote>
4050 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
4051 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
4052 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
4053 than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That no
4054 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
4055 account for at least some of the loss. <quote>From 1999 to 2001, the average
4056 price of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19.</quote><footnote>
4057 <!-- f13 -->
4058 <para>
4059 Jane Black, <quote>Big Music's Broken Record,</quote> BusinessWeek online, 13
4060 February 2003, available at
4061 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #17</ulink>.
4062 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane</primary></indexterm>
4063 </para>
4064 </footnote>
4065 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
4066 the decline. As Jane Black of <citetitle>BusinessWeek</citetitle> notes, <quote>The
4067 soundtrack to the film <citetitle>High Fidelity</citetitle> has a list price of
4068 $18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
4069 $19.99.</quote><footnote><para>
4070 <!-- f14 -->
4071 Ibid.
4072 </para></footnote>
4073 </para>
4074 <para>
4075
4076 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
4077 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
4078 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
4079 that the RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
4080 estimates that 2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
4081 although 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4082 free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 percent.
4083 </para>
4084 <para>
4085 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
4086 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
4087 The recording industry constantly asks, <quote>What's the difference between
4088 downloading a song and stealing a CD?</quote>&mdash;but their own numbers
4089 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
4090 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
4091 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
4092 downloads. If every download were a lost sale&mdash;if every use of
4093 Kazaa <quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit</quote>&mdash;then the industry
4094 would have suffered a 100 percent drop in sales last year, not a 7
4095 percent drop. If 2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4096 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, then there is
4097 a huge difference between <quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.</quote>
4098 </para>
4099 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'/>
4100 <para>
4101 These are the harms&mdash;alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
4102 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
4103 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
4104 these costs?
4105 </para>
4106 <para>
4107 One benefit is type C sharing&mdash;making available content that
4108 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
4109 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
4110 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
4111 available.<footnote><para>
4112 <!-- f15 -->
4113 By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels
4114 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
4115 Law&mdash;Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
4116 Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April
4117 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
4118 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #18</ulink>.
4119 </para></footnote>
4120 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
4121 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
4122 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
4123 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
4124 sense <emphasis>to the company</emphasis> to make it available.
4125 </para>
4126 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4127 <para>
4128 In real space&mdash;long before the Internet&mdash;the market had a simple
4129 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
4130 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
4131 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
4132 today.<footnote><para>
4133 <!-- f16 -->
4134 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4135 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
4136 in existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the
4137 United States, an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter
4138 Press, <citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
4139 Market</citetitle> (2002), available at
4140 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #19</ulink>. Used
4141 records accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See National
4142 Association of Recording Merchandisers, <quote>2002 Annual Survey
4143 Results,</quote> available at
4144 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #20</ulink>.
4145 </para></footnote>
4146 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
4147 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
4148 content, <emphasis>even if the content is still under
4149 copyright</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
4150 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
4151 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
4152 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
4153 the content they sell.
4154 </para>
4155 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
4156 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard</primary></indexterm>
4157 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
4158 <para>
4159 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
4160 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
4161 the content available isn't making money from making the content
4162 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
4163 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
4164 when someone shares my 1949 recording of Bernstein's <quote>Two Love Songs,</quote>
4165 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
4166 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
4167 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
4168 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
4169 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
4170 </para>
4171 <para>
4172 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
4173 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
4174 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
4175 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
4176 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
4177 shut as well?
4178 </para>
4179 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
4180 <indexterm><primary>Doctorow, Cory</primary></indexterm>
4181 <indexterm><primary>Down and Out in the Magic Kingdom (Doctorow)</primary></indexterm>
4182 <para>
4183 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4184 type D sharing to occur&mdash;the sharing of content that copyright owners
4185 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4186 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4187 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
4188 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4189
4190 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4191 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4192 would be a great advertisement for the <quote>real</quote> book. People would read
4193 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4194 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4195 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4196 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4197 great book!)
4198 </para>
4199 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'/>
4200 <para>
4201 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4202 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4203 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4204 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4205 </para>
4206 <para>
4207 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4208 understandably says, <quote>This is how much we've lost,</quote> we must also ask,
4209 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4210 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4211 unavailable?</quote>
4212 </para>
4213 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson' class='endofrange'/>
4214 <para>
4215 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4216 chapter, much of the <quote>piracy</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4217 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4218 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="pirates"/>, much of
4219 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4220 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4221 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4222 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4223 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4224 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4225 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4226 found only with time.
4227 </para>
4228 <para>
4229 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4230 just what you call type A sharing?</quote>
4231 </para>
4232 <para>
4233 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The effect
4234 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4235 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4236 Napster case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4237 developed a technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of
4238 identified
4239
4240 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4241 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4
4242 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4243 <quote>down to zero.</quote><footnote><para>
4244 <!-- f17 -->
4245 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34-
4246 35 (N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183
4247 MHP, available at
4248
4249 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #21</ulink>. For an
4250 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4251 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster</citetitle> (New
4252 York: Crown Business, 2003), 269&ndash;82.
4253 </para></footnote>
4254 </para>
4255 <para>
4256 If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4257 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4258 assure that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance
4259 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of
4260 VCRs or 100 percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns
4261 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4262 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4263 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4264 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4265 </para>
4266 <para>
4267 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4268 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4269 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4270 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4271 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4272 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4273 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4274 </para>
4275 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
4276 <indexterm><primary>composers, copyright protections of</primary></indexterm>
4277 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4278 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
4279 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
4280 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
4281 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>music recordings played on</secondary></indexterm>
4282 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
4283 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright protections in</secondary></indexterm>
4284 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
4285 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
4286 <indexterm><primary>composer's rights vs. producers' rights in</primary></indexterm>
4287 <para>
4288 So, as we've seen, when <quote>mechanical reproduction</quote> threatened the
4289 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4290 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4291 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4292 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4293 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4294 complained to Congress that their <quote>creative property</quote> was not being
4295 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4296 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4297 benefit was enough.
4298 </para>
4299 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
4300 <para>
4301 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4302 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4303 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4304 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4305 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4306 price.
4307 </para>
4308 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='endofrange'/>
4309 <para>
4310
4311 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4312 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4313 pianos, served two important goals&mdash;indeed, the two central goals
4314 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4315 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4316 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4317 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4318 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4319 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4320 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4321 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4322 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4323 Congress chose a path that would assure
4324 <emphasis>compensation</emphasis> without giving the past
4325 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4326 </para>
4327 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='endofrange'/>
4328 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='endofrange'/>
4329 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'/>
4330 <indexterm id='idxbetamax' class='startofrange'><primary>Betamax</primary></indexterm>
4331 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
4332 <para>
4333 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4334 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4335 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4336 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4337 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4338 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4339 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4340 <quote>record</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4341 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4342 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4343 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4344 </para>
4345 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='endofrange'/>
4346 <para>
4347 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4348 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4349 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4350 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4351 machine to copy only if there were a special <quote>copy me</quote> signal on the
4352 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4353 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4354 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4355 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4356 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4357 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4358 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4359 for the architecture it chose.
4360 </para>
4361 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4362 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on VCR technology</secondary></indexterm>
4363 <para>
4364 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4365 champion. Valenti called VCRs <quote>tapeworms.</quote> He warned, <quote>When there are
4366 20, 30, 40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4367 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4368 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4369 copyright.</quote><footnote><para>
4370 <!-- f18 -->
4371 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4372 S. 1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st
4373 and 2nd sess., 459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4374 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4375 </para></footnote>
4376 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4377 creative judgment,</quote> he told Congress, <quote>to understand the devastation
4378 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4379 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4380 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4381 and plain common sense.</quote><footnote><para>
4382 <!-- f19 -->
4383 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475.
4384 </para></footnote>
4385 Indeed, as surveys would later show, 45
4386 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more<footnote><para>
4387 <!-- f20 -->
4388 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 480 F. Supp. 429,
4389 (C.D. Cal., 1979).
4390 </para></footnote>
4391 &mdash; a use the Court would later hold was not <quote>fair.</quote> By
4392 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4393 copyright infringement without creating a mechanism to compensate
4394 copyright owners,</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would <quote>take from the
4395 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4396 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4397 profit from its reproduction.</quote><footnote><para>
4398 <!-- f21 -->
4399 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony
4400 of Jack Valenti).
4401 </para></footnote>
4402 </para>
4403 <indexterm startref='idxbetamax' class='endofrange'/>
4404 <para>
4405 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4406 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4407 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction&mdash;leading Judge Alex
4408 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the <quote>Hollywood
4409 Circuit</quote>&mdash;held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4410 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4411 rule, this totally familiar technology&mdash;which Jack Valenti had
4412 called <quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry</quote> (worse
4413 yet, it was a <emphasis>Japanese</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4414 American film industry)&mdash;was an illegal
4415 technology.<footnote><para>
4416 <!-- f22 -->
4417 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th Cir.
4418 1981).
4419 </para></footnote>
4420 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex</primary></indexterm>
4421 </para>
4422 <para>
4423 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4424
4425 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4426 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4427 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4428 Court wrote,
4429 </para>
4430 <blockquote>
4431 <para>
4432 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4433 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4434 market
4435 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4436 authority
4437 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4438 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4439 implicated
4440 by such new technology.<footnote><para>
4441 <!-- f23 -->
4442 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417, 431 (1984).
4443 </para></footnote>
4444 </para>
4445 </blockquote>
4446 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='endofrange'/>
4447 <para>
4448 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4449 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4450 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4451 enough, this <quote>taking</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4452 together, a pattern is clear:
4453 </para>
4454
4455 <informaltable id="t1">
4456 <tgroup cols="4" align="left">
4457 <thead>
4458 <row>
4459 <entry>CASE</entry>
4460 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS <quote>PIRATED</quote></entry>
4461 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS</entry>
4462 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS</entry>
4463 </row>
4464 </thead>
4465 <tbody>
4466 <row>
4467 <entry>Recordings</entry>
4468 <entry>Composers</entry>
4469 <entry>No protection</entry>
4470 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4471 </row>
4472 <row>
4473 <entry>Radio</entry>
4474 <entry>Recording artists</entry>
4475 <entry>N/A</entry>
4476 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4477 </row>
4478 <row>
4479 <entry>Cable TV</entry>
4480 <entry>Broadcasters</entry>
4481 <entry>No protection</entry>
4482 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4483 </row>
4484 <row>
4485 <entry>VCR</entry>
4486 <entry>Film creators</entry>
4487 <entry>No protection</entry>
4488 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4489 </row>
4490 </tbody>
4491 </tgroup>
4492 </informaltable>
4493 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'/>
4494 <para>
4495 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4496 way content was distributed.<footnote><para>
4497 <!-- f24 -->
4498 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4499 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4500 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4501 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4502 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4503 1992 (Title 17 of the <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat.
4504 4237, codified at 17 U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4505 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4506 Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 71. See also Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,</quote>
4507 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 293&ndash;96.
4508 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
4509 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
4510 </para></footnote>
4511 In each case, throughout our history,
4512 that change meant that someone got a <quote>free ride</quote> on someone else's
4513 work.
4514 </para>
4515 <para>
4516 In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4517 Congress eliminate all free riding. In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of
4518 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4519 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4520 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of <quote>piracy.</quote>
4521 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4522 the behavior of the <quote>pirates.</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4523 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4524 interests at stake.
4525 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4526 </para>
4527 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
4528 <para>
4529 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4530 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4531 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4532 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4533 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4534 regulated?
4535 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4536 to $15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4537 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4538 permission to record a song?
4539 </para>
4540 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on balance of interests in copyright law</secondary></indexterm>
4541 <para>
4542 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4543 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4544 copyright <quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4545 over all possible uses of his work.</quote><footnote><para>
4546 <!-- f25 -->
4547 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
4548 (1984).
4549 </para></footnote>
4550 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4551 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4552 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4553 balancing has historically been done <emphasis>after</emphasis> a
4554 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4555 facilitate the distribution of content.
4556 </para>
4557 <para>
4558 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4559 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4560 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4561 should not become a tool for <quote>stealing</quote> from artists. But neither
4562 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4563 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4564 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4565 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4566 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4567 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4568 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4569 public interest that innovation continue.
4570 </para>
4571 <para>
4572
4573 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4574 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4575 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4576 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4577 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4578 efficient. Yet these <quote>potential public benefits,</quote> as John Schwartz
4579 writes in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, <quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4580 fight.</quote><footnote><para>
4581 <!-- f26 -->
4582 John Schwartz, <quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4583 Echoes Past Efforts,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 September 2003, C3.
4584 </para></footnote>
4585 </para>
4586 <para>
4587 <emphasis role='strong'>Yet when anyone</emphasis> begins to talk
4588 about <quote>balance,</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4589 argument. <quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4590 incentives,</quote> they say, <quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4591 content,</quote> the warriors insist, <quote>is our
4592 <emphasis>property</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4593 `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4594 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4595 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether
4596 the car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?</quote>
4597 </para>
4598 <para>
4599 <quote>It is <emphasis>our property</emphasis>,</quote> the warriors
4600 insist. <quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4601 is protected.</quote>
4602 </para>
4603 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4604 </section>
4605 </chapter>
4606 </part>
4607 <part id="c-property">
4608 <title><quote>PROPERTY</quote></title>
4609 <partintro>
4610 <para>
4611
4612 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4613 <emphasis role='strong'>The copyright warriors</emphasis> are right: A
4614 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4615 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4616 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4617 that partially determine the price she can get.
4618 </para>
4619 <para>
4620 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a <quote>property</quote> right is a
4621 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4622 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4623 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4624 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4625 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4626 when I take the good <emphasis>idea</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4627 table in the backyard&mdash;by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4628 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4629 then?
4630 </para>
4631 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
4632 <para>
4633 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4634 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4635 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4636 in the ordinary case&mdash;indeed, in practically every case except for a
4637 narrow
4638 range of exceptions&mdash;ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4639 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress&mdash;though I
4640 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4641 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4642 when I copy the way someone else dresses), <quote>He who receives an idea
4643 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4644 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.</quote><footnote><para>
4645 <!-- f1 -->
4646 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in
4647 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson</citetitle>, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4648 Ellery Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333&ndash;34.
4649 </para></footnote>
4650 </para>
4651 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>intangibility of</secondary></indexterm>
4652 <para>
4653 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4654 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4655 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4656 expression
4657 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4658 property.
4659 </para>
4660 <para>
4661 But how, and to what extent, and in what form&mdash;the details,
4662 in other words&mdash;matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4663 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4664 <quote>property</quote> in its proper context.<footnote><para>
4665 <!-- f2 -->
4666 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4667 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4668 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4669 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4670 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4671 Adam Mossoff, <quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,</quote>
4672 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review</citetitle> 45 (2003): 373, 429 n. 241.
4673 </para></footnote>
4674 </para>
4675 <para>
4676 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4677 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4678 <quote>copyright material is property</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4679 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4680 these stories, the significance of this true
4681 statement&mdash;<quote>copyright material is property</quote>&mdash; will be a bit
4682 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4683 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4684 </para>
4685 </partintro>
4686
4687 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4688 <chapter label="6" id="founders">
4689 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders</title>
4690 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for</secondary></indexterm>
4691 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
4692 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
4693 <indexterm id='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='startofrange'><primary>England, copyright laws developed in</primary></indexterm>
4694 <indexterm id='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='startofrange'><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>history of copyright law in</secondary></indexterm>
4695 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4696 <indexterm><primary>Henry V</primary></indexterm>
4697 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4698 <indexterm id='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='startofrange'><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4699 <para>
4700 <emphasis role='strong'>William Shakespeare</emphasis> wrote
4701 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> in 1595. The play was first
4702 published in 1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4703 written. He would continue to write plays through 1613, and the plays
4704 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4705 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4706 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4707 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4708 Henry V: <quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4709 clichés.</quote>
4710 </para>
4711 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4712 <indexterm id='idxtonsonjacob' class='startofrange'><primary>Tonson, Jacob</primary></indexterm>
4713 <para>
4714 In 1774, almost 180 years after <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> was written, the
4715 <quote>copy-right</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4716 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.<footnote><para>
4717 <!-- f1 -->
4718 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben</primary></indexterm>
4719 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John</primary></indexterm>
4720 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4721 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4722 handsome <quote>definitive editions</quote> of classic works. In addition to <citetitle>Romeo and
4723 Juliet</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4724 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4725 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, <quote>Jacob Tonson,
4726 Bookseller,</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar</citetitle> 61:3 (1992): 424&ndash;31.
4727 </para></footnote>
4728 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4729 the Conger<footnote><para>
4730 <!-- f2 -->
4731 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle> (Nashville:
4732 Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 151&ndash;52.
4733 </para></footnote>
4734 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4735 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the <quote>copy</quote> of
4736 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4737 that no
4738 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4739 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4740 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4741 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4742 </para>
4743 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4744 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4745 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
4746 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4747 <para>
4748 Now, there's something puzzling about the year 1774 to anyone who
4749 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4750 history of copyright is 1710, the year that the British Parliament
4751 adopted the first <quote>copyright</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4752 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4753 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4754 works already published by 1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4755 additional years.<footnote><para>
4756 <!-- f3 -->
4757 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4758 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4759 <quote>copyright law.</quote> See Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 40.
4760 </para></footnote> Under this law, <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> should have been
4761 free in 1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4762 Tonson's control in 1774?
4763 </para>
4764 <indexterm startref='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='endofrange'/>
4765 <indexterm startref='idxtonsonjacob' class='endofrange'/>
4766 <indexterm id='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
4767 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
4768 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (1662)</primary></indexterm>
4769 <para>
4770 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a <quote>copyright</quote>
4771 was&mdash;indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4772 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4773 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of 1662, had
4774 expired in 1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4775 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4776 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4777 that the publishers, or <quote>Stationers,</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4778 books.
4779 </para>
4780 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='endofrange'/>
4781 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
4782 <para>
4783 There was no <emphasis>positive</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4784 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4785 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4786 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4787 from legislatures <quote>positive law.</quote> We call the words from judges
4788 <quote>common law.</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4789 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4790 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4791 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4792 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4793 </para>
4794 <indexterm startref='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='endofrange'/>
4795 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4796 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4797 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
4798 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4799 <para>
4800 This question was important to the publishers, or <quote>booksellers,</quote> as
4801 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4802 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4803 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4804
4805 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4806 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4807 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4808 ultimately
4809 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4810 </para>
4811 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>as narrow monopoly right</secondary></indexterm>
4812 <para>
4813 The Statute of Anne granted the author or <quote>proprietor</quote> of a book an
4814 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4815 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4816 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4817 copyright <quote>expired,</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4818 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4819 believed.
4820 </para>
4821 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne' class='endofrange'/>
4822 <para>
4823 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4824 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4825 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4826 <emphasis>at all?</emphasis>
4827 </para>
4828 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'/>
4829 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4830 <indexterm><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4831 <para>
4832 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4833 strong claim. Take <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> as an example: That play
4834 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4835 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4836 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4837 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4838 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4839 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4840 reason is there to allow someone else to <quote>steal</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4841 </para>
4842 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4843 <para>
4844 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4845 about the notion of <quote>copyright</quote> that existed at the time of the
4846 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4847 <quote>booksellers.</quote>
4848 </para>
4849 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
4850 <para>
4851 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4852 to apply the concept of <quote>copyright</quote> ever more broadly. But in 1710, it
4853 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4854 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4855 others from reprinting a book. In 1710, the <quote>copy-right</quote> was a right
4856 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4857 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4858 generally how
4859 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4860 a work could be <emphasis>used</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4861 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4862 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4863 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4864 </para>
4865 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4866 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4867 <para>
4868 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4869 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4870 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4871 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4872 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4873 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4874 allowed to make his films. The <quote>copy-right</quote> was only an exclusive
4875 right to print&mdash;no less, of course, but also no more.
4876 </para>
4877 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England</primary></indexterm>
4878 <indexterm id='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='startofrange'><primary>monopoly, copyright as</primary></indexterm>
4879 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (1656)</primary></indexterm>
4880 <para>
4881 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4882 They had had a long and ugly experience with <quote>exclusive rights,</quote>
4883 especially <quote>exclusive rights</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4884 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4885 monopolies&mdash;especially monopolies for works that already
4886 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4887 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4888 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In 1656, it passed the
4889 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4890 inventions. And by 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4891 monopoly in publishing.
4892 </para>
4893 <para>
4894 Thus the <quote>copy-right,</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4895 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4896 claim that <quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,</quote> try
4897 sounding convincing when uttering, <quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4898 have it forever.</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4899 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4900 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4901 </para>
4902 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
4903 <indexterm id='idxbooksellersenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>booksellers, English</primary></indexterm>
4904 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4905 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4906 <para>
4907 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4908 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4909 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4910 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4911 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4912
4913 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4914 kind&mdash;tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4915 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4916 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as <quote>old patentees
4917 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling</quote>; they were <quote>men who do
4918 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4919 indetted.</quote><footnote><para>
4920
4921 <!-- f4 -->
4922 Philip Wittenberg, <citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4923 Property</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31.
4924 </para></footnote>
4925 </para>
4926 <indexterm><primary>Enlightenment</primary></indexterm>
4927 <indexterm><primary>knowledge, freedom of</primary></indexterm>
4928 <para>
4929 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4930 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4931 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4932 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4933 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4934 with that idea.
4935 </para>
4936 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament2' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4937 <para>
4938 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4939 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4940 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4941 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4942 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4943 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4944 compromise
4945 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4946 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4947 construction and spread of culture.
4948 </para>
4949 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne2' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)
4950 </primary></indexterm>
4951 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
4952 <para>
4953 When 1731 (1710 + 21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4954 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4955 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4956 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4957 to control publication. But in 1735 and 1737, they tried to persuade
4958 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4959 they said; they needed more time.
4960 </para>
4961 <para>
4962 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4963 words that echo today,
4964 </para>
4965 <blockquote>
4966 <para>
4967 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4968 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4969 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4970 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4971 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4972 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4973 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4974 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4975 Booksellers.<footnote><para>
4976 <!-- f5 -->
4977 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4978 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4979 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4980 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4981 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4982 mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4983 al., 8, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618).
4984 </para></footnote>
4985 </para>
4986 </blockquote>
4987 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne2' class='endofrange'/>
4988 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='endofrange'/>
4989 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
4990 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
4991 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
4992 <para>
4993 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4994 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4995 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
4996 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
4997 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
4998 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
4999 creative <quote>property</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
5000 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
5001 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
5002 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
5003 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
5004 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
5005 way to protect authors.
5006 </para>
5007 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament2' class='endofrange'/>
5008 <para>
5009 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
5010 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
5011 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
5012 <quote>The publishers &hellip; had as much concern for authors as a cattle
5013 rancher has for cattle.</quote><footnote><para>
5014 <!-- f6 -->
5015 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5016 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
5017 Lyman Ray Patterson, <quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
5018 Law Review</citetitle> 40 (1987): 28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
5019 Vaidhyanathan, 37&ndash;48.
5020 </para></footnote>
5021 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
5022 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
5023 </para>
5024 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5025 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5026 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5027 <para>
5028 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
5029 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
5030 Donaldson.<footnote><para>
5031 <!-- f7 -->
5032 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, <citetitle>Authorship and Copyright</citetitle>
5033 (London: Routledge, 1992), 62&ndash;69.
5034 </para></footnote>
5035 </para>
5036 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne3' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
5037 <indexterm id='idxconger' class='startofrange'><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
5038 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James</primary></indexterm>
5039 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew</primary></indexterm>
5040 <para>
5041 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
5042 career in Edinburgh in 1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
5043 reprints <quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,</quote> at least
5044 under the Statute of Anne.<footnote><para>
5045 <!-- f8 -->
5046 Mark Rose, <citetitle>Authors and Owners</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
5047 1993), 92.
5048 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
5049 </para></footnote>
5050 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
5051 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
5052 and became <quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.</quote> <quote>[A]mong
5053 them,</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was <quote>the young James Boswell
5054 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
5055 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.</quote><footnote><para>
5056 <!-- f9 -->
5057 Ibid., 93.
5058 </para></footnote>
5059 </para>
5060 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5061 <para>
5062 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
5063 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
5064 inexpensive editions <quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
5065 of the supposed common law right of Literary
5066 Property.</quote><footnote><para>
5067 <!-- f10 -->
5068 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5069 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle>, 167 (quoting
5070 Borwell).
5071 </para></footnote>
5072 His books undercut the Conger prices by 30 to 50 percent, and he
5073 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
5074 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
5075 </para>
5076 <indexterm startref='idxconger' class='endofrange'/>
5077 <indexterm id='idxmillarvtaylor' class='startofrange'><primary>Millar v. Taylor</primary></indexterm>
5078 <para>
5079 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block <quote>piracy</quote> like
5080 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the <quote>pirates,</quote>
5081 the most important early victory being <citetitle>Millar</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Taylor</citetitle>.
5082 </para>
5083 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='endofrange'/>
5084 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers' class='endofrange'/>
5085 <indexterm id='idxthomsonjames' class='startofrange'><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5086 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5087 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)</primary></indexterm>
5088 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert</primary></indexterm>
5089 <para>
5090 Millar was a bookseller who in 1729 had purchased the rights to James
5091 Thomson's poem <quote>The Seasons.</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
5092 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
5093 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
5094 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
5095 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.<footnote><para>
5096 <!-- f11 -->
5097 Howard B. Abrams, <quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
5098 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review</citetitle> 29
5099 (1983): 1152.
5100 </para></footnote>
5101 </para>
5102 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
5103 <para>
5104 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
5105 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
5106 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
5107 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
5108 law would protect the author against subsequent <quote>pirates.</quote>
5109 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
5110 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
5111 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
5112 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
5113 </para>
5114 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw' class='endofrange'/>
5115 <indexterm startref='idxthomsonjames' class='endofrange'/>
5116 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='endofrange'/>
5117 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament3' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5118 <para>
5119 Considered as a matter of abstract justice&mdash;reasoning as if
5120 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
5121 principles&mdash;Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
5122 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
5123 with in 1710: How best to limit
5124 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
5125 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
5126 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in 1710, but
5127 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
5128 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
5129 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
5130 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
5131 </para>
5132 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='endofrange'/>
5133 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5134 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers2' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5135 <para>
5136 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
5137 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
5138 </para>
5139 <indexterm><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5140 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
5141 <indexterm id='idxhouseoflords' class='startofrange'><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5142 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>House of Lords vs.</secondary></indexterm>
5143 <para>
5144 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
5145 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
5146 Thomas Beckett.<footnote><para>
5147 <!-- f12 -->
5148 Ibid., 1156.
5149 </para></footnote>
5150 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
5151 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in <citetitle>Millar</citetitle>,
5152 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
5153 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
5154 Court. In February of 1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
5155 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
5156 </para>
5157 <indexterm startref='idxmillarvtaylor' class='endofrange'/>
5158 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament3' class='endofrange'/>
5159 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson v. Beckett</primary></indexterm>
5160 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5161 <para>
5162 As few legal cases ever do, <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle> drew an
5163 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
5164 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
5165 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
5166 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
5167 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
5168 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
5169 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
5170 </para>
5171 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne3' class='endofrange'/>
5172 <para>
5173 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
5174 presented to the House and voted upon first by the <quote>law lords,</quote>
5175 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
5176 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
5177 House of Lords generally voted.
5178 </para>
5179 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='endofrange'/>
5180 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5181 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5182 <para>
5183 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
5184 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
5185 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
5186 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
5187 (22 to 11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
5188 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
5189 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
5190 passed into the public domain.
5191 </para>
5192 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis</primary></indexterm>
5193 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John</primary></indexterm>
5194 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel</primary></indexterm>
5195 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
5196 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
5197 <para>
5198 <quote>The public domain.</quote> Before the case of <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle>
5199 v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
5200 England. Before 1774, there was a strong argument that common law
5201 copyrights were perpetual. After 1774, the public domain was
5202 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
5203 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
5204 history&mdash;including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
5205 and Bunyan&mdash;were free of legal restraint.
5206 </para>
5207 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='endofrange'/>
5208 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers2' class='endofrange'/>
5209 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw2' class='endofrange'/>
5210 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='endofrange'/>
5211 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5212 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5213 <para>
5214 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
5215 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
5216 where most of the <quote>pirate publishers</quote> did their work, people
5217 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the <citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser</citetitle>
5218 reported, <quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
5219 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
5220 decision of which so many individuals were interested.</quote> <quote>Great
5221 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
5222 and illuminations.</quote><footnote><para>
5223 <!-- f13 -->
5224 Rose, 97.
5225 </para></footnote>
5226 </para>
5227 <indexterm startref='idxhouseoflords' class='endofrange'/>
5228 <para>
5229 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
5230 equally strong in the opposite direction. The <citetitle>Morning Chronicle</citetitle>
5231 reported:
5232 </para>
5233 <blockquote>
5234 <para>
5235 By the above decision &hellip; near 200,000 pounds worth of what was
5236 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
5237 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
5238 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
5239 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
5240 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
5241 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
5242 successors.<footnote><para>
5243 <!-- f14 -->
5244 Ibid.
5245 </para></footnote>
5246 </para>
5247 </blockquote>
5248 <indexterm><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5249 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5250 <para>
5251 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
5252 <quote>Ruined</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
5253 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
5254 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
5255 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
5256 <emphasis>free</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
5257 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
5258 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
5259 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
5260 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
5261 book from someone. But <emphasis>free</emphasis> in the sense that the
5262 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
5263 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
5264 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
5265 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
5266 develop&mdash; chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
5267 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a <emphasis>competitive
5268 context</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
5269 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
5270 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
5271 </para>
5272 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellersenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5273 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5274 <para>
5275 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
5276 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
5277 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
5278 protected.
5279 </para>
5280 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='endofrange'/>
5281 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5282 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5283 <indexterm startref='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='endofrange'/>
5284 <indexterm startref='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='endofrange'/>
5285 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='endofrange'/>
5286 <indexterm startref='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='endofrange'/>
5287 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='endofrange'/>
5288 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='endofrange'/>
5289 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
5290 </chapter>
5291 <chapter label="7" id="recorders">
5292 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders</title>
5293 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
5294 <indexterm id='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>documentary film</primary></indexterm>
5295 <indexterm id='idxelsejon' class='startofrange'><primary>Else, Jon</primary></indexterm>
5296 <indexterm id='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>in documentary film</secondary></indexterm>
5297 <indexterm id='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>fair use of copyrighted material in</secondary></indexterm>
5298 <para>
5299 <emphasis role='strong'>Jon Else</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5300 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5301 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5302 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5303 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5304 </para>
5305 <para>
5306 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5307 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5308 today.
5309 </para>
5310 <indexterm id='idxwagnerrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5311 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5312 <para>
5313 In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5314 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5315 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5316 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5317 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5318 stage.
5319 </para>
5320 <indexterm id='idxsimpsonsthe' class='startofrange'><primary>Simpsons, The</primary></indexterm>
5321 <para>
5322 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5323 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5324 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5325 and the opera company played Wagner, was <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. As Else judged
5326 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5327 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5328 about the scene.
5329 </para>
5330 <indexterm startref='idxwagnerrichard' class='endofrange'/>
5331 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>multiple copyrights associated with</secondary></indexterm>
5332 <para>
5333 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5334 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>.
5335 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5336 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5337 unless <quote>fair use</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5338 </para>
5339 <indexterm id='idxgraciefilms' class='startofrange'><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5340 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt' class='startofrange'><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5341 <para>
5342 Else called <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5343 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5344 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5345 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5346 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5347 </para>
5348 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5349 <para>
5350 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5351 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5352 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5353 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5354 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5355 </para>
5356 <indexterm startref='idxgraciefilms' class='endofrange'/>
5357 <para>
5358 Then, as Else told me, <quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5359 &hellip; that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation&mdash;or at
5360 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.</quote>
5361 And second, Fox <quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5362 to use this four-point-five seconds of &hellip; entirely unsolicited
5363 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.</quote>
5364 </para>
5365 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt' class='endofrange'/>
5366 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='endofrange'/>
5367 <indexterm id='idxherrerarebecca' class='startofrange'><primary>Herrera, Rebecca</primary></indexterm>
5368 <para>
5369 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5370 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5371 explained to her, <quote>There must be some mistake here. &hellip; We're
5372 asking for your educational rate on this.</quote> That was the educational
5373 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5374 confirm what he had been told.
