1 <?xml version='
1.0' encoding='UTF-
8'
?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href=
"docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type=
"text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012 with input from Martin Borg. -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC
"-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
13 <!ENTITY translationblock
"">
15 <book id=
"index" lang=
"en">
17 <title>Free Culture
</title>
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
21 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
22 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY
</subtitle>
24 <pubdate>2004-
03-
25</pubdate>
26 <releaseinfo>Version
2004-
02-
10</releaseinfo>
30 <firstname>Lawrence
</firstname>
31 <surname>Lessig
</surname>
35 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
36 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
38 <subjectset scheme=
"libraryofcongress">
40 <subjectterm>Intellectual property
—United States.
</subjectterm>
43 <subjectterm>Mass media
—United States.
</subjectterm>
46 <subjectterm>Technological innovations
—United States.
</subjectterm>
49 <subjectterm>Art
—United States.
</subjectterm>
55 <publishername>The Penguin Press
</publishername>
56 <address><city>New York
</city></address>
61 <holder>Lawrence Lessig
</holder>
67 <imagedata fileref=
"images/cc.png" contentdepth=
"3em" width=
"100%" align=
"center"/>
70 <imagedata fileref=
"images/cc.svg" contentdepth=
"3em" width=
"100%" align=
"center"/>
73 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved
</phrase>
79 This version of
<citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle> is licensed under
80 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
81 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
82 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
83 <ulink url=
"http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/
1.0/
</ulink>
88 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR
</title>
91 (
<ulink url=
"http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org
</ulink>),
92 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
93 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
94 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
95 (
<ulink url=
"http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org
</ulink>).
96 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House,
2001) and Code: And
97 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books,
1999), Lessig is a member of
98 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
99 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
100 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
101 twice listed in BusinessWeek's
<quote>e.biz
25,
</quote> and named one of Scientific
102 American's
<quote>50 visionaries.
</quote> A graduate of the University of
103 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
104 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
109 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
110 <mediaobject role=
"cover">
111 <imageobject remap=
"lrg" role=
"front-large">
112 <imagedata fileref=
"images/cover.png" format=
"PNG" width=
"444" />
115 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
116 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
118 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
119 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
121 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
122 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
127 <biblioid class=
"isbn">1-
59420-
006-
8</biblioid>
130 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
132 <biblioid class=
"libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
136 <dedication id=
"salespoints">
139 You can buy a copy of this book by clicking on one of the links below:
141 <itemizedlist mark=
"number" spacing=
"compact">
142 <listitem><para><ulink url=
"http://www.amazon.com/">Amazon
</ulink></para></listitem>
143 <listitem><para><ulink url=
"http://www.barnesandnoble.com/">B
&N
</ulink></para></listitem>
144 <listitem><para><ulink url=
"http://www.penguin.com/">Penguin
</ulink></para></listitem>
145 <!-- <ulink url="">Local Bookstore</ulink> -->
148 <!-- PAGE BREAK 2 -->
149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
150 <dedication id=
"alsobylessig">
153 ALSO BY LAWRENCE LESSIG
156 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
159 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
162 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
163 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
164 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
167 THE PENGUIN PRESS, a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc.
375 Hudson Street New
171 Copyright
© Lawrence Lessig. All rights reserved.
174 Excerpt from an editorial titled
<quote>The Coming of Copyright Perpetuity,
</quote>
175 <citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>, January
16,
2003. Copyright
176 © 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted with permission.
179 Cartoon in
<xref linkend=
"fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/> by Paul Conrad, copyright Tribune
180 Media Services, Inc. All rights reserved. Reprinted with permission.
183 Diagram in
<xref linkend=
"fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership"/> courtesy of the office of FCC
184 Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
187 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
191 Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law to lock down
192 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
201 ISBN
1-
59420-
006-
8 (hardcover)
205 1. Intellectual property
—United States.
2. Mass media
—United States.
208 3. Technological innovations
—United States.
4. Art
—United States. I. Title.
214 343.7309'
9—dc22
217 This book is printed on acid-free paper.
220 Printed in the United States of America
226 Designed by Marysarah Quinn
234 Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of
235 this publication may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a
236 retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means
237 (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise),
238 without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and
239 the above publisher of this book.
242 The scanning, uploading, and distribution of this book via the
243 Internet or via any other means without the permission of the
244 publisher is illegal and punishable by law. Please purchase only
245 authorized electronic editions and do not participate in or encourage
246 electronic piracy of copyrighted materials. Your support of the
247 author's rights is appreciated.
251 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
252 <dedication><title></title>
254 To Eric Eldred
—whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
262 <title>List of figures
</title>
269 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
270 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
271 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
272 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
277 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
281 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
282 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
283 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
284 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
285 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
286 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
290 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
291 2 Architecture and Law: Force
292 2 Market: Concentration
295 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
296 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
297 2 Constraining Creators
298 2 Constraining Innovators
299 2 Corrupting Citizens
301 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
302 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
306 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
307 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
309 2 1. More Formalities
310 3 Registration and Renewal
313 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
314 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
315 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
321 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
323 <preface id=
"preface">
324 <title>PREFACE
</title>
325 <indexterm id='idxpoguedavid' class='startofrange'
><primary>Pogue, David
</primary></indexterm>
327 <emphasis role=
"bold">At the end
</emphasis> of his review of my first
328 book,
<citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
</citetitle>, David
329 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
330 computer-related texts, wrote this:
334 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
335 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
336 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
337 system, you can always flip off the modem.
<footnote id=
"preface01"><para>
338 David Pogue,
<quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
30 January
2000.
343 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book
—that
344 software, or
<quote>code,
</quote> functioned as a kind of law
—and his review
345 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
346 could always
<quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome
</quote>-like simply flip a
347 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
348 any troubles that exist in
<emphasis>that
</emphasis> space wouldn't
349 <quote>affect
</quote> us anymore.
352 Pogue might have been right in
1999—I'm skeptical, but maybe.
353 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
354 <citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
355 causes even after the modem is turned
357 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
358 on-line have fundamentally affected
<quote>people who aren't online.
</quote> There
359 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
361 <indexterm startref='idxpoguedavid' class='endofrange'
/>
363 But unlike
<citetitle>Code
</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
364 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
365 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
366 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
370 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
371 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of
<quote>free culture
</quote>—not
372 <quote>free
</quote> as in
<quote>free beer
</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
373 free software movement
<footnote>
375 Richard M. Stallman,
<citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies
</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed.
2002).
376 </para></footnote>), but
<quote>free
</quote> as in
<quote>free speech,
</quote> <quote>free markets,
</quote>
377 <quote>free trade,
</quote> <quote>free enterprise,
</quote> <quote>free will,
</quote> and
<quote>free elections.
</quote> A
378 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
379 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
380 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
381 follow-on creators and innovators remain
<emphasis>as free as
382 possible
</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
383 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
384 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
385 <quote>permission culture
</quote>—a culture in which creators get to create
386 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
390 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not
<quote>we
</quote>
391 on the Left or
<quote>you
</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
392 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
393 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
394 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
395 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
396 culture deem fundamental.
398 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'
><primary>power, concentration of
</primary></indexterm>
399 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace
</primary></indexterm>
400 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
401 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted
</primary></indexterm>
403 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
404 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
405 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
406 generated more than
700,
000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
407 As William Safire described marching
<quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
408 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
409 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,
</quote> he formulated perhaps
410 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
415 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
416 power
—political, corporate, media, cultural
—should be anathema to
417 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
418 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
419 the greatest expression of democracy.
<footnote><para> William Safire,
420 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
22 May
2003.
421 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
426 This idea is an element of the argument of
<citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle>, though my
427 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
428 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
429 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
430 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
431 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
432 you
—whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
433 Safire's left or on his right.
435 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'
/>
437 <emphasis role=
"strong">The inspiration
</emphasis> for the title and for
438 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
439 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
440 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in
<citetitle>Free Software, Free
441 Society
</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
442 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
443 that this work is
<quote>merely
</quote> derivative.
446 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
447 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
448 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
449 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
450 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
451 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
452 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
453 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
456 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
457 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
458 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
459 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
460 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
464 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
465 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
466 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
467 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
468 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
469 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
470 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
475 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
478 <chapter label=
"0" id=
"c-introduction">
479 <title>INTRODUCTION
</title>
480 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'
><primary>Wright brothers
</primary></indexterm>
482 <emphasis role=
"strong">On December
17</emphasis>,
1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
483 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
484 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
485 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
486 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
487 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
489 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.
</primary></indexterm>
490 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'
><primary>land ownership, air traffic and
</primary></indexterm>
491 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
493 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
494 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
495 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
496 and all the space above, to
<quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.
</quote><footnote><para>
497 St. George Tucker,
<citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries
</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
498 Rothman Reprints,
1969),
18.
501 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
502 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
503 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
505 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'
/>
507 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
508 law
—deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
509 by the most important legal thinkers of our past
—mattered. If
510 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
511 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
512 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
513 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
515 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
516 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
518 In
1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
519 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
520 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
521 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
522 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
523 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
524 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to
<quote>an indefinite
525 extent, upwards,
</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
526 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
528 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
529 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
530 <indexterm id='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='startofrange'
><primary>Douglas, William O.
</primary></indexterm>
531 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='startofrange'
><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on airspace vs. land rights
</secondary></indexterm>
533 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
534 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
535 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
536 <quote>taking
</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
537 that
<quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
538 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.
</quote> But Justice Douglas
539 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
540 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
544 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
545 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
546 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
547 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
548 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
549 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
550 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
551 the public has a just claim.
<footnote>
553 United States v. Causby, U.S.
328 (
1946):
256,
261. The Court did find
554 that there could be a
<quote>taking
</quote> if the government's use of its land
555 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
556 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece,
<quote>(Intellectual)
557 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
558 Authorship,
</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review
</citetitle> 48 (
1996):
1293,
1333. See also Paul
559 Goldstein,
<citetitle>Real Property
</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press,
1984),
561 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
562 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
567 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.
</quote>
569 <indexterm startref='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='endofrange'
/>
571 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
572 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
573 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
575 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line:
<quote>Common sense revolts
576 at the idea.
</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
577 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
578 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
579 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
581 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
582 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
583 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers
</primary></indexterm>
585 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
586 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
587 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
588 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
589 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
590 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
591 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
592 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
593 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by
<quote>what
594 seemed reasonable
</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
595 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
596 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
597 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
598 end, the force of what seems
<quote>obvious
</quote> to everyone else
—the power of
599 <quote>common sense
</quote>—would prevail. Their
<quote>private interest
</quote> would not be
600 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
602 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'
/>
603 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'
/>
604 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'
/>
605 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='endofrange'
/>
606 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'
><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard
</primary></indexterm>
607 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham
</primary></indexterm>
608 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
609 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
610 <indexterm id='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='startofrange'
><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of
</secondary></indexterm>
612 <emphasis role='strong'
>Edwin Howard Armstrong
</emphasis> is one of
613 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
614 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
615 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
616 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
617 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
618 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in
1831. But
619 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
620 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
621 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
625 On the day after Christmas,
1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
626 for his most significant invention
—FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
627 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
628 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
629 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
630 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
631 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
632 much less transmitter power and static.
635 On November
5,
1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
636 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
637 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
638 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
639 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
640 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
641 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
642 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
643 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.
</quote>
646 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
650 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
651 sounded like a glass of water being poured.
… A paper was crumpled
652 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
653 fire.
… Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
654 and guitar number were performed.
… The music was projected with a
655 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio
<quote>music
656 box.
</quote><footnote><para>
657 Lawrence Lessing,
<citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong
</citetitle>
658 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company,
1956),
209.
662 <indexterm id='idxrca' class='startofrange'
><primary>RCA
</primary></indexterm>
663 <indexterm id='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='startofrange'
><primary>media
</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in
</secondary></indexterm>
665 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
666 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
667 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
668 AM radio market. By
1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
669 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
670 a handful of networks.
673 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David
</primary></indexterm>
675 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
676 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
677 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
678 that removed static from
<quote>radio.
</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
679 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
683 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
684 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
685 revolution
— start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
686 RCA.
<footnote><para> See
<quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
687 Electronic Era,
</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
688 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
690 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
1</ulink>.
694 <indexterm id='idxfmradio' class='startofrange'
><primary>FM radio
</primary></indexterm>
695 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David
</primary></indexterm>
697 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
698 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
699 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
702 <indexterm id='idxlessinglawrence' class='startofrange'
><primary>Lessing, Lawrence
</primary></indexterm>
705 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
706 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
707 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
708 unrestrained, posed
… a complete reordering of radio power
709 … and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
710 on which RCA had grown to power.
<footnote><para>Lessing,
226.
714 <indexterm id='idxfcconfmradio' class='startofrange'
><primary>FCC
</primary><secondary>on FM radio
</secondary></indexterm>
716 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
717 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
718 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
719 FM radio's deployment generally. In
1936, RCA hired the former head
720 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
721 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM
—principally by moving FM
722 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
723 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
724 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
725 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
726 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
728 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
731 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
732 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
733 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
734 deviousness.
<footnote><para>
739 <indexterm startref='idxlessinglawrence' class='endofrange'
/>
740 <indexterm><primary>AT
&T
</primary></indexterm>
742 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
743 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
744 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
745 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
746 (This change was strongly supported by AT
&T, because the loss of
747 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
748 wired links from AT
&T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
751 <indexterm startref='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='endofrange'
/>
752 <indexterm startref='idxfcconfmradio' class='endofrange'
/>
754 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
755 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
756 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
757 invalid
—baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
758 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
759 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
760 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
761 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
762 now broke, in
1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
763 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
765 <indexterm startref='idxfmradio' class='endofrange'
/>
766 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'
/>
767 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
768 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
770 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
771 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
772 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
773 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
774 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
775 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
776 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
777 course always public spirited; the reality is something
778 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
779 to themselves, would crumble in
781 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
782 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
783 effect of technological change.
785 <indexterm startref='idxrca' class='endofrange'
/>
786 <indexterm startref='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='endofrange'
/>
787 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>development of
</secondary></indexterm>
789 <emphasis role=
"strong">There's no
</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
790 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
791 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
792 Internet and American Life Project,
58 percent of Americans had access
793 to the Internet in
2002, up from
49 percent two years
794 before.
<footnote><para>
795 Amanda Lenhart,
<quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
796 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,
</quote> Pew Internet and American
797 Life Project,
15 April
2003:
6, available at
798 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
2</ulink>.
800 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
804 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
805 changed things. Some of these changes are technical
—the Internet has
806 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
807 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
808 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
809 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
810 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
811 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
812 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
815 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
816 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
817 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
818 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
819 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
820 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
823 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'
/>
824 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel
</primary></indexterm>
825 <indexterm id='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='startofrange'
><primary>culture
</primary><secondary>commercial vs. noncommercial
</secondary></indexterm>
826 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah
</primary></indexterm>
828 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
829 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
830 regulation of each. By
<quote>commercial culture
</quote> I mean that part of our
831 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
832 <quote>noncommercial culture
</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
834 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
835 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
836 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his
<quote>Reader,
</quote> or
837 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
840 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
841 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
842 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
843 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
844 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
845 left this culture
<quote>free.
</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
846 individuals shared and transformed their culture
—telling
847 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
848 clubs, sharing music, making tapes
—were left alone by the law.
850 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>commercial creativity as primary purpose of
</secondary></indexterm>
852 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
853 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
854 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
855 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
856 marketplace.
<footnote>
858 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
859 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
860 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
861 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
862 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
863 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
864 D. Brandeis,
<quote>The Right to Privacy,
</quote> Harvard Law Review
4 (
1890):
193,
866 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
868 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
869 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
870 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
871 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
873 <indexterm><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
874 <indexterm><primary>permission culture
</primary><secondary> free culture vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
876 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
877 been erased.
<footnote><para>
878 See Jessica Litman,
<citetitle>Digital Copyright
</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
880 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica
</primary></indexterm>
882 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
883 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
884 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
885 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
886 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
887 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
888 the balance of our history
—between uses of our culture that were
889 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission
—has
890 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
891 culture, more and more a permission culture.
893 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
894 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
895 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
896 <indexterm><primary>protection of artists vs. business interests
</primary></indexterm>
898 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
899 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
900 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
901 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
902 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
903 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
904 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
905 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
906 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
907 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
910 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='endofrange'
/>
912 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
913 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
914 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
915 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
916 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
917 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
918 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
919 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
920 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
921 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
922 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
923 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
924 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
925 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
926 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
927 than creators do today
—all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
928 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
931 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
932 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
933 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
934 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
935 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
936 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
939 <indexterm startref='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='endofrange'
/>
940 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack
</primary><secondary> on creative property rights
</secondary></indexterm>
942 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
943 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
944 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
945 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions
—whether
<quote>piracy
</quote> will
946 be permitted, and whether
<quote>property
</quote> will be protected. The
<quote>war
</quote> that
947 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet
—what
948 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
949 calls his
<quote>own terrorist war
</quote><footnote><para>
950 Amy Harmon,
<quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
951 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,
</quote> <citetitle>New York
952 Times
</citetitle>,
17 January
2002.
953 </para></footnote>—has been framed as a battle about the
954 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
955 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
959 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
960 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
961 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
962 <quote>creative property.
</quote> I believe that
<quote>piracy
</quote> is wrong, and that the
963 law, properly tuned, should punish
<quote>piracy,
</quote> whether on or off the
967 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
968 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
969 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet
<quote>pirates
</quote> will also rid our
970 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
972 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>First Amendment to
</secondary></indexterm>
973 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>as protection of creators
</secondary></indexterm>
974 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment
</primary></indexterm>
975 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
977 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first
180 years of
978 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
979 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
980 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
981 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,
<footnote>
983 Neil W. Netanel,
<quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,
</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
984 Journal
</citetitle> 106 (
1996):
283.
985 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
987 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
988 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
989 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
990 could cultivate and extend our culture.
993 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
994 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
995 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
996 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist
–like,
997 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
998 granted
—but it is not often granted to the critical or the
999 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
1000 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
1001 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
1003 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Should "Is it" be "It is" ? -->
1005 The story that follows is about this war. Is it not about the
1006 <quote>centrality of technology
</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
1007 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
1008 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
1009 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
1010 against an industry.
1013 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
1014 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
1015 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
1016 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
1017 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
1018 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
1019 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
1021 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
1022 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
1023 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='startofrange'
><primary>intellectual property rights
</primary></indexterm>
1025 <emphasis role=
"strong">Like the Causbys'
</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about
<quote>property.
</quote> The
1026 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
1027 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
1028 this
<quote>property
</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
1029 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
1030 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
1031 of
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
1032 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
1033 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
1034 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
1035 <quote>trespassing
</quote> upon legitimate claims of
<quote>property.
</quote> It is as plain to
1036 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
1039 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
1040 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
1041 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers
</primary></indexterm>
1043 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
1044 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
1045 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
1046 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
1048 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
1049 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
1052 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of
</primary></indexterm>
1054 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
1055 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
1056 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
1057 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
1058 our
<quote>culture
</quote> was as
<quote>owned
</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
1059 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
1060 <emphasis>uses
</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
1061 accepted as it is now.
1064 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
1065 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
1066 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
1067 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1070 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1071 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1074 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1075 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1076 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1077 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1078 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1081 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1082 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1083 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1084 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1087 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
1088 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
1090 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1091 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1092 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1093 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of
<quote>intellectual
1094 property.
</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1095 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1096 this silliness will be much more profound.
1097 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1099 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='endofrange'
/>
1101 <emphasis role=
"strong">The struggle
</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas:
<quote>piracy
</quote> and
1102 <quote>property.
</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1106 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1107 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1108 obscure French theorists
—however natural that is for the weird
1109 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1110 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1111 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1114 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1115 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1116 government, pushed by big media to respond to this
<quote>something new,
</quote> is
1117 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1118 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let
<quote>common
1119 sense
</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1120 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1121 law
—and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1122 fundamental about who we have always been.
1125 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1126 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1127 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1128 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1129 of one more consequence of this form of corruption
—a consequence
1130 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1133 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1134 <part id=
"c-piracy">
1135 <title><quote>PIRACY
</quote></title>
1137 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1138 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>English
</secondary></indexterm>
1139 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord
</primary></indexterm>
1140 <indexterm><primary>music publishing
</primary></indexterm>
1141 <indexterm><primary>sheet music
</primary></indexterm>
1143 <emphasis role=
"strong">Since the inception
</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1144 been a war against
<quote>piracy.
</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1145 <quote>piracy,
</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1146 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1147 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1151 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1152 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1153 of them for his own use.
<footnote><para>
1155 <citetitle>Bach
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Longman
</citetitle>,
98 Eng. Rep.
1274 (
1777) (Mansfield).
1158 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='endofrange'
/>
1160 <indexterm><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary> efficient content distribution on
</secondary></indexterm>
1161 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='startofrange'
><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing
</primary><secondary>efficiency of
</secondary></indexterm>
1163 Today we are in the middle of another
<quote>war
</quote> against
<quote>piracy.
</quote> The
1164 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1165 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1166 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1167 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1168 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1169 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1172 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1173 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1174 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1175 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1176 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will
<quote>rob the author of the
1179 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='endofrange'
/>
1181 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1182 increasingly to technology to defend their
<quote>property
</quote> against this
1183 <quote>piracy.
</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1184 raised to believe that
<quote>property
</quote> should be
<quote>free.
</quote> Forget tattoos,
1185 never mind body piercing
—our kids are becoming
1186 <emphasis>thieves
</emphasis>!
1189 There's no doubt that
<quote>piracy
</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1190 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1191 notion of
<quote>piracy
</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1192 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1195 The idea goes something like this:
1199 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1200 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1201 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1202 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1203 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1207 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP
</primary></indexterm>
1208 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle
</primary></indexterm>
1209 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts
</primary></indexterm>
1210 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='startofrange'
><primary>creative property
</primary><secondary><quote>if value, then right
</quote> theory of
</secondary></indexterm>
1211 <indexterm id='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='startofrange'
><primary><quote>if value, then right
</quote> theory
</primary></indexterm>
1213 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1214 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the
<quote>if value, then right
</quote>
1215 theory of creative property
<footnote><para>
1217 See Rochelle Dreyfuss,
<quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1218 in the Pepsi Generation,
</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review
</citetitle> 65 (
1990):
397.
1220 —if there is value, then someone must have a
1221 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1222 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1223 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.
<footnote><para>
1225 Lisa Bannon,
<quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1226 Up,
</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal
</citetitle>,
21 August
1996, available at
1227 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
3</ulink>; Jonathan
1228 Zittrain,
<quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1229 Speech, No One Wins,
</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe
</citetitle>,
24 November
2002.
1230 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
1232 There was
<quote>value
</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1233 <quote>right
</quote>—even against the Girl Scouts.
1235 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='endofrange'
/>
1237 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1238 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1239 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1240 of law protecting creative property. But the
<quote>if value, then right
</quote>
1241 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1242 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1244 <indexterm startref='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='endofrange'
/>
1245 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
1246 <indexterm id='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='startofrange'
><primary>creativity
</primary><secondary>legal restrictions on
</secondary></indexterm>
1248 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1249 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1250 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1251 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1252 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1255 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1256 takes care to draw
—the distinction between republishing someone's
1257 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1258 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1259 copyright law today regulates both.
1261 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='endofrange'
/>
1263 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1264 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1265 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1266 entities could bear the burden of the law
—even the burden of the
1267 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1268 more expense of doing business.
1270 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>creativity impeded by
</secondary></indexterm>
1271 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
1272 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)
</primary></indexterm>
1274 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1275 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1276 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1277 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1278 <quote>copying,
</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1279 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1280 outweighs any original benefit
—certainly as it affects
1281 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1282 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1283 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1284 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1285 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1286 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1287 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1288 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1289 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1290 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the
<quote>Rise of the Creative
1291 Class.
</quote><footnote>
1294 In
<citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class
</citetitle> (New York:
1295 Basic Books,
2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1296 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1297 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1298 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1299 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1300 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1302 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
1303 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)
</primary></indexterm>
1305 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1306 this creative class.
1308 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='endofrange'
/>
1310 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1311 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1312 context the current battles about behavior labeled
<quote>piracy.