5375 </para>
5376 <indexterm><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5377 <para>
5378 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,</quote> he told me. <quote>Yes, you
5379 have your facts straight,</quote> she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the
5380 clip of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5381 about
5382
5383 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5384 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, <quote>And
5385 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.</quote> As an assistant
5386 to Herrera told Else later on, <quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5387 the money.</quote>
5388 </para>
5389 <indexterm startref='idxherrerarebecca' class='endofrange'/>
5390 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5391 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The</primary></indexterm>
5392 <para>
5393 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5394 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5395 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5396 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5397 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5398 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5399 </para>
5400 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5401 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt2' class='startofrange'><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5402 <para>
5403 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5404 copyright to <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5405 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5406 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5407 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5408 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5409 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5410 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5411 says the owner gets to control.
5412 </para>
5413 <para>
5414 For example, <quote>public performance</quote> is a use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> that the
5415 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5416 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see <quote>My
5417 Favorite <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>,</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5418 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5419 whatever she wants&mdash;$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set
5420 by the law.
5421 </para>
5422 <para>
5423 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5424 thought is <quote>fair use.</quote><footnote><para>
5425 <!-- f1 -->
5426 For an excellent argument that such use is <quote>fair use,</quote> but that
5427 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is <quote>fair use,</quote> see Richard
5428 A. Posner with William F. Patry, <quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5429 Wake of <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5430 Law School, 5 August 2003.
5431 </para></footnote>
5432 Else's use of just 4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>
5433 episode is clearly a fair use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>&mdash;and fair use does
5434 not require the permission of anyone.
5435 </para>
5436 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='endofrange'/>
5437 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt2' class='endofrange'/>
5438 <para>
5439 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5440 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon <quote>fair use.</quote> Here's his reply:
5441 </para>
5442 <blockquote>
5443 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
5444 <para>
5445 The <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5446 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5447 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5448 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was <quote>clearly
5449 fair use</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5450 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5451 </para>
5452 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
5453 <listitem>
5454 <indexterm><primary>Errors and Omissions insurance</primary></indexterm>
5455 <para>
5456 <!-- 1. -->
5457 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5458 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5459 <quote>visual cue sheet</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5460 shot in the film. They take a dim view of <quote>fair use,</quote> and a claim of
5461 <quote>fair use</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5462 </para></listitem>
5463 <listitem>
5464 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5465 <indexterm><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5466 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George</primary></indexterm>
5467 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5468 <para>
5469 <!-- 2. -->
5470 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5471 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5472 tracking down and stopping unlicensed <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> usage, just as George
5473 Lucas had a very high profile litigating <citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5474 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5475 license to four seconds of <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5476 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5477 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5478 principle.
5479 </para></listitem>
5480 <listitem><para>
5481 <!-- 3. -->
5482 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5483 School &hellip; who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5484 that Fox would <quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5485 life,</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5486 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5487 pockets, me or them.
5488 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5489 </para>
5490 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='endofrange'/>
5491 </listitem>
5492 <listitem><para>
5493 <!-- 4. -->
5494 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5495 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5496 money.
5497 </para></listitem>
5498 </orderedlist>
5499 </blockquote>
5500 <indexterm startref='idxsimpsonsthe' class='endofrange'/>
5501 <para>
5502 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5503 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5504 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5505 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5506 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5507 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5508 </para>
5509 <para>
5510 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5511 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5512 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5513 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5514 not.
5515 </para>
5516 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='endofrange'/>
5517 <indexterm startref='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5518 <indexterm startref='idxelsejon' class='endofrange'/>
5519 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5520 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='endofrange'/>
5521 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='endofrange'/>
5522 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5523 </chapter>
5524 <chapter label="8" id="transformers">
5525 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers</title>
5526 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul</primary></indexterm>
5527 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5528 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary></indexterm>
5529 <para>
5530 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5531 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5532 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5533 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5534 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5535 anticipation of the power of networks.
5536 </para>
5537 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on</secondary></indexterm>
5538 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in</primary></indexterm>
5539 <para>
5540 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5541 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology&mdash;not to distribute
5542 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5543 difficult. In 1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5544 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5545 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5546 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5547 important to his career.
5548 </para>
5549 <para>
5550 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5551 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5552 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5553 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5554 </para>
5555 <para>
5556 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5557 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5558 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5559 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5560 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5561 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5562 </para>
5563 <para>
5564 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. <quote>Our
5565 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5566 Eastwood's films,</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5567 arose. <quote>No one had ever really done this before,</quote> Alben explained. <quote>No
5568 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5569 actor's career.</quote>
5570 </para>
5571 <para>
5572 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5573 Slade asked, <quote>Well, what will it take?</quote>
5574 </para>
5575 <para>
5576 Alben replied, <quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5577 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5578 else that we want to use in these film clips.</quote> Slade said, <quote>Great! Go
5579 for it.</quote><footnote>
5580 <para>
5581 <!-- f1 -->
5582 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5583 publicity&mdash;rights an artist has to control the commercial
5584 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden <quote>Rip, Mix,
5585 Burn</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5586 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of</secondary></indexterm>
5587 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5588 </para></footnote>
5589 </para>
5590 <para>
5591 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5592 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5593 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5594 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5595 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5596 </para>
5597 <para>
5598 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5599 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5600 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5601 </para>
5602 <blockquote>
5603 <para>
5604 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5605 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include&mdash;of
5606 course we were going to use the <quote>Make my day</quote> clip from <citetitle>Dirty
5607 Harry</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5608 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5609 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5610 </para>
5611 <para>
5612 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5613 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5614 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5615 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5616 rate at the time was about $600. So we had to identify the
5617 people&mdash;some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5618 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5619 glass&mdash;is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5620 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5621 started calling people.
5622 </para>
5623 </blockquote>
5624 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald</primary></indexterm>
5625 <para>
5626 Some actors were glad to help&mdash;Donald Sutherland, for example,
5627 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5628 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5629 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5630 know, $1,200?</quote> And they would say, <quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5631 to get $1,200.</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5632 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5633 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5634 career.
5635 </para>
5636 <para>
5637 It was one <emphasis>year</emphasis> later&mdash;<quote>and even then we
5638 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.</quote>
5639 </para>
5640 <para>
5641 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5642 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5643 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5644 </para>
5645 <blockquote>
5646 <para>
5647 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5648 hands and said, <quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5649 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5650 actors.</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5651 constituent parts and said, <quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5652 directors, &hellip; this many musicians,</quote> and we just went at it very
5653 systematically and cleared the rights.
5654 </para>
5655 </blockquote>
5656 <para>
5657
5658 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5659 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5660 loved it, and it sold very well.
5661 </para>
5662 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter</primary></indexterm>
5663 <para>
5664 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5665 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5666 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, <quote>There is
5667 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5668 at all.</quote><footnote><para>
5669 <!-- f2 -->
5670 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, <citetitle>Seven
5671 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition</citetitle>, available at
5672 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #22</ulink>.
5673 </para></footnote>
5674 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5675 has to be made?
5676 </para>
5677 <para>
5678 For, as he acknowledged, <quote>very few &hellip; have the time and resources,
5679 and the will to do this,</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5680 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5681 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5682 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5683 </para>
5684 <blockquote>
5685 <para>
5686 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5687 he or she gets paid very well. &hellip; And then when 30 seconds of
5688 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5689 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person &hellip; should be
5690 compensated for that.
5691 </para>
5692 </blockquote>
5693 <para>
5694 Or at least, is this <emphasis>how</emphasis> the artist should be
5695 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5696 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5697 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5698 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5699 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5700 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5701 made to be more clean?
5702 </para>
5703 <blockquote>
5704 <para>
5705 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5706 mechanism&mdash;where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5707 subject to estranged former spouses&mdash;you'd see a lot more of this
5708 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5709 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5710 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5711 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5712 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5713 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5714 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5715 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5716 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5717 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5718 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, <quote>Oh, I
5719 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5720 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5721 money,</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5722 </para>
5723 </blockquote>
5724 <para>
5725 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5726 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5727 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5728 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5729 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5730 </para>
5731 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'/>
5732 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'/>
5733 <para>
5734 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5735 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5736 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5737 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5738 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5739 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5740 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5741 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5742 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5743 <quote>Does this still make sense?</quote>
5744 </para>
5745 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'/>
5746 <para>
5747 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5748 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5749 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5750 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5751
5752 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5753 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5754 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5755 </para>
5756 <para>
5757 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5758 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode.
5759 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5760 judges loved every minute of it.
5761 </para>
5762 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David</primary></indexterm>
5763 <para>
5764 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5765 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5766 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5767 room of over 250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5768 began his talk with a question: <quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5769 were just violated in this room?</quote>
5770 </para>
5771 <para>
5772 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5773 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David</primary></indexterm>
5774 <indexterm><primary>Court of Appeals</primary><secondary>Ninth Circuit</secondary></indexterm>
5775 <indexterm><primary>Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals</primary></indexterm>
5776 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
5777 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5778 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5779 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5780 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5781 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle
5782 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5783 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5784 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5785 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5786 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5787 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5788 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5789 couldn't easily do them legally.
5790 </para>
5791 <para>
5792 We live in a <quote>cut and paste</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5793 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5794 and paste architecture of the Internet created&mdash;in a second you can
5795 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5796 planted in your presentation.
5797 </para>
5798 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos</primary></indexterm>
5799 <para>
5800 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5801 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5802 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5803 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5804 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5805 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5806 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5807 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5808 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5809 </para>
5810 <para>
5811 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5812 wanted to be <quote>legal,</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5813 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5814 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5815 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5816 </para>
5817 <para>
5818 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5819 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5820 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5821 necessarily requiring that the <quote>free</quote> use be free as in <quote>free beer.</quote>
5822 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5823 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5824 along: a rule, for example, that says <quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5825 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5826 will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5827 copyright owner.</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5828 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5829 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5830 registers the work.
5831 </para>
5832 <para>
5833 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5834 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5835 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5836 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5837 </para>
5838 <para>
5839 <emphasis role='strong'>In February 2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5840 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5841 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live</citetitle> and
5842 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5843 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5844 would work together to form a <quote>unique filmmaking pact.</quote> Under the
5845 agreement, DreamWorks <quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5846 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and&mdash;with the use
5847 of stateof-the-art digital technology&mdash;insert Myers and other
5848 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5849 entertainment.</quote>
5850 </para>
5851 <para>
5852 The announcement called this <quote>film sampling.</quote> As Myers explained,
5853 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5854 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5855 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5856 to take that same concept and apply it to film.</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5857 quoted as saying, <quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5858 new audiences, it is Mike.</quote>
5859 </para>
5860 <para>
5861 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5862 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5863 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5864 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5865 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5866 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5867 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5868 privilege reserved for the funny and famous&mdash;and presumably rich.
5869 </para>
5870 <para>
5871 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5872 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of <quote>fair use.</quote>
5873 Much of <quote>sampling</quote> should be considered <quote>fair use.</quote> But few would
5874 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5875 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5876 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5877 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5878 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5879 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5880 process is a process of paying lawyers&mdash;again a privilege, or perhaps a
5881 curse, reserved for the few.
5882 </para>
5883 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5884 </chapter>
5885 <chapter label="9" id="collectors">
5886 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors</title>
5887 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
5888 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
5889 <para>
5890 <emphasis role='strong'>In April 1996</emphasis>, millions of
5891 <quote>bots</quote>&mdash;computer codes designed to
5892 <quote>spider,</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5893 content&mdash;began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5894 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5895 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5896 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5897 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5898 Internet and stored them.
5899 </para>
5900 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5901 <para>
5902 By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5903 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5904 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5905 the world. Using a technology called <quote>the Way Back Machine,</quote> you could
5906 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to 1996, as
5907 well as when those pages changed.
5908 </para>
5909 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Orwell, George</primary></indexterm>
5910 <para>
5911 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5912 appreciated. In the dystopia described in <citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5913 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5914 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5915 reports.
5916 </para>
5917 <para>
5918 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5919 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5920 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5921 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5922 </para>
5923 <para>
5924 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5925 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5926 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5927 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5928 library&mdash;constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5929 </para>
5930 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'/>
5931 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5932 <para>
5933 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5934 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5935 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5936 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5937 what others might prefer you forget.<footnote><para>
5938 <!-- f1 -->
5939 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
5940 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases</primary></indexterm>
5941 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5942 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003,
5943 press release stated, <quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.</quote> That was
5944 later changed, without notice, to <quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5945 Have Ended.</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003.
5946 </para></footnote>
5947 </para>
5948 <indexterm><primary>history, records of</primary></indexterm>
5949 <para>
5950 <emphasis role='strong'>We take it</emphasis> for granted that we can
5951 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5952 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5953 race riots in Watts in 1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in 1963,
5954 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5955 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5956 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
5957 remember&mdash;not just what it is convenient to remember, but
5958 remember something close to the truth.
5959 </para>
5960 <para>
5961 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5962 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We <emphasis>all</emphasis>
5963 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
5964 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
5965 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
5966 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
5967 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
5968 </para>
5969 <para>
5970 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5971 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5972 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5973 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5974 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5975 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5976 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5977 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet&mdash;the
5978 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5979 </para>
5980 <para>
5981 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5982 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5983 researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5984 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5985 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5986 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5987 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10
5988 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5989 </para>
5990 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
5991 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive</primary></indexterm>
5992 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University</primary></indexterm>
5993 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5994 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>archival function of</secondary></indexterm>
5995 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage2' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
5996 <para>
5997 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
5998 human history. At the end of 2002, it held <quote>two hundred and thirty
5999 terabytes of material</quote>&mdash;and was <quote>ten times larger than the
6000 Library of Congress.</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
6001 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
6002 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
6003 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
6004 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
6005 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
6006 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University&mdash;thanks to a
6007 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
6008 is available to scholars for a very low fee. <quote>But other than that,
6009 [television] is almost unavailable,</quote> Kahle told me. <quote>If you were
6010 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
6011 just a graduate student?</quote> As Kahle put it,
6012 </para>
6013 <blockquote>
6014 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan</primary></indexterm>
6015 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes</primary></indexterm>
6016 <para>
6017 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
6018 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
6019 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
6020 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
6021 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
6022
6023 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
6024 <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode that came out after it &hellip; it would be almost
6025 impossible. &hellip; Those materials are almost unfindable. &hellip;
6026 </para>
6027 </blockquote>
6028 <indexterm><primary>newspapers</primary><secondary>archives of</secondary></indexterm>
6029 <para>
6030 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
6031 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
6032 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
6033 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
6034 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
6035 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
6036 </para>
6037 <para>
6038 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
6039 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
6040 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
6041 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
6042 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
6043 work.
6044 </para>
6045 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
6046 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6047 <para>
6048 These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library
6049 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
6050 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
6051 borrow back the deposits&mdash;for an unlimited time at no cost. In
6052 1915 alone, there were more than 5,475 films deposited and <quote>borrowed
6053 back.</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
6054 held by any library. The copy exists&mdash;if it exists at
6055 all&mdash;in the library archive of the film company.<footnote><para>
6056 <!-- f2 -->
6057 Doug Herrick, <quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
6058 the Library of Congress,</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly</citetitle> 13 nos. 2&ndash;3
6059 (1980): 5; Anthony Slide, <citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
6060 Preservation in the United States</citetitle> (Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland &amp;
6061 Co., 1992), 36.
6062 </para></footnote>
6063 </para>
6064 <para>
6065 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
6066 were originally not copyrighted&mdash;there was no way to capture the
6067 broadcasts, so there was no fear of <quote>theft.</quote> But as technology enabled
6068 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
6069 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
6070 <quote>copyrighted.</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
6071 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
6072 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
6073 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
6074 </para>
6075 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
6076 <para>
6077 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and
6078 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
6079 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
6080 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
6081 September 11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
6082 stations from around the world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made
6083 their coverage during the week of September 11 available free on-line.
6084 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
6085 events of that day.
6086 </para>
6087 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive</primary></indexterm>
6088 <indexterm><primary>archive.org</primary><seealso>Internet Archive</seealso></indexterm>
6089 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage2' class='endofrange'/>
6090 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6091 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive</primary></indexterm>
6092 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film</primary></indexterm>
6093 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films</primary></indexterm>
6094 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick</primary></indexterm>
6095 <para>
6096 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
6097 archive of film includes close to 45,000 <quote>ephemeral films</quote> (meaning
6098 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
6099 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
6100 1,300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
6101 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
6102 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
6103 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
6104 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
6105 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
6106 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
6107 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
6108 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the <quote>Duck and Cover</quote> film
6109 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
6110 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
6111 few minutes&mdash;for free.
6112 </para>
6113 <para>
6114 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
6115 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
6116 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
6117 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
6118 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
6119 to find them.
6120 </para>
6121 <para>
6122 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
6123 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
6124 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
6125 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
6126 property, but during a second life that all creative property
6127 has&mdash;a noncommercial life.
6128 </para>
6129 <para>
6130 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
6131 of creative property goes through different <quote>lives.</quote> In its first
6132 life, if the
6133
6134 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
6135 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
6136 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
6137 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
6138 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
6139 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
6140 </para>
6141 <para>
6142 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
6143 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
6144 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
6145 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
6146 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
6147 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
6148 longer sold.
6149 </para>
6150 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6151 <para>
6152 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
6153 very quickly (the average today is after about a year<footnote><para>
6154 <!-- f3 -->
6155 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6156 Dave Barns, <quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
6157 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>,
6158 5 September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927
6159 and 1946, only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese,
6160 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,</quote> <citetitle>Boston
6161 College Law Review</citetitle> 44 (2003): 593 n. 51.
6162 </para></footnote>). After
6163 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
6164 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
6165 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
6166 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
6167 important to the spread and stability of culture.
6168 </para>
6169 <para>
6170 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
6171 creative property does not hold true with the most important
6172 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
6173 centuries. For these&mdash;television, movies, music, radio, the
6174 Internet&mdash;there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
6175 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes &amp;
6176 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
6177 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
6178 disappears.
6179 </para>
6180 <para>
6181 <emphasis role='strong'>For most of</emphasis> the twentieth century,
6182 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
6183 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
6184 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
6185 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
6186 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
6187 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
6188 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
6189 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
6190 little practical effect.
6191 </para>
6192 <para>
6193 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
6194 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
6195 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
6196 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
6197 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
6198 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
6199 </para>
6200 <para>
6201 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
6202 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
6203 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
6204 Kahle describes,
6205 </para>
6206 <blockquote>
6207 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>total number of</secondary></indexterm>
6208 <para>
6209 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
6210 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
6211 movies, &hellip; and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
6212 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
6213 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
6214 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
6215 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
6216 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
6217 &hellip; thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
6218 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
6219 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
6220 </para>
6221 </blockquote>
6222 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
6223 <para>
6224 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
6225 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
6226 libraries or archives could be. <emphasis>When</emphasis> the
6227 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
6228 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
6229 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
6230 will draw upon it to understand it;
6231 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
6232 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
6233 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
6234 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past&mdash;a
6235 future <emphasis>for</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
6236 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
6237 </para>
6238 <para>
6239 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
6240 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
6241 call these <quote>archives,</quote> as warm as the idea of a <quote>library</quote> might seem,
6242 the <quote>content</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
6243 someone's <quote>property.</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
6244 that Kahle and others would exercise.
6245 </para>
6246 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'/>
6247 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
6248 </chapter>
6249 <chapter label="10" id="property-i">
6250 <title>CHAPTER TEN: <quote>Property</quote></title>
6251 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon</primary></indexterm>
6252 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
6253 <para>
6254 <emphasis role='strong'>Jack Valenti</emphasis> has been the president
6255 of the Motion Picture Association of America since 1966. He first came
6256 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
6257 administration&mdash;literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
6258 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
6259 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
6260 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
6261 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
6262 </para>
6263 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
6264 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment</primary></indexterm>
6265 <indexterm><primary>MGM</primary></indexterm>
6266 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6267 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox</primary></indexterm>
6268 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6269 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
6270 <para>
6271 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
6272 Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal
6273 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
6274 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
6275 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
6276 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
6277 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
6278 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
6279 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
6280 Warner Brothers.
6281 </para>
6282 <para>
6283 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
6284 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
6285 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
6286 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
6287 political skill of a Southerner&mdash;the ability to appear simple and
6288 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
6289 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
6290 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
6291 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
6292 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
6293 Washingtonian way.
6294 </para>
6295 <para>
6296 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
6297 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
6298 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
6299 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
6300 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
6301 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
6302 redefine the meaning of <quote>creative property.</quote>
6303 </para>
6304 <para>
6305 In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
6306 perfectly:
6307 </para>
6308 <blockquote>
6309 <para>
6310 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
6311 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
6312 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
6313 theme which animates this entire debate: <emphasis>Creative property
6314 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
6315 other property owners in the nation</emphasis>. That is the issue.
6316 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
6317 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.<footnote><para>
6318 <!-- f1 -->
6319 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R.
6320 4794, H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the
6321 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
6322 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
6323 Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack
6324 Valenti).
6325 </para></footnote>
6326 </para>
6327 </blockquote>
6328 <para>
6329 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
6330 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
6331 <quote>central theme</quote> to which <quote>reasonable men and women</quote> will return is
6332 this:
6333 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6334 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6335 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.</quote>
6336 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6337 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6338 </para>
6339 <para>
6340 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6341 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6342 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6343 extreme a claim made by <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> who is serious in
6344 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6345 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6346 it comes to the nature and scope of <quote>creative property.</quote> His views
6347 have <emphasis>no</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6348 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6349 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6350 </para>
6351 <para>
6352 While <quote>creative property</quote> is certainly <quote>property</quote> in a nerdy and
6353 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,<footnote><para>
6354 <!-- f2 -->
6355 Lawyers speak of <quote>property</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6356 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6357 object. Thus, my <quote>property right</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6358 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For
6359 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of <quote>property</quote> to
6360 <quote>lawyer talk,</quote> see Bruce Ackerman, <citetitle>Private Property and the
6361 Constitution</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 26&ndash;27.
6362 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6363 <quote>creative property owners</quote> have been <quote>accorded the same rights and
6364 protection resident in all other property owners.</quote> Indeed, if creative
6365 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6366 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6367 in our tradition.
6368 </para>
6369 <para>
6370 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6371 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6372 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6373 overturned in 1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6374 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6375 culture would develop.
6376 </para>
6377 <para>
6378 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6379 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6380 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6381 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6382 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6383 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6384 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6385 the same would be to
6386
6387 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6388 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6389 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6390 perfect control.
6391 </para>
6392 <para>
6393 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6394 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6395 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6396 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6397 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6398 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6399 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6400 </para>
6401 <para>
6402 <emphasis role='strong'>To get</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6403 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6404 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6405 </para>
6406 <para>
6407 The framers of our Constitution loved <quote>property.</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6408 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6409 important requirement. If the government takes your property&mdash;if
6410 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6411 farm&mdash;it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's <quote>Takings
6412 Clause,</quote> to pay you <quote>just compensation</quote> for that taking. The
6413 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6414 sacred. It cannot <emphasis>ever</emphasis> be taken from the property
6415 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6416 </para>
6417 <para>
6418 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6419 Valenti calls <quote>creative property.</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6420 power to create <quote>creative property,</quote> the Constitution
6421 <emphasis>requires</emphasis> that after a <quote>limited time,</quote> Congress
6422 take back the rights that it has granted and set the <quote>creative
6423 property</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6424 the expiration of a copyright term <quote>takes</quote> your copyright and turns it
6425 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6426 pay <quote>just compensation</quote> for this <quote>taking.</quote> Instead, the same
6427 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6428 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6429 requires that you lose your <quote>creative property</quote> right without any
6430 compensation at all.
6431 </para>
6432 <para>
6433 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6434 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6435 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6436 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6437 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6438 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6439 itself.
6440 </para>
6441 <indexterm id='idxjeffersonthomas' class='startofrange'><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
6442 <para>
6443 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6444 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6445 The Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6446 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6447 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6448 president (as it did in 1800). The framers were no doubt
6449 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6450 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6451 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6452 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6453 </para>
6454 <para>
6455 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6456 least try to understand <emphasis>why</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6457 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6458 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6459 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6460 domain?
6461 </para>
6462 <indexterm startref='idxjeffersonthomas' class='endofrange'/>
6463
6464 <para>
6465 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6466 history of these <quote>creative property</quote> rights, and the control that they
6467 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6468 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6469 should be at the core of this war: Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis>
6470 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6471 <emphasis>whether</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6472 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6473 ought to be. Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6474 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6475 also control how culture develops.
6476 </para>
6477 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>four modalities of constraint on</secondary></indexterm>
6478 <indexterm id='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>four modalities of</secondary></indexterm>
6479 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as ex post regulation modality</secondary></indexterm>
6480 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6481 <para>
6482
6483 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6484 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6485 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6486 than the narrow language of the law allows. In <citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6487 Cyberspace</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6488 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6489 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6490 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6491 </para>
6492 <figure id="fig-1331">
6493 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.</title>
6494 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6495 </figure>
6496 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6497 <para>
6498 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6499 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6500 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6501 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6502 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6503 be regulated&mdash; either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6504 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6505 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6506 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6507 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6508 Web, you can be punished
6509 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6510 with a $150,000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6511 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6512 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6513 </para>
6514 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6515 <para>
6516 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6517 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6518 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6519 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6520 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6521 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6522 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6523 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6524 the source of the enforcement.
6525 </para>
6526 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6527 <para>
6528 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6529 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6530 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6531 norms&mdash;it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6532 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6533 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6534 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6535 individual or group might behave.
6536 </para>
6537 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6538 <para>
6539 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6540 <quote>architecture</quote>&mdash;the physical world as one finds it&mdash;is a
6541 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6542 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6543 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6544 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6545 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6546 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6547 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6548 theft, but by nature, by <quote>architecture.</quote> If a 500-pound boulder
6549 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6550 constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6551 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6552 </para>
6553 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6554 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6555 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints' class='endofrange'/>
6556 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6557 <para>
6558
6559 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6560 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6561 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6562 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6563 undermined by another.
6564 </para>
6565 <para>
6566 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6567 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6568 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6569 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6570 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6571 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6572 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6573 </para>
6574 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6575 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6576 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6577 <indexterm id='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>driving speed, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6578 <indexterm id='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>speeding, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6579 <para>
6580 So, for example, consider the <quote>freedom</quote> to drive a car at a high
6581 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6582 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6583 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6584 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6585 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6586 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6587 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6588 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6589 the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own
6590 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6591 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6592 </para>
6593 <para>
6594 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6595 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6596 special role in affecting the three.<footnote><para>
6597 <!-- f3 -->
6598 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6599 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6600 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6601 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6602 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Code: And
6603 Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90&ndash;95;
6604 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>The New Chicago School,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies</citetitle>,
6605 June 1998.
6606 </para></footnote>
6607 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6608 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6609 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6610 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6611 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6612 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6613 used to require that other laws be more
6614 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6615 strict&mdash;a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6616 limit, for example&mdash;so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6617 driving.
6618 </para>
6619 <indexterm startref='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6620 <indexterm startref='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6621 <figure id="fig-1361">
6622 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.</title>
6623 <graphic fileref="images/1361.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6624
6625 </figure>
6626 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6627 <para>
6628 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6629 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6630 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6631 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6632 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6633 another.<footnote>
6634 <para>
6635 <!-- f4 -->
6636 Some people object to this way of talking about <quote>liberty.</quote> They object
6637 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6638 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6639 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6640 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6641 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6642 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6643 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6644 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6645 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6646 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6647 of liberty. As I argued in <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, we come from a
6648 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6649 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6650 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6651 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6652 <citetitle>On Liberty</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6653 1978), 19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6654 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons, <quote>The
6655 Right to Work,</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6656 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays</citetitle> (London:
6657 Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6658 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6659 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6660 places easier; 42 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
6661 12101 (2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6662 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6663 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6664 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6665 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (1990)</primary></indexterm>
6666 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.</primary></indexterm>
6667 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6668 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6669 </para></footnote>
6670 </para>
6671 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='endofrange'/>
6672 <section id="hollywood">
6673 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right</title>
6674 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
6675 <para>
6676 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6677 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6678 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6679 rallying makes sense.
6680 </para>
6681 <para>
6682 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6683 Internet:
6684 </para>
6685 <figure id="fig-1371">
6686 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
6687 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6688
6689 </figure>
6690 <indexterm id='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='startofrange'><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6691 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6692 <indexterm id='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='startofrange'><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6693 <para>
6694 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6695 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6696 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6697 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6698 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6699 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6700 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6701 recognize&mdash;kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6702 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6703 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6704 this form of infringement.
6705 </para>
6706 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright regulatory balance lost with</secondary></indexterm>
6707 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>regulatory balance lost in</secondary></indexterm>
6708 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6709 <indexterm><primary>MP3s</primary></indexterm>
6710 <para>
6711 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6712 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6713 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6714 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6715 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6716 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6717 </para>
6718 <indexterm startref='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='endofrange'/>
6719 <indexterm startref='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='endofrange'/>
6720 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>established industries threatened by changes in</secondary></indexterm>
6721 <para>
6722 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6723 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6724 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6725 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6726 Iraq
6727 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6728 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6729 looting that results.
6730 </para>
6731 <figure id="fig-1381">
6732 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.</title>
6733 <graphic fileref="images/1381.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6734
6735 </figure>
6736 <indexterm><primary>Commerce, U.S. Department of</primary></indexterm>
6737 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
6738 <para>
6739 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6740 warriors. Indeed, in a <quote>White Paper</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6741 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995,
6742 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6743 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6744 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should
6745 strengthen intellectual property law, (2) businesses should adopt
6746 innovative marketing techniques, (3) technologists should push to
6747 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (4) educators should
6748 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6749 </para>
6750 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='endofrange'/>
6751 <indexterm startref='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='endofrange'/>
6752 <indexterm><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6753 <indexterm><primary>steel industry</primary></indexterm>
6754 <para>
6755 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed&mdash;if it was to
6756 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6757 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6758 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6759 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6760 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6761 life. Homeowners living in a
6762
6763 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6764 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6765 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6766 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6767 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6768 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6769 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6770 </para>
6771 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='endofrange'/>
6772 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='endofrange'/>
6773 <indexterm><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
6774 <para>
6775 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6776 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6777 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6778 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6779 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6780 Brown describes it, its <quote>architecture of revenue.</quote>
6781 </para>
6782 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
6783 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
6784 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
6785 <indexterm><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
6786 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
6787 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
6788 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry</primary></indexterm>
6789 <indexterm><primary>remote channel changers</primary></indexterm>
6790 <para>
6791 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6792 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6793 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6794 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6795 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20
6796 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6797 of digital cameras.<footnote><para>
6798 <!-- f5 -->
6799 See Geoffrey Smith, <quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?</quote>
6800 BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at
6801 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #23</ulink>. For a more
6802 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6803 R. Schoenberger, <quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?</quote> Forbes.com, 6
6804 October 2003, available at
6805 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #24</ulink>.
6806 </para></footnote>
6807
6808 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6809 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6810 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6811 <emphasis>for the purpose of</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6812 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6813 weakened the <quote>stickiness</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6814 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf), and it
6815 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6816 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6817 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6818 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6819 </para>
6820 <indexterm id='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='startofrange'><primary>free market, technological changes in</primary></indexterm>
6821 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
6822 <indexterm><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
6823 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
6824 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
6825 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
6826 <indexterm><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
6827 <para>
6828 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6829 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6830 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6831 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6832 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6833 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6834 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6835 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, <quote>established companies
6836 have an interest in excluding future competitors.</quote><footnote><para>
6837 <!-- f6 -->
6838 Fred Warshofsky, <citetitle>The Patent Wars</citetitle> (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170&ndash;71.