</quote>
1316 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1317 <chapter label=
"1" id=
"creators">
1318 <title>CHAPTER ONE: Creators
</title>
1319 <indexterm id='idxanimatedcartoons' class='startofrange'
><primary>animated cartoons
</primary></indexterm>
1320 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'
><primary>cartoon films
</primary></indexterm>
1321 <indexterm id='idxfilmsanimated' class='startofrange'
><primary>films
</primary><secondary>animated
</secondary></indexterm>
1322 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatwillie' class='startofrange'
><primary>Steamboat Willie
</primary></indexterm>
1323 <indexterm id='idxmickeymouse' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mickey Mouse
</primary></indexterm>
1325 <emphasis role=
"strong">In
1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1326 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called
<citetitle>Plane Crazy
</citetitle>.
1327 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1328 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound,
<citetitle>Steamboat Willie
</citetitle> brought
1329 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1331 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1333 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1334 movie
<citetitle>The Jazz Singer
</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1335 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1336 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1337 Disney ran a test in the summer of
1928, the results were unambiguous.
1338 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1342 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1343 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1344 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1345 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1346 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1349 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1350 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1351 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1352 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1353 synchronization was pretty close.
1356 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1357 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1358 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1359 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1360 it was something new!
<footnote><para>
1362 Leonard Maltin,
<citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1363 Cartoons
</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books,
1987),
34–35.
1367 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub
</primary></indexterm>
1369 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1370 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly:
<quote>I have never been so thrilled
1371 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.
</quote>
1374 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1375 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1376 rarely
—except in Disney's hands
—been anything more than
1377 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1378 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1379 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1380 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1382 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt' class='endofrange'
/>
1383 <indexterm id='idxkeatonbuster' class='startofrange'
><primary>Keaton, Buster
</primary></indexterm>
1384 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='startofrange'
><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
1386 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that
1928 also marks
1387 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1388 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1389 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was
<citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr
</citetitle>.
1392 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in
1895. In the era of silent
1393 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1394 uncontrollable laughter from his audience.
<citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1395 Jr
</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1396 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton
—wildly popular
1397 and among the best of its genre.
1399 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1400 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1402 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr
</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1404 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1405 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1406 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,
<footnote><para>
1408 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1409 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
4</ulink>.
1410 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1411 use the music for five songs in
<citetitle>Steamboat Willie
</citetitle>:
<quote>Steamboat Bill,
</quote> <quote>The
1412 Simpleton
</quote> (Delille),
<quote>Mischief Makers
</quote> (Carbonara),
<quote>Joyful Hurry No.
1</quote>
1413 (Baron), and
<quote>Gawky Rube
</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song,
<quote>The Turkey in the
1414 Straw,
</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1415 Harry Surden,
10 July
2003, on file with author.
1417 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1418 the invention of synchronized sound in
<citetitle>The Jazz Singer
</citetitle> that we
1419 get
<citetitle>Steamboat Willie
</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1420 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song
<quote>Steamboat Bill,
</quote>
1421 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1424 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatwillie' class='endofrange'
/>
1425 <indexterm startref='idxmickeymouse' class='endofrange'
/>
1426 <indexterm startref='idxkeatonbuster' class='endofrange'
/>
1427 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='endofrange'
/>
1428 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='startofrange'
><primary>creativity
</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works
</secondary></indexterm>
1429 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Inc.
</primary></indexterm>
1431 This
<quote>borrowing
</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1432 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1433 films of his day.
<footnote><para>
1435 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman,
<quote>The Mouse
1436 that Ate the Public Domain,
</quote> Findlaw,
5 March
2002, at
1437 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
5</ulink>.
1439 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1440 knockoffs
—slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1441 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1442 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1443 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1444 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1445 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1446 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1449 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales' class='startofrange'
><primary>Grimm fairy tales
</primary></indexterm>
1451 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1452 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1453 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1454 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1455 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1456 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1457 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1460 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1461 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1462 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1463 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1464 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1465 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1466 work of others is astonishing when set together:
<citetitle>Snow White
</citetitle>
1467 (
1937),
<citetitle>Fantasia
</citetitle> (
1940),
<citetitle>Pinocchio
</citetitle> (
1940),
<citetitle>Dumbo
</citetitle>
1468 (
1941),
<citetitle>Bambi
</citetitle> (
1942),
<citetitle>Song of the South
</citetitle> (
1946),
1469 <citetitle>Cinderella
</citetitle> (
1950),
<citetitle>Alice in Wonderland
</citetitle> (
1951),
<citetitle>Robin
1470 Hood
</citetitle> (
1952),
<citetitle>Peter Pan
</citetitle> (
1953),
<citetitle>Lady and the Tramp
</citetitle>
1471 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1472 (
1955),
<citetitle>Mulan
</citetitle> (
1998),
<citetitle>Sleeping Beauty
</citetitle> (
1959),
<citetitle>101
1473 Dalmatians
</citetitle> (
1961),
<citetitle>The Sword in the Stone
</citetitle> (
1963), and
1474 <citetitle>The Jungle Book
</citetitle> (
1967)
—not to mention a recent example
1475 that we should perhaps quickly forget,
<citetitle>Treasure Planet
</citetitle>
1476 (
2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1477 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1478 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1479 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1481 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales' class='endofrange'
/>
1483 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1484 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1485 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1486 its importance. We could call this
<quote>Disney creativity,
</quote> though that
1487 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely,
<quote>Walt Disney
1488 creativity
</quote>—a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1489 culture around us and makes it something different.
1491 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='endofrange'
/>
1492 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='endofrange'
/>
1493 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='endofrange'
/>
1494 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
1495 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>defined
</secondary></indexterm>
1496 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>traditional term for conversion to
</secondary></indexterm>
1497 <para> In
1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1498 relatively fresh. The public domain in
1928 was not very old and was
1499 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1500 thirty years
—for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1501 copyrighted.
<footnote><para>
1503 Until
1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1504 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the
<quote>average
</quote> term by
1506 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1507 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if
100 copyrights are registered in year
1508 1, and only
15 are renewed, and the renewal term is
28 years, then the
1510 term is
32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1511 Web site associated with this book, available at
1512 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
6</ulink>.
1514 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1515 copyright holders of a creative work had an
<quote>exclusive right
</quote> to control
1516 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1517 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1520 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1521 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1522 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a
<quote>lawyer-free
1523 zone.
</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1524 for Disney to use and build upon in
1928. It was free for
1525 anyone
— whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1526 approved or not
—to use and build upon.
1528 <indexterm startref='idxanimatedcartoons' class='endofrange'
/>
1529 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsanimated' class='endofrange'
/>
1531 This is the ways things always were
—until quite recently. For most
1532 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1533 until
1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1534 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1536 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1537 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1538 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the
1960s and
1970s
1539 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1540 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1541 content from before the Great Depression.
1543 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'
/>
1544 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc' class='endofrange'
/>
1545 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='endofrange'
/>
1546 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='endofrange'
/>
1547 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='endofrange'
/>
1548 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1550 <emphasis role=
"strong">Of course
</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on
<quote>Walt Disney creativity.
</quote>
1551 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1552 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1555 <indexterm id='idxcomicsjapanese' class='startofrange'
><primary>comics, Japanese
</primary></indexterm>
1556 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1557 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics' class='startofrange'
><primary>Japanese comics
</primary></indexterm>
1558 <indexterm id='idxmanga' class='startofrange'
><primary>manga
</primary></indexterm>
1559 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1561 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1562 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture:
<citetitle>manga
</citetitle>, or
1563 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some
40 percent of
1564 publications are comics, and
30 percent of publication revenue derives
1565 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1566 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1567 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1570 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1571 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1572 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1573 the stories that these
<quote>graphic novels
</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1574 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are
<quote>men in tights.
</quote>
1575 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1576 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1577 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1578 interestingly different way.
1581 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1582 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1583 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1585 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='startofrange'
><primary>creativity
</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works
</secondary></indexterm>
1586 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics' class='startofrange'
><primary>doujinshi comics
</primary></indexterm>
1588 This is the phenomenon of
<citetitle>doujinshi
</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1589 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1590 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is
<emphasis>just
</emphasis> a
1591 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1592 transforming it either subtly or
1593 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1594 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1595 develop it differently
—with a different story line. Or the comic can
1596 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1597 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently
<quote>different.
</quote> But they
1598 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1599 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1600 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1602 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1604 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1605 huge. More than
33,
000 <quote>circles
</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1606 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than
450,
000 Japanese come
1607 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1608 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1609 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1610 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1611 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1612 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1614 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>Japanese
</secondary></indexterm>
1615 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
1617 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1618 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1619 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1620 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1621 one. Doujinshi are plainly
<quote>derivative works.
</quote> There is no general
1622 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1623 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1624 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with
<citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1625 Jr
</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that
<quote>taking
</quote> without
1626 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1627 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1628 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1630 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt2' class='endofrange'
/>
1631 <indexterm id='idxwinickjudd' class='startofrange'
><primary>Winick, Judd
</primary></indexterm>
1633 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1634 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1635 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me,
<quote>The
1636 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1637 in Japan now.
… American comics were born out of copying each
1638 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1639 other.
… That's how [the artists] learn to draw
—by going into comic
1640 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them
</quote>
1641 and building from them.
<footnote><para>
1643 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud,
<citetitle>Reinventing Comics
</citetitle> (New
1644 York: Perennial,
2000).
1647 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='endofrange'
/>
1648 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics
</primary></indexterm>
1650 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1651 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1652 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me,
<quote>there are these rules
1653 and you have to stick to them.
</quote> There are things Superman
<quote>cannot
</quote>
1654 do.
<quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1655 which are fifty years old.
</quote>
1657 <indexterm startref='idxwinickjudd' class='endofrange'
/>
1658 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>Japanese
</secondary></indexterm>
1659 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese
</primary></indexterm>
1660 <indexterm id='idxmehrasalil' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mehra, Salil
</primary></indexterm>
1662 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1663 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1664 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1665 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1666 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1667 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1668 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.
<footnote><para>
1670 See Salil K. Mehra,
<quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1671 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?
</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1672 Review
</citetitle> 55 (
2002):
155,
182.
<quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1673 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1674 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1675 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1676 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1677 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.
</quote>
1680 <indexterm startref='idxcomicsjapanese' class='endofrange'
/>
1681 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics' class='endofrange'
/>
1682 <indexterm startref='idxmanga' class='endofrange'
/>
1684 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1685 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1686 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1687 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1688 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1689 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1690 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1691 a more general pattern of blocking this
<quote>free taking
</quote> by the doujinshi
1694 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='endofrange'
/>
1695 <indexterm startref='idxmehrasalil' class='endofrange'
/>
1697 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1698 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1699 a friend from a major Japanese law firm.
<quote>We don't have enough
1700 lawyers,
</quote> he told me one afternoon. There
<quote>just aren't enough resources
1701 to prosecute cases like this.
</quote>
1704 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1705 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1706 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1707 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1708 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1709 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1710 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1711 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1712 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1713 their clients or hurt them?
1715 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics' class='endofrange'
/>
1717 <emphasis role='strong'
>Let's pause
</emphasis> for a moment.
1720 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1721 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1722 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1725 We live in a world that celebrates
<quote>property.
</quote> I am one of those
1726 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1727 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1728 <quote>intellectual property.
</quote><footnote><para>
1730 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
1731 The term
<citetitle>intellectual property
</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1732 Siva Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
11 (New York: New York
1733 University Press,
2001). See also Lawrence Lessig,
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle>
1734 (New York: Random House,
2001),
293 n.
26. The term accurately
1735 describes a set of
<quote>property
</quote> rights
—copyright, patents,
1736 trademark, and trade-secret
—but the nature of those rights is
1739 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1740 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1743 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt3' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1744 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Grimm fairy tales
</primary></indexterm>
1745 <indexterm><primary>Keaton, Buster
</primary></indexterm>
1747 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1748 plenty of value out there that
<quote>property
</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1749 mean
<quote>money can't buy you love,
</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1750 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1751 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1752 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1753 condemning that taking as wrong
— even though trivial, even if
1754 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1755 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1756 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1757 Disney's use would have been considered
<quote>fair.
</quote> There was nothing
1758 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1761 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='startofrange'
><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary>derivative works based on
</secondary></indexterm>
1763 Thus, even though the things that Disney took
—or more generally,
1764 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity
—are
1765 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1767 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1768 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1771 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='endofrange'
/>
1772 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>Japanese
</secondary></indexterm>
1773 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese
</primary></indexterm>
1774 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='startofrange'
><primary>doujinshi comics
</primary></indexterm>
1775 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Japanese comics
</primary></indexterm>
1776 <indexterm id='idxmanga2' class='startofrange'
><primary>manga
</primary></indexterm>
1778 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1779 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1780 work
—or even one copy
—without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1781 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1782 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1783 form, whether large or small.
1785 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='endofrange'
/>
1787 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1788 say that the copycat comic artists are
<quote>stealing.
</quote> This form of Walt
1789 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1790 particular find it hard to say why.
1792 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='endofrange'
/>
1793 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='endofrange'
/>
1794 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='endofrange'
/>
1795 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='endofrange'
/>
1796 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics2' class='endofrange'
/>
1797 <indexterm startref='idxmanga2' class='endofrange'
/>
1798 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
1800 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1801 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1802 without asking or paying for the privilege. (
<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1803 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1804 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?
</quote>) Acting companies
1805 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1806 permission from anyone. (Does
<emphasis>anyone
</emphasis> believe
1807 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1808 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1809 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1810 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late
1990s;
1811 two volcano disaster films in
1997.
1814 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1815 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1816 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1817 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1818 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1819 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1820 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking
—free
1821 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1822 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1824 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt3' class='endofrange'
/>
1826 The hard question is therefore not
<emphasis>whether
</emphasis> a
1827 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1828 question instead is
<quote><emphasis>How
</emphasis> free is this culture?
</quote>
1829 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1830 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1831 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1832 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1833 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1834 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1838 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1839 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1840 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1842 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='endofrange'
/>
1844 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1846 <chapter label=
"2" id=
"mere-copyists">
1847 <title>CHAPTER TWO:
<quote>Mere Copyists
</quote></title>
1848 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis
</primary></indexterm>
1849 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology' class='startofrange'
><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
1850 <indexterm id='idxphotography' class='startofrange'
><primary>photography
</primary></indexterm>
1852 <emphasis role='strong'
>In
1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1853 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1854 <quote>photographs.
</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1855 <quote>daguerreotypes.
</quote> The process was complicated and
1856 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1857 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1858 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1859 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1861 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William
</primary></indexterm>
1863 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1864 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1865 <quote>automatic pictures.
</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1866 making
<quote>negatives.
</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1867 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1868 the
1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1869 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1870 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1873 <indexterm id='idxeastmangeorge' class='startofrange'
><primary>Eastman, George
</primary></indexterm>
1875 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1876 didn't happen until
1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1877 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1878 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1879 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1880 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1881 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1882 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1883 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1884 population of photographers.
1886 <indexterm id='idxkodakcameras' class='startofrange'
><primary>Kodak cameras
</primary></indexterm>
1887 <indexterm id='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='startofrange'
><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)
</primary></indexterm>
1889 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1890 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1891 marketed on the basis of its simplicity.
<quote>You press the button and we
1892 do the rest.
</quote><footnote><para>
1894 Reese V. Jenkins,
<citetitle>Images and Enterprise
</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1975),
112.
1895 </para></footnote> As he described in
<citetitle>The Kodak Primer
</citetitle>:
1899 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1900 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1901 that only an expert can do.
… We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1902 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1903 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1904 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1905 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1906 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1907 chemicals.
<footnote>
1910 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian
</primary></indexterm>
1911 Brian Coe,
<citetitle>The Birth of Photography
</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1916 <indexterm startref='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='endofrange'
/>
1918 For $
25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1919 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1920 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1921 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1922 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1923 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in
1888; one
1924 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1925 From
1888 through
1909, while industrial production was rising by
4.7
1926 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by
11
1927 percent.
<footnote><para>
1930 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1931 an average annual increase of over
17 percent.
<footnote><para>
1933 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p.
178.
1936 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian
</primary></indexterm>
1939 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1940 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1941 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1942 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1943 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1944 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes,
<quote>For the
1945 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1946 permanent record of his family and its activities.
… For the first
1947 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1948 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1949 interpretation or bias.
</quote><footnote><para>
1954 <indexterm><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression
</secondary></indexterm>
1955 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>democratic
</secondary></indexterm>
1957 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1958 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1959 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1960 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1961 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1962 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its
<quote>quality
</quote>;
1963 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1964 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1965 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1966 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1969 <indexterm startref='idxkodakcameras' class='endofrange'
/>
1970 <indexterm id='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='startofrange'
><primary>permissions
</primary><secondary>photography exempted from
</secondary></indexterm>
1972 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1973 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1974 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1975 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1976 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1977 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1978 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1979 he wanted. Their answer was no.
<footnote><para>
1981 For illustrative cases, see, for example,
<citetitle>Pavesich
</citetitle>
1982 v.
<citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co
</citetitle>.,
50 S.E.
68 (Ga.
1905);
1983 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Chinn
</citetitle>,
123090 S.W.
364,
366
1984 (Ky.
1909);
<citetitle>Corliss
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Walker
</citetitle>,
64 F.
280 (Mass.
1988 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology' class='endofrange'
/>
1989 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt4' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1990 <indexterm id='idximagesownershipof' class='startofrange'
><primary>images, ownership of
</primary></indexterm>
1992 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1993 familiar. The photographer was
<quote>taking
</quote> something from the person or
1994 building whose photograph he shot
—pirating something of
1995 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1996 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1998 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1999 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
2000 that they thought valuable.
2002 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
2003 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
2004 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology2' class='startofrange'
><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
2006 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
2007 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
2008 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
2009 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
2010 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.
<footnote>
2013 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis,
<quote>The Right to Privacy,
</quote>
2014 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review
</citetitle> 4 (
1890):
193.
2015 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
2016 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.
</primary></indexterm>
2017 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
2018 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
2019 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr
</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
2020 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
2022 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt4' class='endofrange'
/>
2024 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
2025 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
2026 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
2027 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
2028 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
2029 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
2030 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
2031 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
2032 clearing the rights to do the capturing.
<footnote><para>
2034 See Melville B. Nimmer,
<quote>The Right of Publicity,
</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
2035 Problems
</citetitle> 19 (
1954):
203; William L. Prosser,
<quote>Privacy,
</quote> <citetitle>California Law
2036 Review
</citetitle> 48 (
1960)
398–407;
<citetitle>White
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
2037 Inc
</citetitle>.,
971 F.
2d
1395 (
9th Cir.
1992), cert. denied,
508 U.S.
951
2041 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras
</primary></indexterm>
2042 <indexterm><primary>Napster
</primary></indexterm>
2044 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
2045 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
2046 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
2047 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
2048 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
2049 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
2050 Kodak would be benefiting from the
<quote>theft
</quote> committed by the
2051 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
2052 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
2053 from the
<quote>image-right
</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
2054 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
2055 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
2056 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
2058 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology2' class='endofrange'
/>
2059 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology3' class='startofrange'
><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
2060 <indexterm><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression
</secondary></indexterm>
2061 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>democratic
</secondary></indexterm>
2064 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
2065 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
2066 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
2067 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
2068 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
2069 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
2070 technology as they did
—since professionals could have more
2071 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
2072 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
2073 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
2074 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
2077 <indexterm startref='idxphotography' class='endofrange'
/>
2078 <indexterm startref='idxeastmangeorge' class='endofrange'
/>
2079 <indexterm startref='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='endofrange'
/>
2080 <indexterm startref='idximagesownershipof' class='endofrange'
/>
2082 <emphasis role='strong'
>If you drive
</emphasis> through San
2083 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
2084 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
2085 <quote>Just Think!
</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
2086 there's little that's
<quote>just
</quote> cerebral in the projects
2087 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
2088 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
2089 the film of your VCR. Rather the
<quote>film
</quote> of digital
2090 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
2091 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
2092 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
2093 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
2094 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
2095 think. By tinkering, they learn.
2098 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
2099 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
2100 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it,
<quote>Five years ago, a good
2101 real-time digital video editing system cost $
25,
000. Today you can get
2102 professional quality for $
595.
</quote><footnote><para>
2104 H. Edward Goldberg,
<quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
2105 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,
</quote>
2106 cadalyst, February
2002, available at
2107 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
7</ulink>.
2109 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
2110 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
2111 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
2112 learning more and more of something teachers call
<quote>media literacy.
</quote>
2114 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave
</primary></indexterm>
2116 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
2117 <quote>Media literacy,
</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
2118 Think!, puts it,
<quote>is the ability
… to understand, analyze, and
2119 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2120 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2121 the way people access it.
</quote>
2124 This may seem like an odd way to think about
<quote>literacy.
</quote> For most
2125 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2126 and noticing split infinitives are the things that
<quote>literate
</quote> people know
2129 <indexterm><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
2130 <indexterm><primary>commercials
</primary></indexterm>
2131 <indexterm><primary>television
</primary><secondary>advertising on
</secondary></indexterm>
2133 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average
390 hours of
2134 television commercials per year, or between
20,
000 and
45,
000
2135 commercials generally,
<footnote><para>
2137 Judith Van Evra,
<citetitle>Television and Child Development
</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2138 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates,
1990);
<quote>Findings on Family and TV
2139 Study,
</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post
</citetitle>,
25 May
1997, B6.
2141 it is increasingly important to understand the
<quote>grammar
</quote> of media. For
2142 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2143 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2144 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2145 (at least at first) terrible media.
2148 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2149 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2150 has written understands how difficult writing is
—how difficult
2151 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2152 language to be understandable
—few of us have any real sense of
2153 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2154 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2155 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2157 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology3' class='endofrange'
/>
2159 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2160 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2161 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2162 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2163 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2164 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2166 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
2167 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='startofrange'
><primary>Daley, Elizabeth
</primary></indexterm>
2169 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2170 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2171 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2173 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2174 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2175 about
<quote>the placement of objects, color,
… rhythm, pacing, and
2176 texture.
</quote><footnote>
2179 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish,
13 December
2181 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2182 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth
</primary></indexterm>
2184 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2185 <quote>played
</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2186 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2187 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2188 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2189 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2190 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2191 to a wildly successful author.
<footnote><para>
2193 See Scott Steinberg,
<quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,
</quote> E!online,
4
2194 November
2000, available at
2195 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
8</ulink>;
<quote>Timeline,
</quote> 22 November
2000,
2197 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
9</ulink>.
2200 <indexterm><primary>computer games
</primary></indexterm>
2202 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2203 describes,
<quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2204 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2205 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2206 led.
</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2209 Yet the push for an expanded literacy
—one that goes beyond text
2210 to include audio and visual elements
—is not about making better
2211 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2212 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2216 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2217 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2218 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2219 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2224 <quote>Read-only.
</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2225 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2229 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2230 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2231 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2232 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2234 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2235 and this literacy in particular, is to
<quote>empower people to choose the
2236 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2237 express.
</quote><footnote>
2240 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2241 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2242 </para></footnote> It is to enable students
<quote>to communicate in the
2243 language of the twenty-first century.
</quote><footnote><para>
2248 <indexterm id='idxbarishstephanie' class='startofrange'
><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2250 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2251 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2252 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2253 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2254 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2255 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2256 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2257 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2258 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2259 students know something about
—gun violence.
2261 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='endofrange'
/>
2263 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2264 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2265 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2266 away. The
<quote>kids were showing up at
6 A.M. and leaving at
5 at night,
</quote>
2267 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2268 what education should be about
—learning how to express themselves.
2271 Using whatever
<quote>free web stuff they could find,
</quote> and relatively simple
2272 tools to enable the kids to mix
<quote>image, sound, and text,
</quote> Barish said
2273 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2274 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2275 close to the lives of these students. The project
<quote>gave them a tool
2276 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2277 it,
</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2278 expression
—far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2279 been created using only text.
<quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2280 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2281 gone and done something else,
</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2282 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2283 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2284 <emphasis>these
</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2285 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2287 <indexterm startref='idxbarishstephanie' class='endofrange'
/>
2290 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2291 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?
</quote> I asked. In part,
2292 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2293 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of
<quote>constructing
2294 meaning.
</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2295 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2296 part
—and increasingly, not the most powerful part
—of
2297 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2302 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2303 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2304 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2305 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2306 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2307 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2308 you say,
<quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.