6839 </para></footnote>
6840 And relative to a
6841 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6842 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6843 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6844 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6845 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6846 Brezhnev.
6847 </para>
6848 <para>
6849 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6850 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6851 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6852 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6853 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6854 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6855 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6856 opportunities for innovation and change.
6857 </para>
6858 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
6859 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
6860 <indexterm><primary>speech, freedom of</primary><secondary>constitutional guarantee of</secondary></indexterm>
6861 <para>
6862 In the context of laws regulating speech&mdash;which include,
6863 obviously, copyright law&mdash;that duty is even stronger. When the
6864 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6865 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6866 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6867 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6868 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6869 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: <quote>Congress
6870 shall make no law &hellip; abridging the freedom of speech.</quote> So when
6871 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would <quote>abridge</quote> the freedom
6872 of speech, it should ask&mdash; carefully&mdash;whether such
6873 regulation is justified.
6874 </para>
6875 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='endofrange'/>
6876 <indexterm startref='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='endofrange'/>
6877 <para>
6878 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6879 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6880 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6881 <quote>justified.</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6882 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6883 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6884 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6885 </para>
6886 <para>
6887 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6888 </para>
6889 <indexterm id='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='startofrange'><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann</primary></indexterm>
6890 <indexterm id='idxddt' class='startofrange'><primary>DDT</primary></indexterm>
6891 <indexterm id='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='startofrange'><primary>insecticide, environmental consequences of</primary></indexterm>
6892 <indexterm id='idxfarming' class='startofrange'><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6893 <para>
6894 In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss
6895 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6896 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the
6897 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6898 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6899 </para>
6900 <para>
6901 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6902 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6903 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6904 </para>
6905 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6906 <indexterm><primary>Silent Spring (Carson)</primary></indexterm>
6907 <indexterm id='idxenvironmentalism' class='startofrange'><primary>environmentalism</primary></indexterm>
6908 <para>
6909 But in 1962, Rachel Carson published <citetitle>Silent Spring</citetitle>, which argued that
6910 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6911 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6912 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6913 </para>
6914 <para>
6915 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6916 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6917 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6918 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6919 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6920 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6921 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6922 </para>
6923 <indexterm startref='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='endofrange'/>
6924 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James</primary></indexterm>
6925 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovative freedom balanced with fair compensation in</secondary></indexterm>
6926 <para>
6927 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6928 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an <quote>environmentalism</quote> for
6929 culture.<footnote><para>
6930 <!-- f7 -->
6931 See, for example, James Boyle, <quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6932 Environmentalism for the Net?</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal</citetitle> 47 (1997): 87.
6933 </para></footnote>
6934 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6935 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6936 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6937 <quote>for free.</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6938 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6939 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6940 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6941 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6942 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6943 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6944 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6945 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6946 </para>
6947 <indexterm startref='idxfarming' class='endofrange'/>
6948 <para>
6949 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6950 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6951 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6952 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6953 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6954 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6955 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6956 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6957 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6958 </para>
6959 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='endofrange'/>
6960 <para>
6961 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6962 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6963 be lost.
6964 </para>
6965 <indexterm startref='idxddt' class='endofrange'/>
6966 <indexterm startref='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='endofrange'/>
6967 <indexterm startref='idxenvironmentalism' class='endofrange'/>
6968 </section>
6969 <section id="beginnings">
6970 <title>Beginnings</title>
6971 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>on creative property</secondary></indexterm>
6972 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
6973 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
6974 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
6975 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
6976 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>constitutional tradition on</secondary></indexterm>
6977 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
6978 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
6979 <para>
6980 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6981 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of <quote>creative
6982 property</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6983 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6984 </para>
6985 <indexterm id='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>in constitutional Progress Clause</secondary></indexterm>
6986 <para>
6987 The power to establish <quote>creative property</quote> rights is granted to
6988 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6989 odd. Article I, section 8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that:
6990 </para>
6991 <para>
6992 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6993 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6994 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
6995
6996 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
6997 We can call this the <quote>Progress Clause,</quote> for notice what this clause
6998 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
6999 <quote>creative property rights.</quote> It says that Congress has the power
7000 <emphasis>to promote progress</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
7001 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
7002 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
7003 </para>
7004 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
7005 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
7006 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>history of American</secondary></indexterm>
7007 <para>
7008 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
7009 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="founders"/>,
7010 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
7011 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
7012 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
7013 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
7014 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
7015 copyrights extend <quote>to Authors</quote> only.
7016 </para>
7017 <indexterm><primary>Senate, U.S.</primary></indexterm>
7018 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>structural checks and balances of</secondary></indexterm>
7019 <indexterm><primary>electoral college</primary></indexterm>
7020 <para>
7021 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
7022 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
7023 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
7024 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
7025 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
7026 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
7027 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
7028 to reinforce the power of the states&mdash;including the Senate, whose
7029 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
7030 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
7031 case, a <emphasis>structure</emphasis> built checks and balances into
7032 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
7033 concentrations of power.
7034 </para>
7035 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='endofrange'/>
7036 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
7037 <para>
7038 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call <quote>copyright</quote>
7039 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
7040 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
7041 <quote>copyright</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210
7042 years since they first struck its design.
7043 </para>
7044 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='endofrange'/>
7045 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='endofrange'/>
7046 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='endofrange'/>
7047 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
7048 <para>
7049 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
7050 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
7051 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
7052 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
7053 started here:
7054 </para>
7055 <figure id="fig-1441">
7056 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.</title>
7057 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7058 </figure>
7059 <para>
7060 We will end here:
7061 </para>
7062 <figure id="fig-1442">
7063 <title><quote>Copyright</quote> today.</title>
7064 <graphic fileref="images/1442.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7065 </figure>
7066 <para>
7067 Let me explain how.
7068 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
7069 </para>
7070 </section>
7071 <section id="lawduration">
7072 <title>Law: Duration</title>
7073 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
7074 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7075 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7076 <indexterm><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>common law protections of</secondary></indexterm>
7077 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>balance of U.S. content in</secondary></indexterm>
7078 <para>
7079 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
7080 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
7081 the English had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws
7082 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
7083 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
7084 authorship.<footnote>
7085 <para>
7086 <!-- f8 -->
7087 William W. Crosskey, <citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
7088 the United States</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press, 1953), vol. 1,
7089 485&ndash;86: <quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
7090 Law of the Land,' <emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
7091 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law</emphasis></quote>
7092 (emphasis added).
7093 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.</primary></indexterm>
7094 </para></footnote>
7095 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
7096 States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
7097 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
7098 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
7099 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
7100 domain to reprint and distribute works.
7101 </para>
7102 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
7103 <indexterm id='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>federal vs. state</secondary></indexterm>
7104 <para>
7105 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
7106 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
7107 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
7108 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
7109 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
7110 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
7111 </para>
7112 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
7113 <para>
7114 In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
7115 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
7116 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
7117 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
7118 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
7119 </para>
7120 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='endofrange'/>
7121 <para>
7122 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
7123 ten years of the Republic, only 5 percent of the works were actually
7124 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
7125 in the United States both before 1790 and from 1790 through 1800, 95
7126 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
7127 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
7128 likely within fourteen years.<footnote><para>
7129 <!-- f9 -->
7130 Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790
7131 to 1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, <citetitle>A
7132 History of Book Publishing in the United States</citetitle>, vol. 1, <citetitle>The Creation
7133 of an Industry, 1630&ndash;1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000
7134 imprints recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
7135 1790 act; William J. Maher, <citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
7136 and the Copyright Law of 1790 in Historical Context</citetitle>, 7&ndash;10 (2002),
7137 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
7138 #25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
7139 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
7140 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
7141 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
7142 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
7143 Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124. </para></footnote>
7144 </para>
7145 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact' class='endofrange'/>
7146 <indexterm startref='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='endofrange'/>
7147 <para>
7148 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
7149 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
7150 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
7151 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
7152 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
7153 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
7154 copyright, either.
7155 </para>
7156 <para>
7157 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
7158 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
7159 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
7160 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
7161 domain.<footnote><para>
7162 <!-- f10 -->
7163 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
7164 instance, of the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were
7165 renewed in 1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
7166 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, <quote>Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright,</quote>
7167 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright</citetitle>, vol. 1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
7168 1963), 618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
7169 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote>
7170 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 471, 498&ndash;501, and
7171 accompanying figures. </para></footnote>
7172 </para>
7173 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='endofrange'/>
7174 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
7175 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
7176 <para>
7177 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
7178 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
7179 out of print after one year.<footnote><para>
7180 <!-- f11 -->
7181 See Ringer, ch. 9, n. 2. </para></footnote> When that happens, the
7182 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
7183 no longer <emphasis>effectively</emphasis> controlled by
7184 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
7185 is to sell the books as used books; that use&mdash;because it does not
7186 involve publication&mdash;is effectively free.
7187 </para>
7188 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7189 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
7190 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
7191 <para>
7192 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
7193 changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28
7194 years to a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
7195 from 14 years to 28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
7196 the term increased once again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal
7197 term of 14 years to 28 years, setting a maximum term of 56 years.
7198 </para>
7199 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7200 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
7201 <para>
7202 Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
7203 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
7204 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
7205 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
7206 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
7207 In 1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
7208 And in 1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
7209 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
7210 </para>
7211 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
7212 <para>
7213 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
7214 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
7215 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
7216 years, or 70 percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years
7217
7218 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
7219 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
7220 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
7221 of the expiration of a copyright term.
7222 </para>
7223 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='endofrange'/>
7224 <para>
7225 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
7226 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
7227 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
7228 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
7229 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
7230 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
7231 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
7232 value.
7233 </para>
7234 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7235 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>of natural authors vs. corporations</secondary></indexterm>
7236 <indexterm><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>copyright terms for</secondary></indexterm>
7237 <para>
7238 The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For
7239 all works created after 1978, there was only one copyright term&mdash;the
7240 maximum term. For <quote>natural</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
7241 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992,
7242 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
7243 before 1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
7244 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
7245 was ninety-five years.
7246 </para>
7247 <para>
7248 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
7249 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
7250 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
7251 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
7252 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
7253 that terms be <quote>limited,</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
7254 them.
7255 </para>
7256 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='endofrange'/>
7257 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
7258 <para>
7259 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
7260 dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to
7261 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
7262 in 1973 was just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
7263 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
7264 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95
7265 years.<footnote><para>
7266 <!-- f12 -->
7267 These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the
7268 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
7269 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
7270 Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote> loc. cit.
7271 </para></footnote>
7272 </para>
7273 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='endofrange'/>
7274 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='endofrange'/>
7275 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='endofrange'/>
7276 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='endofrange'/>
7277 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='endofrange'/>
7278 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
7279 </section>
7280 <section id="lawscope">
7281 <title>Law: Scope</title>
7282 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7283 <para>
7284 The <quote>scope</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
7285 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
7286 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
7287 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
7288 </para>
7289 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7290 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>historical shift in copyright coverage of</secondary></indexterm>
7291 <para>
7292 In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only <quote>maps,
7293 charts, and books.</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
7294 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
7295 the author the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> copyrighted works. That
7296 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
7297 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
7298 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
7299 did not extend to what lawyers call <quote>derivative works.</quote> It would not,
7300 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
7301 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
7302 (such as a drama based on a published book).
7303 </para>
7304 <para>
7305 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
7306 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
7307 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
7308 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
7309 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
7310 work not only the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> the work, but also the
7311 exclusive right of control over any <quote>copies</quote> of that work. And most
7312 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
7313 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
7314 <quote>derivative work</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
7315 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
7316 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
7317 on the initial creative work.
7318 </para>
7319 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>marking of</secondary></indexterm>
7320 <indexterm id='idxformalities' class='startofrange'><primary>formalities</primary></indexterm>
7321 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>registration requirement of</secondary></indexterm>
7322 <para>
7323 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
7324 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
7325 complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition
7326 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
7327 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
7328 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
7329 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
7330 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
7331 famous &copy; or the word <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>. And for most
7332 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
7333 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
7334 secured.
7335 </para>
7336 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='endofrange'/>
7337 <para>
7338 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
7339 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
7340 in the first ten years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible
7341 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
7342 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
7343 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
7344 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
7345 copyrighted&mdash;that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
7346 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
7347 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
7348 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
7349 original author.
7350 </para>
7351 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>European</secondary></indexterm>
7352 <para>
7353 All of these <quote>formalities</quote> were abolished in the American system when
7354 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
7355 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
7356 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
7357 a &copy;; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
7358 copy available for others to copy.
7359 </para>
7360 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='endofrange'/>
7361 <indexterm startref='idxformalities' class='endofrange'/>
7362 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='endofrange'/>
7363 <para>
7364 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
7365 differences.
7366 </para>
7367 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact2' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7368 <para>
7369 If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who
7370 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
7371 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
7372 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
7373 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were
7374 174 publishers in the United States.<footnote><para>
7375 <!-- f13 -->
7376 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, <quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
7377 Creation of American Literature,</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
7378 International Law and Politics</citetitle> 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
7379 Federal Copyright Records, 1790&ndash;1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987).
7380
7381 </para></footnote>
7382 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
7383 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
7384 the United States&mdash;publishers.
7385 </para>
7386 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7387 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7388 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7389 <para>
7390 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
7391 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
7392 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
7393 was totally unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and made
7394 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
7395 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
7396 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
7397 were restrained.
7398 </para>
7399 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact2' class='endofrange'/>
7400 <para>
7401 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
7402 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
7403 every note to your spouse, every doodle, <emphasis>every</emphasis>
7404 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form&mdash;all of this is
7405 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
7406 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
7407 protect it.
7408 </para>
7409 <para>
7410 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
7411 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
7412 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
7413 </para>
7414 <para>
7415 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
7416 control
7417 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
7418 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of <quote>derivative
7419 rights.</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
7420 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
7421 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
7422 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
7423 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
7424 exclusive
7425 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
7426 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
7427 </para>
7428 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7429 <para>
7430 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
7431 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
7432 expansion
7433 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
7434 copyright.
7435 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
7436 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
7437 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
7438 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
7439 </para>
7440 <para>
7441 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
7442 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
7443 within a free culture&mdash;at least, it's astonishing when you
7444 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
7445 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
7446 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
7447 <emphasis>that</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
7448 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
7449 all&mdash;they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
7450 not protect derivative rights at all.<footnote><para>
7451 <!-- f14 -->
7452 Jonathan Zittrain, <quote>The Copyright Cage,</quote> <citetitle>Legal
7453 Affairs</citetitle>, July/August 2003, available at
7454 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #26</ulink>.
7455 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
7456 </para></footnote>
7457 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
7458 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7459 the wrong of direct piracy.
7460 </para>
7461 <para>
7462 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7463 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7464 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7465 of my book.<footnote><para>
7466 <!-- f15 -->
7467 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7468 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7469 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere <quote>copies</quote> and
7470 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld, <quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7471 Copyright's Constitutionality,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7472 Journal</citetitle> 112 (2002): 1&ndash;60 (see especially
7473 pp. 53&ndash;59).
7474 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb</primary></indexterm>
7475 </para></footnote>
7476 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7477 </para>
7478 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7479 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
7480 <indexterm><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
7481 <para>
7482 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7483 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7484 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7485 called <quote>Mickey Mouse,</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7486 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7487 created?
7488 </para>
7489 <para>
7490 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7491 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7492 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7493 the rights originally granted.
7494 </para>
7495 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7496 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='endofrange'/>
7497 </section>
7498 <section id="lawreach">
7499 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach</title>
7500 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7501 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7502 <para>
7503 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7504 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7505 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7506 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.<footnote><para>
7507 <!-- f16 -->
7508 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7509 certainly regulates more than <quote>copies</quote>&mdash;a public performance of a
7510 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7511 per se doesn't make a copy; 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7512 106(4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a <quote>copy</quote>; 17
7513 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section 112(a). But the presumption under the
7514 existing law (which regulates <quote>copies;</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7515 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7516 </para></footnote>
7517 </para>
7518 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
7519 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>other property rights vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7520 <para>
7521 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7522 <quote>Copies.</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7523 <emphasis>copy</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7524 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that <quote>creative
7525 property</quote> deserves the <quote>same rights</quote> as all other property, it is the
7526 <emphasis>obvious</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7527 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7528 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7529 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7530 copies should <emphasis>not</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7531 law. More precisely, they should not <emphasis>always</emphasis> be
7532 the trigger for copyright law.
7533 </para>
7534 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='endofrange'/>
7535 <para>
7536 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7537 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7538 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7539 the law of copyright automatically applies,<footnote><para>
7540 <!-- f17 -->
7541 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7542 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7543 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7544 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7545 technology.
7546 </para></footnote>
7547 because it is clear that the
7548 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7549 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7550 </para>
7551 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7552 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='endofrange'/>
7553 <para>
7554 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7555 empty circle.
7556 </para>
7557 <figure id="fig-1521">
7558 <title>All potential uses of a book.</title>
7559 <graphic fileref="images/1521.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7560 </figure>
7561 <indexterm id='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>three types of uses of</secondary></indexterm>
7562 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7563 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright applicability altered by technology of</secondary></indexterm>
7564 <indexterm id='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='startofrange'><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright intent altered by</secondary></indexterm>
7565 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7566 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7567 <para>
7568 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7569 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7570 all its potential <emphasis>uses</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7571 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7572 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7573 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7574 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7575 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7576 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7577 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7578 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7579 acts do not make a copy.
7580 </para>
7581 <figure id="fig-1531">
7582 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.</title>
7583 <graphic fileref="images/1531.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7584 </figure>
7585 <para>
7586 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7587 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7588 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7589 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7590 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see
7591 diagram in <xref linkend="fig-1541"/>).
7592 </para>
7593 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7594 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7595 <indexterm id='idxfairuse' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary></indexterm>
7596 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7597 <para>
7598 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7599 that remain unregulated because the law considers these <quote>fair uses.</quote>
7600 </para>
7601 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7602 <figure id="fig-1541">
7603 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.</title>
7604 <graphic fileref="images/1541.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7605 </figure>
7606 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
7607 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
7608 <para>
7609 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7610 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7611 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7612 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7613 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7614 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7615 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such <quote>fair uses</quote>
7616 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7617 </para>
7618 <figure id="fig-1542">
7619 <title>Unregulated copying considered <quote>fair uses.</quote></title>
7620 <graphic fileref="images/1542.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7621 </figure>
7622 <para> </para>
7623 <figure id="fig-1551">
7624 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.</title>
7625 <graphic fileref="images/1551.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7626 </figure>
7627 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7628 <para>
7629 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7630 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7631 sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that
7632 are nonetheless deemed <quote>fair</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7633 </para>
7634 <indexterm startref='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='endofrange'/>
7635 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7636 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
7637 <indexterm><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7638 <para>
7639 Enter the Internet&mdash;a distributed, digital network where every use
7640 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.<footnote><para>
7641 <!-- f18 -->
7642 I don't mean <quote>nature</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7643 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7644 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7645 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7646 of copies remain.
7647 </para></footnote>
7648 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7649 digital network, the scope of category 1 changes dramatically. Uses
7650 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7651 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7652 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7653 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7654 a copy&mdash;category 1 gets sucked into category 2. And those who
7655 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7656 exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7657 shift.
7658 </para>
7659 <indexterm startref='idxfairuse' class='endofrange'/>
7660 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='endofrange'/>
7661 <para>
7662 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7663 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7664 be no plausible <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>-related argument that
7665 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7666 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7667 the book once, ten times, or every
7668 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7669 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7670 use&mdash;reading&mdash; could be regulated by copyright law because
7671 none of those uses produced a copy.
7672 </para>
7673 <indexterm id='idxebooks' class='startofrange'><primary>e-books</primary></indexterm>
7674 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>technological developments and</secondary></indexterm>
7675 <para>
7676 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7677 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7678 only once or only once a month, then <emphasis>copyright
7679 law</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7680 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7681 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7682 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7683 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7684 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7685 copyright owner's wish.
7686 </para>
7687 <para>
7688 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7689 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7690 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7691 points also become clear:
7692 </para>
7693 <para>
7694 First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7695 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7696 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7697 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7698 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7699 part of free culture before the Internet.
7700 </para>
7701 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7702 <para>
7703 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7704 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7705 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7706 <emphasis>any</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7707 using a machine. <quote>Copy and paste</quote> and <quote>cut and paste</quote> become
7708 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7709 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7710 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7711 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7712 creative work.
7713 </para>
7714 <indexterm id='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7715 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7716 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>fair use vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7717 <para>
7718 Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary
7719
7720 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7721 burden on category 3 (<quote>fair use</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7722 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7723 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7724 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7725 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7726 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7727 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7728 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7729 regulated.
7730 </para>
7731 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='endofrange'/>
7732 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='endofrange'/>
7733 <indexterm startref='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='endofrange'/>
7734 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='endofrange'/>
7735 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='endofrange'/>
7736 <para>
7737 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7738 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7739 depend upon fair use&mdash;never even addressing the earlier question
7740 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7741 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7742 <emphasis>unregulated</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7743 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7744 enough.
7745 </para>
7746 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='endofrange'/>
7747 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'/>
7748 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson2' class='endofrange'/>
7749 <indexterm startref='idxebooks' class='endofrange'/>
7750 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='endofrange'/>
7751 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='endofrange'/>
7752 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='endofrange'/>
7753 <indexterm id='idxvideopipeline' class='startofrange'><primary>Video Pipeline</primary></indexterm>
7754 <indexterm id='idxadvertising' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
7755 <indexterm id='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='startofrange'><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>trailer advertisements of</secondary></indexterm>
7756 <para>
7757 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7758 in the business of making <quote>trailer</quote> advertisements for movies available
7759 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7760 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7761 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7762 </para>
7763 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7764 <para>
7765 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it began
7766 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7767 previews. The idea was to expand their <quote>selling by sampling</quote>
7768 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7769 <quote>browsing.</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7770 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7771 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7772 </para>
7773 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
7774 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7775 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7776 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
7777 <para>
7778 In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7779 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7780 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7781 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7782 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7783 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter&mdash;he had built a
7784 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7785 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7786 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7787 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7788 <quote>fair use</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7789 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7790 their rights.
7791 </para>
7792 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising' class='endofrange'/>
7793 <indexterm startref='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='endofrange'/>
7794 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7795 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>willful infringement findings in</secondary></indexterm>
7796 <indexterm><primary>willful infringement</primary></indexterm>
7797 <para>
7798 Disney countersued&mdash;for $100 million in damages. Those damages
7799 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had <quote>willfully
7800 infringed</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7801 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7802 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7803 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7804 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7805 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $100 million.
7806 </para>
7807 <para>
7808 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7809 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7810 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7811 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7812 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7813 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7814 Disney's permission.
7815 </para>
7816 <indexterm><primary>first-sale doctrine</primary></indexterm>
7817 <para>
7818 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7819 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7820 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7821 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7822 was in the marketplace, the <quote>first-sale doctrine</quote> would free the
7823 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7824 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7825 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7826 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7827 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7828 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7829 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7830 </para>
7831 <indexterm startref='idxvideopipeline' class='endofrange'/>
7832 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc2' class='endofrange'/>
7833 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='endofrange'/>
7834 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='endofrange'/>
7835 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='endofrange'/>
7836 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='endofrange'/>
7837 <indexterm><primary>Barnes &amp; Noble</primary></indexterm>
7838 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7839 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
7840 <para>
7841 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7842 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7843 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes &amp; Noble has the
7844 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7845 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7846 abuse. If Barnes &amp; Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7847 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7848 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7849 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7850 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7851 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7852 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7853 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7854 happening are quite slight.
7855 </para>
7856 <para>
7857 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7858 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7859 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7860 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7861 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7862 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7863 </para>
7864 </section>
7865 <section id="lawforce">
7866 <title>Architecture and Law: Force</title>
7867 <para>
7868 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7869 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7870 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7871 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7872 </para>
7873 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>technology as automatic enforcer of</secondary></indexterm>
7874 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright enforcement controlled by</secondary></indexterm>
7875 <para>
7876 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7877 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7878 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7879 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7880 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7881 your freedom.
7882 </para>
7883 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca</primary></indexterm>
7884 <indexterm id='idxmarxbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7885 <indexterm id='idxwarnerbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7886 <para>
7887 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7888 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7889 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7890 <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7891 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7892 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7893 plan.<footnote><para>
7894 <!-- f19 -->
7895 See David Lange, <quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7896 Contemporary Problems</citetitle> 44 (1981): 172&ndash;73.
7897 </para></footnote>
7898 </para>
7899 <para>
7900 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7901 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers <quote>were brothers long before
7902 you were.</quote><footnote><para>
7903 <!-- f20 -->
7904 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
7905 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and
7906 Copywrongs</citetitle>, 1&ndash;3.
7907 </para></footnote>
7908 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7909 <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7910 trying to control <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>, then the Marx
7911 Brothers would insist on control over <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>.
7912 </para>
7913 <para>
7914 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7915 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7916 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7917 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7918 </para>
7919 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7920 <para>
7921 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7922 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7923 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7924 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7925 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7926 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7927 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7928 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7929 </para>
7930 <indexterm startref='idxwarnerbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7931 <indexterm startref='idxmarxbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7932
7933 <indexterm id='idxadobeebookreader' class='startofrange'><primary>Adobe eBook Reader</primary></indexterm>
7934 <para>
7935 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7936 </para>
7937 <para>
7938 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7939 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7940 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7941 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7942 technology.
7943 </para>
7944 <para>
7945 In <xref linkend="fig-example-adobe-ebook-reader"/> is a picture of an old version of my
7946 Adobe eBook Reader.
7947 </para>
7948 <para>
7949 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7950 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7951 public domain: <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, for example, is in
7952 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7953 public domain: My own book <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
7954 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7955 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7956 copy of
7957 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7958 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7959 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
7960 </para>
7961 <figure id="fig-example-adobe-ebook-reader">
7962 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader</title>
7963 <graphic fileref="images/example-adobe-ebook-reader.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7964 </figure>
7965 <para>
7966 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7967 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7968 </para>
7969 <figure id="fig-1612">
7970 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.</title>
7971 <graphic fileref="images/1612.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7972 </figure>
7973 <para>
7974 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7975 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
7976 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
7977 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
7978 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
7979 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>
7980 read aloud through the computer.
7981 </para>
7982 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle</primary></indexterm>
7983 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics</citetitle>, (Aristotle)</primary></indexterm>
7984 <para>
7985 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7986 translation): Aristotle's <citetitle>Politics</citetitle>.
7987 </para>
7988 <figure id="fig-1621">
7989 <title>E-book of Aristotle's <quote>Politics</quote></title>
7990 <graphic fileref="images/1621.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7991 </figure>
7992 <para>
7993 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7994 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
7995 the book.
7996 </para>
7997 <figure id="fig-1622">
7998 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle's <quote>Politics</quote>.</title>
7999 <graphic fileref="images/1622.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8000 </figure>
8001 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
8002 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
8003 <para>
8004 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
8005 original e-book version of my last book, <citetitle>The Future of
8006 Ideas</citetitle>:
8007 </para>
8008 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
8009 <figure id="fig-1631">
8010 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>The Future of Ideas</quote>.</title>
8011 <graphic fileref="images/1631.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8012 </figure>
8013 <para>
8014 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
8015 </para>
8016 <para>
8017 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
8018 <quote>permissions</quote>&mdash; as if the publisher has the power to control how
8019 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
8020 certainly does have the power&mdash;up to the limits of the copyright
8021 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
8022 power.<footnote><para>
8023 <!-- f21 -->
8024 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
8025 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
8026 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
8027 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
8028 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
8029 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
8030 subsequently acquired the book.
8031 </para></footnote>
8032 When my e-book of <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> says I have the
8033 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
8034 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
8035 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
8036 control that the law would enable.
8037 </para>
8038 <para>
8039 The control comes instead from the code&mdash;from the technology
8040 within which the e-book <quote>lives.</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
8041 permissions, they are not the sort of <quote>permissions</quote> that most of us
8042 deal with. When a teenager gets <quote>permission</quote> to stay out till
8043 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
8044 till 2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
8045 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
8046 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
8047 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
8048 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
8049 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
8050 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
8051 aloud&mdash;it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
8052 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
8053 won't read aloud.
8054 </para>
8055 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8056 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8057 <para>
8058 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
8059 These are <emphasis>controls</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
8060 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
8061 you tried to type <quote>Warner Brothers,</quote> erased <quote>Brothers</quote> from the
8062 sentence.
8063 </para>
8064 <para>
8065 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
8066 <emphasis>law</emphasis> as copyright <emphasis>code</emphasis>. The
8067 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
8068 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
8069 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
8070 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
8071 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
8072 </para>
8073 <para>
8074 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
8075 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
8076 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
8077 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
8078 to defeat these protections as well?
8079 </para>
8080 <para>
8081 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
8082 eBook Reader.
8083 </para>
8084 <indexterm id='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='startofrange'><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)</primary></indexterm>
8085 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>e-book restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
8086 <para>
8087 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
8088 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
8089 on the Adobe site was a copy of <citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
8090 Wonderland</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
8091 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
8092 following report:
8093 </para>
8094 <figure id="fig-1641">
8095 <title>List of the permissions for <quote>Alice's Adventures in
8096 Wonderland</quote>.</title>
8097 <graphic fileref="images/1641.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8098 </figure>
8099 <!-- PAGE BREAK 164-->
8100 <para>
8101 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
8102 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
8103 <quote>permissions</quote> indicated, not allowed to <quote>read aloud</quote>!
8104 </para>
8105 <para>
8106 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
8107 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
8108 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
8109 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
8110 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
8111 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
8112 </para>
8113 <para>
8114 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
8115 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
8116 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
8117 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
8118 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
8119 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
8120 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
8121 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
8122 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
8123 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
8124 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
8125 </para>
8126 <indexterm startref='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='endofrange'/>
8127 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='endofrange'/>
8128 <para>
8129 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
8130 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
8131 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
8132 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
8133 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
8134 often crazy.
8135 </para>
8136 <indexterm startref='idxadobeebookreader' class='endofrange'/>
8137 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet2' class='endofrange'/>
8138 <para>
8139 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
8140 story of mine that makes the same point.
8141 </para>
8142 <indexterm id='idxaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8143 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog1' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8144 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8145 <para>
8146 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named <quote>Aibo.</quote> The Aibo
8147 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
8148 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
8149 </para>
8150 <para>
8151 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
8152 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
8153 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
8154 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
8155 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
8156 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
8157 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
8158 </para>
8159 <para>
8160 <quote>Teach</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
8161 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
8162 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
8163 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
8164 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
8165 their computer <quote>dog</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
8166 </para>
8167 <indexterm><primary>hacks</primary></indexterm>
8168 <para>
8169 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
8170 <citetitle>hack</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
8171 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
8172 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
8173 them, <citetitle>hack</citetitle> is a much more positive
8174 term. <citetitle>Hack</citetitle> just means code that enables the
8175 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
8176 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
8177 old computer doesn't run, or <quote>drive,</quote> the printer. If you discovered
8178 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
8179 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
8180 you just bought.
8181 </para>
8182 <para>
8183 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
8184 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
8185 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
8186 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
8187 ethically.
8188 </para>
8189 <para>
8190 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
8191 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
8192 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
8193 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
8194 than Sony had built.
8195 </para>
8196 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8197 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog1' class='endofrange'/>
8198 <indexterm startref='idxaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8199 <para>
8200 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
8201 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
8202 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
8203 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
8204 the
8205
8206 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
8207 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
8208 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
8209 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
8210 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
8211 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
8212 thought, <emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
8213 a robot dog to dance?</emphasis>
8214 </para>
8215 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>government case against</secondary></indexterm>
8216 <para>
8217 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show&mdash;
8218 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
8219 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
8220 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
8221 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
8222 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
8223 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
8224 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
8225 into being silent about something he knew very well.
8226 </para>
8227 <para>
8228 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.<footnote><para>
8229 <!-- f22 -->
8230 See Pamela Samuelson, <quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,</quote>
8231 <citetitle>Science</citetitle> 293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, <quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
8232 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect</citetitle>,
8233 January 2002; <quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
8234 DMCA,</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter</citetitle>, 11 December 2001; Bill
8235 Holland, <quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,</quote> <citetitle>Billboard</citetitle>,
8236 May 2001; Janelle Brown, <quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?</quote> Salon.com,
8237 April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, <quote>Frequently Asked
8238 Questions about <citetitle>Felten and USENIX</citetitle> v. <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> Legal Case,</quote> available at
8239 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #27</ulink>.
8240 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
8241 </para></footnote>
8242 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
8243 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
8244 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
8245 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
8246 </para>
8247 <para>
8248 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
8249 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
8250 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
8251 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
8252 <quote>this music cannot be copied,</quote> and have a computer respect that
8253 command. The technology was to be part of a <quote>trusted system</quote> of
8254 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
8255 Internet much more.
8256 </para>
8257 <para>
8258 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
8259 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
8260 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
8261 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
8262 </para>
8263 <para>
8264 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
8265 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
8266 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
8267 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
8268 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
8269 </para>
8270 <para>
8271 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
8272 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
8273 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
8274 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
8275 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
8276 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
8277 </para>
8278 <para>
8279 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
8280 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
8281 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
8282 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
8283 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
8284 constituted, succeed.
8285 </para>
8286 <indexterm id='idxaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8287 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog2' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8288 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8289 <para>
8290 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
8291 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
8292 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
8293 wrote:
8294 </para>
8295 <blockquote>
8296 <para>
8297 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
8298 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
8299 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
8300 </para>
8301 </blockquote>
8302 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8303 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog2' class='endofrange'/>
8304 <indexterm startref='idxaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8305 <para>
8306 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
8307 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
8308 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
8309 </para>
8310 <blockquote>
8311 <para>
8312 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
8313 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
8314 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
8315 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
8316 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (<quote>DMCA</quote>).
8317 </para>
8318 </blockquote>
8319 <para>
8320 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
8321 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
8322 spreading such information an offense.
8323 </para>
8324 <para>
8325 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
8326 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
8327 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
8328 These new technologies would be copyright protection
8329 technologies&mdash; technologies to control the replication and
8330 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
8331 <emphasis>code</emphasis> to modify the original
8332 <emphasis>code</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
8333 protection for copyright owners.
8334 </para>
8335 <para>
8336 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
8337 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
8338 <emphasis>legal code</emphasis> intended to buttress
8339 <emphasis>software code</emphasis> which itself was intended to
8340 support the <emphasis>legal code of copyright</emphasis>.
8341 </para>
8342 <para>
8343 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
8344 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
8345 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
8346 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
8347 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
8348 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
8349 have been a copyright violation.
8350 </para>
8351 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8352 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8353 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8354 <para>
8355 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
8356 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
8357 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
8358 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
8359 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
8360 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
8361 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
8362 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
8363 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
8364 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
8365 </para>
8366 <para>
8367 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
8368 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
8369 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
8370 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
8371 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
8372 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
8373 </para>
8374 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8375 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8376 <para>
8377 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
8378 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
8379 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
8380 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
8381 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
8382 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka <quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers</citetitle>,</quote>
8383 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
8384 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
8385 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8386 </para>
8387 <blockquote>
8388 <para>
8389 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
8390 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
8391 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
8392 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
8393 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
8394 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the <quote>Neighborhood</quote>
8395 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
8396 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
8397 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
8398 broadcasting has always been <quote>You are an important person just the way
8399 you are. You can make healthy decisions.</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
8400 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
8401 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
8402 important.<footnote><para>
8403 <!-- f23 -->
8404 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8405 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
8406 455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
8407 James Lardner, <citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
8408 the VCR</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270&ndash;71.
8409 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8410 </para></footnote>
8411 </para>
8412 </blockquote>
8413 <para>
8414 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
8415 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
8416 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
8417 the VCR responsible.
8418 </para>
8419 <para>
8420 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
8421 the DMCA.
8422 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8423 </para>
8424 <para>
8425 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
8426 </para>
8427 <para>
8428 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
8429 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
8430 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
8431 pirating of copyrighted material&mdash;a bad end. Or they can be used
8432 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
8433 would be considered fair use&mdash;a good end.
8434 </para>
8435 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'><primary>handguns</primary></indexterm>
8436 <para>
8437 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
8438 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
8439 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
8440 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
8441 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
8442 and bad uses.
8443 </para>
8444 <figure id="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig">
8445 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.</title>
8446 <graphic fileref="images/1711.png" align="center" width="70%"></graphic>
8447 </figure>
8448 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8449 <para>
8450 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
8451 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
8452 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: <emphasis>No one ever
8453 died from copyright circumvention</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
8454 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
8455 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
8456 </para>
8457 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'/>
8458 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'/>
8459 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8460 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8461 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8462 <para>
8463 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
8464 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
8465 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
8466 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
8467 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
8468 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
8469 </para>
8470 <para>
8471 This is how <emphasis>code</emphasis> becomes
8472 <emphasis>law</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
8473 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
8474 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
8475 law&mdash;increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
8476 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
8477 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
8478 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect&mdash;at
8479 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
8480 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
8481 </para>
8482 <para>
8483 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
8484 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
8485 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
8486 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
8487 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
8488 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
8489 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
8490 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
8491 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
8492 </para>
8493 <para>
8494
8495 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
8496 For example, imagine you were part of a <citetitle>Star Trek</citetitle> fan club. You
8497 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
8498 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
8499 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
8500 simply continue it.<footnote><para>
8501 <!-- f24 -->
8502 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, <quote>Legal Fictions,
8503 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
8504 Entertainment Law Journal</citetitle> 17 (1997): 651.
8505 </para></footnote>
8506 </para>
8507 <para>
8508 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
8509 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
8510 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
8511 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
8512 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
8513 </para>
8514 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
8515 <para>
8516 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
8517 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
8518 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
8519 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
8520 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
8521 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
8522 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
8523 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
8524 </para>
8525 <para>
8526 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
8527 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
8528 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
8529 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8530 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8531 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8532 </para>
8533 </section>
8534 <section id="marketconcentration">
8535 <title>Market: Concentration</title>
8536 <para>
8537 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically&mdash;tripled in
8538 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8539 well&mdash;from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8540 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8541 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8542 find better ways
8543 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8544 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8545 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8546 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8547 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8548 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8549 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8550 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8551 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8552 control.
8553 </para>
8554 <para>
8555 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8556 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8557 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8558 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8559 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8560 </para>
8561 <para>
8562 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8563 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8564 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8565 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8566 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8567 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8568 announced in June 2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8569 live in a world where just three companies control more than 85 percent
8570 of the media.
8571 </para>
8572 <para>
8573 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8574 nature.
8575 </para>
8576 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8577 <indexterm><primary>BMG</primary></indexterm>
8578 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
8579 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John</primary></indexterm>
8580 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8581 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8582 <para>
8583 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8584 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8585 ownership, <quote>five companies control 85 percent of our media sources.</quote><footnote><para>
8586 <!-- f25 -->
8587 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8588 Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003)
8589 (statement of Senator John McCain). </para></footnote>
8590 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8591 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 percent of the
8592 U.S. music market.<footnote><para>
8593 <!-- f26 -->
8594 Lynette Holloway, <quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8595 Slide,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 23 December 2002.
8596 </para></footnote>
8597 The <quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8598 programming to 74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.</quote><footnote><para>
8599 <!-- f27 -->
8600 Molly Ivins, <quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette</citetitle>,
8601 31 May 2003.
8602 </para></footnote>
8603 </para>
8604 <para>
8605 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8606 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8607 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8608 seventy-five stations. Today <emphasis>one</emphasis> company owns
8609 more than 1,200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8610 total number of radio owners dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most
8611 markets, the two largest broadcasters control 74 percent of that
8612 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control 90 percent of
8613 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8614 </para>
8615 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8616 <para>
8617 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8618 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8619 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8620 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8621 the United States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all
8622 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent
8623 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8624 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8625 protected&mdash; by the market.
8626 </para>
8627 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8628 <para>
8629 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8630 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8631 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8632 </para>
8633 <blockquote>
8634 <para>
8635 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8636 unmatched in its integration. They supply content&mdash;Fox movies
8637 &hellip; Fox TV shows &hellip; Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8638 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8639 advertisers&mdash;in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8640 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8641 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8642 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8643 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8644 the same function in the United States.<footnote><para>
8645 <!-- f28 -->
8646 James Fallows, <quote>The Age of Murdoch,</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly</citetitle> (September
8647 2003): 89.
8648 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8649 </para></footnote>
8650 </para>
8651 </blockquote>
8652 <para>
8653 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8654 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8655 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8656 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8657 </para>
8658 <figure id="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership">
8659 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.</title>
8660 <graphic fileref="images/pattern-modern-media-ownership.png" align="center" width="90%"></graphic>
8661 </figure>
8662 <para>
8663 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8664 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8665 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8666 distribute content?
8667 </para>
8668 <para>
8669 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8670 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8671 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8672 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8673 </para>
8674 <para>
8675 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8676 integration may matter.
8677 </para>
8678 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman</primary></indexterm>
8679 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8680 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8681 <para>
8682 In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle>. He took
8683 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8684 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8685 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8686 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8687 </para>
8688 <para>
8689 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8690 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8691 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8692 control.<footnote><para>
8693 <!-- f29 -->
8694 Leonard Hill, <quote>The Axis of Access,</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8695 Forum, <quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,</quote> St. Louis,
8696 Missouri, 3 April 2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8697 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #28</ulink>;
8698 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8699 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #29</ulink>).
8700 </para></footnote>
8701 </para>
8702 <para>
8703
8704 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8705 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8706 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8707 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8708 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992,
8709 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8710 television&mdash;75 percent of it&mdash;was <quote>independent</quote> of the
8711 networks.
8712 </para>
8713 <para>
8714 In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8715 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985,
8716 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8717 2002, only five independent television studios remained. <quote>In 1992,
8718 only 15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8719 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8720 controlled companies more than quintupled to 77 percent.</quote> <quote>In 1992, 16
8721 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8722 year there was one.</quote><footnote><para>
8723 <!-- f30 -->
8724 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8725 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st
8726 sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8727 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8728 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8729 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8730 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February
8731 2003.
8732 </para></footnote>
8733 In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8734 that ran it. <quote>In the ten-year period between 1992 and 2002, the number
8735 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8736 increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8737 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8738 63%.</quote><footnote><para>
8739 <!-- f31 -->
8740 Ibid.
8741 </para></footnote>
8742 </para>
8743 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8744 <para>
8745 Today, another Norman Lear with another <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle> would
8746 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8747 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8748 owned by the network.
8749 </para>
8750 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry</primary></indexterm>
8751 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill</primary></indexterm>
8752 <para>
8753 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8754 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8755 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8756 </para>
8757 <blockquote>
8758 <para>
8759 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8760 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8761 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8762 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8763 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8764 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8765 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8766 handful.<footnote><para>
8767 <!-- f32 -->
8768 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers</citetitle>, Bill
8769 Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at
8770 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #31</ulink>.
8771 </para></footnote>
8772 </para>
8773 </blockquote>
8774 <para>
8775 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8776 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8777 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8778 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8779 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8780 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8781 question without risk of consequence&mdash;not necessarily banishment
8782 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8783 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8784 democracy.
8785 </para>
8786 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.</primary></indexterm>
8787 <para>
8788 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8789 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the <quote>Innovator's
8790 Dilemma</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8791 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8792 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8793 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.<footnote><para>
8794 <!-- f33 -->
8795 Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8796 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle>
8797 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press, 1997). Christensen
8798 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8799 Kim B. Clark, <quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8800 Concepts in Technological Evolution,</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy</citetitle> 14 (1985):
8801 235&ndash;51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8802 Kaplan, <citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8803 Underperform the Market&mdash;and How to Successfully Transform Them</citetitle>
8804 (New York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001). </para></footnote>
8805
8806 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8807 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8808 sprinting.
8809 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
8810 </para>
8811 <para>
8812 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8813 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8814 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8815 measure.
8816 </para>
8817 <para>
8818 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8819 suggest the concern.
8820 </para>
8821 <para>
8822 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8823 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8824 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8825 </para>
8826 <para>
8827 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8828 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8829 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8830
8831 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8832 wrecked by drugs&mdash;though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8833 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8834 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8835 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8836 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8837 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8838 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8839 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8840 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8841 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8842 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8843 outweigh these costs.
8844 </para>
8845 <para>
8846 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8847 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8848 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8849 these issues.
8850 </para>
8851 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8852 <indexterm id='idxcommercials' class='startofrange'><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
8853 <indexterm id='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='startofrange'><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
8854 <indexterm><primary>Nick and Norm anti-drug campaign</primary></indexterm>
8855 <para>
8856 Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8857 a media campaign as part of the <quote>war on drugs.</quote> The campaign produced
8858 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8859 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8860 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8861 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8862 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8863 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8864 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8865 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8866 </para>
8867 <para>
8868 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8869 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8870 </para>
8871 <para>
8872 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8873 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8874 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8875 war. Can you do it?
8876 </para>
8877 <para>
8878 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8879 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8880 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8881 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8882 message will be heard then?
8883 </para>
8884 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
8885 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
8886 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on television advertising bans</secondary></indexterm>
8887 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>controversy avoided by</secondary></indexterm>
8888 <para>
8889 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8890 <quote>controversial</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8891 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8892 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8893 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8894 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8895 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8896 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8897 rights of the stations to be this biased.<footnote><para>
8898 <!-- f34 -->
8899 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8900 <indexterm><primary>Comcast</primary></indexterm>
8901 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project</primary></indexterm>
8902 <indexterm><primary>NBC</primary></indexterm>
8903 <indexterm><primary>WJOA</primary></indexterm>
8904 <indexterm><primary>WRC</primary></indexterm>
8905 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8906 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads
8907 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8908 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as <quote>against
8909 [their] policy.</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8910 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8911 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8912 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8913 Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8914 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, <quote>On the
8915 Issue of an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV
8916 Networks,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 13 March
8917 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time there is very little
8918 that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to even the playing
8919 field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, <quote>Ad Hoc Access:
8920 The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8921 Radio,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review</citetitle> 6
8922 (1988): 449&ndash;79, and for a more recent summary of the stance of
8923 the FCC and the courts, see <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors
8924 Association</citetitle> v. <citetitle>FCC</citetitle>, 184 F. 3d 872
8925 (D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8926 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8927 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8928 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, <quote>Antidiesel Group
8929 Fuming After Muni Rejects Ad,</quote> SFGate.com, 16 June 2003,
8930 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
8931 #32</ulink>. The ground was that the criticism was <quote>too
8932 controversial.</quote>
8933 </para></footnote>
8934 </para>
8935 <indexterm startref='idxcommercials' class='endofrange'/>
8936 <indexterm startref='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='endofrange'/>
8937 <para>
8938 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well&mdash;if we lived
8939 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8940 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8941 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8942 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8943 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8944 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8945 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8946 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8947 </para>
8948 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'/>
8949 </section>
8950 <section id="together">
8951 <title>Together</title>
8952 <para>
8953 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8954 copyright warriors that the government should <quote>protect my property.</quote>
8955 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8956 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8957 </para>
8958 <para>
8959 But when we see how dramatically this <quote>property</quote> has changed&mdash;
8960 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8961 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8962 cultivate our culture is dramatically different&mdash;the claim begins
8963 to seem
8964
8965 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8966 less innocent and obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to
8967 supplement the law's control, and (2) the power of concentrated
8968 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8969 the massively expanded <quote>property</quote> rights granted by copyright
8970 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8971 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8972 be redefined.
8973 </para>
8974 <para>
8975 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8976 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8977 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8978 our culture today.
8979 </para>
8980 <para>
8981 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8982 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8983 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8984 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8985 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8986 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8987 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8988 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8989 traditionally defined copyright's regulation&mdash;a weakening of that
8990 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
8991 </para>
8992 <para>
8993 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
8994 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
8995 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
8996 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
8997 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
8998 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
8999 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
9000 future. And these changes have to be <emphasis>reductions</emphasis>
9001 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
9002 in control that technology and the market enable.
9003 </para>
9004 <para>
9005 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
9006 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
9007 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
9008 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
9009 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
9010 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
9011 more of the development of our culture than now</emphasis>.
9012 </para>
9013 <para>
9014 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
9015 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
9016 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
9017 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
9018 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
9019 were independent of the networks. <emphasis>Never</emphasis> has
9020 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
9021 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
9022 regulation&mdash;a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
9023 energy of a nation at the founding&mdash;is now a massive regulation
9024 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
9025 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
9026 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
9027 known.<footnote><para>
9028 <!-- f35 -->
9029 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
9030 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his <quote>four surrenders</quote> of
9031 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan, 159&ndash;60.
9032 </para></footnote>
9033 </para>
9034 <para>
9035 <emphasis role='strong'>This has been</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
9036 point can now be briefly stated.
9037 </para>
9038 <para>
9039 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
9040 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
9041 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
9042 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
9043 that copyright law has undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this:
9044 </para>
9045
9046 <informaltable id="t2">
9047 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9048 <thead>
9049 <row>
9050 <entry></entry>
9051 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9052 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9053 </row>
9054 </thead>
9055 <tbody>
9056 <row>
9057 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9058 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9059 <entry>Free</entry>
9060 </row>
9061 <row>
9062 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9063 <entry>Free</entry>
9064 <entry>Free</entry>
9065 </row>
9066 </tbody>
9067 </tgroup>
9068 </informaltable>
9069
9070 <para>
9071 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
9072 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
9073 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
9074
9075 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
9076 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
9077 noncommercial work was also free.
9078 </para>
9079 <para>
9080 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
9081 </para>
9082
9083 <informaltable id="t3">
9084 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9085 <thead>
9086 <row>
9087 <entry></entry>
9088 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9089 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9090 </row>
9091 </thead>
9092 <tbody>
9093 <row>
9094 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9095 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9096 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9097 </row>
9098 <row>
9099 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9100 <entry>Free</entry>
9101 <entry>Free</entry>
9102 </row>
9103 </tbody>
9104 </tgroup>
9105 </informaltable>
9106
9107 <para>
9108 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law&mdash;if
9109 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
9110 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
9111 transformation were still essentially free.
9112 </para>
9113 <para>
9114 In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
9115 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
9116 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
9117 expanded. Thus by 1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
9118 we could say the law began to look like this:
9119 </para>
9120
9121 <informaltable id="t4">
9122 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9123 <thead>
9124 <row>
9125 <entry></entry>
9126 <entry>COPY</entry>
9127 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9128 </row>
9129 </thead>
9130 <tbody>
9131 <row>
9132 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9133 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9134 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9135 </row>
9136 <row>
9137 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9138 <entry>&copy; / Free</entry>
9139 <entry>Free</entry>
9140 </row>
9141 </tbody>
9142 </tgroup>
9143 </informaltable>
9144
9145 <para>
9146 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
9147 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
9148 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
9149 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
9150 that the law now looks like this:
9151 </para>
9152
9153 <informaltable id="t5">
9154 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9155 <thead>
9156 <row>
9157 <entry></entry>
9158 <entry>COPY</entry>
9159 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9160 </row>
9161 </thead>
9162 <tbody>
9163 <row>
9164 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9165 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9166 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9167 </row>
9168 <row>
9169 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9170 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9171 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9172 </row>
9173 </tbody>
9174 </tgroup>
9175 </informaltable>
9176
9177 <para>
9178 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
9179 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
9180 creativity&mdash;
9181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
9182 commercial or not, transformative or not&mdash;with the same rules
9183 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
9184 </para>
9185 <para>
9186 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
9187 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
9188 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
9189 these domains actually does any good.
9190 </para>
9191 <para>
9192 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
9193 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
9194 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
9195 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
9196 reasons sketched especially in chapters
9197 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/> and
9198 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>, one
9199 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
9200 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
9201 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
9202 </para>
9203 <para>
9204 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
9205 course copyright is a kind of <quote>property,</quote> and of course, as with any
9206 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
9207 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
9208 property rights<footnote><para>
9209 <!-- f36 -->
9210 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement</primary></indexterm>
9211 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
9212 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
9213 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, <quote>The
9214 Disintegration of Property,</quote> in <citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property</citetitle>, J. Roland
9215 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
9216 Press, 1980).
9217 </para></footnote>)
9218 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
9219 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
9220 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
9221 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the <quote>copyright</quote>
9222 did not control <emphasis>at all</emphasis> the freedom of others to
9223 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
9224 free, and for almost 180 years our country consistently protected a
9225 vibrant and rich free culture.
9226 </para>
9227 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
9228 <para>
9229 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
9230 limits on the scope of the interests protected by <quote>property.</quote> The very
9231 birth of <quote>copyright</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
9232 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
9233 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9234 linkend="founders"/>). The tradition of <quote>fair use</quote> is
9235 animated by a similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the
9236 costs of exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the
9237 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9238 linkend="recorders"/>). Adding
9239 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
9240 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
9241 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter <xref
9242 xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>). And
9243 granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect, claims of
9244 property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing the soul
9245 of a culture (chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9246 linkend="collectors"/>). Free cultures, like free markets, are built
9247 with property. But the nature of the property that builds a free
9248 culture is very different from the extremist vision that dominates the
9249 debate today.
9250 </para>
9251 <para>
9252 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
9253 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
9254 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
9255 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
9256 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
9257 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
9258 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
9259 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
9260 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
9261 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
9262 lawyer.
9263 </para>
9264 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
9265 </section>
9266 </chapter>
9267 </part>
9268 <part id="c-puzzles">
9269 <title>PUZZLES</title>
9270
9271 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
9272 <chapter label="11" id="chimera">
9273 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera</title>
9274 <indexterm id='idxchimera' class='startofrange'><primary>chimeras</primary></indexterm>
9275 <indexterm id='idxwells' class='startofrange'><primary>Wells, H. G.</primary></indexterm>
9276 <indexterm id='idxtcotb' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The</quote> (Wells)</primary></indexterm>
9277
9278 <para>
9279 <emphasis role='strong'>In a well-known</emphasis> short story by
9280 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
9281 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
9282 Andes.<footnote><para>
9283 <!-- f1. -->
9284 H. G. Wells, <quote>The Country of the Blind</quote> (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells,
9285 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
9286 York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
9287 </para></footnote>
9288 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with <quote>sweet water, pasture,
9289 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
9290 that bore an excellent fruit.</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
9291 takes this as an opportunity. <quote>In the Country of the Blind,</quote> he tells
9292 himself, <quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.</quote> So he resolves to live with the
9293 villagers to explore life as a king.
9294 </para>
9295 <para>
9296 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
9297 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
9298 <quote>blind.</quote> They don't have the word <citetitle>blind</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
9299 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
9300 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
9301 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. <quote>`You
9302 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
9303 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
9304 alone!'</quote>
9305 </para>
9306 <para>
9307 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
9308 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
9309 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
9310 affection, a young woman who to him seems <quote>the most beautiful thing in
9311 the whole of creation,</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
9312 description of what he sees <quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
9313 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
9314 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
9315 indulgence.</quote> <quote>She did not believe,</quote> Wells tells us, and <quote>she could
9316 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.</quote>
9317 </para>
9318 <para>
9319 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his <quote>mysteriously delighted</quote>
9320 love, the father and the village object. <quote>You see, my dear,</quote> her
9321 father instructs, <quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
9322 anything right.</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
9323 </para>
9324 <para>
9325 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. <quote>His brain
9326 is affected,</quote> he reports.
9327 </para>
9328 <para>
9329 <quote>What affects it?</quote> the father asks. <quote>Those queer things that are
9330 called the eyes &hellip; are diseased &hellip; in such a way as to affect
9331 his brain.</quote>
9332 </para>
9333 <para>
9334 The doctor continues: <quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
9335 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
9336 simple and easy surgical operation&mdash;namely, to remove these
9337 irritant bodies [the eyes].</quote>
9338 </para>
9339 <para>
9340 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
9341 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
9342 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
9343 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
9344 </para>
9345 <para>
9346 <emphasis role='strong'>It sometimes</emphasis> happens that the eggs
9347 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
9348 <quote>chimera.</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
9349 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
9350 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
9351
9352 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
9353 plot for murder mysteries. <quote>But the DNA shows with 100 percent
9354 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
9355 scene. &hellip;</quote>
9356 </para>
9357 <indexterm startref='idxtcotb' class='endofrange'/>
9358 <indexterm startref='idxwells' class="endofrange"/>
9359 <para>
9360 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
9361 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
9362 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
9363 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
9364 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
9365 understanding of a <quote>person</quote> should reflect this reality.
9366 </para>
9367 <para>
9368 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
9369 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
9370 unfairly enough, <quote>the copyright wars,</quote> the more I think we're dealing
9371 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question <quote>What is
9372 p2p file sharing?</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
9373 wrong. One side says, <quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
9374 others' records&mdash;the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
9375 thirty years without any question at all.</quote> That's true, at least in
9376 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
9377 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
9378 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
9379 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
9380 </para>
9381 <para>
9382 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
9383 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
9384 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
9385 <quote>friends</quote> beyond recognition to say <quote>my ten thousand best friends</quote> can
9386 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
9387 what <quote>we have always been allowed to do,</quote> we have not always been
9388 allowed to share music with <quote>our ten thousand best friends.</quote>
9389 </para>
9390 <para>
9391 Likewise, when the other side says, <quote>File sharing is just like walking
9392 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
9393 with it,</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
9394 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
9395 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
9396 from Tower.
9397 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9398 </para>
9399 <para>
9400
9401 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
9402 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
9403 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
9404 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
9405 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
9406 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
9407 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
9408 $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
9409 CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.)
9410 </para>
9411 <para>
9412 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
9413 that it is both&mdash;both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
9414 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
9415 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
9416 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
9417 </para>
9418 <para>
9419 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
9420 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
9421 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
9422 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
9423 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
9424 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
9425 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
9426 implemented.<footnote><para>
9427 <!-- f2. -->
9428 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9429 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
9430 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
9431 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003,
9432 available at
9433 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9434 #33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
9435 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
9436 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
9437 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, <quote>House Bill Aims to Up
9438 Stakes on Piracy,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 17 July 2003, available at
9439 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #34</ulink>. Civil
9440 penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied song. For a recent
9441 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
9442 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 songs
9443 through a family computer, see <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
9444 re. Verizon Internet Services)</citetitle>, 240 F. Supp. 2d 24
9445 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $90
9446 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
9447 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
9448 $12,000 to $17,500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
9449 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $98
9450 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
9451 Elizabeth Young, <quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,</quote> redandblack.com,
9452 August 2003, available at
9453 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #35</ulink>. For an
9454 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
9455 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
9456 identities, see James Collins, <quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
9457 Name Students,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 8 August 2003, D3, available at
9458 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #36</ulink>.
9459 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
9460 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
9461 </para></footnote>
9462
9463 </para>
9464 <indexterm startref='idxchimera' class='endofrange'/>
9465 <para>
9466 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
9467 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
9468 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
9469 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
9470 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
9471 </para>
9472 <para>
9473 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
9474 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
9475 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
9476 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
9477 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
9478 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe <emphasis>either</emphasis> extreme
9479 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
9480 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
9481 </para>
9482 <para>
9483
9484 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
9485 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
9486 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
9487 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
9488 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
9489 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
9490 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
9491 </para>
9492 <para>
9493 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to <quote>steal</quote> music. My
9494 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
9495 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
9496 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
9497 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
9498 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
9499 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
9500 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
9501 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
9502 protection for copyrighted material,
9503 </para>
9504 <blockquote>
9505 <para>
9506 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
9507 material, and we want to protect those rights.
9508 </para>
9509 <para>
9510 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
9511 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
9512 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
9513 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
9514 produce a totally different industry model.
9515 </para>
9516 <para>
9517 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
9518 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
9519 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
9520 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
9521 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
9522 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
9523 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
9524 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
9525 interests.<footnote><para>
9526 <!-- f3. -->
9527 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
9528 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
9529 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
9530 House Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement of Peter
9531 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
9532 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
9533 Congressional Testimony File. </para></footnote>
9534 </para>
9535 </blockquote>
9536 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
9537 <para>
9538 In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
9539 one of <quote>the major labels.</quote> Its position on these matters has now
9540 changed.
9541 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9542 </para>
9543 <para>
9544 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
9545 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9546 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9547 </para>
9548
9549 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9550 </chapter>
9551 <chapter label="12" id="harms">
9552 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms</title>
9553 <para>
9554 <emphasis role='strong'>To fight</emphasis> <quote>piracy,</quote> to
9555 protect <quote>property,</quote> the content industry has launched a
9556 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9557 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9558 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9559 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9560 </para>
9561 <para>
9562 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9563 particular, the consequences for <quote>free culture.</quote> But my aim now is to
9564 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9565 justified?
9566 </para>
9567 <para>
9568 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9569 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9570 power of the property called <quote>intellectual property</quote> is at its greatest in
9571 our history.
9572 </para>
9573 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
9574 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
9575 <para>
9576 Yet <quote>common sense</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9577 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9578 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9579 rejection of <quote>piracy</quote> still has play.
9580 </para>
9581 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9582 <para>
9583 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9584 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9585 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9586 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9587 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9588 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9589 </para>
9590 <section id="constrain">
9591 <title>Constraining Creators</title>
9592 <para>
9593 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9594 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9595 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9596 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9597 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9598 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9599 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9600 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9601 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9602 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9603 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9604 weave together a string&mdash;a mash-up&mdash; of songs from your
9605 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9606 </para>
9607 <para>
9608 This digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> is in part an extension of the
9609 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9610 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9611 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9612 of digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9613 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9614 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9615 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9616 the culture all around.
9617 </para>
9618 <para>
9619 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9620 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9621
9622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9623
9624 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9625 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9626 storytelling extended across the globe.
9627 </para>
9628 <para>
9629 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9630 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9631 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9632 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9633 that catalog cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9634 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9635 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9636 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9637 work is presumptively illegal.
9638 </para>
9639 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom</primary></indexterm>
9640 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9641 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9642 <indexterm><primary>doctors malpractice claims against</primary></indexterm>
9643 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
9644 <para>
9645 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9646 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9647 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9648 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9649 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9650 by the RIAA (Jesse Jordan of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9651 labelnumber" linkend="catalogs"/> was just one) were threatened with a
9652 $98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted songs
9653 to be copied. Yet World-Com&mdash;which defrauded investors of $11
9654 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization of
9655 over $200 billion&mdash;received a fine of a mere $750
9656 million.<footnote><para>
9657 <!-- f1. -->
9658 See Lynne W. Jeter, <citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom</citetitle>
9659 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley &amp; Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of
9660 the settlement, see MCI press release, <quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9661 Approval for SEC Settlement</quote> (7 July 2003), available at
9662 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #37</ulink>.
9663 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom</primary></indexterm>
9664 </para></footnote>
9665 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9666 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9667 no more than $250,000 in damages for pain and
9668 suffering.<footnote>
9669 <para>
9670 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9671 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For
9672 an overview, see Tanya Albert, <quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9673 Say Tort Reformers,</quote> amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at
9674 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #38</ulink>,
9675 and <quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,</quote> CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003,
9676 available at
9677 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9678 recent months.