</quote>
2309 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2310 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2311 you. [But i]nstead, if you say,
<quote>Well, with all these things that you
2312 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2313 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2314 for me something that reflects that.
</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2315 camera and
… saying,
<quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2316 make a little movie.
</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2317 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2318 about the topic.
…
2321 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2322 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2323 bump up against the fact,
<quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2324 to write something.
</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2325 they would rewrite a paragraph
5,
6,
7,
8 times, till they got it right.
2328 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2329 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2330 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2331 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2332 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2333 had a lot of power with this language.
2335 <!-- FIXME removed a " from the end of the previous paragraph that did
2336 not match with any start quote. -->
2338 <indexterm id='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='startofrange'
><primary>September
11,
2001, terrorist attacks of
</primary></indexterm>
2339 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center
</primary></indexterm>
2340 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage' class='startofrange'
><primary>news coverage
</primary></indexterm>
2342 <emphasis role='strong'
>When two planes
</emphasis> crashed into the
2343 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2344 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2345 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2346 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2347 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2348 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2349 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2350 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2354 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2355 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2356 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was
<quote>balance,
</quote>
2357 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2358 increasingly come to expect it,
<quote>news as entertainment,
</quote> even if the
2359 entertainment is tragedy.
2361 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
2362 <indexterm><primary>CBS
</primary></indexterm>
2364 But in addition to this produced news about the
<quote>tragedy of September
2365 11,
</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2366 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2367 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2368 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2369 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2370 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2371 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2372 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2373 the term in his book
<citetitle>Cyber Rights
</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2374 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2375 was also the Internet.
2377 <indexterm startref='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='endofrange'
/>
2379 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet
—though I do think the
2380 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2381 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2382 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2384 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2385 by a student on the
<quote>Just Think!
</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2389 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2390 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2391 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2392 tradition
—not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2393 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2394 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2395 spread practically instantaneously.
2397 <indexterm><primary>September
11,
2001, terrorist attacks of
</primary></indexterm>
2398 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs' class='startofrange'
><primary>blogs (Web-logs)
</primary></indexterm>
2399 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>blogs on
</secondary></indexterm>
2400 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs' class='startofrange'
><primary>Web-logs (blogs)
</primary></indexterm>
2402 September
11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2403 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2404 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2405 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2406 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2407 cultures, it records private facts in a public way
—it's a kind
2408 of electronic
<citetitle>Jerry Springer
</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2410 <indexterm><primary>political discourse
</primary></indexterm>
2411 <indexterm id='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>public discourse conducted on
</secondary></indexterm>
2413 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2414 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2415 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2416 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2417 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2418 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2419 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2420 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2421 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2422 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2423 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2424 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2426 <indexterm id='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='startofrange'
><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression
</secondary></indexterm>
2427 <indexterm id='idxelections' class='startofrange'
><primary>elections
</primary></indexterm>
2428 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='startofrange'
><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>democratic
</secondary></indexterm>
2430 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2431 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2432 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2433 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2434 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2436 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2437 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2438 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2440 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs' class='endofrange'
/>
2441 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson' class='endofrange'
/>
2442 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs' class='endofrange'
/>
2443 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de
</primary></indexterm>
2444 <indexterm id='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='startofrange'
><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>public discourse in
</secondary></indexterm>
2445 <indexterm><primary>jury system
</primary></indexterm>
2447 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2448 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2449 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2450 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2451 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2452 most important account of early
<quote>Democracy in America.
</quote> It wasn't
2453 popular elections that fascinated him
—it was the jury, an
2454 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2455 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2456 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2457 deliberated. Members argued about the
<quote>right
</quote> result; they tried to
2458 persuade each other of the
<quote>right
</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2459 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2460 come to an end.
<footnote><para>
2462 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville,
<citetitle>Democracy in America
</citetitle>,
2463 bk.
1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books,
2000), ch.
16.
2466 <indexterm startref='idxelections' class='endofrange'
/>
2468 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2469 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2470 are pushing to create just such an institution.
<footnote><para>
2472 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin,
<quote>Deliberation Day,
</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2473 Political Philosophy
</citetitle> 10 (
2) (
2002):
129.
2475 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2476 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2477 place for
<quote>democratic deliberation
</quote> to occur.
2479 <indexterm id='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='startofrange'
><primary>political discourse
</primary></indexterm>
2481 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2482 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2483 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2484 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2485 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2486 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.
<footnote><para>
2488 Cass Sunstein,
<citetitle>Republic.com
</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2001),
2489 65–80,
175,
182,
183,
192.
2490 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2491 little beyond what our friends say.
2493 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>blogs (Web-logs)
</primary></indexterm>
2494 <indexterm><primary>e-mail
</primary></indexterm>
2495 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>blogs on
</secondary></indexterm>
2496 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Web-logs (blogs)
</primary></indexterm>
2497 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='endofrange'
/>
2498 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='endofrange'
/>
2499 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='endofrange'
/>
2501 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2502 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2503 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2504 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2505 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2507 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2508 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2512 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2513 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2514 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2515 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2516 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2517 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2519 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard
</primary></indexterm>
2521 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2522 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the
2004 presidential race
2523 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2524 is having an effect.
2526 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent
</primary></indexterm>
2527 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom
</primary></indexterm>
2528 <indexterm id='idxmediablogpressureon' class='startofrange'
><primary>media
</primary><secondary>blog pressure on
</secondary></indexterm>
2529 <indexterm id='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>news events on
</secondary></indexterm>
2531 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2532 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2533 <quote>misspoke
</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2534 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2535 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2536 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2537 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2538 more instances of the same
<quote>misspeaking
</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2539 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2540 resign as senate majority leader.
<footnote><para>
2542 Noah Shachtman,
<quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,
</quote> New
2543 York Times,
16 January
2003, G5.
2546 <indexterm id='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>media
</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of
</secondary></indexterm>
2548 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2549 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2550 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2551 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2554 <indexterm startref='idxmediablogpressureon' class='endofrange'
/>
2555 <indexterm><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>peer-generated rankings on
</secondary></indexterm>
2557 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2558 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2559 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2560 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2561 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2562 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2563 peer-generated rankings.
2565 <indexterm startref='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='endofrange'
/>
2566 <indexterm id='idxjournalism' class='startofrange'
><primary>journalism
</primary></indexterm>
2567 <indexterm id='idxwinerdave' class='startofrange'
><primary>Winer, Dave
</primary></indexterm>
2569 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2570 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2571 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2572 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2573 difference is the absence of a financial
<quote>conflict of interest.
</quote> <quote>I think you
2574 have to take the conflict of interest
</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2575 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2576 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2577 get it out of the way.
</quote>
2579 <indexterm><primary>CNN
</primary></indexterm>
2580 <indexterm><primary>media
</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of
</secondary></indexterm>
2581 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war
</primary></indexterm>
2582 <indexterm><primary>media
</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in
</secondary></indexterm>
2584 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2585 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2586 from the public than an unconcentrated media can
—as CNN admitted
2587 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2588 its own employees.
<footnote><para>
2590 Telephone interview with David Winer,
16 April
2003.
2592 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2593 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2594 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2595 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2596 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2597 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2598 told her that
<emphasis>they
</emphasis> were writing
<quote>the story.
</quote>)
2600 <indexterm startref='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='endofrange'
/>
2602 Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2603 debate
—<quote>amateur
</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced,
2604 but in the sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to
2605 give their reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a
2606 story, as reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds
2607 from across the southwest United States turned to the Internet to
2608 retell what they had seen.
<footnote><para>
2610 John Schwartz,
<quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2611 Information Online,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
2 February
2003, A28; Staci
2612 D. Kramer,
<quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,
</quote>
2613 Online Journalism Review,
2 February
2003, available at
2614 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
10</ulink>.
2616 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2617 <quote>triangulate,
</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2618 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2619 out of it
</quote>—with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2622 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2623 with blogs.
<quote>It's going to become an essential skill,
</quote> Winer predicts,
2624 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2625 not clear that
<quote>journalism
</quote> is happy about this
—some journalists
2626 have been told to curtail their blogging.
<footnote>
2629 <indexterm><primary>CNN
</primary></indexterm>
2630 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war
</primary></indexterm>
2631 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
2632 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)
</primary></indexterm>
2633 See Michael Falcone,
<quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?
</quote> <citetitle>New
2634 York Times
</citetitle>,
29 September
2003, C4. (
<quote>Not all news organizations have
2635 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2636 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2637 war on March
9, stopped posting
12 days later at his bosses'
2638 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a
<citetitle>Houston Chronicle
</citetitle> reporter, was
2639 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2640 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.
</quote>)
2642 But it is clear that we are still in transition.
<quote>A
2644 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2645 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,
</quote> Winer told me.
2646 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2647 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2648 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said,
<quote>we will
2649 be the last thing that gets shut down.
</quote>
2651 <indexterm startref='idxjournalism' class='endofrange'
/>
2653 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because
<quote>you
2654 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.
</quote>
2655 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2656 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2657 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2658 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2659 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2660 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2661 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2662 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2663 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2664 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2665 extraordinary to report.
2667 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage' class='endofrange'
/>
2668 <indexterm startref='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='endofrange'
/>
2669 <indexterm startref='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='endofrange'
/>
2670 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs2' class='endofrange'
/>
2671 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson2' class='endofrange'
/>
2672 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs2' class='endofrange'
/>
2673 <indexterm startref='idxwinerdave' class='endofrange'
/>
2674 <indexterm id='idxbrownjohnseely' class='startofrange'
><primary>Brown, John Seely
</primary></indexterm>
2675 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'
><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
2677 <emphasis role='strong'
>John Seely Brown
</emphasis> is the chief
2678 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2679 describes it, is
<quote>human learning and
… the creation of
2680 knowledge ecologies for creating
… innovation.
</quote>
2683 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2684 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2685 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2686 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2690 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When
<quote>a lot of us grew up,
</quote>
2691 he explains, that tinkering was done
<quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2692 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.
</quote> But digital technologies
2693 enable a different kind of tinkering
—with abstract ideas though
2694 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2695 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2696 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2697 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2698 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2699 or
<quote>free collage,
</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2700 the tinkering of many others.
2703 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2704 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2705 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2706 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2707 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2710 This opportunity creates a
<quote>completely new kind of learning platform,
</quote>
2711 as Brown describes.
<quote>As soon as you start doing that, you
…
2712 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2713 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2714 if they can improve it.
</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2715 apprenticeship.
<quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.
</quote>
2718 In this process,
<quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2719 They are code.
</quote> Kids are
<quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2720 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2721 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2722 platform.
… You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2723 you tinker the more you improve.
</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2727 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2728 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2729 it,
<quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2730 intelligence.
</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2731 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2732 text.
<quote>The Web
… says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2733 you are visual, if you are interested in film
… [then] there is a
2734 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2735 these multiple forms of intelligence.
</quote>
2737 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'
/>
2738 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2740 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2741 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2743 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2744 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2745 kind of recognition.
2748 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2749 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2750 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2751 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2752 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2753 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2754 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2757 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2758 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2759 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>)
2760 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the
<quote>right to
2761 tinker
</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2762 general.
<footnote><para>
2764 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel,
<quote>Technological Access
2765 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,
</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2766 of the Association for Computer Machinery
</citetitle> 43 (
2000):
9.
2768 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2769 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2772 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,
</quote> Brown
2773 explains. We need to
<quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2774 and want to learn.
</quote>
2777 <quote>Yet,
</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2778 evince,
<quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2779 natural tendencies of today's digital kids.
… We're building an
2780 architecture that unleashes
60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2781 system that closes down that part of the brain.
</quote>
2783 <indexterm startref='idxbrownjohnseely' class='endofrange'
/>
2785 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2786 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2787 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2788 the law to close down that technology.
2791 <quote>No way to run a culture,
</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2792 chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"collectors"/>,
2793 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2795 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2797 <chapter label=
"3" id=
"catalogs">
2798 <title>CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
</title>
2799 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse
</primary></indexterm>
2800 <indexterm><primary>RPI
</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)
</see></indexterm>
2801 <indexterm id='idxrensselaer' class='startofrange'
><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)
</primary></indexterm>
2802 <indexterm id='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)
</primary><secondary>computer network search engine of
</secondary></indexterm>
2803 <indexterm id='idxsearchengines' class='startofrange'
><primary>search engines
</primary></indexterm>
2804 <indexterm id='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='startofrange'
><primary>university computer networks, p2p sharing on
</primary></indexterm>
2805 <indexterm id='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>search engines used on
</secondary></indexterm>
2807 <emphasis role='strong'
>In the fall
</emphasis> of
2002, Jesse Jordan
2808 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2809 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2810 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2811 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2812 was available on the RPI network.
2815 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2816 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2817 to information sciences. More than
65 percent of its five thousand
2818 undergraduates finished in the top
10 percent of their high school
2819 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2820 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2823 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2824 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2825 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2826 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2827 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2829 <indexterm id='idxgoogle' class='startofrange'
><primary>Google
</primary></indexterm>
2831 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2832 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2833 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2834 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2835 engines can do this even better. The idea of
<quote>intranet
</quote> search
2836 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2837 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2838 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2839 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2840 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2842 <indexterm startref='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='endofrange'
/>
2843 <indexterm id='idxjordanjesse' class='startofrange'
><primary>Jordan, Jesse
</primary></indexterm>
2844 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>network file system of
</secondary></indexterm>
2846 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2847 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2848 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2849 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2850 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2851 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2852 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2854 <indexterm startref='idxgoogle' class='endofrange'
/>
2856 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2857 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2858 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2859 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2860 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2861 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2862 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2863 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2864 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2867 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='endofrange'
/>
2869 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2870 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2871 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2872 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2873 be on users' computers.
2875 <indexterm startref='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='endofrange'
/>
2877 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2878 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2879 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2880 might have created; university brochures
—basically anything that
2881 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2882 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2885 <indexterm><primary>Google
</primary></indexterm>
2886 <indexterm><primary>education
</primary><secondary>tinkering as means of
</secondary></indexterm>
2888 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2889 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2890 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and
—so that this
2891 point is absolutely clear
—Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2892 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2893 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2894 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2895 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2896 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2897 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2898 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2899 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2902 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>in recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
2903 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>against student file sharing
</secondary></indexterm>
2904 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of
</secondary></indexterm>
2905 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by
</secondary></indexterm>
2906 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='endofrange'
/>
2908 On April
3,
2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2909 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2910 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2911 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2912 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2913 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2914 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2917 <quote>It was absurd,
</quote> he told me.
<quote>I don't think I did anything
2918 wrong.
… I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2919 engine that I ran or
… what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2920 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2921 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2922 easier to use
</quote>—again, a
<emphasis>search engine
</emphasis>,
2923 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2924 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2925 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2926 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2929 <indexterm startref='idxsearchengines' class='endofrange'
/>
2930 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of
</secondary></indexterm>
2931 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>statutory damages of
</secondary></indexterm>
2932 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>individual defendants intimidated by
</secondary></indexterm>
2933 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages
</primary></indexterm>
2934 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>intimidation tactics of
</secondary></indexterm>
2936 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2937 network and had therefore
<quote>willfully
</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2938 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2939 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2940 <quote>willful infringement,
</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2941 call
<quote>statutory damages.
</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2942 claim $
150,
000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2943 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2944 Jesse pay them at least $
15,
000,
000.
2946 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University
</primary></indexterm>
2947 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University
</primary></indexterm>
2949 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2950 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2951 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2952 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2953 huge demands for
<quote>damages
</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2954 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2955 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $
100
2956 <emphasis>billion
</emphasis>—six times the
2957 <emphasis>total
</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2958 2001.
<footnote><para>
2961 Tim Goral,
<quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-
2-P Networks:
2962 Suit Alleges $
97.8 Billion in Damages,
</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC
</citetitle> 6
2963 (
2003):
5, available at
2003 WL
55179443.
2966 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaer' class='endofrange'
/>
2968 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2969 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2970 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2971 $
12,
000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2972 $
12,
000 to dismiss the case.
2974 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt
</primary></indexterm>
2976 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2977 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2978 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2979 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2980 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2981 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2982 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse,
<quote>You don't want to pay another
2983 visit to a dentist like me.
</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2984 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2986 <indexterm><primary>legal system, attorney costs in
</primary></indexterm>
2988 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2989 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2990 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2991 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2992 at least $
250,
000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2993 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2994 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2995 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2998 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $
250,
000 and a chance at winning,
2999 or $
12,
000 and a settlement.
3001 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
3002 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in
</secondary></indexterm>
3003 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>lobbying power of
</secondary></indexterm>
3005 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
3006 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
3007 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
3008 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
3009 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $
1 million a year.
3010 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
3011 artist makes $
45,
900.
<footnote><para>
3013 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (
2001)
3014 (
27–2042—Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
3015 the Arts,
<citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon
</citetitle> (
2000).
3017 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
3018 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
3019 student for running a search engine?
<footnote><para>
3021 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in
<quote>KaZaA and Punishment,
</quote>
3022 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, A24.
3025 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='endofrange'
/>
3026 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='endofrange'
/>
3028 On June
23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
3029 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
3030 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $
15 million lawsuit became an
3035 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
3036 an activist.
… [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
3037 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
3038 absurd what the RIAA has done.
3042 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
3043 his father told me, Jesse
<quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
3044 I.
… He's not a tree hugger.
… I think it's bizarre that they would
3045 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
3046 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.
</quote>
3048 <indexterm startref='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='endofrange'
/>
3049 <indexterm startref='idxjordanjesse' class='endofrange'
/>
3050 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'
/>
3051 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='endofrange'
/>
3052 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='endofrange'
/>
3053 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='endofrange'
/>
3054 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
3056 <chapter label=
"4" id=
"pirates">
3057 <title>CHAPTER FOUR:
<quote>Pirates
</quote></title>
3058 <indexterm id='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>in development of content industry
</secondary></indexterm>
3059 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right
</quote> theory
</primary></indexterm>
3061 <emphasis role='strong'
>If
<quote>piracy
</quote> means
</emphasis>
3062 using the creative property of others without their
3063 permission
—if
<quote>if value, then right
</quote> is
3064 true
—then the history of the content industry is a history of
3065 piracy. Every important sector of
<quote>big media
</quote>
3066 today
—film, records, radio, and cable TV
—was born of a
3067 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
3068 generation's pirates join this generation's country club
—until
3074 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.
<footnote><para>
3076 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
3077 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
3078 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
87–93,
3079 which details Edison's
<quote>adventures
</quote> with copyright and patent.
3081 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
3082 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
3083 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
3084 exercised through a monopoly
<quote>trust,
</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
3085 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
3086 property
—patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
3087 this creative property
3088 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
3089 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
3092 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
3096 A January
1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
3097 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
3098 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
3099 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
3100 summer of
1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
3101 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
3102 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
3104 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William
</primary></indexterm>
3105 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company
</primary></indexterm>
3106 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
3108 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
3109 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
3110 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
3111 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
3112 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
3113 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
3114 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
3115 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
3116 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
3117 license was revoked.
<footnote><para>
3119 J. A. Aberdeen,
<citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
3120 Picture Producers
</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment,
2000) and expanded texts
3121 posted at
<quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
3122 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,
</quote> available at
3123 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
11</ulink>. For a
3124 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
3125 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker,
<quote>From
3126 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
3127 the Propertization of Copyright
</quote> (September
2002), University of
3128 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
3129 Working Paper No.
159.
3130 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
3135 The Napsters of those days, the
<quote>independents,
</quote> were companies like
3136 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
3137 resisted.
<quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
3138 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
3139 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.
</quote><footnote><para>
3141 Marc Wanamaker,
<quote>The First Studios,
</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority
</citetitle>, archived at
3142 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
12</ulink>.
3144 That led the independents to flee the East
3145 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
3146 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
3147 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
3151 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
3152 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
3153 patent holder a truly
<quote>limited
</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
3155 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
3156 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
3157 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
3158 Edison's creative property.
3161 <section id=
"recordedmusic">
3162 <title>Recorded Music
</title>
3163 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on music recordings
</secondary></indexterm>
3165 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
3166 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
3168 <indexterm id='idxfourneauxhenri' class='startofrange'
><primary>Fourneaux, Henri
</primary></indexterm>
3169 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil
</primary></indexterm>
3171 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
3172 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
3173 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
3174 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
3175 their music. In other words, in
1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
3176 1899 hit
<quote>Happy Mose,
</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
3177 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
3178 right to perform it publicly.
3180 <indexterm><primary>Beatles
</primary></indexterm>
3182 But what if I wanted to record
<quote>Happy Mose,
</quote> using Edison's phonograph
3183 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
3184 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
3185 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
3186 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
3187 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
3188 <quote>public performance
</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
3189 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
3190 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
3191 brain are not
—yet
— regulated by copyright law). So if I
3192 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
3193 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
3194 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
3195 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
3196 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
3197 its composer anything.
3199 <indexterm startref='idxfourneauxhenri' class='endofrange'
/>
3201 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
3202 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
3203 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
3205 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred
</primary></indexterm>
3209 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3210 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3211 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3212 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3213 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3214 rights.
<footnote><para>
3216 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3217 S.
6330 and H.R.
19853 Before the ( Joint) Committees on Patents,
59th
3218 Cong.
59,
1st sess. (
1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3219 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in
<citetitle>Legislative History of the
3220 Copyright Act
</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3221 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints,
1976).
3222 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred
</primary></indexterm>
3226 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip
</primary></indexterm>
3228 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3229 people's works were
<quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3230 genius of American composers,
</quote><footnote><para>
3232 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
223
3233 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3235 and the
<quote>music publishing industry
</quote>
3236 was thereby
<quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.
</quote><footnote><para>
3238 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
226
3239 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3242 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible,
<quote>When they make money
3243 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.
</quote><footnote><para>
3245 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
23
3246 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3249 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company
</primary></indexterm>
3250 <indexterm><primary>player pianos
</primary></indexterm>
3251 <indexterm><primary>sheet music
</primary></indexterm>
3252 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
3253 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
3254 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in
</secondary></indexterm>
3255 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>statutory license system in
</secondary></indexterm>
3257 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3258 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3259 player piano argued that
<quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3260 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3261 of anything he had before their introduction.
</quote> Rather, the machines
3262 increased the sales of sheet music.
<footnote><para>
3265 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
283–84
3266 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3267 Perforating Company of New York).
3268 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3269 Congress was
<quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3270 they represent, and whose servants they are.
</quote> <quote>All talk about
3271 `theft,'
</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3272 wrote,
<quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3273 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3274 statute.
</quote><footnote><para>
3276 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
376 (prepared
3277 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3278 Graphophone Company Association).
3281 <indexterm><primary>cover songs
</primary></indexterm>
3283 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3284 <emphasis>and
</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3285 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the
<quote>mechanical
3286 reproductions
</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3287 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3288 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3289 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3290 recorded once. This is the part of
3292 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3293 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3294 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3295 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3297 <indexterm id='idxcompulsorylicense' class='startofrange'
><primary>compulsory license
</primary></indexterm>
3298 <indexterm id='idxstatutorylicenses' class='startofrange'
><primary>statutory licenses
</primary></indexterm>
3300 American law ordinarily calls this a
<quote>compulsory license,
</quote> but I will
3301 refer to it as a
<quote>statutory license.
</quote> A statutory license is a license
3302 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3303 Copyright Act in
1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3304 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3305 the fee set by the statute.
3307 <indexterm id='idxgrishamjohn' class='startofrange'
><primary>Grisham, John
</primary></indexterm>
3309 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3310 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3311 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3312 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3313 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3314 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3317 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='endofrange'
/>
3318 <indexterm><primary>Beatles
</primary></indexterm>
3320 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3321 thus, in effect, the law
<emphasis>subsidizes
</emphasis> the recording
3322 industry through a kind of piracy
—by giving recording artists a
3323 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3324 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3325 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3326 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3327 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3328 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3329 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3330 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3331 creativity.
<footnote><para>
3334 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S.
2499, S.
2900, H.R.
243, and
3335 H.R.
11794 Before the ( Joint) Committee on Patents,
60th Cong.,
1st
3336 sess.,
217 (
1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3337 in
<citetitle>Legislative History of the
1909 Copyright Act
</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3338 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints,
1976).