9679 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.</primary></indexterm>
9680 </para></footnote>
9681 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9682 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9683 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9684 </para>
9685 <indexterm><primary>art, underground</primary></indexterm>
9686 <para>
9687 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9688 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9689 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9690 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9691 Disneys <quote>pirates.</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9692 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9693 designed to
9694
9695 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9696 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9697 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9698 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9699 we will begin to see a world of underground art&mdash;not because the
9700 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9701 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9702 fraught. Already, exhibits of <quote>illegal art</quote> tour the United
9703 States.<footnote><para>
9704 <!-- f3. -->
9705
9706 See Danit Lidor, <quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,</quote> <citetitle>Wired</citetitle>, 7 July
9707 2003, available at
9708 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9709 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #41</ulink>.
9710 </para></footnote>
9711 In what does their <quote>illegality</quote> consist?
9712 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9713 critical or reflective.
9714 </para>
9715 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9716 <para>
9717 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9718 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9719 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. But an
9720 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9721 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9722 discovered in 2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9723 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9724 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9725 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9726 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9727 </para>
9728 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
9729 <para>
9730 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9731 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9732 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9733 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9734 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9735 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9736 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9737 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9738 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9739 </para>
9740 <para>
9741 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9742 described in chapter
9743 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/>, in
9744 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9745 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9746 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9747 use.
9748 </para>
9749 <para>
9750
9751 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9752 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9753 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9754 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad&mdash;in
9755 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9756 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9757 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9758 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9759 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9760 </para>
9761 <para>
9762 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9763 <quote>breathing room</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9764 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9765 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9766 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9767 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9768 journalists&mdash; these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9769 these rules have little relationship to the <quote>law</quote> with which judges
9770 comfort themselves.
9771 </para>
9772 <para>
9773 For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful
9774 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9775 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9776 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9777 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak&mdash;in that
9778 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9779 <quote>copyright</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9780 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9781 culture that is free.
9782 </para>
9783 <para>
9784 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9785 </para>
9786 <blockquote>
9787 <para>
9788 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9789 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9790 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9791 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made &hellip; you're not
9792 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9793 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9794 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, <quote>This has been
9795 cleared.</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9796 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9797 </para>
9798 </blockquote>
9799 </section>
9800 <section id="innovators">
9801 <title>Constraining Innovators</title>
9802 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovation hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
9803 <indexterm id='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>innovation</primary><secondary>industry establishment opposed to</secondary></indexterm>
9804 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
9805 <para>
9806 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9807 story&mdash;creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9808 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9809 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9810 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9811 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9812 </para>
9813 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints2' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9814 <para>
9815 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9816 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9817 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9818 one at that, <xref xrefstyle="select: pagenumber"
9819 linkend="innovators"/> pages into a book like this), then you
9820 can see this other aspect by substituting <quote>free market</quote>
9821 every place I've spoken of <quote>free culture.</quote> The point is
9822 the same, even if the interests affecting culture are more
9823 fundamental.
9824 </para>
9825 <para>
9826 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9827 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9828 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary&mdash;at
9829 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9830 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9831 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9832 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9833 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9834 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9835 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9836 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9837 </para>
9838 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints2' class='endofrange'/>
9839 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9840 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
9841 <para>
9842 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9843 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9844 strategy that I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9845 labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9846 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9847 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9848 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9849 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9850 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9851 lesson. That lesson&mdash;what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9852 <quote>nuclear pall</quote> that has fallen over the Valley&mdash;has been learned.
9853 </para>
9854 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
9855 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
9856 <para>
9857 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9858 I told in <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9859 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9860 </para>
9861 <indexterm id='idxmpcom' class='startofrange'><primary>MP3.com</primary></indexterm>
9862 <indexterm id='idxmympcom' class='startofrange'><primary>my.mp3.com</primary></indexterm>
9863 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael</primary></indexterm>
9864 <para>
9865 In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9866 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9867 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9868 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9869 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9870 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9871 </para>
9872 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9873 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>preference data on</secondary></indexterm>
9874 <para>
9875 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9876 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9877 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9878 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9879 Raitt. And so on.
9880 </para>
9881 <para>
9882 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9883 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9884 preference data. In January 2000, the company launched a service
9885 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9886 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9887 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9888 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9889 wherever you were&mdash;at work or at home&mdash;you could get access
9890 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9891 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9892 </para>
9893 <para>
9894 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9895 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9896
9897 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9898 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9899 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9900 the kind of content the users liked.
9901 </para>
9902 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'/>
9903 <para>
9904 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000
9905 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9906 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9907 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9908 therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9909 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9910 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9911 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was 50,000
9912 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers something
9913 they had already bought.
9914 </para>
9915 <indexterm id='idxvivendiuniversal' class='startofrange'><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9916 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
9917 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9918 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9919 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
9920 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
9921 <indexterm><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>outsize penalties of</secondary></indexterm>
9922 <para>
9923 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9924 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9925 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9926 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9927 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9928 MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9929 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $54 million. Vivendi
9930 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9931 </para>
9932 <para>
9933 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9934 </para>
9935 <para>
9936 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9937 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9938 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9939 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9940 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9941 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9942 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9943 demanded.
9944 </para>
9945 <indexterm startref='idxvivendiuniversal' class='endofrange'/>
9946 <para>
9947 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9948 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9949 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9950 clients in this
9951 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9952 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9953 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9954 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9955 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9956 </para>
9957 <indexterm startref='idxmpcom' class='endofrange'/>
9958 <indexterm startref='idxmympcom' class='endofrange'/>
9959 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='endofrange'/>
9960 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9961 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
9962 <indexterm id='idxbmw' class='startofrange'><primary>BMW</primary></indexterm>
9963 <indexterm id='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='startofrange'><primary>cars, MP3 sound systems in</primary></indexterm>
9964 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
9965 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John</primary></indexterm>
9966 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9967 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad</primary></indexterm>
9968 <indexterm><primary>MP3 players</primary></indexterm>
9969 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>venture capital for</secondary></indexterm>
9970 <indexterm id='idxneedlemanrafe' class='startofrange'><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
9971 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
9972 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
9973 <para>
9974 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003,
9975 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9976 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9977 its development, its cofounder (John Hummer), and general partner
9978 (Hank Barry).<footnote><para>
9979 <!-- f4. -->
9980 See Joseph Menn, <quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9981 Times</citetitle>, 23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9982 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, <quote>The Music
9983 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,</quote> Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available
9984 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #42</ulink>.
9985 See also Jon Healey, <quote>Online Music Services Besieged,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9986 Times</citetitle>, 28 May 2001.
9987 </para></footnote>
9988 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
9989 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
9990 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
9991 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
9992 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
9993 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
9994 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
9995 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
9996 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
9997 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
9998 <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
9999 discussion with BMW:
10000 </para>
10001 <blockquote>
10002 <para>
10003 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
10004 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
10005 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
10006 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
10007 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
10008 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
10009 United States with bona fide MP3 players. &hellip; <footnote>
10010 <para>
10011 <!-- f5. -->
10012 Rafe Needleman, <quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,</quote> <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, 16 June
10013 2003, available at
10014 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #43</ulink>. I am grateful
10015 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
10016 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
10017 </para></footnote>
10018 </para>
10019 </blockquote>
10020 <indexterm startref='idxbmw' class='endofrange'/>
10021 <indexterm startref='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='endofrange'/>
10022 <indexterm startref='idxneedlemanrafe' class='endofrange'/>
10023 <para>
10024 This is the world of the mafia&mdash;filled with <quote>your money or your
10025 life</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
10026 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
10027 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
10028 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
10029 constantly threatened by litigation.
10030 </para>
10031 <para>
10032
10033 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
10034 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
10035 enterprises. The point is the definition of <quote>illegal.</quote> The law is a
10036 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
10037 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
10038 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
10039 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
10040 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
10041 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
10042 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
10043 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
10044 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
10045 much less creativity.
10046 </para>
10047 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
10048 <para>
10049 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
10050 use. Whatever the <quote>real</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
10051 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
10052 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
10053 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
10054 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
10055 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
10056 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
10057 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
10058 produce an overregulated-regulated market.
10059 </para>
10060 <para>
10061 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
10062 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
10063 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
10064 culture&mdash;a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
10065 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
10066 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
10067 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
10068 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
10069 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
10070 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
10071 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
10072 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
10073 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
10074 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
10075 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
10076 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
10077 result.
10078 </para>
10079 <para>
10080 <emphasis role='strong'>The uncertainty</emphasis> of the law is one
10081 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
10082 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
10083 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
10084 better protects their content.
10085 </para>
10086 <para>
10087 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
10088 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
10089 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
10090 this feature is a <quote>bug.</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
10091 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
10092 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
10093 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables <quote>piracy,</quote> then,
10094 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
10095 </para>
10096 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10097 <para>
10098 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
10099 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
10100 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
10101 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.<footnote><para>
10102 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> GartnerG2 and
10103 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
10104 (2003), 33&ndash;35, available at
10105 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10106 </para></footnote>
10107 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
10108 <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
10109 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
10110 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
10111 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
10112 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
10113 copyright violators and disable their machines.<footnote><para>
10114 <!-- f7. -->
10115 GartnerG2, 26&ndash;27.
10116 </para></footnote>
10117 </para>
10118 <para>
10119 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
10120 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
10121 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
10122 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
10123 and costs on
10124 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
10125 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
10126 those requirements.
10127 </para>
10128 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
10129 <para>
10130 In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
10131 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
10132 would impose.<footnote><para>
10133 <!-- f8. -->
10134 See David McGuire, <quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,</quote> Newsbytes,
10135 February 2002 (Entertainment).
10136 </para></footnote>
10137 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
10138 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
10139 harm than good.
10140 </para>
10141 <para>
10142 <emphasis role='strong'>There is one</emphasis> more obvious way in
10143 which this war has harmed innovation&mdash;again, a story that will be
10144 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
10145 </para>
10146 <para>
10147 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
10148 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
10149 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
10150 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
10151 </para>
10152 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
10153 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
10154 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
10155 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
10156 <para>
10157 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10158 linkend="property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
10159 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
10160 Jessica Litman in her book <citetitle>Digital
10161 Copyright</citetitle>,<footnote><para>
10162 <!-- f9. -->
10163 Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (Amherst,
10164 N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 2001).
10165 <indexterm><primary>Digital Copyright (Litman)</primary></indexterm>
10166 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
10167 </para></footnote>
10168 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter
10169 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/> details,
10170 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
10171 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
10172 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
10173 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
10174 </para>
10175 <para>
10176 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
10177 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
10178 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
10179 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
10180 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
10181 </para>
10182 <indexterm id='idxinternetradioon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>radio on</secondary></indexterm>
10183 <indexterm id='idxradiooninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
10184 <para>
10185 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.<footnote><para>
10186 <!-- f10. -->
10187 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.</primary></indexterm>
10188 The only circuit court exception is found in <citetitle>Recording Industry
10189 Association of America (RIAA)</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems</citetitle>, 180 F. 3d
10190 1072 (9th Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
10191 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
10192 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
10193 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
10194 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
10195 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
10196 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Grokster, Ltd</citetitle>., 259 F. Supp. 2d
10197 1029 (C.D. Cal., 2003), where the court found the link between the
10198 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
10199 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
10200 liability.
10201 </para></footnote>
10202 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
10203 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
10204 here.<footnote><para>
10205 <!-- f11. -->
10206 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy</primary></indexterm>
10207 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
10208 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz</primary></indexterm>
10209 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10210 For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
10211 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize
10212 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
10213 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
10214 August 2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
10215 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
10216 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that
10217 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
10218 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
10219 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
10220 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, <quote>Copyright and
10221 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003, 33&ndash;34,
10222 available at
10223 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10224 </para></footnote>
10225 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
10226 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
10227 </para>
10228 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10229 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
10230 <para>
10231
10232 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
10233 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10234 linkend="pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
10235 artist doesn't get paid for that <quote>radio performance</quote> unless he or she
10236 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
10237 version of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote>&mdash;to memorialize her famous
10238 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden&mdash;
10239 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
10240 copyright owners of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> would get some money, whereas
10241 Marilyn Monroe would not.
10242 </para>
10243 <para>
10244 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
10245 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
10246 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
10247 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
10248 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
10249 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
10250 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
10251 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
10252 recording artists.
10253 </para>
10254 <para>
10255 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
10256 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
10257 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
10258 spectrum. Thus, I can <quote>tune in</quote> to an Internet radio station in
10259 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
10260 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
10261 metropolitan area.
10262 </para>
10263 <para>
10264 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
10265 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
10266 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
10267 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
10268 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
10269 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
10270 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
10271 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
10272 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
10273 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
10274 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
10275 </para>
10276 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
10277 <para>
10278
10279 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
10280 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
10281 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
10282 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
10283 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
10284 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
10285 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
10286 FM radio,
10287 </para>
10288 <blockquote>
10289 <para>
10290 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
10291 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
10292 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
10293 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
10294 than by technical restrictions. &hellip; Armstrong likened the situation
10295 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
10296 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
10297 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
10298 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
10299 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
10300 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
10301 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
10302 shackles.<footnote><para>
10303 <!-- f12. -->
10304 Lessing, 239.
10305 </para></footnote>
10306 </para>
10307 </blockquote>
10308 <para>
10309 This potential for FM radio was never realized&mdash;not
10310 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
10311 underestimated the power of <quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
10312 legislation</quote><footnote><para>
10313 <!-- f13. -->
10314 Ibid., 229.
10315 </para></footnote>
10316 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
10317 </para>
10318 <para>
10319 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
10320 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
10321 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
10322 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
10323 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
10324 radio?
10325 </para>
10326 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10327 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
10328 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on radio</secondary></indexterm>
10329 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
10330 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10331 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
10332 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>Internet radio hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
10333 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10334 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
10335 <para>
10336 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
10337 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
10338
10339 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
10340 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
10341 of Internet radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
10342 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
10343 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
10344 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
10345 of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> on the air, <emphasis>Internet radio
10346 does</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
10347 radio&mdash;the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
10348 burdens terrestrial radio.
10349 </para>
10350 <para>
10351 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
10352 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
10353 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
10354 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
10355 over $1 million a year.<footnote>
10356 <para>
10357 <!-- f14. -->
10358 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
10359 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
10360 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
10361 iLaw (Stanford), 3 July 2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
10362 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
10363 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
10364 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP
10365 DTRA 1 and 2, available at
10366 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #45</ulink>.
10367 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
10368 C. Picker, <quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
10369 Distribution,</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin</citetitle> (Summer/Fall 2002): 461: <quote>This was
10370 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
10371 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
10372 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
10373 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
10374 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.</quote>
10375 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)</primary></indexterm>
10376 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
10377 </para></footnote>
10378 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
10379 equivalent fee.
10380 </para>
10381 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='endofrange'/>
10382 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='endofrange'/>
10383 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='endofrange'/>
10384 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='endofrange'/>
10385 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='endofrange'/>
10386 <para>
10387 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
10388 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
10389 station) would have to collect the following data from <emphasis>every
10390 listening transaction</emphasis>:
10391 </para>
10392 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
10393 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
10394 <listitem><para>
10395 name of the service;
10396 </para></listitem>
10397 <listitem><para>
10398 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
10399 </para></listitem>
10400 <listitem><para>
10401 type of program (archived/looped/live);
10402 </para></listitem>
10403 <listitem><para>
10404 date of transmission;
10405 </para></listitem>
10406 <listitem><para>
10407 time of transmission;
10408 </para></listitem>
10409 <listitem><para>
10410 time zone of origination of transmission;
10411 </para></listitem>
10412 <listitem><para>
10413 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
10414 </para></listitem>
10415 <listitem><para>
10416 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
10417 </para></listitem>
10418 <listitem><para>
10419 sound recording title;
10420 </para></listitem>
10421 <listitem><para>
10422 ISRC code of the recording;
10423 </para></listitem>
10424 <listitem><para>
10425 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
10426 </para></listitem>
10427 <listitem><para>
10428 featured recording artist;
10429 </para></listitem>
10430 <listitem><para>
10431 retail album title;
10432 </para></listitem>
10433 <listitem><para>
10434 recording label;
10435 </para></listitem>
10436 <listitem><para>
10437 UPC code of the retail album;
10438 </para></listitem>
10439 <listitem><para>
10440 catalog number;
10441 </para></listitem>
10442 <listitem><para>
10443 copyright owner information;
10444 </para></listitem>
10445 <listitem><para>
10446 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
10447 </para></listitem>
10448 <listitem><para>
10449 name of the service or entity;
10450 </para></listitem>
10451 <listitem><para>
10452 channel or program;
10453 </para></listitem>
10454 <listitem><para>
10455 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
10456 </para></listitem>
10457 <listitem><para>
10458 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
10459 </para></listitem>
10460 <listitem><para>
10461 time zone where the signal was received (user);
10462 </para></listitem>
10463 <listitem><para>
10464 unique user identifier;
10465 </para></listitem>
10466 <listitem><para>
10467 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
10468 </para></listitem>
10469 </orderedlist>
10470 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
10471 <para>
10472 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
10473 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
10474 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
10475 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
10476 Internet radio has to pay a <emphasis>type of copyright fee</emphasis>
10477 that terrestrial radio does not.
10478 </para>
10479 <para>
10480 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
10481 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
10482 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
10483 </para>
10484 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
10485 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
10486 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10487 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10488 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10489 <para>
10490 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
10491 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
10492 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
10493 </para>
10494 <blockquote>
10495 <para>
10496 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
10497 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
10498 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
10499 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
10500 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
10501 webcasters asked the RIAA, &hellip; <quote>How do you come up with a
10502
10503 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
10504 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
10505 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
10506 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
10507 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
10508 business. &hellip;</quote>
10509 </para>
10510 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10511 <para>
10512 And the RIAA experts said, <quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
10513 industry with thousands of webcasters, <emphasis>we think it should be
10514 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
10515 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market</emphasis>.</quote> (Emphasis
10516 added.)
10517 </para>
10518 </blockquote>
10519 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'/>
10520 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='endofrange'/>
10521 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='endofrange'/>
10522 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='endofrange'/>
10523 <para>
10524 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
10525 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
10526 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
10527 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
10528 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
10529 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
10530 effective to prevent it.
10531 </para>
10532 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10533 <indexterm startref='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='endofrange'/>
10534 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='endofrange'/>
10535 <indexterm startref='idxinternetradioon' class='endofrange'/>
10536 <indexterm startref='idxradiooninternet' class='endofrange'/>
10537 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10538 </section>
10539 <section id="corruptingcitizens">
10540 <title>Corrupting Citizens</title>
10541 <para>
10542 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
10543 dinosaurs
10544 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
10545 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
10546 </para>
10547 <para>
10548 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
10549 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
10550 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
10551 </para>
10552 <para>
10553 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
10554 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
10555 large number of citizens. According to <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, 43 million
10556 Americans downloaded music in May 2002.<footnote><para>
10557 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, <quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,</quote> Pew
10558 Internet and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at
10559 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #46</ulink>.
10560 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that 37 million
10561 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early 2001.
10562 </para></footnote>
10563 According to the RIAA,
10564 the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
10565 set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As the
10566
10567 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
10568 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
10569 the world, but against students building search engines, and
10570 increasingly
10571 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
10572 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
10573 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
10574 extreme
10575 response by the other.
10576 </para>
10577 <para>
10578 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
10579 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
10580 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
10581 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
10582 ($15,000,000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
10583 paying all the money in the world in damages ($250,000 in legal fees)
10584 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
10585 ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
10586 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September 2003, the RIAA
10587 sued 261 individuals&mdash;including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
10588 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
10589 was.<footnote><para>
10590 <!-- f16. -->
10591 Alex Pham, <quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,</quote> <citetitle>Los
10592 Angeles Times</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, Business.
10593 </para></footnote>
10594 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
10595 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
10596 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000
10597 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
10598 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
10599 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
10600 they oppose.
10601 </para>
10602 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition</primary></indexterm>
10603 <para>
10604 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
10605 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
10606 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
10607 consumption of alcohol was 1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
10608 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just 30 percent
10609 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10610 consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition
10611 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10612 number were criminals.<footnote><para>
10613 <!-- f17. -->
10614 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, <quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10615 Prohibition,</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review</citetitle> 81, no. 2 (1991): 242.
10616 </para></footnote>
10617 We have
10618 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10619 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10620 narcotics that 7 percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.<footnote><para>
10621 <!-- f18. -->
10622 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10623 Reform Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of
10624 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10625 </para></footnote>
10626 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of
10627 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10628 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10629 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10630 cheat.<footnote><para>
10631 <!-- f19. -->
10632 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, <quote>Tax
10633 Compliance,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature</citetitle> 36 (1998): 818 (survey of
10634 compliance literature).
10635 </para></footnote>
10636 We pride ourselves on our <quote>free society,</quote> but an endless array of
10637 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10638 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10639 </para>
10640 <indexterm><primary>law schools</primary></indexterm>
10641 <para>
10642 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10643 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10644 students about the importance of <quote>ethics.</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10645 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10646 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10647 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10648 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10649 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10650 teach them how to behave ethically&mdash;how to say no to bribes, or
10651 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10652 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10653 Americans&mdash;more significantly in some parts of America than in
10654 others, but still, everywhere in America today&mdash;can't live their
10655 lives both normally and legally, since <quote>normally</quote> entails a certain
10656 degree of illegality.
10657 </para>
10658 <para>
10659 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10660 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10661 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10662 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10663 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10664 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10665 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10666 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10667 to consider the alternative.
10668 </para>
10669 <para>
10670
10671 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10672 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10673 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10674 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10675 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10676 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10677 </para>
10678 <para>
10679 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10680 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10681 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10682 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10683 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10684 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10685 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10686 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10687 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10688 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10689 introduced this different idea of <quote>sharing.</quote> We need to be able to
10690 call these twenty million Americans <quote>citizens,</quote> not <quote>felons.</quote>
10691 </para>
10692 <para>
10693 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10694 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10695 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10696 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10697 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10698 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10699 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10700 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10701 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10702 a nation of felons?
10703 </para>
10704 <para>
10705 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10706 </para>
10707 <para>
10708 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10709 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10710 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10711 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10712 used
10713
10714 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10715 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That <quote>use</quote> of the
10716 recordings is free.
10717 </para>
10718 <para>
10719 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10720 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10721 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am <quote>free</quote> to copy,
10722 or <quote>rip,</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10723 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that <quote>freedom</quote> was a
10724 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the <quote>Rip, Mix, Burn</quote>
10725 capacities of digital technologies.
10726 </para>
10727 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda</primary></indexterm>
10728 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>mix technology and</secondary></indexterm>
10729 <para>
10730 This <quote>use</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10731 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10732 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10733 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10734 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10735 Others&mdash;the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10736 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10737 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10738 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10739 </para>
10740 <para>
10741 This use is enabled by unprotected media&mdash;either CDs or records.
10742 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10743 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10744 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10745 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10746 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10747 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10748 on people's machines.
10749 </para>
10750 <para>
10751 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10752 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10753 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10754 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10755 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10756 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10757
10758 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10759 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10760 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10761 plastic or were part of a massively complex <quote>digital rights
10762 management</quote> system.
10763 </para>
10764 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'/>
10765 <para>
10766 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10767 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10768 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10769 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10770 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10771 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10772 freedom to move content easily?
10773 </para>
10774 <para>
10775 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10776 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10777 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10778 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10779 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10780 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10781 alternative&mdash;namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10782 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10783 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10784 </para>
10785 <para>
10786 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10787 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10788 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10789 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10790 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10791 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10792 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10793 </para>
10794 <para>
10795 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10796 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10797 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10798 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10799 </para>
10800 <para>
10801 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10802 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10803
10804 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10805
10806 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10807 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10808 </para>
10809 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
10810 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
10811 <para>
10812 <emphasis role='strong'>There's one more</emphasis> aspect to this
10813 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10814 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10815 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10816 <quote>collateral damage</quote> that <quote>arises whenever you turn
10817 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.</quote> This
10818 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10819 </para>
10820 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10821 <para>
10822 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,</quote> von Lohmann
10823 explains,
10824 </para>
10825 <blockquote>
10826 <para>
10827 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10828 evaporate to one degree or another. &hellip; If you're a copyright
10829 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10830 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10831 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10832 access? &hellip; Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, <quote>Oh, well,
10833 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.</quote> Well, what this campaign
10834 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10835 American Internet-using population into <quote>lawbreakers.</quote>
10836 </para>
10837 </blockquote>
10838 <para>
10839 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10840 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10841 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10842 </para>
10843 <para>
10844 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA
10845 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10846 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10847 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10848 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10849 an Internet user is revealed.
10850 </para>
10851 <para>
10852 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10853 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10854 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10855 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10856 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10857 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10858 the family could be liable for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10859 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10860 Jesse Jordan.<footnote><para>
10861 <!-- f20. -->
10862 See Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10863 Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,</quote>
10864 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, <quote>Worried Parents
10865 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10866 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10867 Being Sued,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson
10868 Graham, <quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 15 September
10869 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, <quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10870 Fan, Either,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 25 September 2003, C1; Margo Varadi, <quote>Is
10871 Brianna a Criminal?</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star</citetitle>, 18 September 2003, P7.
10872 </para></footnote>
10873
10874 </para>
10875 <para>
10876 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10877 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10878 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.<footnote><para>
10879 <!-- f21. -->
10880 See <quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10881 Some Methods Used,</quote> CNN.com, available at
10882 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #47</ulink>.
10883 </para></footnote>
10884 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10885 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10886 one of those MP3s will have the same <quote>fingerprint.</quote>
10887 </para>
10888 <para>
10889 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10890 friend gives a CD to your daughter&mdash;a collection of songs just
10891 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10892 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10893 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10894 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10895 network is <quote>cooperating</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10896 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10897 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10898 as a <quote>criminal.</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10899 to deploy,<footnote><para>
10900 <!-- f22. -->
10901 See Jeff Adler, <quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,</quote>
10902 <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, <quote>Four
10903 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10904 Colleges,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10905 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10906 Monitor</citetitle>, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, <quote>Music
10907 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10908 Lawsuit Possible,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 16 July 2003, 1C; Beth Cox, <quote>RIAA
10909 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,</quote> <citetitle>Internet News</citetitle>, 30 January
10910 2003, available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10911 #48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Download Warning 101: Freshman
10912 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10913 Sharing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 11 August 2003, E11; <quote>Raid, Letters
10914 Are Weapons at Universities,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 26 September 2000, 3D.
10915 </para></footnote>
10916 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10917 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10918 </para>
10919 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'/>
10920 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10921 <para>
10922 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10923 a lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10924 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10925 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10926 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10927 this <quote>contraband</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10928 college students
10929
10930 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10931 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10932 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10933 Says von Lohmann,
10934 </para>
10935 <blockquote>
10936 <para>
10937 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10938 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10939 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10940 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10941 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10942 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10943 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10944 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10945 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10946 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10947 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10948 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10949 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10950 larger number of Americans than drug use. &hellip; If forty to sixty
10951 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10952 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10953 million of them.
10954 </para>
10955 </blockquote>
10956 <para>
10957 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered <quote>criminals</quote> under
10958 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective&mdash;
10959 securing rights to authors&mdash;without these millions being
10960 considered <quote>criminals,</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10961 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10962 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10963 </para>
10964
10965 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10966 </section>
10967 </chapter>
10968 </part>
10969 <part id="c-balances">
10970 <title>BALANCES</title>
10971 <partintro>
10972
10973 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10974 <para>
10975 <emphasis role='strong'>So here's</emphasis> the picture: You're
10976 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
10977 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
10978 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
10979 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10980 </para>
10981 <para>
10982 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10983 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10984 stop&mdash;or before she understands just why she should
10985 stop&mdash;the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10986 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10987 everything around.
10988 </para>
10989 <para>
10990 <emphasis role='strong'>A war</emphasis> about copyright rages all
10991 around&mdash;and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
10992 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
10993 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
10994 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
10995 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
10996 that if let alone would burn itself out.
10997 </para>
10998 <para>
10999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
11000 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
11001 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
11002 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
11003 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
11004 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
11005 made that is happening all around.
11006 </para>
11007 <para>
11008 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
11009 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
11010 gasoline onto this fire.
11011 </para>
11012 <para>
11013 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
11014 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
11015 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
11016 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
11017 </para>
11018 <para>
11019 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
11020 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
11021 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
11022 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
11023 success will require.
11024 </para>
11025 </partintro>
11026
11027 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
11028 <chapter label="13" id="eldred">
11029 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred</title>
11030 <indexterm id='idxeldrederic' class='startofrange'><primary>Eldred, Eric</primary></indexterm>
11031 <indexterm id='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='startofrange'><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel</primary></indexterm>
11032 <para>
11033 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
11034 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
11035 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
11036 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
11037 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
11038 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
11039 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
11040 </para>
11041 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>of public-domain literature</secondary></indexterm>
11042 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>library of works derived from</secondary></indexterm>
11043 <para>
11044 It didn't work&mdash;at least for his daughters. They didn't find
11045 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
11046 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
11047 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
11048 them available for free.
11049 </para>
11050 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt5' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11051 <indexterm><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
11052 <para>
11053 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
11054 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
11055 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
11056 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
11057 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
11058 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
11059 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
11060 many others, into a form more accessible&mdash;technically
11061 accessible&mdash;today.
11062 </para>
11063 <indexterm><primary>Scarlet Letter, The (Hawthorne)</primary></indexterm>
11064 <para>
11065 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
11066 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's <citetitle>Scarlet Letter</citetitle> had passed into the
11067 public domain in 1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
11068 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
11069 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
11070 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
11071 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
11072 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (<citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle>), sometimes not
11073 (<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame</citetitle>, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>). These are all
11074 commercial publications of public domain works.
11075 </para>
11076 <indexterm startref='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='endofrange'/>
11077 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt5' class='endofrange'/>
11078 <para>
11079 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
11080 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
11081 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
11082 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
11083 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
11084 call the <quote>noncommercial publishing industry,</quote> which before the
11085 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
11086 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
11087 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
11088 generally.<footnote><para>
11089 <!-- f1. -->
11090 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
11091 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
11092 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
11093 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers&mdash;people who
11094 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
11095 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
11096 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
11097 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
11098 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
11099 Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on
11100 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
11101 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
11102 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
11103 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
11104 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
11105 protect noncommercial pornographers.</para></footnote>
11106 </para>
11107 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
11108 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11109 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
11110 <indexterm><primary>Frost, Robert</primary></indexterm>
11111 <indexterm><primary>New Hampshire (Frost)</primary></indexterm>
11112 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
11113 <indexterm id='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
11114 <para>
11115 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's
11116 collection of poems <citetitle>New Hampshire</citetitle> was slated to
11117 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
11118 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
11119 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
11120 linkend="property-i"/>, in 1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
11121 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights&mdash;this time by
11122 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
11123 than 1923 to his collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
11124 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
11125 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
11126 more than 1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
11127 </para>
11128 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='endofrange'/>
11129 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
11130 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11131 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11132 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
11133 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11134 <para>
11135
11136 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
11137 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
11138 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
11139 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
11140 <quote>copyrights should be forever.</quote><footnote><para>
11141 <!-- f2. -->
11142 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11143 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11144 The full text is: <quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
11145 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
11146 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
11147 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
11148 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
11149 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
11150 Congress,</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998).
11151 </para></footnote>
11152 </para>
11153 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
11154 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>felony punishment for infringement of</secondary></indexterm>
11155 <indexterm><primary>NET (No Electronic Theft) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11156 <indexterm><primary>No Electronic Theft (NET) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11157 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>felony punishments for</secondary></indexterm>
11158 <para>
11159 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
11160 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
11161 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
11162 second law passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
11163 of publishing would make Eldred a felon&mdash;whether or not anyone
11164 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
11165 to undertake.
11166 </para>
11167 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='endofrange'/>
11168 <indexterm id='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
11169 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
11170 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause2' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
11171 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11172 <para>
11173 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
11174 constitutional
11175 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
11176 interpretation.
11177 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
11178 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
11179 importantly
11180 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
11181 </para>
11182 <blockquote>
11183 <para>
11184 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science &hellip;
11185 by securing for limited Times to Authors &hellip; exclusive Right to
11186 their &hellip; Writings. &hellip;
11187 </para>
11188 </blockquote>
11189 <indexterm startref='idxeldrederic' class='endofrange'/>
11190 <para>
11191 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
11192 clause of Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
11193 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
11194 something&mdash;for example, to regulate <quote>commerce among the several
11195 states</quote> or <quote>declare War.</quote> But here, the <quote>something</quote> is something quite
11196 specific&mdash;to <quote>promote &hellip; Progress</quote>&mdash;through means that
11197 are also specific&mdash; by <quote>securing</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights</quote> (i.e.,
11198 copyrights) <quote>for limited Times.</quote>
11199 </para>
11200 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='endofrange'/>
11201 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause2' class='endofrange'/>
11202 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='endofrange'/>
11203 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
11204 <para>
11205 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
11206 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
11207 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
11208 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be <quote>limited</quote> will have
11209 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
11210 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
11211 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
11212 what the Constitution plainly forbids&mdash;perpetual terms <quote>on the
11213 installment plan,</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
11214 </para>
11215 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='endofrange'/>
11216 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='endofrange'/>
11217 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11218 <para>
11219 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
11220 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
11221 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
11222 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
11223 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
11224 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
11225 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
11226 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
11227 this gravy train going.
11228 </para>
11229 <para>
11230 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
11231 government. <quote>Corruption</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
11232 bribed. Rather, <quote>corruption</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
11233 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
11234 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
11235 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
11236 do&mdash;and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
11237 </para>
11238 <para>
11239 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
11240 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
11241 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
11242 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry
11243 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
11244 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
11245 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
11246 published by anyone for free.
11247 </para>
11248 <para>
11249 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from
11250 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
11251 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
11252 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
11253 report:
11254 </para>
11255 <para>
11256 <quote>Next year,</quote> the adviser announces, <quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
11257
11258 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
11259 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
11260 receiving the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of
11261 those works.</quote>
11262 </para>
11263 <para>
11264 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,</quote> she continues, <quote>that
11265 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
11266 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
11267 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.</quote>
11268 </para>
11269 <para>
11270 <quote>Hope?</quote> a fellow board member says. <quote>Can't we be doing something
11271 about it?</quote>
11272 </para>
11273 <para>
11274 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>We could contribute
11275 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
11276 they support the bill.</quote>
11277 </para>
11278 <para>
11279 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
11280 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. <quote>How much
11281 would we get if this extension were passed?</quote> you ask the adviser. <quote>How
11282 much is it worth?</quote>
11283 </para>
11284 <para>
11285 <quote>Well,</quote> the adviser says, <quote>if you're confident that you will continue
11286 to get at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
11287 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent),
11288 then this law would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate.</quote>
11289 </para>
11290 <para>
11291 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
11292 correct conclusion:
11293 </para>
11294 <para>
11295 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
11296 $1,000,000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
11297 contributions
11298 would assure that the bill was passed?</quote>
11299 </para>
11300 <para>
11301 <quote>Absolutely,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>It is worth it to you to
11302 contribute
11303 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
11304 copyrights. Which for us means over $1,000,000.</quote>
11305 </para>
11306 <para>
11307 You quickly get the point&mdash;you as the member of the board and, I
11308 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
11309 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
11310 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
11311 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
11312 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
11313 copyrights
11314 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
11315 the copyright term extended.
11316 </para>
11317 <para>
11318 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
11319 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
11320 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
11321 </para>
11322 <para>
11323 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
11324 Copyright
11325 Term Extension Act, this <quote>theory</quote> about incentives was proved
11326 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
11327 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
11328 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
11329 contributions.<footnote><para>
11330 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, <quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
11331 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years,</quote>
11332 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 17 October 1998, 22.
11333 </para></footnote>
11334 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
11335 $1.5 million lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more
11336 than $200,000 in campaign contributions.<footnote><para>
11337 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, <quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
11338 Age,</quote> available at
11339 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #49</ulink>.
11340 </para></footnote>
11341 Disney is estimated to have
11342 contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in the
11343 cycle.<footnote><para>
11344 <!-- f5. -->
11345 Alan K. Ota, <quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,</quote>
11346 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week</citetitle>, 8 August 1990, available at
11347 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #50</ulink>.
11348 </para></footnote>
11349
11350 </para>
11351 <para>
11352 <emphasis role='strong'>Constitutional law</emphasis> is not oblivious
11353 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
11354 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
11355 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
11356 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
11357 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
11358 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
11359 constitutional requirement that terms be <quote>limited.</quote> If
11360 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
11361 again.
11362 </para>
11363 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='endofrange'/>
11364 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='endofrange'/>
11365 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='endofrange'/>
11366 <para>
11367 It was also my judgment that <emphasis>this</emphasis> Supreme Court
11368 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
11369 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
11370 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
11371 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
11372 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
11373 Supreme Court's
11374
11375 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
11376 decision in 1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
11377 guns near schools.
11378 </para>
11379 <para>
11380 Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
11381 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
11382 power to regulate only <quote>commerce among the several states</quote> (aka
11383 <quote>interstate
11384 commerce</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
11385 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
11386 interstate
11387 commerce.
11388 </para>
11389 <para>
11390 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
11391 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
11392 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
11393 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
11394 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
11395 </para>
11396 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
11397 <para>
11398 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
11399 that in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The government had
11400 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
11401 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
11402 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
11403 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
11404 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
11405 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
11406 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
11407 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
11408 position to second-guess Congress.
11409 </para>
11410 <para>
11411 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,</quote>
11412 the Chief Justice wrote.<footnote><para>
11413 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995).
11414 </para></footnote>
11415 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
11416 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
11417 Congress's power. The decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
11418 later in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>.<footnote><para>
11419 <!-- f7. -->
11420 <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>, 529 U.S. 598 (2000).
11421 </para></footnote>
11422 </para>
11423 <para>
11424 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
11425 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.<footnote><para>
11426 <!-- f8. -->
11427 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
11428 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
11429 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
11430 by the government would allow the government unending power to
11431 regulate commerce&mdash;the limitation to interstate commerce
11432 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
11433 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
11434 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights&mdash;the
11435 limitation to <quote>limited times</quote> notwithstanding.
11436 </para></footnote>
11437 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
11438 yield the conclusion that Congress
11439 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
11440 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
11441 term, then there would be no <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power over
11442 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
11443 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
11444 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
11445 term of existing copyrights.
11446 </para>
11447 <para>
11448 <emphasis>If</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
11449 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> stood for
11450 politics&mdash;a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
11451 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
11452 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
11453 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
11454 demonstrating the <quote>fidelity</quote> in such an interpretation of the
11455 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
11456 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
11457 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
11458 were going to be petty politicians.
11459 </para>
11460 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
11461 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
11462 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11463 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11464 <para>
11465 <emphasis role='strong'>Now let's pause</emphasis> for a moment to
11466 make sure we understand what the argument in
11467 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
11468 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
11469 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
11470 piracy&mdash;piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
11471 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
11472 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
11473 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
11474 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
11475 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
11476 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
11477 power&mdash;expressed through the power of lobbyists' money&mdash;to
11478 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
11479 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
11480 piracy that affects us all.
11481 </para>
11482 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association</primary></indexterm>
11483 <para>
11484 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
11485
11486 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
11487 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
11488 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than <quote>legal piracy.</quote><footnote><para>
11489 <!-- f9. -->
11490 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11491 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available
11492 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #51</ulink>.
11493 </para></footnote>
11494 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
11495 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
11496 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
11497 charter.
11498 </para>
11499 <para>
11500 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
11501 copyright
11502 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
11503 influence
11504 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
11505 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
11506 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
11507 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
11508 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
11509 bought to extend them again.
11510 </para>
11511 <para>
11512 <emphasis role='strong'>It is valuable</emphasis> copyrights that are
11513 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
11514 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.</quote> These works are too valuable for
11515 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
11516 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
11517 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
11518 the 1920s and 1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
11519 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
11520 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
11521 and no longer available as a result.
11522 </para>
11523 <para>
11524 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to
11525 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
11526 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
11527 copyright holders for that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
11528 But the law and its effect were not limited to that 2 percent. The law
11529 extended the terms of copyright generally.<footnote><para>
11530 <!-- f10. --> The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
11531 Congressional
11532 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
11533 of Petitioners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 7, available at
11534 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #52</ulink>.
11535 </para></footnote>
11536
11537 </para>
11538 <para>
11539 Think practically about the consequence of this
11540 extension&mdash;practically,
11541 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
11542
11543 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
11544 work. In 1930, 10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those
11545 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
11546 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
11547 remaining
11548 9,873. What would you have to do?
11549 </para>
11550 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11551 <para>
11552 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were
11553 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
11554 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
11555 titles and authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration
11556 and renewal records for works published in 1930. That will produce a
11557 list of books still under copyright.
11558 </para>
11559 <para>
11560 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
11561 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
11562 </para>
11563 <para>
11564 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
11565 owners
11566 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
11567 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
11568 being at least a list?
11569 </para>
11570 <para>
11571 But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in
11572 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
11573 practically
11574 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
11575 thousands
11576 of such records&mdash;especially since the person who registered is
11577 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930!
11578 </para>
11579 <para>
11580 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,</quote> the
11581 apologists for the system respond. <quote>Why should there be a list of
11582 copyright owners?</quote>
11583 </para>
11584 <para>
11585 Well, actually, if you think about it, there <emphasis>are</emphasis>
11586 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
11587 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
11588 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
11589 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
11590 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
11591 what tangible property.
11592 </para>
11593 <para>
11594 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
11595 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
11596 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
11597
11598 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
11599 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
11600 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
11601 happen
11602 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
11603 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
11604 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
11605 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
11606 know quite well who owns what property.
11607 </para>
11608 <para>
11609 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
11610 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
11611 already
11612 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
11613 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
11614 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
11615 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
11616 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
11617 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
11618 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
11619 </para>
11620 <para>
11621 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
11622 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
11623 consequence
11624 for other creative works is much more dire.
11625 </para>
11626 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'><primary>Agee, Michael</primary></indexterm>
11627 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
11628 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films</primary></indexterm>
11629 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The</primary></indexterm>
11630 <para>
11631 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
11632 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
11633 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
11634 made between 1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, <citetitle>The Lucky Dog</citetitle>, is
11635 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923
11636 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
11637 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
11638 money. According to one estimate, <quote>Roach has sold about 60,000
11639 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's silent
11640 films.</quote><footnote><para>
11641 <!-- f11. -->
11642 See David G. Savage, <quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,</quote>
11643 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, <quote>Classic Movies,
11644 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
11645 Down Copyright Extension,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 9 October 2002.
11646 </para></footnote>
11647 </para>
11648 <para>
11649 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
11650 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
11651 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11652 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11653 </para>
11654 <para>
11655 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11656
11657 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11658 any continuing commercial value. The rest&mdash;to the extent it
11659 survives at all&mdash;sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11660 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11661 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11662 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11663 work available for distribution.
11664 </para>
11665 <para>
11666 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11667 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11668 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11669 it cost more than $10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11670 film in 1993, it can now cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of
11671 8 mm film.<footnote><para>
11672 <!-- f12. -->
11673 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11674 Supporting the Petitoners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11675 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01- 618), 12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11676 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11677 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, available at
11678 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #53</ulink>.
11679 </para></footnote>
11680
11681 </para>
11682 <para>
11683 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11684 important.
11685 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11686 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11687 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11688 locate the copyright owner.
11689 </para>
11690 <para>
11691 Or more accurately, <emphasis>owners</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11692 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11693 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11694 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11695 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11696 to these films is exceptionally high.
11697 </para>
11698 <para>
11699 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11700 copyright owner when she shows up?</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11701 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11702 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11703 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11704 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11705 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11706 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11707 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11708 </para>
11709 <para>
11710 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11711
11712 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11713 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11714 benefit
11715 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11716 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11717 the copyright expires.
11718 </para>
11719 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'/>
11720 <para>
11721 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11722 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11723 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11724 canisters
11725 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11726 than dust.
11727 </para>
11728 <para>
11729 <emphasis role='strong'>Of all the</emphasis> creative work produced
11730 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11731 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11732 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11733 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11734 the copyright acts as an <quote>engine of free expression.</quote>
11735 </para>
11736 <para>
11737 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11738 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11739 indicated,
11740 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11741 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11742 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11743 distributors,
11744 the commercial life ends.
11745 </para>
11746 <para>
11747 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11748 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes &amp; Noble, and
11749 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11750 between
11751 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11752 Friday
11753 night watching a 1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11754 of culture is important and valuable&mdash;for entertainment but also, and
11755 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11756 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11757 have, we need to have access to this history.
11758 </para>
11759 <para>
11760 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11761
11762 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11763 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11764 this context do no good.
11765 </para>
11766 <para>
11767 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11768 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11769 <emphasis>copyright-related use</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11770 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11771 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11772 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11773 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11774 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11775 was independent of copyright law.
11776 </para>
11777 <para>
11778 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11779 a film&mdash;the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs&mdash;were
11780 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11781 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11782 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11783 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11784 market didn't have more to offer.
11785 </para>
11786 <para>
11787 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11788 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11789 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11790 would not have interfered with anything.
11791 </para>
11792 <para>
11793 But this situation has now changed.
11794 </para>
11795 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11796 <para>
11797 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11798 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11799 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11800 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11801 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11802 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11803 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11804 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11805 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11806 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11807 </para>
11808 <para>
11809 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11810 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11811 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11812 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11813 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11814 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11815 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11816 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11817 written for a radically different context.
11818 </para>
11819 <para>
11820 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11821 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11822 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11823 <emphasis>copyright</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11824 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11825 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11826 context, copyright is serving no purpose <emphasis>at all</emphasis>
11827 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11828 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11829 </para>
11830 <para>
11831 You may well ask, <quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11832 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11833 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11834 culture widely?</quote>
11835 </para>
11836 <para>
11837 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11838 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes &amp; Noble
11839 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11840 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11841 of a library is to serve what <quote>the market</quote> would demand. But if you
11842 think the role of a library is bigger than this&mdash;if you think its
11843 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11844 particular bit of that culture or not&mdash;then we can't count on the
11845 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11846 </para>
11847 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'/>
11848 <para>
11849 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11850 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11851 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11852 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11853
11854 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11855 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11856 culture, 94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11857 1923 and 1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11858 commercial market, if access is a value, then 6 percent is a failure
11859 to provide that value.<footnote><para>
11860 <!-- f13. -->
11861 Jason Schultz, <quote>The Myth of the 1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,</quote> 20
11862 December 2002, available at
11863 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #54</ulink>.
11864 </para></footnote>
11865
11866 </para>
11867 <para>
11868 <emphasis role='strong'>In January 1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11869 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11870 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11871 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (1)
11872 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11873 <quote>limited Times</quote> requirement, and (2) that extending terms
11874 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11875 </para>
11876 <para>
11877 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11878 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11879 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11880 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11881 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11882 </para>
11883 <para>
11884 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11885 copyrights be for <quote>limited Times</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11886 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11887 <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11888 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11889 terms that are <quote>limited.</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11890 to interpret the term <quote>limited Times</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11891 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11892 power to extend existing terms.
11893 </para>
11894 <para>
11895 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11896 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11897 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11898 whole, where the court will sit <quote>en banc</quote> to hear the case.
11899 </para>
11900 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David</primary></indexterm>
11901 <para>
11902 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11903 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11904
11905 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11906 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11907 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11908 overstepped its bounds.
11909 </para>
11910 <para>
11911 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11912 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11913 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11914 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11915 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11916 </para>
11917 <para>
11918 But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11919 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11920 was set for October of 2002. The summer would be spent writing
11921 briefs and preparing for argument.
11922 </para>
11923 <para>
11924 <emphasis role='strong'>It is over</emphasis> a year later as I write
11925 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
11926 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
11927 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
11928 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
11929 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
11930 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
11931 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
11932 client, Eric Eldred.
11933 </para>
11934 <para>
11935 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11936 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11937 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11938 mistake lost it.
11939 </para>
11940 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11941 <para>
11942 <emphasis role='strong'>The mistake</emphasis> was made early, though
11943 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
11944 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
11945 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
11946 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
11947 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11948 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11949 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11950 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11951 </para>
11952 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11953 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan</primary></indexterm>
11954 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11955 <para>
11956 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11957 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11958 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11959 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11960 told me, if we could make the issue seem <quote>important</quote> to the Supreme
11961 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11962 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against <quote>the
11963 most powerful media companies in the world.</quote>
11964 </para>
11965 <para>
11966 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
11967 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
11968 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
11969 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
11970 <quote>right</quote> as in <quote>true,</quote> I thought, but it is <quote>wrong</quote> as in <quote>it just shouldn't be
11971 that way.</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
11972 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
11973 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
11974 interpretation
11975 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
11976 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
11977 unconstitutional,
11978 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
11979 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
11980 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
11981 Constitution,
11982 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
11983 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
11984 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
11985 </para>
11986 <para>
11987 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
11988 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
11989 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
11990 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
11991 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
11992 why it was unconstitutional.
11993 </para>
11994 <para>
11995 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
11996
11997 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
11998 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
11999 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
12000 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
12001 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
12002 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
12003 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
12004 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
12005 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
12006 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
12007 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
12008 <emphasis>law</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
12009 the widest range of credible critics&mdash;credible not because they
12010 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
12011 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
12012 </para>
12013 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
12014 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis</primary></indexterm>
12015 <para>
12016 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
12017 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
12018 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
12019 Congress. In November 1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
12020 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
12021 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
12022 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
12023 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
12024 to get bogged down?</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
12025 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
12026 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
12027 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
12028 </para>
12029 <para>
12030 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
12031 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
12032 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
12033 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
12034 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
12035 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
12036 </para>
12037 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12038 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
12039 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12040 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
12041 <para>
12042 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
12043 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
12044
12045 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
12046 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/Linux
12047 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
12048 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
12049 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
12050 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
12051 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
12052 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
12053 </para>
12054 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries</primary></indexterm>
12055 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union</primary></indexterm>
12056 <para>
12057 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
12058 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
12059 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
12060 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
12061 </para>
12062 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
12063 <para>
12064 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
12065 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
12066 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
12067 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
12068 clear.
12069 </para>
12070 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George</primary></indexterm>
12071 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
12072 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James</primary></indexterm>
12073 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12074 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton</primary></indexterm>
12075 <para>
12076 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
12077 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
12078 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
12079 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
12080 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
12081 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
12082 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
12083 nothing more than <quote>rent-seeking</quote>&mdash;the fancy term economists use
12084 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
12085 </para>
12086 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12087 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan</primary></indexterm>
12088 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen</primary></indexterm>
12089 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12090 <para>
12091 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
12092 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
12093 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
12094 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
12095 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
12096 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
12097 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
12098 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
12099
12100 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
12101 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
12102 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
12103 </para>
12104 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12105 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
12106 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Commerce Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
12107 <para>
12108 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
12109 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
12110 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
12111 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
12112 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
12113 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
12114 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
12115 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
12116 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
12117 confidence in our argument.
12118 </para>
12119 <para>
12120 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
12121 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these <quote>friends</quote> included
12122 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
12123 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
12124 copyright holders.
12125 </para>
12126 <para>
12127 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
12128 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either&mdash;they
12129 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
12130 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
12131 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
12132 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
12133 wanted to control.
12134 </para>
12135 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George</primary></indexterm>
12136 <indexterm><primary>Porgy and Bess</primary></indexterm>
12137 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
12138 <para>
12139 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
12140 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
12141 Dr. Seuss's work&mdash; better than allowing it to fall into the
12142 public domain&mdash;because if this creativity were in the public
12143 domain, then people could use it to <quote>glorify drugs or to create
12144 pornography.</quote><footnote><para>
12145 <!-- f14. -->
12146 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
12147 U.S. (2003) (No. 01-618), 19.
12148 </para></footnote>
12149 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
12150 <quote>protection</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
12151 to license <citetitle>Porgy and Bess</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
12152 Americans in the cast.<footnote><para>
12153 <!-- f15. -->
12154 Dinitia Smith, <quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
12155 Mouse Joins the Fray,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 28 March 1998, B7.
12156 </para></footnote>
12157 That's
12158 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
12159 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
12160 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
12161 </para>
12162 <para>
12163 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
12164 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
12165 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
12166 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
12167 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, <quote>Give us twenty years
12168 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
12169 better with them than anyone else.</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
12170 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
12171 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
12172 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
12173 </para>
12174 <para>
12175 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
12176 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
12177 copyrights&mdash;extensions that would further concentrate the market;
12178 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
12179 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
12180 </para>
12181 <para>
12182 <emphasis role='strong'>Between February</emphasis> and October, there
12183 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
12184 I set the strategy.
12185 </para>
12186 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
12187 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12188 <para>
12189 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
12190 called <quote>the Conservatives.</quote> The other we called <quote>the Rest.</quote> The
12191 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
12192 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
12193 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
12194 five who had supported the <citetitle>Lopez/Morrison</citetitle> line
12195 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
12196 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
12197 </para>
12198 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12199 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12200 <para>
12201 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
12202 Congress's power. These four&mdash;Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
12203 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer&mdash;had repeatedly argued that
12204 the Constitution
12205 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
12206 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
12207 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
12208 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
12209 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
12210 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
12211 </para>
12212 <para>
12213 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
12214 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
12215 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
12216 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
12217 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
12218 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
12219 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
12220 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
12221 sense.
12222 </para>
12223 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12224 <para>
12225 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
12226 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
12227 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
12228 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
12229 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
12230 these retrospective extensions.
12231 </para>
12232 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'/>
12233 <para>
12234 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
12235 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
12236 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
12237 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
12238 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
12239 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
12240 </para>
12241 <para>
12242 This analysis of <quote>the Rest</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
12243 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
12244 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
12245 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
12246 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation&mdash;the
12247 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
12248 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
12249 powers have limits.
12250 </para>
12251 <para>
12252 This then was the core of our strategy&mdash;a strategy for which I am
12253 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
12254 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
12255 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
12256 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
12257 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
12258 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
12259 supposed to be <quote>limited.</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
12260 reconcile <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> with
12261 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
12262 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
12263 be limited.
12264 </para>
12265 <para>
12266 <emphasis role='strong'>The argument</emphasis> on the government's
12267 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
12268 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
12269 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
12270 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
12271 that practice is unconstitutional.
12272 </para>
12273 <para>
12274 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
12275 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in 1831
12276 and in 1909. And of course, in 1962, Congress began extending
12277 existing
12278 terms regularly&mdash;eleven times in forty years.
12279 </para>
12280 <para>
12281 But this <quote>consistency</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
12282 extended
12283 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
12284 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
12285 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
12286 existing
12287 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
12288 restraint
12289 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
12290 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
12291 hesitated
12292 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
12293 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
12294 </para>
12295 <para>
12296 <emphasis role='strong'>Oral argument</emphasis> was scheduled for the
12297 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
12298 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
12299 <quote>mooted</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
12300
12301 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
12302 help in the case. Such <quote>moots</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
12303 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
12304 </para>
12305 <para>
12306 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
12307 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
12308 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
12309 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
12310 Congress
12311 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
12312 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
12313 this central idea.
12314 </para>
12315 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12316 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12317 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12318 <para>
12319 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
12320 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
12321 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
12322 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
12323 </para>
12324 <para>
12325 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
12326 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
12327 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
12328 the harm&mdash;passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
12329 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.</quote>
12330 </para>
12331 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12332 <para>
12333 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
12334 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
12335 right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
12336 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
12337 does the right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it is right. As
12338 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
12339 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
12340 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
12341 </para>
12342 <para>
12343 <emphasis role='strong'>The night before</emphasis> the argument, a
12344 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
12345 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
12346 culture. Hundreds stood in line
12347
12348 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
12349 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
12350 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
12351 </para>
12352 <para>
12353 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
12354 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
12355 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
12356 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
12357 congressmen
12358 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
12359 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
12360 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
12361 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
12362 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
12363 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
12364 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
12365 family of the Justices.
12366 </para>
12367 <para>
12368 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
12369 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
12370 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
12371 those enumerated powers had any limit.
12372 </para>
12373 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12374 <para>
12375 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
12376 The history was bothering her.
12377 </para>
12378 <blockquote>
12379 <para>
12380 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
12381 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
12382 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
12383 practice that began with the very first act.
12384 </para>
12385 </blockquote>
12386 <para>
12387 She was quite willing to concede <quote>that this flies directly in the face
12388 of what the framers had in mind.</quote> But my response again and again
12389 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
12390 </para>
12391 <blockquote>
12392 <para>
12393 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
12394 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
12395 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
12396 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
12397 is yes.
12398 </para>
12399 </blockquote>
12400 <para>
12401 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
12402 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
12403 Kennedy, who observed,
12404 </para>
12405 <blockquote>
12406 <para>
12407 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
12408 the '76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
12409 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
12410 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
12411 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
12412 </para>
12413 </blockquote>
12414 <para>
12415 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
12416 student,
12417 I answered,
12418 </para>
12419 <blockquote>
12420 <para>
12421 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
12422 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
12423 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
12424 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
12425 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
12426 </para>
12427 </blockquote>
12428 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12429 <para>
12430 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
12431 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
12432 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
12433 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
12434 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
12435 </para>
12436 <para>
12437 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
12438 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> ruling,
12439 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
12440 </para>
12441 <para>
12442 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
12443 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
12444
12445 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
12446 </para>
12447 <blockquote>
12448 <para>
12449 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
12450 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
12451 </para>
12452 <para>
12453 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
12454 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
12455 domain
12456 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
12457 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
12458 into the Copyright Clause.
12459 </para>
12460 </blockquote>
12461 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.</primary></indexterm>
12462 <para>
12463 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
12464 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
12465 asked Solicitor General Olson,
12466 </para>
12467 <blockquote>
12468 <para>
12469 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12470 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
12471 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
12472 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12473 time.
12474 </para>
12475 </blockquote>
12476 <para>
12477 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
12478 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
12479 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
12480 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
12481 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
12482 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
12483 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
12484 Patent Clause&mdash; indeed, the very first case striking a law of
12485 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
12486 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
12487 Court to my side.
12488 </para>
12489 <para>
12490 <emphasis role='strong'>As I left</emphasis> the court that day, I
12491 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
12492 hundred questions I wished I had
12493
12494 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
12495 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
12496 optimistic.
12497 </para>
12498 <para>
12499 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
12500 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
12501 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
12502 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
12503 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
12504 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
12505 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
12506 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
12507 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
12508 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
12509 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court&mdash;in particular,
12510 the Conservatives&mdash;would feel itself constrained by the rule of
12511 law that it had established elsewhere.
12512 </para>
12513 <para>
12514 <emphasis role='strong'>The morning</emphasis> of January 15, 2003, I
12515 was five minutes late to the office and missed the 7:00 A.M. call from
12516 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
12517 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
12518 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
12519 majority. There were two dissents.
12520 </para>
12521 <para>
12522 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
12523 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
12524 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
12525 </para>
12526 <para>
12527 My <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
12528 money in the world against <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. And here
12529 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
12530 reasoning.
12531 </para>
12532 <para>
12533 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
12534 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
12535 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
12536 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
12537 even appear in the Court's opinion.
12538 </para>
12539 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12540 <para>
12541
12542 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
12543 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
12544 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
12545 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
12546 </para>
12547 <para>
12548 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable&mdash;for her, and for Justice
12549 Souter. Neither believes in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
12550 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
12551 they had worked so hard to defeat.
12552 </para>
12553 <para>
12554 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
12555 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
12556 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
12557 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
12558 reconcile the two simply <emphasis>by not addressing the
12559 argument</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
12560 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
12561 followed from the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
12562 be limited, but in this context it would not.
12563 </para>
12564 <para>
12565 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
12566 they would respect? By what right did they&mdash;the silent
12567 five&mdash;get to select the part of the Constitution they would
12568 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
12569 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
12570 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
12571 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
12572 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
12573 the system we have.
12574 </para>
12575 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12576 <para>
12577 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
12578 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
12579 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
12580 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
12581 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
12582 the Court discounted the parallel&mdash;without explaining how the
12583 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
12584 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
12585 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
12586 </para>
12587 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12588 <para>
12589 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
12590 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
12591 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
12592 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
12593 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8
12594 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
12595 that the actual number was 99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
12596 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
12597 <quote>limited,</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
12598 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
12599 </para>
12600 <para>
12601 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
12602 because neither believed in the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
12603 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
12604 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
12605 Sentelle. It was <citetitle>Hamlet</citetitle> without the Prince.
12606 </para>
12607 <para>
12608 <emphasis role='strong'>Defeat brings depression</emphasis>. They say
12609 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
12610 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
12611 sorts.
12612 </para>
12613 <indexterm><primary>originalism</primary></indexterm>
12614 <para>
12615 It was first anger with the five <quote>Conservatives.</quote> It would have been
12616 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> didn't
12617 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
12618 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
12619 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
12620 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
12621 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is <quote>originalism</quote>&mdash;to
12622 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
12623 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
12624 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> and many other <quote>originalist</quote> rulings. Where was their
12625 <quote>originalism</quote> now?
12626 </para>
12627 <para>
12628 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
12629 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
12630 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
12631 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
12632
12633 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
12634 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
12635 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
12636 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
12637 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
12638 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
12639 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
12640 own principles.
12641 </para>
12642 <para>
12643 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
12644 myself.
12645 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
12646 the law as it is.
12647 </para>
12648 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12649 <para>
12650 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
12651 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
12652 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
12653 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
12654 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
12655 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12656 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12657 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12658 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12659 </para>
12660 <para>
12661 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12662 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12663 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12664 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12665 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12666 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12667 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12668 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12669 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12670 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12671 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12672 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12673 effort to persuade; but I
12674 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12675 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12676 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12677 should decide the issue.
12678 </para>
12679 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12680 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12681 <para>
12682 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12683 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12684 Kathleen Sullivan?
12685 </para>
12686 <para>
12687 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12688 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12689 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12690 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12691 </para>
12692 <para>
12693 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12694 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12695 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12696 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12697 have persuaded.
12698 </para>
12699 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12700 <para>
12701 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12702 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12703 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12704 case was a mistake. <quote>The Court is not ready,</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12705 issue should not be raised until it is.
12706 </para>
12707 <para>
12708 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12709 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12710 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12711 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12712 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12713 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12714 this case&mdash;a decision I had made four years before&mdash;was wrong.
12715 </para>
12716 <para>
12717 <emphasis role='strong'>While the reaction</emphasis> to the Sonny
12718 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12719 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12720 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12721 that battle over ideas. Where
12722
12723 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12724 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12725 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12726 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12727 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12728 harmful law. <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12729 </para>
12730 <blockquote>
12731 <para>
12732 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12733 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12734 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12735 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12736 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12737 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12738 </para>
12739 </blockquote>
12740 <para>
12741 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12742 hilarious images&mdash;of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12743 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced in
12744 <xref linkend="fig-18"/>. The <quote>powerful and wealthy</quote> line is a bit
12745 unfair. But the punch in the face felt exactly like that.
12746 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12747 </para>
12748 <figure id="fig-18">
12749 <title>Tom the Dancing Bug cartoon</title>
12750 <graphic fileref="images/tom-the-dancing-bug.png" align="center" width="95%"></graphic>
12751 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12752 </figure>
12753 <para>
12754 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12755 quote from <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>. That <quote>grand experiment</quote> we call the
12756 <quote>public domain</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think, <quote>Honey,
12757 I shrunk the Constitution.</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12758 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12759 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12760 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12761 </para>
12762 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12763 </chapter>
12764 <chapter label="14" id="eldred-ii">
12765 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II</title>
12766 <para>
12767 <emphasis role='strong'>The day</emphasis>
12768 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12769 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12770 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was denied&mdash;meaning the case was
12771 really finally over&mdash;fate would have it that I was giving a
12772 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12773 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12774 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12775 wrote an op-ed piece.