3341 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='endofrange'
/>
3342 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'
/>
3343 <indexterm startref='idxgrishamjohn' class='endofrange'
/>
3345 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3346 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3347 records. As a
1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3352 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3353 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3354 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3355 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3356 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3357 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3358 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3359 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3360 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before
1909 and
3361 the
1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3362 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3363 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3364 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3365 choice.
<footnote><para>
3367 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R.
2512, House Committee
3368 on the Judiciary,
90th Cong.,
1st sess., House Document no.
83, (
8
3369 March
1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3370 this report.
</para></footnote>
3373 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='endofrange'
/>
3374 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='endofrange'
/>
3375 <indexterm startref='idxcompulsorylicense' class='endofrange'
/>
3376 <indexterm startref='idxstatutorylicenses' class='endofrange'
/>
3378 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3379 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3382 <section id=
"radio">
3383 <title>Radio
</title>
3384 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and
</secondary></indexterm>
3385 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
3387 Radio was also born of piracy.
3390 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3391 <quote>public performance
</quote> of the composer's work.
<footnote><para>
3393 See
17 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, sections
106 and
110. At the beginning,
3394 record companies printed
<quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast
</quote> and other
3395 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3396 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3397 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3398 station. See
<citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Whiteman
</citetitle>,
114 F.
2d
86 (
2nd
3399 Cir.
1940). See also Randal C. Picker,
<quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3400 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3401 Copyright,
</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review
</citetitle> 70 (
2003):
281.
3402 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned
</primary></indexterm>
3403 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
3405 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3406 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3407 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3410 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3411 copy of the
<emphasis>composer's
</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3412 also performing a copy of the
<emphasis>recording artist's
</emphasis>
3413 work. It's one thing to have
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote> sung on the radio by the
3414 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3415 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3416 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3417 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3418 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3420 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
3422 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3425 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3426 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3427 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3428 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3429 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3430 of playing the song.
3432 <indexterm id='idxmadonna' class='startofrange'
><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
3434 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3435 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3436 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3437 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3440 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3441 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3442 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3443 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3444 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3445 <quote>protected
</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3446 <emphasis>pirate
</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3449 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='endofrange'
/>
3450 <indexterm startref='idxmadonna' class='endofrange'
/>
3452 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3453 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3454 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3455 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3456 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3457 to take something for nothing.
3459 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='endofrange'
/>
3461 <section id=
"cabletv">
3462 <title>Cable TV
</title>
3463 <indexterm id='idxcabletelevision' class='startofrange'
><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
3465 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3468 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3469 television in
1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3470 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3471 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3472 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3473 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3474 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3475 did
— Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3478 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas
</primary></indexterm>
3479 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin
</primary></indexterm>
3480 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.
</primary></indexterm>
3482 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3483 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3484 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.
</quote><footnote><para>
3486 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV: Hearing on S.
1006 Before the
3487 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3488 Committee on the Judiciary,
89th Cong.,
2nd sess.,
78 (
1966)
3489 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3491 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.
</primary></indexterm>
3493 There may have been a
<quote>public interest
</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3494 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3495 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony,
<quote>Does public
3496 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?
</quote><footnote><para>
3498 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3499 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3501 As another broadcaster put it,
3505 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3506 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3507 paid for.
<footnote><para>
3509 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3510 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3515 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3519 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3520 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3521 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3522 think there are harsher words which would fit it.
<footnote><para>
3524 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3525 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3526 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3530 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton
</primary></indexterm>
3532 These were
<quote>free-ride[rs],
</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3533 Heston said, who were
<quote>depriving actors of
3534 compensation.
</quote><footnote><para>
3536 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3537 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3538 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton
</primary></indexterm>
3543 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3544 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3548 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3549 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3550 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3551 should be permitted to extend that monopoly.
… The
3553 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3554 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3555 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.
<footnote><para>
3557 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
216 (statement of Edwin M.
3558 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3559 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin
</primary></indexterm>
3561 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin
</primary></indexterm>
3565 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3566 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3569 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3570 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they
<quote>pirated.
</quote>
3571 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3572 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3573 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3574 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3575 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3576 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3577 companies thus built their empire in part upon a
<quote>piracy
</quote> of the value
3578 created by broadcasters' content.
3580 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='endofrange'
/>
3581 <indexterm startref='idxcabletelevision' class='endofrange'
/>
3583 <emphasis role='strong'
>These separate stories
</emphasis> sing a
3584 common theme. If
<quote>piracy
</quote> means using value from someone
3585 else's creative property without permission from that creator
—as
3586 it is increasingly described today
<footnote><para>
3588 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association,
<citetitle>The Engine
3589 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet
—The Myth of Free
3590 Information
</citetitle>, available at
3591 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
13</ulink>.
<quote>The
3592 threat of piracy
—the use of someone else's creative work without
3593 permission or compensation
—has grown with the Internet.
</quote>
3595 — then
<emphasis>every
</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3596 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3597 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV.
… The list is long and
3598 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3599 last. Every generation
—until now.
3601 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3604 <chapter label=
"5" id=
"piracy">
3605 <title>CHAPTER FIVE:
<quote>Piracy
</quote></title>
3607 <emphasis role='strong'
>There is piracy
</emphasis> of copyrighted
3608 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3609 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3610 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3611 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3612 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3615 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of
<quote>taking
</quote>
3616 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3617 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3618 taking
<quote>piracy,
</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3619 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3620 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3621 has so often done in the past.
3622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3624 <section id=
"piracy-i">
3625 <title>Piracy I
</title>
3626 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
3627 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of
</secondary></indexterm>
3629 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3630 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3631 content, copy it, and sell it
—all without the permission of a copyright
3632 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $
4.6 billion
3633 every year to physical piracy
<footnote><para>
3635 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry),
<citetitle>The
3636 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report
2003</citetitle>, July
2003, available
3637 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
14</ulink>. See
3638 also Ben Hunt,
<quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,
</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3639 Times
</citetitle>,
14 February
2003,
11.
3641 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3642 estimates that it loses $
3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3645 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3646 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3647 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3648 This piracy is wrong.
3651 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3652 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3653 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3654 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3655 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3656 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3657 of our existence, treated as right.
3660 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3661 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3662 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3663 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3664 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3665 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3666 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3667 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3668 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3671 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3672 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3673 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3674 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3675 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3679 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3680 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3681 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3682 of intellectual property law.
<footnote><para>
3684 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3685 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?
</citetitle> (New York: The
3686 New Press,
2003),
10–13,
209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3687 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3688 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3689 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3690 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3691 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3692 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3693 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3694 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3695 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3696 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3697 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3699 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents
</primary></indexterm>
3700 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
3701 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3702 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3703 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3706 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
3708 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3709 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3710 to American CDs at
50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3711 bought those American CDs at $
15 a copy. So no one really has any
3712 less money than they otherwise would have had.
<footnote><para>
3714 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3715 Liebowitz,
<citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy
</citetitle> (New York: Amacom,
2002),
3716 144–90.
<quote>In some instances
… the impact of piracy on the
3717 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3718 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3719 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3720 pirating were not an option.
</quote> Ibid.,
149.
3721 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
3725 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3726 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3727 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3728 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3729 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes
& Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3730 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?
</quote>
3731 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes
&
3732 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3733 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3734 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3735 piracy of the tangible.
3737 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'
/>
3739 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3740 property right of a very special sort, it
<emphasis>is
</emphasis> a
3741 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3742 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3743 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3744 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3745 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3746 give people the right to
<quote>take
</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3747 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3749 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3750 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3751 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3752 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3753 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3754 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what
<quote>property
</quote> means.
3756 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
3757 <indexterm><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>in Asia
</secondary></indexterm>
3758 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)
</primary></indexterm>
3759 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3760 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3761 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of
</secondary></indexterm>
3762 <indexterm><primary>Windows
</primary></indexterm>
3763 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>international software piracy of
</secondary></indexterm>
3764 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of
</secondary></indexterm>
3766 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3767 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese
<quote>steal
</quote>
3768 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3769 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3770 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3771 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3772 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3773 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3774 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3775 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3776 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3778 <indexterm><primary>law
</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in
</secondary></indexterm>
3780 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3781 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3782 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3783 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3784 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3785 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3787 <indexterm><primary>Netscape
</primary></indexterm>
3788 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer
</primary></indexterm>
3789 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3790 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3792 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3793 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3794 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3795 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3796 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3797 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3798 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3799 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3800 what
—at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3801 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3802 violating the law is still wrong.
3805 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3806 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3807 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3808 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3809 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3810 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3811 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3812 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3816 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3817 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all
<quote>piracy
</quote> is. Or
3818 at least, not all
<quote>piracy
</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3819 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of
<quote>piracy
</quote> are useful
3820 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3821 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3822 <quote>piracy
</quote> in that sense of the term.
3825 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3826 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3827 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3828 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3831 For (
1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3832 controlling industry; and (
2) like the original recording industry, it
3833 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (
3) unlike cable
3834 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3837 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3838 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3842 <section id=
"piracy-ii">
3843 <title>Piracy II
</title>
3845 The key to the
<quote>piracy
</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that
<quote>rob[s]
3846 the author of [his] profit.
</quote><footnote><para>
3848 <citetitle>Bach
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Longman
</citetitle>,
98 Eng. Rep.
1274 (
1777).
3850 This means we must determine whether
3851 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3852 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3853 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3854 author of his profit.
3856 <indexterm><primary>innovation
</primary></indexterm>
3857 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn
</primary></indexterm>
3859 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3860 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3861 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3862 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well
<footnote><para>
3864 <indexterm><primary>innovation
</primary></indexterm>
3865 See Clayton M. Christensen,
<citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3866 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business
</citetitle> (New York:
3867 HarperBusiness,
2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3868 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3869 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3870 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3871 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3872 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig,
<citetitle>Future
</citetitle>,
89–92,
139.
3874 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.
</primary></indexterm>
3875 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3876 put together components that had been developed independently.
3879 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July
1999,
3880 Napster amassed over
10 million users within nine months. After
3881 eighteen months, there were close to
80 million registered users of the
3882 system.
<footnote><para>
3884 See Carolyn Lochhead,
<quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,
</quote> <citetitle>San
3885 Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
24 September
2002, A1;
<quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,
</quote>
3886 <citetitle>New Scientist
</citetitle>,
6 July
2002,
42; Benny Evangelista,
<quote>Napster Names CEO,
3887 Secures New Financing,
</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
23 May
2003, C1;
3888 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,
</quote> <citetitle>Economist
</citetitle>,
24 June
2000,
23; John Naughton,
3889 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet
</quote> (London)
<citetitle>Times
</citetitle>,
26 July
2002,
18.
3891 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3892 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3893 boasts over
100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3894 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3895 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3896 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend
—
3897 or your
20,
000 best friends.
3900 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3901 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3902 September
2002 estimated that
60 million Americans had downloaded
3903 music
—28 percent of Americans older than
12.
<footnote><para>
3906 See Ipsos-Insight,
<citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution
</citetitle>
3907 (September
2002), reporting that
28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3908 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and
30 percent have
3909 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3911 A survey by the NPD group quoted in
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>
3912 estimated that
43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3913 exchange content in May
2003.
<footnote><para>
3915 Amy Harmon,
<quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,
</quote> <citetitle>New
3916 York Times
</citetitle>,
6 June
2003, A1.
3918 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3919 massive quantity of content is being
<quote>taken
</quote> on these networks. The
3920 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3921 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3924 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3925 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3926 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3927 complicated than one might think. So consider
—a bit more
3928 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3929 do
—the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3933 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3934 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3935 different kinds into four types.
3937 <orderedlist numeration=
"upperalpha">
3939 <indexterm><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
3942 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3943 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3944 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3945 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3946 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3947 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3948 users who download instead of purchasing.
3952 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3953 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3954 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3955 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3956 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3957 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3958 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3963 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3964 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3965 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3966 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3967 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3968 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3969 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend
<quote>recalling
</quote> old
3970 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3971 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3972 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3973 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero
—the same
3974 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of
1960s
45-rpm records to
3978 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3980 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3981 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3986 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3989 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3990 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3991 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3992 harmful.
<footnote><para>
3994 See Liebowitz,
<citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy
</citetitle>,
148–49.