12776 </para>
12777 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12778 <para>
12779 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12780 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12781 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12782 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12783 Justice Kennedy: <quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12784 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12785 that.</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12786 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12787 </para>
12788 <para>
12789 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12790 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12791 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12792 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12793 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12794 the work passed into the public domain.
12795 </para>
12796 <para>
12797 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12798 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12799 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12800 </para>
12801 <para>
12802 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12803 is either the <quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act</quote> or the <quote>Copyright
12804 Term Deregulation Act.</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12805 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12806 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12807 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $1. But for
12808 everything else, let the content go.
12809 </para>
12810 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12811 <para>
12812 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12813 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12814 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12815 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12816 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12817 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12818 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12819 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12820 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12821 the stupid harm of the present system.
12822 </para>
12823 <para>
12824 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12825 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12826 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12827 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12828 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12829 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12830 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12831 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12832 where copyright owners could be identified.
12833 </para>
12834 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12835 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12836 <para>
12837 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12838 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
12839 linkend="property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12840 removed in 1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12841 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.<footnote><para>
12842 <!-- f1. -->
12843 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law</primary></indexterm>
12844 Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12845 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12846 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12847 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act,
12848 every text of the Convention has provided that <quote>the enjoyment and the
12849 exercise</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention <quote>shall not be subject
12850 to any formality.</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12851 embodied in Article 5(2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12852 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12853 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12854 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12855 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12856 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12857 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12858 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12859 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>International
12860 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12861 Press, 2001), 153&ndash;54. </para></footnote>
12862 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a <quote>natural right.</quote> Natural
12863 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12864 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12865 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12866 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12867 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12868 </para>
12869 <para>
12870 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12871 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12872 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12873 <quote>Walt Disney creativity</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12874 know what's protected and what's not.
12875 </para>
12876 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12877 <para>
12878 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12879 Berlin in 1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12880 Convention in 1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12881 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12882 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12883 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12884 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an <citetitle>i</citetitle> or cross a
12885 <citetitle>t</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12886 </para>
12887 <para>
12888 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12889 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12890 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12891 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12892 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12893 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12894 </para>
12895 <para>
12896 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12897 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12898 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12899 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12900 burden
12901 imposed upon creators.
12902 </para>
12903 <para>
12904 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was
12905 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12906
12907 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12908 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12909 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12910 the government. He has a property right over the table <quote>naturally,</quote>
12911 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12912 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12913 table.
12914 </para>
12915 <para>
12916 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12917 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12918 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12919 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12920 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12921 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12922 spread.
12923 </para>
12924 <para>
12925 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12926 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12927 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12928 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12929 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12930 important reason to secure registration&mdash;both because it makes
12931 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12932 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12933 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12934 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12935 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12936 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12937 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12938 system of protection for property generally.
12939 </para>
12940 <para>
12941 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12942 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12943 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12944 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12945 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12946 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12947 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12948 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12949
12950 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12951 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12952 <emphasis>lawyer</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12953 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
12954 </para>
12955 <para>
12956 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12957 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12958 didn't <quote>get.</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
12959 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
12960 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, <quote>short,</quote> then this
12961 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
12962 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
12963 be presumptively uncontrolled.
12964 </para>
12965 <para>
12966 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
12967 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
12968 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
12969 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
12970 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
12971 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
12972 seen before <emphasis>because there are no formalities</emphasis>.
12973 </para>
12974 <para>
12975 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
12976 it is worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
12977 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
12978 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
12979 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
12980 </para>
12981 <para>
12982 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
12983 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
12984 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
12985 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
12986 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you.
12987 </para>
12988 <para>
12989 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
12990 registering the work mean that the $1 is really misleading? Isn't the
12991 hassle worth more than $1? Isn't that the real problem with
12992 registration?
12993 </para>
12994 <para>
12995 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
12996 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
12997 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
12998
12999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
13000 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
13001 address the real problem of <emphasis>governments</emphasis> standing
13002 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
13003 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
13004 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
13005 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
13006 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
13007 upon historical data, that system would move up to 98 percent of
13008 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
13009 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
13010 </para>
13011 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
13012 <para>
13013 <emphasis role='strong'>When Steve Forbes</emphasis> endorsed the
13014 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
13015 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
13016 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
13017 willing to take the first step.
13018 </para>
13019 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe</primary></indexterm>
13020 <para>
13021 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
13022 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
13023 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
13024 possible. In May 2003, it looked as if the bill would be
13025 introduced. On May 16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, <quote>we are
13026 close.</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
13027 something good might happen here.
13028 </para>
13029 <para>
13030 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
13031 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
13032 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
13033 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
13034 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
13035 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
13036 </para>
13037 <para>
13038 The MPAA argued first that Congress had <quote>firmly rejected the central
13039 concept in the proposed bill</quote>&mdash;that copyrights be renewed. That
13040 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's <quote>firm rejection</quote> had occurred
13041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
13042 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
13043 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
13044 owners&mdash;apparently those who could not afford the $1 fee. Third,
13045 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
13046 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
13047 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
13048 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
13049 off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
13050 argued that the bill would impose <quote>enormous</quote> costs, since a
13051 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
13052 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
13053 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
13054 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
13055 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
13056 film is a valid derivative use.
13057 </para>
13058 <para>
13059 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
13060 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
13061 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
13062 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
13063 or not&mdash;a controversial claim in any case&mdash;unless they know
13064 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
13065 </para>
13066 <para>
13067 <emphasis role='strong'>At the beginning</emphasis> of this book, I
13068 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
13069 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
13070 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
13071 opposition&mdash;the power of the side that fought to defend the
13072 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
13073 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
13074 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
13075 </para>
13076 <para>
13077 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
13078 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
13079 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
13080 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
13081 sense?
13082 </para>
13083 <para>
13084
13085 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
13086 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
13087 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
13088 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
13089 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
13090 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
13091 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
13092 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
13093 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
13094 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
13095 </para>
13096 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin</primary></indexterm>
13097 <para>
13098 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
13099 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
13100 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
13101 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
13102 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
13103 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the <quote>Dark
13104 Content</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
13105 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
13106 </para>
13107 <para>
13108 What does this industry really want?
13109 </para>
13110 <para>
13111 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
13112 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
13113 protecting <emphasis>their</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
13114 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
13115 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
13116 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
13117 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
13118 content that doesn't require <emphasis>their</emphasis> permission
13119 first.
13120 </para>
13121 <para>
13122 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
13123 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
13124 its aim not the protection of <quote>property</quote> but the rejection of a
13125 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
13126 theirs. <emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
13127 theirs</emphasis>.
13128 </para>
13129 <para>
13130 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
13131 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
13132
13133 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
13134 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
13135 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
13136 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
13137 and to share its own creation.
13138 </para>
13139 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13140 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13141 <para>
13142 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
13143 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
13144 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
13145 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
13146 block the progress of others.
13147 </para>
13148 <para>
13149 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
13150 <quote>property</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
13151 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
13152 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing <quote>permission
13153 society.</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
13154 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
13155 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
13156 </para>
13157 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
13158 </chapter>
13159 </part>
13160 <chapter label="15" id="c-conclusion">
13161 <title>CONCLUSION</title>
13162 <indexterm id='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='startofrange'><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in</primary></indexterm>
13163 <indexterm id='idxaidsmedications' class='startofrange'><primary>AIDS medications</primary></indexterm>
13164 <indexterm id='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='startofrange'><primary>antiretroviral drugs</primary></indexterm>
13165 <indexterm id='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>developing countries, foreign patent costs in</primary></indexterm>
13166 <indexterm id='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='startofrange'><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13167 <indexterm id='idxhivaidstherapies' class='startofrange'><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies</primary></indexterm>
13168 <para>
13169 <emphasis role='strong'>There are more</emphasis> than 35 million
13170 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
13171 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
13172 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
13173 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
13174 </para>
13175 <para>
13176 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
13177 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
13178 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
13179 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
13180 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
13181 the disease almost invisible.
13182 </para>
13183 <para>
13184 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
13185 United States, they cost between $10,000 and $15,000 per person per
13186 year. Today, some cost $25,000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
13187 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
13188 population:
13189 $15,000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
13190 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.<footnote><para>
13191 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, <quote>Final Report: Integrating
13192 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy</quote> (London, 2002),
13193 available at
13194 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
13195 release
13196 issued 9 July 2002, only 230,000 of the 6 million who need drugs in
13197 the developing world receive them&mdash;and half of them are in Brazil.
13198 </para></footnote>
13199 </para>
13200 <indexterm id='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13201 <indexterm id='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>pharmaceutical patents</primary></indexterm>
13202 <para>
13203 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
13204 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
13205 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
13206 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
13207 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
13208 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
13209 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
13210 </para>
13211 <para>
13212 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
13213 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
13214 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
13215 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
13216 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
13217 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
13218 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
13219 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
13220 changes.
13221 </para>
13222 <para>
13223 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
13224 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
13225 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
13226 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
13227 costs significantly below the market price.
13228 </para>
13229 <indexterm id='idxinternationallaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>international law</primary></indexterm>
13230 <indexterm id='idxparallelimportation' class='startofrange'><primary>parallel importation</primary></indexterm>
13231 <indexterm id='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='startofrange'><primary>South Africa, Republic of, pharmaceutical imports by</primary></indexterm>
13232 <para>
13233 In 1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
13234 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
13235 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
13236 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
13237 Africa from India. This is called <quote>parallel importation,</quote> and it is
13238 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
13239 permitted within the European Union.<footnote>
13240 <para>
13241 <!-- f2. -->
13242 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
13243 Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37.
13244 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13245 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13246 </para></footnote>
13247 </para>
13248 <indexterm><primary>United States Trade Representative (USTR)</primary></indexterm>
13249 <para>
13250 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
13251 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
13252 characterized it, <quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa &hellip;
13253 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
13254 imports.</quote><footnote><para>
13255 <!-- f3. -->
13256 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13257 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13258 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13259 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 14, available at
13260 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #56</ulink>. For a
13261 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
13262 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
13263 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess.,
13264 Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150&ndash;57 (statement of James
13265 Love).
13266 </para></footnote>
13267 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
13268 government asked South Africa to change the law&mdash;and to add
13269 pressure to that request, in 1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
13270 possible trade sanctions.
13271 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
13272 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
13273 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
13274 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
13275 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
13276 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
13277 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
13278 patent&mdash; pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
13279 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
13280 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
13281 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.<footnote><para>
13282 <!-- f4. -->
13283 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13284 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13285 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13286 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 15. </para></footnote>
13287 </para>
13288 <indexterm startref='idxparallelimportation' class='endofrange'/>
13289 <para>
13290 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
13291 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
13292 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
13293 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
13294 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
13295 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
13296 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
13297 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
13298 </para>
13299 <para>
13300 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
13301 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
13302 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
13303 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
13304 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
13305 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save 15 to 30 million lives.
13306 </para>
13307 <para>
13308 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
13309 profits of United States drug companies&mdash;at least, not substantially. It
13310 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
13311 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
13312 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
13313 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
13314 by U.S. companies.
13315 </para>
13316 <para>
13317 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
13318 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
13319 argument
13320 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
13321 about the sanctity of property.<footnote><para>
13322 <!-- f5. -->
13323 See Sabin Russell, <quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
13324 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24
13325 May 1999, A1, available at
13326 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #57</ulink>
13327 (<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
13328 system of intellectual property protection</quote>); Robert Weissman, <quote>AIDS
13329 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
13330 Medicines,</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus</citetitle> 4:23 (August 1999), available at
13331 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #58</ulink>
13332 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, <quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
13333 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
13334 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
13335 Symposium Journal</citetitle> (Spring 2001): 175.
13336 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
13337 </para></footnote>
13338 It was because <quote>intellectual property</quote> would be violated that these
13339 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
13340 importance of <quote>intellectual property</quote> that led these government actors
13341 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
13342 </para>
13343 <indexterm startref='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='endofrange'/>
13344 <para>
13345 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
13346 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
13347 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
13348 direct cost would be to speed the death of 15 to 30 million Africans,
13349 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the <quote>sanctity</quote> of an
13350 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
13351 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
13352 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
13353 </para>
13354 <indexterm id='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>in pharmaceutical industry</secondary></indexterm>
13355 <para>
13356 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
13357 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
13358 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
13359 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
13360 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system&mdash;
13361 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
13362 </para>
13363 <para>
13364 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
13365 drug companies would love&mdash;they say, and I believe them&mdash;to
13366 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
13367 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
13368 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
13369 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
13370 </para>
13371 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>of drug patents</secondary></indexterm>
13372 <para>
13373 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
13374 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
13375 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, <quote>How
13376 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $1 a pill, but the same
13377 drug would cost an American $1,500?</quote> Because there is no <quote>sound
13378 bite</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
13379 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
13380 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
13381 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
13382 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
13383 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
13384 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal&mdash;the sanctity of an
13385 idea called <quote>intellectual property.</quote>
13386 </para>
13387 <indexterm startref='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='endofrange'/>
13388 <indexterm startref='idxaidsmedications' class='endofrange'/>
13389 <indexterm startref='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='endofrange'/>
13390 <indexterm startref='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='endofrange'/>
13391 <indexterm startref='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='endofrange'/>
13392 <indexterm startref='idxhivaidstherapies' class='endofrange'/>
13393 <indexterm startref='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='endofrange'/>
13394 <para>
13395 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
13396 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
13397 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
13398 What is the argument?
13399 </para>
13400 <para>
13401 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
13402 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
13403 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
13404 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
13405 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
13406 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
13407 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
13408 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
13409 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
13410 were balanced in just this sense.
13411 </para>
13412 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='endofrange'/>
13413 <indexterm startref='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13414 <indexterm startref='idxinternationallaw2' class='endofrange'/>
13415 <para>
13416 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
13417 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
13418 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
13419 our tradition, now reigns in this culture&mdash;bizarrely, and with
13420 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
13421 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
13422 </para>
13423 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13424 <para>
13425 <emphasis role='strong'>A simple idea</emphasis> blinds us, and under
13426 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
13427 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
13428 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
13429 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
13430 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
13431 control of that property removes our
13432 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
13433 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
13434 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
13435 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
13436 this common sense open its eyes.
13437 </para>
13438 <para>
13439 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
13440 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
13441 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
13442 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
13443 to fight <quote>piracy,</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
13444 the idea of <quote>creative property,</quote> while transforming real creators into
13445 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
13446 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
13447 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
13448 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
13449 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
13450 produce the <quote>perfect storm</quote> for free culture.
13451 </para>
13452 <indexterm><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
13453 <indexterm><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13454 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13455 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
13456 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13457 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
13458 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
13459 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>public projects in</secondary></indexterm>
13460 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)</primary></indexterm>
13461 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust</primary></indexterm>
13462 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13463 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web</primary></indexterm>
13464 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System</primary></indexterm>
13465 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
13466 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13467 <para>
13468 <emphasis role='strong'>In August 2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
13469 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
13470 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.<footnote><para>
13471 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>,
13472 August 2003, E1, available at
13473 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #59</ulink>; William New, <quote>Global Group's
13474 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13475 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13476 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #60</ulink>; William New, <quote>U.S. Official
13477 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13478 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13479 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #61</ulink>.
13480 </para></footnote>
13481 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
13482 a meeting to discuss <quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
13483 goods.</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
13484 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
13485 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
13486 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
13487 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
13488 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
13489 that I describe in chapter
13490 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="c-afterword"/>. It
13491 included a project to develop single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs),
13492 which are thought to have great significance in biomedical
13493 research. (That nonprofit project comprised a consortium of the
13494 Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and technological companies,
13495 including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
13496 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
13497 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
13498 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
13499 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
13500 in the early 1980s. And it included <quote>open source and free software.</quote>
13501 </para>
13502 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'/>
13503 <para>
13504 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
13505 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
13506 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
13507 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
13508 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
13509 </para>
13510 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>in international debate on intellectual property</secondary></indexterm>
13511 <para>
13512 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.<footnote><para>
13513 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
13514 meeting.
13515 </para></footnote>
13516 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
13517 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
13518 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
13519 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
13520 property issues.
13521 </para>
13522 <indexterm id='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='startofrange'><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13523 <para>
13524 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
13525 about WIPO. In February 2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
13526 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
13527 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
13528 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
13529 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
13530 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
13531 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
13532 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
13533 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
13534 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
13535 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
13536 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
13537 talk about an <quote>Information Society</quote> unless one also talked about the
13538 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
13539 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
13540 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
13541 stuff of
13542 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
13543 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
13544 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
13545 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
13546 </para>
13547 <para>
13548 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
13549 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
13550 thus the meeting about <quote>open and collaborative projects to create
13551 public goods</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
13552 </para>
13553 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='endofrange'/>
13554 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='endofrange'/>
13555 <indexterm startref='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='endofrange'/>
13556 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
13557 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
13558 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>on free software</secondary></indexterm>
13559 <para>
13560 But there is one project within that list that is highly
13561 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is <quote>open source
13562 and free software.</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
13563 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
13564 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
13565 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
13566 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
13567 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
13568 rather than <quote>proprietary software,</quote> for their own internal uses.
13569 </para>
13570 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft</quote> licenses</primary></indexterm>
13571 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13572 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13573 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13574 <para>
13575 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
13576 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
13577 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
13578 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
13579 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
13580 operating system, the most famous bit of <quote>free software</quote>&mdash;and IBM
13581 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support <quote>open source and
13582 free software</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
13583 to support a mode of software development that is different from
13584 Microsoft's.<footnote><para>
13585 <!-- f8. -->
13586 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
13587 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
13588 <quote>open source</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
13589 principal opposition is to <quote>free software</quote> licensed under a <quote>copyleft</quote>
13590 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
13591 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, <quote>The Future
13592 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
13593 Toward Open Source Software</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
13594 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
13595 Public Policy Research, 2002), 69, available at
13596 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #62</ulink>. See also
13597 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, <citetitle>The Commercial Software
13598 Model</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (3
13599 May 2001), available at
13600 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #63</ulink>.
13601 </para></footnote>
13602 </para>
13603 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='endofrange'/>
13604 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)</primary></indexterm>
13605 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)</primary></indexterm>
13606 <para>
13607 More important for our purposes, to support <quote>open source and free
13608 software</quote> is not to oppose copyright. <quote>Open source and free software</quote>
13609 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
13610 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
13611 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
13612 by
13613 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
13614 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
13615 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
13616 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
13617 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
13618 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
13619 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
13620 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
13621 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
13622 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
13623 </para>
13624 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13625 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13626 <indexterm id='idxkrimjonathan' class='startofrange'><primary>Krim, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
13627 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by</secondary></indexterm>
13628 <para>
13629 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
13630 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
13631 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
13632 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
13633 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
13634 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
13635 States government to veto the meeting.<footnote><para>
13636 <!-- f9. -->
13637 Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> available at <ulink
13638 url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #64</ulink>.
13639 </para></footnote>
13640 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
13641 </para>
13642 <para>
13643 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
13644 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
13645 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
13646 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
13647 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
13648 its lobbying efforts.
13649 </para>
13650 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='endofrange'/>
13651 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13652 <para>
13653 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
13654 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
13655 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
13656 Office, explained that <quote>open-source software runs counter to the
13657 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.</quote>
13658 She is quoted as saying, <quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
13659 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
13660 goals of WIPO.</quote>
13661 </para>
13662 <indexterm startref='idxkrimjonathan' class='endofrange'/>
13663 <para>
13664 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
13665 </para>
13666 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='endofrange'/>
13667 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
13668 <para>
13669 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
13670 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
13671 right called <quote>copyright</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
13672 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it <quote>runs counter</quote> to the mission
13673 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
13674 in understanding&mdash;the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
13675 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
13676 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
13677 </para>
13678 <indexterm><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13679 <indexterm><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13680 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs</primary></indexterm>
13681 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13682 <para>
13683 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to <quote>promote</quote>
13684 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
13685 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
13686 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
13687 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
13688 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
13689 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
13690 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
13691 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
13692 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
13693 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
13694 </para>
13695 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
13696 <para>
13697 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
13698 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
13699 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13700 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13701 <emphasis>their</emphasis> rights. If they want to <quote>waive</quote> or
13702 <quote>disclaim</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13703 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $20 billion to do
13704 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13705 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13706 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13707 to do with <emphasis>their</emphasis> property.
13708 </para>
13709 <indexterm id='idxboland' class='startofrange'><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13710 <para>
13711 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13712 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,</quote> she's
13713 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13714 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13715 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13716 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from <quote>waiving</quote> or
13717 <quote>disclaiming</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13718 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13719 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13720 way possible.
13721 </para>
13722 <indexterm id='idxfeudalsystem' class='startofrange'><primary>feudal system</primary></indexterm>
13723 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>feudal system of</secondary></indexterm>
13724 <para>
13725 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13726 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called <quote>feudalism.</quote> Under
13727 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13728 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13729 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13730 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13731 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13732 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13733 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13734 that control.
13735 </para>
13736 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13737 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13738 <para>
13739 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13740 choice we are now making about intellectual property.<footnote><para>
13741 <!-- f10. -->
13742 See Drahos with Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism</citetitle>, 210&ndash;20.
13743 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13744 </para></footnote>
13745 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13746 choice now is whether that information society will be
13747 <emphasis>free</emphasis> or <emphasis>feudal</emphasis>. The trend is
13748 toward the feudal.
13749 </para>
13750 <indexterm startref='idxfeudalsystem' class='endofrange'/>
13751 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='endofrange'/>
13752 <para>
13753 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13754 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13755 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13756 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13757 </para>
13758 <blockquote>
13759 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='endofrange'/>
13760 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='endofrange'/>
13761 <para>
13762 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13763 it should be (<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13764 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13765 not simply to promote intellectual property rights</quote>), not as it is. If
13766 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13767 say anything wrong. But in the world
13768 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13769 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13770 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13771 </para>
13772 </blockquote>
13773 <para>
13774 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13775 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13776 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13777 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13778 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13779 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13780 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13781 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13782 </para>
13783 <indexterm startref='idxboland' class='endofrange'/>
13784 <para>
13785 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13786 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13787 <quote>goal</quote> of a government should be <quote>to promote the right balance</quote> of
13788 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13789 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. <quote>Typical for
13790 an academic,</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13791 </para>
13792 <para>
13793 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13794 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13795 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13796 our own country's history).
13797 </para>
13798 <para>
13799 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13800 government should be to <quote>seek balance,</quote> then count me with the silly,
13801 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13802 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13803 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13804 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13805 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13806 not lies is just na&iuml;ve, then who have we, the most powerful
13807 democracy in the world, become?
13808 </para>
13809 <para>
13810 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13811 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13812 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13813 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13814 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13815 been part of our tradition for most of our history&mdash;free culture.
13816 </para>
13817 <para>
13818 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13819 </para>
13820 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
13821 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
13822 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted</primary></indexterm>
13823 <para>
13824 <emphasis role='strong'>There are moments</emphasis> of hope in this
13825 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13826 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13827 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13828 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13829 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13830 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13831 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing 700,000 letters were
13832 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13833 </para>
13834 <para>
13835 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13836 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13837 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13838 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13839 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13840 concentration in the media.
13841 </para>
13842 <para>
13843 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13844 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13845 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13846 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13847 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13848 </para>
13849 <para>
13850 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13851 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13852 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13853 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13854 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13855 range of rights&mdash;property rights of a historically extreme
13856 form&mdash;that makes their bigness bad.
13857 </para>
13858 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13859 <para>
13860 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13861 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13862 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13863 Americans have a long history of fighting <quote>big,</quote> wisely or not. That
13864 we could be motivated to fight <quote>big</quote> again is not something new.
13865 </para>
13866 <para>
13867 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13868 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13869 the idea of <quote>intellectual property.</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13870 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13871 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13872 called <quote>property</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13873 </para>
13874 <para>
13875 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13876 of our tragedy.
13877 </para>
13878 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob</primary></indexterm>
13879 <para>
13880 <emphasis role='strong'>As I write</emphasis> these final words, the
13881 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
13882 three hundred individuals.<footnote><para>
13883 <!-- f11. -->
13884 John Borland, <quote>RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers,</quote> CNET News.com, September
13885 2003, available at
13886 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #65</ulink>; Paul
13887 R. La Monica, <quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,</quote> CNN/Money, 8 September
13888 2003, available at
13889 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #66</ulink>; Soni
13890 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, <quote>Sued for a Song,
13891 N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among 261 Cited as Sharers,</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News</citetitle>, 9
13892 September 2003, 3; Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13893 Targets; Single Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13894 Defendants,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13895 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,</quote> <citetitle>Wired News</citetitle>, 10 September 2003,
13896 available at
13897 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #67</ulink>.
13898 </para></footnote>
13899 Eminem has just been sued for <quote>sampling</quote> someone else's
13900 music.<footnote><para>
13901 <!-- f12. -->
13902 Jon Wiederhorn, <quote>Eminem Gets Sued &hellip; by a Little Old Lady,</quote>
13903 mtv.com, 17 September 2003, available at
13904 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #68</ulink>.
13905 </para></footnote>
13906 The story about Bob Dylan <quote>stealing</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13907 finished making the rounds.<footnote><para>
13908 <!-- f13. -->
13909 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, <quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13910 Dylan Songs,</quote> Kansascity.com, 9 July 2003, available at
13911 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #69</ulink>.
13912 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13913 </para></footnote>
13914 An insider from Hollywood&mdash;who insists he must remain
13915 anonymous&mdash;reports <quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13916 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13917 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13918 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13919 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.</quote> Congressmen are
13920 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13921 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13922 kids who use a computer to share content.
13923 </para>
13924 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13925 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13926 <indexterm><primary>BBC</primary></indexterm>
13927 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in</primary></indexterm>
13928 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
13929 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto</primary></indexterm>
13930 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>public creative archive in</secondary></indexterm>
13931 <para>
13932 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13933 that it will build a <quote>Creative Archive,</quote> from which British citizens can
13934 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.<footnote><para>
13935 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,</quote> BBC press release,
13936 24 August 2003, available at
13937 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #70</ulink>.
13938 </para></footnote>
13939 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13940 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13941 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13942 country.<footnote><para>
13943 <!-- f15. -->
13944 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,</quote> Creative Commons Weblog, 6 August 2003,
13945 available at
13946 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #71</ulink>.
13947 </para></footnote>
13948 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13949 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13950 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13951 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13952 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13953 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13954 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13955 day into the Causbys.
13956 </para>
13957 <para>
13958 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
13959 potential is ever to be realized.
13960
13961 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
13962
13963 </para>
13964 </chapter>
13965 <chapter label="16" id="c-afterword">
13966 <title>AFTERWORD</title>
13967 <para>
13968
13969 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
13970 <emphasis role='strong'>At least some</emphasis> who have read this
13971 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
13972 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
13973 </para>
13974 <para>
13975 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
13976 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
13977 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
13978 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
13979 </para>
13980 <para>
13981 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
13982 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
13983 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists&mdash;all to tell this
13984 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
13985 is so important.
13986 </para>
13987 <para>
13988 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
13989 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
13990 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
13991 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
13992 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
13993 </para>
13994 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
13995
13996 <section id="usnow">
13997 <title>US, NOW</title>
13998 <para>
13999 <emphasis role='strong'>Common sense</emphasis> is with the copyright
14000 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
14001 extremes&mdash;as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
14002 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
14003 choice, then the warriors should win.
14004 </para>
14005 <para>
14006 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
14007 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
14008 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright&mdash;<quote>All Rights
14009 Reserved</quote>&mdash; and those who reject copyright&mdash;<quote>No Rights
14010 Reserved.</quote> The <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
14011 permission before you <quote>use</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The <quote>No
14012 Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
14013 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
14014 </para>
14015 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
14016 <indexterm id='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>initial free character of</secondary></indexterm>
14017 <para>
14018 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
14019 tilted in the <quote>no rights reserved</quote> direction. Content could be copied
14020 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
14021 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
14022 the
14023
14024 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
14025 original design of the Internet was <quote>no rights reserved.</quote> Content was
14026 <quote>taken</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
14027 unprotected.
14028 </para>
14029 <para>
14030 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
14031 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
14032 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
14033 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
14034 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
14035 architecture made the effective default <quote>no rights reserved,</quote> the
14036 future architecture will make the effective default <quote>all rights
14037 reserved.</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
14038 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
14039 content requires permission. The <quote>cut and paste</quote> world that defines
14040 the Internet today will become a <quote>get permission to cut and paste</quote>
14041 world that is a creator's nightmare.
14042 </para>
14043 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='endofrange'/>
14044 <indexterm startref='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='endofrange'/>
14045 <para>
14046 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle&mdash;neither
14047 <quote>all rights reserved</quote> nor <quote>no rights reserved</quote> but <quote>some rights
14048 reserved</quote>&mdash; and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
14049 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
14050 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
14051 before.
14052 </para>
14053 <section id="examples">
14054 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples</title>
14055 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>restoration efforts on previous aspects of</secondary></indexterm>
14056 <indexterm id='idxbrowsing' class='startofrange'><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
14057 <indexterm id='idxprivacyrights2' class='startofrange'><primary>privacy rights</primary></indexterm>
14058 <para>
14059 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
14060 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
14061 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
14062 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
14063 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
14064 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
14065 to your neighbors or boss. The <quote>privacy</quote> of your browsing habits was
14066 assured.
14067 </para>
14068 <para>
14069 What made it assured?
14070 </para>
14071 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
14072 <para>
14073 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
14074 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>, your
14075 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
14076 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
14077 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
14078 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
14079 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
14080 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
14081 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
14082 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
14083 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
14084 (there is no law protecting <quote>privacy</quote> in public places), and in many
14085 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
14086 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
14087 </para>
14088 <indexterm id='idxamazon' class='startofrange'><primary>Amazon</primary></indexterm>
14089 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet</primary></indexterm>
14090 <indexterm id='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>privacy protection on</secondary></indexterm>
14091 <para>
14092 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
14093 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
14094 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
14095 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
14096 <quote>recently viewed</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
14097 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
14098 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any <quote>privacy</quote>
14099 protected by the friction disappears, too.
14100 </para>
14101 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>privacy rights in use of</secondary></indexterm>
14102 <para>
14103 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
14104 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
14105 people should have the <quote>right</quote> to browse in a library without the
14106 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
14107 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
14108 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
14109 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
14110 disappears.
14111 </para>
14112 <indexterm startref='idxbrowsing' class='endofrange'/>
14113 <indexterm startref='idxamazon' class='endofrange'/>
14114 <para>
14115 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define <quote>privacy</quote>
14116 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
14117 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
14118 friction did.<footnote><para>
14119 <!-- f1. -->
14120
14121 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, <quote>Fair Information Practices and the
14122 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
14123 Law Review</citetitle> 1 (2001): par. 6&ndash;18, available at
14124
14125 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>
14126 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
14127 also Jeffrey Rosen, <citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
14128 in an Anxious Age</citetitle> (New York: Random House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs
14129 between technology and privacy).</para></footnote>
14130 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
14131 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
14132
14133 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
14134 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
14135 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
14136 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
14137 </para>
14138 <indexterm startref='idxprivacyrights2' class='endofrange'/>
14139 <indexterm startref='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='endofrange'/>
14140 <indexterm><primary>Data General</primary></indexterm>
14141 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
14142 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
14143 <para>
14144 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
14145 movement. When computers with software were first made available
14146 commercially, the software&mdash;both the source code and the
14147 binaries&mdash; was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
14148 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
14149 care much about controlling their software.
14150 </para>
14151 <indexterm id='idxstallmanrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Stallman, Richard</primary></indexterm>
14152 <para>
14153 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
14154 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
14155 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
14156 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
14157 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
14158 people's work.
14159 </para>
14160 <para>
14161 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
14162 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
14163 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
14164 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
14165 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
14166 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
14167 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
14168 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
14169 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
14170 anything else?
14171 </para>
14172 <indexterm id='idxproprietarycode' class='startofrange'><primary>proprietary code</primary></indexterm>
14173 <para>
14174 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
14175 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
14176 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
14177 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
14178 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
14179 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
14180 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
14181 </para>
14182 <para>
14183 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
14184 early 1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
14185 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
14186 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
14187 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
14188 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
14189 fundamentally weakened.
14190 </para>
14191 <indexterm startref='idxproprietarycode' class='endofrange'/>
14192 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus</primary></indexterm>
14193 <para>
14194 Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
14195 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
14196 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's <quote>Linux</quote>
14197 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
14198 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14199 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14200 </para>
14201 <para>
14202 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
14203 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
14204 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
14205 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
14206 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
14207 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
14208 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
14209 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
14210 byproduct.
14211 </para>
14212 <para>
14213 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
14214 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
14215 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
14216 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
14217 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
14218 what before had been passively guaranteed.
14219 </para>
14220 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='endofrange'/>
14221 <indexterm startref='idxstallmanrichard' class='endofrange'/>
14222 <indexterm id='idxacademicjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
14223 <indexterm id='idxscientificjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>scientific journals</primary></indexterm>
14224 <para>
14225 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
14226 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
14227 scientific journals are produced.
14228 </para>
14229 <indexterm id='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>Lexis and Westlaw</primary></indexterm>
14230 <indexterm id='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
14231 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14232 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>access to opinions of</secondary></indexterm>
14233 <para>
14234 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
14235 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
14236 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
14237 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
14238 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
14239 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
14240 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
14241 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
14242 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
14243 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
14244 and Westlaw are also free
14245 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
14246 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
14247 Court opinion through their respective services.
14248 </para>
14249 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>access fees for material in</secondary></indexterm>
14250 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>license system for rebuilding of</secondary></indexterm>
14251 <para>
14252 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
14253 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
14254 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
14255 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
14256 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
14257 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
14258 access to material that is not in the public domain.
14259 </para>
14260 <indexterm startref='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='endofrange'/>
14261 <indexterm startref='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='endofrange'/>
14262 <para>
14263 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
14264 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
14265 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
14266 </para>
14267 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14268 <para>
14269 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
14270 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
14271 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
14272 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
14273 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
14274 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
14275 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
14276 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
14277 the technology of paper journals (architecture)&mdash;namely, that it
14278 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
14279 </para>
14280 <para>
14281 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
14282 that libraries not give the general public access to the
14283 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
14284 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
14285 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
14286 granted before.
14287 </para>
14288 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
14289 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
14290 <para>
14291 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
14292 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
14293 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
14294 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
14295 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
14296 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
14297 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
14298 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
14299 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
14300 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
14301 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
14302 </para>
14303 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='endofrange'/>
14304 <para>
14305 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
14306 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
14307 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
14308 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
14309 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
14310 presumptively a good&mdash;especially when it helps spread knowledge
14311 and science.
14312 </para>
14313 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='endofrange'/>
14314 <indexterm startref='idxacademicjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14315 <indexterm startref='idxscientificjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14316 </section>
14317 <section id="oneidea">
14318 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea</title>
14319 <indexterm id='idxcreativecommons' class='startofrange'><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
14320 <para>
14321 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
14322 increasing control effected through law and technology.
14323 </para>
14324 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University</primary></indexterm>
14325 <para>
14326 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
14327 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
14328 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
14329 <emphasis>reasonable</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
14330 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
14331 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
14332 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
14333 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
14334 make this possible.
14335 </para>
14336 <para>
14337 <emphasis>Simple</emphasis>&mdash;which means without a middleman, or
14338 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
14339 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
14340 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
14341 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
14342 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
14343 shared. These three expressions together&mdash;a legal license, a
14344 human-readable description, and
14345 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
14346 machine-readable tags&mdash;constitute a Creative Commons license. A
14347 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
14348 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
14349 that the person associated with the license believes in something
14350 different than the <quote>All</quote> or <quote>No</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
14351 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
14352 certain freedoms are given.
14353 </para>
14354 <para>
14355 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
14356 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
14357 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
14358 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
14359 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
14360 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (<quote>share and share
14361 alike</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
14362 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
14363 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
14364 </para>
14365 <para>
14366 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
14367 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
14368 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
14369 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
14370 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
14371 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
14372 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
14373 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
14374 a public domain.
14375 </para>
14376 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia</primary></indexterm>
14377 <para>
14378 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
14379 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
14380 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
14381 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
14382 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
14383 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
14384 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
14385 of content (<quote>content conducers,</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
14386 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
14387 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
14388 </para>
14389 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
14390 <para>
14391 The aim is not to fight the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts. The aim is to
14392 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
14393 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
14394 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
14395 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
14396 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
14397 the background of digital technologies. New rules&mdash;with different
14398 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
14399 them&mdash;are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
14400 to begin to build those rules.
14401 </para>
14402 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
14403 <para>
14404 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
14405 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
14406 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
14407 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
14408 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
14409 </para>
14410 <para>
14411 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
14412 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1)
14413 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
14414 and (2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
14415 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (1) will download
14416 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2)
14417 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
14418 them (2)-goods. If there are more (2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the
14419 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
14420 <emphasis>increase</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
14421 </para>
14422 <para>
14423 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
14424 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
14425 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
14426 was a total success.
14427 </para>
14428 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)</primary></indexterm>
14429 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter</primary></indexterm>
14430 <para>
14431 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
14432 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
14433 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
14434 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled <citetitle>Free for All</citetitle>,
14435 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
14436 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
14437 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
14438 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
14439 well.
14440 </para>
14441 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'/>
14442 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy</primary></indexterm>
14443 <indexterm><primary>rap music</primary></indexterm>
14444 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter</primary></indexterm>
14445 <para>
14446 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
14447 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
14448 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
14449 reasons. Many who use the <quote>sampling license</quote> do so because anything
14450 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
14451 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
14452 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
14453 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
14454 art&mdash;they, too, sample from others. Because the
14455 <emphasis>legal</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
14456 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
14457 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not <quote>allow</quote>
14458 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
14459 high<footnote><para>
14460 <!-- f2. -->
14461 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
14462 Culture Wars</citetitle> (2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
14463 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
14464 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>.
14465 </para></footnote>),
14466 these artists release into the creative environment content
14467 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
14468 </para>
14469 <para>
14470 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
14471 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
14472 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
14473 you are effectively saying you believe in the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote>
14474 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
14475 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
14476 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
14477 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
14478 this notion of <quote>Some Rights Reserved,</quote> and gives many the chance to
14479 say it to others.
14480 </para>
14481 <para>
14482 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
14483 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
14484 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
14485 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
14486
14487 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
14488 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
14489 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
14490 </para>
14491 <para>
14492 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
14493 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
14494 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
14495 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
14496 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
14497 steps are possible.
14498 </para>
14499 <para>
14500 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
14501 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
14502 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
14503 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
14504 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
14505 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
14506 creativity to spread more easily.
14507 </para>
14508 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='endofrange'/>
14509 <indexterm startref='idxcreativecommons' class='endofrange'/>
14510 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
14511 </section>
14512 </section>
14513 <section id="themsoon">
14514 <title>THEM, SOON</title>
14515 <para>
14516 <emphasis role='strong'>We will</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
14517 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
14518 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
14519 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
14520 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
14521 </para>
14522 <para>
14523 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
14524 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
14525 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
14526 to our end.
14527 </para>
14528
14529 <section id="formalities">
14530 <title>1. More Formalities</title>
14531 <para>
14532 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
14533 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
14534 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
14535 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
14536 </para>
14537 <para>
14538 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
14539 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
14540 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
14541 protected.
14542 </para>
14543 <para>
14544 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
14545 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
14546 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
14547 default is control, and <quote>formalities</quote> are banished.
14548 </para>
14549 <para>
14550 Why?
14551 </para>
14552 <para>
14553 As I suggested in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
14554 linkend="property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
14555 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
14556 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
14557 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
14558 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
14559 formalities were getting in the way.
14560 </para>
14561 <para>
14562 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
14563 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
14564 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
14565 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
14566 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
14567 trace&mdash; there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
14568 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
14569 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
14570 past. And thus, the <emphasis>lack</emphasis> of formalities forces
14571 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
14572 </para>
14573 <para>
14574 The law should therefore change this requirement<footnote><para>
14575 <!-- f1. -->
14576 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
14577 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
14578 adopted by other countries as well.</para></footnote>&mdash;but it
14579 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
14580 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
14581 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
14582 </para>
14583 <para>
14584 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
14585 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
14586 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
14587 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
14588 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
14589 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
14590 developed by others.
14591 </para>
14592
14593 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
14594
14595 <section id="registration">
14596 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL</title>
14597 <para>
14598 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
14599 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
14600 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
14601 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
14602 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
14603 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
14604 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
14605 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
14606 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
14607 panic&mdash;nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
14608 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
14609 </para>
14610 <para>
14611 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
14612 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
14613 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
14614 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
14615 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
14616 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
14617 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
14618 </para>
14619 <para>
14620 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
14621 There are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world.
14622 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
14623 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
14624 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
14625 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
14626 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
14627 with which registration occurs up.
14628 </para>
14629 <para>
14630 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
14631 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
14632 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
14633 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
14634 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
14635 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
14636 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
14637 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
14638 formality&mdash;while producing a database
14639 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
14640 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
14641 </para>
14642
14643 </section>
14644 <section id="marking">
14645 <title>MARKING</title>
14646 <para>
14647 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
14648 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
14649 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule&mdash;akin to
14650 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
14651 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
14652 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
14653 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
14654 uniformly across all media.
14655 </para>
14656 <para>
14657 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
14658 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
14659 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
14660 use the work.
14661 </para>
14662 <para>
14663 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
14664 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
14665 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
14666 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
14667 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
14668 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
14669 signal from the failure to mark&mdash;not the loss of the copyright, but the
14670 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
14671 </para>
14672 <para>
14673 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
14674 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
14675 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
14676 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
14677 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
14678 doesn't give permission.<footnote><para>
14679 <!-- f2. -->
14680 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
14681 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
14682 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
14683 </para></footnote>
14684 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be <quote>use unless someone
14685 complains.</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
14686 stop using the work in any new
14687 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
14688 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
14689 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
14690 their work.
14691 </para>
14692 <para>
14693 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
14694 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
14695 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
14696 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
14697 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
14698 </para>
14699 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>copyright marking of</secondary></indexterm>
14700 <para>
14701 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
14702 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
14703 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
14704 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
14705 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
14706 <emphasis>solely</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
14707 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
14708 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
14709 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
14710 other important functions.
14711 </para>
14712 <para>
14713 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
14714 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
14715 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
14716 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
14717 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
14718 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
14719 </para>
14720 <para>
14721 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
14722 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
14723 make things unclear.
14724 </para>
14725 <para>
14726 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
14727 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
14728 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
14729 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
14730 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
14731 that assertion at the appropriate time.
14732 </para>
14733
14734 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
14735 </section>
14736 </section>
14737 <section id="shortterms">
14738 <title>2. Shorter Terms</title>
14739 <para>
14740 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14741 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14742 natural authors.
14743 </para>
14744 <para>
14745 In <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14746 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14747 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14748 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14749 radical. <citetitle>The Economist</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14750 copyright term.<footnote><para>
14751
14752 <!-- f3. -->
14753 <quote>A Radical Rethink,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 366:8308 (25 January 2003): 15,
14754 available at
14755 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #74</ulink>.
14756 </para></footnote>
14757 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14758 </para>
14759 <para>
14760 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14761 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14762 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14763 terms.
14764 </para>
14765 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14766 <listitem><para>
14767 <!-- (1) -->
14768 <emphasis>Keep it short:</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14769 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14770 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14771 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14772 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14773 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14774 </para></listitem>
14775 <listitem><para>
14776 <!-- (2) -->
14777 <emphasis>Keep it simple:</emphasis> The line between the public
14778 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14779 fuzziness of <quote>fair use,</quote> and the distinction between <quote>ideas</quote> and
14780 <quote>expression.</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14781 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14782 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14783 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14784 <quote>lawyer-free zone</quote> makes the complexities of <quote>fair use</quote> and
14785 <quote>idea/expression</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14786 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14787 </para></listitem>
14788 <listitem>
14789 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions</primary></indexterm>
14790 <para>
14791 <!-- (3) -->
14792 <emphasis>Keep it alive:</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14793 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14794 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14795 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14796 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14797 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14798 pension.<footnote><para>
14799 <!-- f4. -->
14800 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14801 and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001),
14802 available at
14803 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #75</ulink>.
14804 </para></footnote>
14805 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14806 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14807 single form.
14808 </para></listitem>
14809 <listitem><para>
14810 <!-- (4) -->
14811 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14812 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14813 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14814 in 1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14815 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14816 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in 1923 than we
14817 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14818 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14819 the number of authors who wrote in 1923. Of course, we can increase
14820 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14821 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14822 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14823 creativity in 1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14824 we can do about that now. </para></listitem>
14825 </orderedlist>
14826 <para>
14827 These changes together should produce an <emphasis>average</emphasis>
14828 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until 1976,
14829 the average term was just 32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14830 same.
14831 </para>
14832 <para>
14833 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas <quote>radical.</quote> (After all, I
14834 call them <quote>extremists.</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14835 than the term under Richard Nixon. How <quote>radical</quote> can it be to ask for
14836 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14837 </para>
14838
14839 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14840
14841 </section>
14842 <section id="freefairuse">
14843 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use</title>
14844 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
14845 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
14846 <para>
14847 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14848 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14849 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14850 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14851 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14852 the emergence of that new technology.
14853 </para>
14854 <para>
14855 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors <quote>exclusive
14856 right</quote> to <quote>their writings.</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14857 right to <quote>their writings</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14858 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14859 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14860 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14861 though that movie is not <quote>my writing.</quote>
14862 </para>
14863 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin</primary></indexterm>
14864 <para>
14865 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it
14866 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14867 control translations and dramatizations of a work.<footnote><para>
14868 <!-- f5. -->
14869 Benjamin Kaplan, <citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14870 University Press, 1967), 32.
14871 </para></footnote>
14872 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14873 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14874 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14875 </para>
14876 <blockquote>
14877 <para>
14878 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14879 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14880 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14881 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.<footnote><para>
14882 <!-- f6. --> Ibid., 56.
14883 </para></footnote>
14884 </para>
14885 </blockquote>
14886 <para>
14887 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14888 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14889 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14890 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14891 Consider each limitation in turn.
14892 </para>
14893 <para>
14894 <emphasis>Term:</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14895 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14896 sense to protect John
14897
14898 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14899 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14900 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14901 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14902 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14903 after the creative work is done.
14904 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
14905 </para>
14906 <para>
14907 <emphasis>Scope:</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14908 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14909 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14910 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14911 material. When all <quote>reuse</quote> of creative material was within the control
14912 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14913 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14914 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14915 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14916 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14917 the creative process. Smothers it.
14918 </para>
14919 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
14920 <para>
14921 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14922 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14923 foreseeable derivative rights&mdash;turning a book into a movie, or a
14924 poem into a musical score&mdash;it doesn't make sense to require
14925 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14926 much more sense.
14927 </para>
14928 <para>
14929 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14930 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14931 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14932 Paul Goldstein.<footnote>
14933 <para>
14934 <!-- f7. -->
14935 Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14936 Jukebox</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187&ndash;216.
14937 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul</primary></indexterm>
14938 </para></footnote>
14939 His view is that the law should be written so that
14940 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14941 </para>
14942 <para>
14943 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14944 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14945 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14946 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14947 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14948 </para>
14949 <para>
14950 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14951 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
14952 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
14953 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
14954 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
14955 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
14956 </para>
14957 </section>
14958
14959 <section id="liberatemusic">
14960 <title>4. Liberate the Music&mdash;Again</title>
14961 <para>
14962 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
14963 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
14964 is, to most people, most pressing&mdash;music. There is no other
14965 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
14966 battles around the sharing of music.
14967 </para>
14968 <para>
14969 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
14970 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
14971 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
14972 killer app&mdash;possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
14973 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
14974 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
14975 innovation on the network.
14976 </para>
14977 <para>
14978 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
14979 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
14980 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
14981 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
14982 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
14983 </para>
14984 <para>
14985 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
14986 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
14987 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
14988 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="piracy"/>, they enable
14989 four different kinds of sharing:
14990 </para>
14991 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
14992 <listitem><para>
14993 <!-- A. -->
14994 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
14995 for purchasing CDs.
14996 </para></listitem>
14997 <listitem><para>
14998 <!-- B. -->
14999 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
15000 on the way to purchasing CDs.
15001 </para></listitem>
15002 <listitem><para>
15003 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
15004 <!-- C. -->
15005 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15006 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
15007 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
15008 </para></listitem>
15009 <listitem><para>
15010 <!-- D. -->
15011 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15012 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
15013 owner plainly endorses.
15014 </para></listitem>
15015 </orderedlist>
15016 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
15017 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
15018 <para>
15019 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
15020 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
15021 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
15022 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
15023 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
15024 significantly weakened.
15025 </para>
15026 <para>
15027 As I said in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
15028 linkend="piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
15029 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
15030 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
15031 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
15032 networks.
15033 </para>
15034 <para>
15035 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
15036 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
15037 should respond.
15038 </para>
15039 <para>
15040 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
15041 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
15042 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
15043 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
15044 is cumbersome and slow&mdash;we in the United States are lucky to have
15045 broadband service at 1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
15046 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
15047 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
15048 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
15049 Internet is mainly just an idea.
15050 </para>
15051 <para>
15052 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
15053 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
15054 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
15055 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
15056 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
15057 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
15058 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
15059 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
15060 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
15061 where everywhere you are&mdash;except maybe the desert or the
15062 Rockies&mdash;you can instantaneously be connected to the
15063 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
15064 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
15065 </para>
15066 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over</primary></indexterm>
15067 <para>
15068 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
15069 give you access to content on the fly&mdash;such as Internet radio,
15070 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
15071 then, is the critical point: When it is <emphasis>extremely</emphasis>
15072 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
15073 <emphasis>easier</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
15074 access to content than it will be to download and store content
15075 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
15076 content</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
15077 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
15078 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
15079 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
15080 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
15081 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
15082 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
15083 paying for this content even though <quote>free</quote> content is available in the
15084 form of MP3s across the Web.<footnote><para>
15085 <!-- f8. -->
15086 See, for example, <quote>Music Media Watch,</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3
15087 April 2002, available at
15088 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #76</ulink>.
15089 </para></footnote>
15090
15091 </para>
15092 <para>
15093 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
15094 present: It is emphatically temporary. The <quote>problem</quote> with file
15095 sharing&mdash;to the extent there is a real problem&mdash;is a problem
15096 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
15097 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
15098 makers today to be <quote>solving</quote> this problem in light of a technology
15099 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
15100 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
15101 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
15102 artists get paid, during
15103
15104 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
15105 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
15106 and twenty-first-century technologies.
15107 </para>
15108 <para>
15109 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different <quote>problems</quote>
15110 here to solve. Let's start with type D content&mdash;uncopyrighted
15111 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
15112 <quote>problem</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
15113 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
15114 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
15115 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
15116 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
15117 order to eliminate kidnapping.
15118 </para>
15119 <para>
15120 Type C content raises a different <quote>problem.</quote> This is content that was,
15121 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
15122 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
15123 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
15124 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
15125 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
15126 way that returns something to the artist.
15127 </para>
15128 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
15129 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
15130 <para>
15131 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
15132 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
15133 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
15134 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
15135 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
15136 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
15137 from the author's perspective, this <quote>sharing</quote> of his content without
15138 his being compensated is less than ideal.
15139 </para>
15140 <para>
15141 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
15142 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
15143 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
15144 providers would be free, under this rule, to <quote>share</quote> that content,
15145 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
15146 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
15147 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
15148 </para>
15149 <para>
15150
15151 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
15152 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
15153 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
15154 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
15155 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
15156 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
15157 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
15158 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
15159 trade.
15160 </para>
15161 <para>
15162 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
15163 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
15164 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
15165 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
15166 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
15167 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
15168 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
15169 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
15170 </para>
15171 <para>
15172 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
15173 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
15174 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
15175 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
15176 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
15177 delivering and accessing content.
15178 </para>
15179 <para>
15180 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
15181 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
15182 </para>
15183 <para>
15184 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
15185 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
15186 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
15187 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
15188 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
15189 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
15190 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
15191 harmed the interests of the content industry.
15192 </para>
15193 <para>
15194 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
15195 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
15196 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
15197 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
15198 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
15199 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
15200 way to compensate those who are harmed.
15201 </para>
15202 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15203 <para>
15204 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
15205 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.<footnote>
15206 <para>
15207 <!-- f9. -->
15208 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15209 William Fisher, <citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities</citetitle> (last
15210 revised: 10 October 2000), available at
15211 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #77</ulink>; William
15212 Fisher, <citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
15213 Entertainment</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
15214 2004), ch. 6, available at
15215 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #78</ulink>. Professor
15216 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
15217 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
15218 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, <quote>Impose a
15219 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,</quote> available at
15220 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Who's Holding Back
15221 Broadband?</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
15222 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
15223 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, 26 February 2002,
15224 available at
15225 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, <citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
15226 Use Fee (IPUF)</citetitle>, 3 March 2002, available at
15227 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
15228 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 13 May
15229 2002, available at
15230 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, <quote>Getting Copyright Right,</quote>
15231 IEEE Spectrum Online, 1 July 2002, available at
15232 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #83</ulink>; Declan
15233 McCullagh, <quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,</quote> CNET News.com, 27 August
15234 2002, available at
15235 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #84</ulink>.
15236 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
15237 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
15238 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
15239 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
15240 debate by about a decade. See
15241 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #85</ulink>.
15242 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William</primary></indexterm>
15243 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
15244 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15245 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'/>
15246 </para></footnote>
15247 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
15248 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
15249 would (1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
15250 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
15251 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
15252 develop (2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
15253 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (3) artists would be
15254 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (4) an appropriate
15255 tax.
15256 </para>
15257 <para>
15258 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
15259 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
15260 <citetitle>Promises to Keep</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
15261 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
15262 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
15263 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
15264 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
15265 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
15266 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
15267 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
15268 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
15269 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
15270 controlling access.
15271 </para>
15272 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'/>
15273 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15274 <para>
15275 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
15276 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
15277 the system supports the widest range of <quote>semiotic democracy</quote>
15278 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
15279 other changes I described were accomplished&mdash;in particular, the
15280 limits on derivative
15281
15282 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
15283 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
15284 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
15285 allowed to do with the content itself.
15286 </para>
15287 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
15288 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore</primary></indexterm>
15289 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
15290 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>prices of</secondary></indexterm>
15291 <para>
15292 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
15293 <quote>harm</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
15294 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
15295 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
15296 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
15297 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat <quote>free</quote> by being
15298 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
15299 of songs at even the very high price of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents,
15300 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
15301 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
15302 Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a song. And no doubt
15303 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
15304 on-line.
15305 </para>
15306 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
15307 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast</secondary></indexterm>
15308 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
15309 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
15310 <indexterm><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in</secondary></indexterm>
15311 <para>
15312 This competition has already occurred against the background of <quote>free</quote>
15313 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
15314 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
15315 that, there is nothing impossible at all about <quote>competing with free.</quote>
15316 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
15317 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
15318 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
15319 theaters are often luxurious&mdash;with <quote>first class</quote> seats, and meals
15320 served while you watch a movie&mdash;as they struggle and succeed in
15321 finding ways to compete with <quote>free.</quote>
15322 </para>
15323 <para>
15324 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
15325 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
15326 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
15327 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
15328 innovators&mdash;ones who would have a right to the content, and would
15329 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
15330 the law.
15331 </para>
15332 <para>
15333 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
15334 </para>
15335 <para>
15336
15337 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
15338 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
15339 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
15340 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
15341 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
15342 create.
15343 </para>
15344 <para>
15345 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
15346 by
15347 </para>
15348 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
15349 <listitem><para>
15350 <!-- 1. -->
15351 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
15352 </para></listitem>
15353 <listitem><para>
15354 <!-- 2. -->
15355 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
15356 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
15357 statute;
15358 </para></listitem>
15359 <listitem><para>
15360 <!-- 3. -->
15361 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
15362 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
15363 </para></listitem>
15364 </orderedlist>
15365 <para>
15366 But what if <quote>piracy</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
15367 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
15368 consumers continue to <quote>take</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
15369 something then?
15370 </para>
15371 <para>
15372 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
15373 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
15374 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
15375 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
15376 technology that is 95 percent secure and produces a market of size <citetitle>x</citetitle>,
15377 or (b) to have a technology that is 50 percent secure but produces a
15378 market of five times <citetitle>x</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
15379 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
15380 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
15381 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
15382 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
15383 pirates.
15384 </para>
15385 <para>
15386 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
15387 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
15388 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
15389
15390 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
15391 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
15392 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
15393 </para>
15394 </section>
15395
15396 <section id="firelawyers">
15397 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers</title>
15398 <para>
15399 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
15400 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
15401 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
15402 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
15403 </para>
15404 <para>
15405 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
15406 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
15407 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
15408 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
15409 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
15410 strong view queers the law.
15411 </para>
15412 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville</primary></indexterm>
15413 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of</secondary></indexterm>
15414 <para>
15415 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
15416 <quote>radical</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
15417 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
15418 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
15419 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
15420 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
15421 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
15422 Nimmer, thought it obvious.<footnote><para>
15423 <!-- f10. -->
15424 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Copyright's First Amendment</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
15425 Memorial Lecture), <citetitle>UCLA Law Review</citetitle> 48 (2001): 1057, 1069&ndash;70.
15426 </para></footnote>
15427
15428 </para>
15429 <para>
15430 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
15431 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
15432 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
15433 </para>
15434 <para>
15435 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
15436 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
15437 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
15438 the legal system are slight.<footnote><para>
15439 <!-- f11. -->
15440 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
15441 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
15442 leading him to question his own publicly stated
15443 position&mdash;twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
15444 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
15445 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
15446 J. Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
15447 Drive the Digital Marketplace</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002), (reviewing his
15448 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
15449 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?</quote> working paper, June 2003,
15450 available at
15451 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #86</ulink>.
15452 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
15453 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
15454 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
15455 <citetitle>Rethinking</citetitle>, 174&ndash;76.
15456 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
15457 </para></footnote>
15458 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
15459 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
15460 them it works.
15461 </para>
15462 <para>
15463 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
15464 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
15465 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
15466 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
15467 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
15468 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
15469 practically never be done.
15470 </para>
15471 <para>
15472 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
15473 billed at the largest firms at more than $400 per hour. How much time
15474 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
15475 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
15476 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
15477 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
15478 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
15479 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
15480 </para>
15481 <para>
15482 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
15483 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
15484 their duty to change the way the law works&mdash;or better, to change the
15485 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
15486 top 1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
15487 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
15488 </para>
15489 <para>
15490 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
15491 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
15492 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
15493 its review.
15494 </para>
15495 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
15496 <para>
15497 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
15498 technology&mdash;the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
15499 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
15500 technology&mdash;a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
15501 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
15502 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
15503 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
15504 </para>
15505 <para>
15506 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture&mdash;but it should
15507 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
15508
15509 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311-->
15510 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
15511 simple pragmatic question: <quote>Will it do good?</quote> When challenged about
15512 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, <quote>Why not?</quote>
15513 </para>
15514 <para>
15515 We should ask, <quote>Why?</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
15516 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
15517 keep your lawyers away.
15518 </para>
15519 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
15520 </section>
15521 </section>
15522 </chapter>
15523 <chapter label="17" id="c-notes">
15524 <title>NOTES</title>
15525 <para>
15526 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
15527 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
15528 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
15529 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
15530 this book. For each link below, you can go to
15531 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
15532 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
15533 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
15534 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
15535 the material.
15536 </para>
15537
15538 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
15539 <?latex \theendnotes ?>
15540
15541 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
15542
15543 </chapter>
15544 <chapter label="18" id="c-acknowledgments">
15545 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS</title>
15546 <para>
15547 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
15548 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
15549 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
15550 to him that this book is dedicated.
15551 </para>
15552 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
15553 <para>
15554 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
15555 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
15556 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
15557 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
15558 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
15559 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
15560 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
15561 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
15562 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
15563 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
15564 critical eye on much of this.
15565 </para>
15566 <para>
15567 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
15568 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
15569 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
15570 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
15571 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
15572 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
15573 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
15574 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
15575 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
15576 </para>
15577 <para>
15578 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
15579 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
15580 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
15581 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
15582 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
15583 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
15584 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
15585 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
15586 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
15587 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
15588 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
15589 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
15590 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
15591 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
15592 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, <quote>Wink,</quote> Roger Wood, <quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,</quote>
15593 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
15594 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
15595 a bunch of great replies.)
15596 </para>
15597 <para>
15598 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
15599 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
15600 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
15601 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
15602 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
15603 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
15604 throughout this book.
15605 </para>
15606 <para>
15607 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
15608 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
15609 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
15610 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
15611 </para>
15612 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->
15613
15614 </chapter>
15615 <index></index>
15616 <colophon>
15617 <para>
15618 Free culture: How big media uses technology and the law to lock down
15619 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
15620 </para>
15621 <para>
15622 Copyright &copy; Lawrence Lessig. Some rights reserved.
15623 </para>
15624 <para>
15625 This version of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is licensed under
15626 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
15627 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
15628 about the license visit
15629 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/</ulink>
15630 </para>
15631 <para>
15632 This digital book was published by Petter Reinholdtsen in 2015. The
15633 original hardcover paper book was published in 2004 by The Penguin
15634 Press.
15635 </para>
15636 <para>
15637 Excerpt from an editorial titled <quote>The Coming of Copyright
15638 Perpetuity,</quote> <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, January
15639 16, 2003. Copyright &copy; 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted
15640 with permission.
15641 </para>
15642 <para>
15643 Cartoon in <xref linkend="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/> by Paul
15644 Conrad, copyright Tribune Media Services, Inc. All rights
15645 reserved. Reprinted with permission.
15646 </para>
15647 <para>
15648 Diagram in <xref linkend="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership"/>
15649 courtesy of the office of FCC Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
15650 </para>
15651
15652 <para>
15653 The source of this version of the text is written using DocBook
15654 notation and the other formats are derived from the DocBook source.
15655 The DocBook source is based on a DocBook XML version created by Hans
15656 Schou, and extended with formatting and index references by Petter
15657 Reinholdtsen. The source files of this book is available as
15658 <ulink url="https://github.com/petterreinholdtsen/free-culture-lessig">a
15659 github project</ulink>.
15660 </para>
15661
15662 <para>
15663 &translationblock;
15664 </para>
15665
15666 <para>
15667 Includes index.
15668 </para>
15669
15670 <para>
15671 Classifications: (Dewey)
15672 306.4
15673 306.40973
15674 306.46
15675 341.7582
15676 343.7309/9,
15677 (UDK) 347.78
15678 (US Lib. of Congress) KF2979.L47 2004
15679 (ACM CRCS) K.4.1
15680 </para>
15681
15682 <para>
15683 <informaltable id="isbn">
15684 <tgroup cols="2" align="left">
15685 <thead>
15686 <row>
15687 <entry>ISBN</entry>
15688 <entry>Format / MIME-type</entry>
15689 </row>
15690 </thead>
15691 <tbody>
15692 <row>
15693 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15694 <entry>text/plain</entry>
15695 </row>
15696 <row>
15697 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15698 <entry>application/pdf</entry>
15699 </row>
15700 <row>
15701 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15702 <entry>text/html</entry>
15703 </row>
15704 <row>
15705 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15706 <entry>application/epub+zip</entry>
15707 </row>
15708 <row>
15709 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15710 <entry>application/docbook+xml</entry>
15711 </row>
15712 <row>
15713 <entry>978-82-92812-XX-Y</entry>
15714 <entry>application/x-mobipocket-ebook</entry>
15715 </row>
15716 </tbody>
15717 </tgroup>
15718 </informaltable>
15719 </para>
15720
15721 </colophon>
15722 </book>