3995 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
3997 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3998 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3999 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
4000 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
4001 answer
—and certainly much more difficult than the current
4002 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
4005 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
4006 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
4007 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
4008 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
4009 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of
<quote>theft
</quote> that is
4010 <quote>devastating
</quote> the industry.
4012 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'
><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
4014 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
4015 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
4016 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
4017 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
4018 & Young put it,
<quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
4019 technology, the labels fought it.
</quote><footnote><para>
4021 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary></indexterm>
4022 See Cap Gemini Ernst
& Young,
<citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
4023 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis
</citetitle> (
2003),
3. This report
4024 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
4025 practice of cassette taping in the
1970s, including an advertising
4026 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption
<quote>Home taping
4027 is killing music.
</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
4028 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
4029 behavior. In
1988,
40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
4030 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
4031 Assessment,
<citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law
</citetitle>,
4032 OTA-CIT-
422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
4033 October
1989),
145–56.
</para></footnote>
4034 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
4035 when record sales fell by
11.4 percent in
1981, the industry claimed
4036 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
4037 regulating technology was the answer.
4039 <indexterm><primary>MTV
</primary></indexterm>
4041 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
4042 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
4043 turnaround.
<quote>In the end,
</quote> Cap Gemini concludes,
<quote>the `crisis'
… was
4044 not the fault of the tapers
—who did not [stop after MTV came into
4045 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
4046 being]
—but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
4047 innovation at the major labels.
</quote><footnote><para>
4049 U.S. Congress,
<citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying
</citetitle>,
4.
4052 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'
/>
4054 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
4055 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
4056 the industry in particular, and society in general
—or at least
4057 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
4058 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
4059 VCR
—the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
4060 harmful. The question is also
<emphasis>how
</emphasis> harmful type A
4061 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
4064 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
4065 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
4066 The
<quote>net harm
</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
4067 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
4068 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
4069 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
4070 therefore have little
<emphasis>static
</emphasis> reason to resist
4074 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>sales levels of
</secondary></indexterm>
4076 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
4077 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
4078 actually suggest it might be close.
4081 In
2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by
8.9 percent,
4082 from
882 million to
803 million units; revenues fell
6.7
4083 percent.
<footnote><para>
4085 See Recording Industry Association of America,
<citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics
</citetitle>,
4087 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
15</ulink>. A later
4088 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
4089 Association of America,
<citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy
</citetitle>,
25 June
2003,
4090 available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
4091 #
16</ulink>:
<quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
4092 have fallen by
26 percent from
1.16 billion units in to
860 million
4093 units in
2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
4094 of sales, revenues are down
14 percent, from $
14.6 billion in to $
12.6
4095 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
4096 industry worldwide has gone from a $
39 billion industry in
2000 down
4097 to a $
32 billion industry in
2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
4100 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
4101 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
4102 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
4103 than
20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since
1999. That no
4104 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
4105 account for at least some of the loss.
<quote>From
1999 to
2001, the average
4106 price of a CD rose
7.2 percent, from $
13.04 to $
14.19.
</quote><footnote>
4109 Jane Black,
<quote>Big Music's Broken Record,
</quote> BusinessWeek online,
13
4110 February
2003, available at
4111 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
17</ulink>.
4112 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane
</primary></indexterm>
4115 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
4116 the decline. As Jane Black of
<citetitle>BusinessWeek
</citetitle> notes,
<quote>The
4117 soundtrack to the film
<citetitle>High Fidelity
</citetitle> has a list price of
4118 $
18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
4119 $
19.99.
</quote><footnote><para>
4126 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
4127 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
4128 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
4129 that the RIAA estimates that
803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
4130 estimates that
2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
4131 although
2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4132 free, sales revenue fell by just
6.7 percent.
4135 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
4136 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
4137 The recording industry constantly asks,
<quote>What's the difference between
4138 downloading a song and stealing a CD?
</quote>—but their own numbers
4139 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
4140 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
4141 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
4142 downloads. If every download were a lost sale
—if every use of
4143 Kazaa
<quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit
</quote>—then the industry
4144 would have suffered a
100 percent drop in sales last year, not a
7
4145 percent drop. If
2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4146 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just
6.7 percent, then there is
4147 a huge difference between
<quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.
</quote>
4149 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'
/>
4151 These are the harms
—alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
4152 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
4153 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
4157 One benefit is type C sharing
—making available content that
4158 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
4159 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
4160 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
4161 available.
<footnote><para>
4163 By one estimate,
75 percent of the music released by the major labels
4164 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
4165 Law
—Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
4166 Senate Committee on the Judiciary,
107th Cong.,
1st sess. (
3 April
4167 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
4168 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
18</ulink>.
4170 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
4171 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
4172 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
4173 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
4174 sense
<emphasis>to the company
</emphasis> to make it available.
4176 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
4178 In real space
—long before the Internet
—the market had a simple
4179 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
4180 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
4181 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
4182 today.
<footnote><para>
4184 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
4185 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
4186 in existence, in
2002, there were
7,
198 used book dealers in the
4187 United States, an increase of
20 percent since
1993. See Book Hunter
4188 Press,
<citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
4189 Market
</citetitle> (
2002), available at
4190 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
19</ulink>. Used
4191 records accounted for $
260 million in sales in
2002. See National
4192 Association of Recording Merchandisers,
<quote>2002 Annual Survey
4193 Results,
</quote> available at
4194 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
20</ulink>.
4196 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
4197 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
4198 content,
<emphasis>even if the content is still under
4199 copyright
</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
4200 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
4201 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
4202 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
4203 the content they sell.
4205 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard
</primary></indexterm>
4206 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
4208 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
4209 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
4210 the content available isn't making money from making the content
4211 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
4212 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
4213 when someone shares my
1949 recording of Bernstein's
<quote>Two Love Songs,
</quote>
4214 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
4215 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
4216 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
4217 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
4218 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
4221 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
4222 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
4223 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
4224 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
4225 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
4228 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of
</secondary></indexterm>
4230 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4231 type D sharing to occur
—the sharing of content that copyright owners
4232 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4233 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4234 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel,
<citetitle>Down and Out in
4235 the Magic Kingdom
</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4237 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4238 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4239 would be a great advertisement for the
<quote>real
</quote> book. People would read
4240 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4241 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4242 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4243 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4246 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'
/>
4248 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4249 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4250 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4251 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4254 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4255 understandably says,
<quote>This is how much we've lost,
</quote> we must also ask,
4256 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4257 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4258 unavailable?
</quote>
4261 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4262 chapter, much of the
<quote>piracy
</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4263 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4264 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"pirates"/>, much of
4265 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4266 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4267 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4268 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4269 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4270 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4271 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4272 found only with time.
4275 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4276 just what you call type A sharing?
</quote>
4279 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The
4281 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4282 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4284 case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4286 a technology to block the transfer of
99.4 percent of identified
4287 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4288 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster
99.4
4289 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4290 <quote>down to zero.
</quote><footnote><para>
4292 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at
34-
4293 35 (N.D. Cal.,
11 July
2001), nos. MDL-
00-
1369 MHP, C
99-
5183
4296 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
21</ulink>. For an
4297 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4298 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster
</citetitle> (New
4299 York: Crown Business,
2003),
269–82.
4303 If
99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4304 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4305 assure that a p2p system is used
100 percent of the time in compliance
4306 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that
100 percent of
4307 VCRs or
100 percent of Xerox machines or
100 percent of handguns
4308 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4309 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4310 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4311 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4314 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4315 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4316 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4317 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4318 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4319 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4320 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4322 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
4323 <indexterm><primary>composers, copyright protections of
</primary></indexterm>
4324 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
4325 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
4326 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on music recordings
</secondary></indexterm>
4327 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in
</secondary></indexterm>
4328 <indexterm><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>music recordings played on
</secondary></indexterm>
4329 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in
</secondary></indexterm>
4330 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>copyright protections in
</secondary></indexterm>
4331 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and
</secondary></indexterm>
4332 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses
</primary></indexterm>
4333 <indexterm><primary>composer's rights vs. producers' rights in
</primary></indexterm>
4335 So, as we've seen, when
<quote>mechanical reproduction
</quote> threatened the
4336 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4337 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4338 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4339 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4340 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4341 complained to Congress that their
<quote>creative property
</quote> was not being
4342 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4343 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4346 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'
><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
4348 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4349 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4350 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4351 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4352 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4355 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='endofrange'
/>
4358 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4359 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4360 pianos, served two important goals
—indeed, the two central goals
4361 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4362 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4363 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4364 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4365 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4366 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4367 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4368 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4369 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4370 Congress chose a path that would assure
4371 <emphasis>compensation
</emphasis> without giving the past
4372 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4374 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='endofrange'
/>
4375 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='endofrange'
/>
4376 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'
/>
4377 <indexterm><primary>Betamax
</primary></indexterm>
4378 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'
><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
4380 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4381 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4382 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4383 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4384 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4385 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4386 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4387 <quote>record
</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4388 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4389 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4390 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4392 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='endofrange'
/>
4394 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4395 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4396 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4397 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4398 machine to copy only if there were a special
<quote>copy me
</quote> signal on the
4399 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4400 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4401 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4402 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4403 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4404 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4405 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4406 for the architecture it chose.
4408 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
4409 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on VCR technology
</secondary></indexterm>
4411 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4412 champion. Valenti called VCRs
<quote>tapeworms.
</quote> He warned,
<quote>When there are
4413 20,
30,
40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4414 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4415 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4416 copyright.
</quote><footnote><para>
4418 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4419 S.
1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary,
97th Cong.,
1st
4420 and
2nd sess.,
459 (
1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4421 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4423 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4424 creative judgment,
</quote> he told Congress,
<quote>to understand the devastation
4425 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4426 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4427 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4428 and plain common sense.
</quote><footnote><para>
4430 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders),
475.
4432 Indeed, as surveys would later show,
45
4433 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more
<footnote><para>
4435 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle>,
480 F. Supp.
429,
4438 — a use the Court would later hold was not
<quote>fair.
</quote> By
4439 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4440 copyright infringement without creating a mechanism to compensate
4441 copyright owners,
</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would
<quote>take from the
4442 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4443 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4444 profit from its reproduction.
</quote><footnote><para>
4446 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders),
485 (testimony
4451 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4452 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4453 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction
—leading Judge Alex
4454 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the
<quote>Hollywood
4455 Circuit
</quote>—held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4456 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4457 rule, this totally familiar technology
—which Jack Valenti had
4458 called
<quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry
</quote> (worse
4459 yet, it was a
<emphasis>Japanese
</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4460 American film industry)
—was an illegal
4461 technology.
<footnote><para>
4463 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle>,
659 F.
2d
963 (
9th Cir.
4466 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
4469 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4471 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4472 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4473 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4478 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4479 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4481 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4483 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4484 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4486 by such new technology.
<footnote><para>
4488 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>.,
464 U.S.
417,
431 (
1984).
4492 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='endofrange'
/>
4494 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4495 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4496 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4497 enough, this
<quote>taking
</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4498 together, a pattern is clear:
4501 <informaltable id=
"t1">
4502 <tgroup cols=
"4" align=
"left">
4506 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS
<quote>PIRATED
</quote></entry>
4507 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS
</entry>
4508 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS
</entry>
4513 <entry>Recordings
</entry>
4514 <entry>Composers
</entry>
4515 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4516 <entry>Statutory license
</entry>
4519 <entry>Radio
</entry>
4520 <entry>Recording artists
</entry>
4522 <entry>Nothing
</entry>
4525 <entry>Cable TV
</entry>
4526 <entry>Broadcasters
</entry>
4527 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4528 <entry>Statutory license
</entry>
4532 <entry>Film creators
</entry>
4533 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4534 <entry>Nothing
</entry>
4539 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'
/>
4541 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4542 way content was distributed.
<footnote><para>
4544 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4545 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4546 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4547 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4548 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4549 1992 (Title
17 of the
<citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>), Pub. L. No.
102-
563,
106 Stat.
4550 4237, codified at
17 U.S.C. §
1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4551 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4552 Lessig,
<citetitle>Future
</citetitle>,
71. See also Picker,
<quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,
</quote>
4553 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review
</citetitle> 70 (
2003):
293–96.
4554 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
4555 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
4557 In each case, throughout our history,
4558 that change meant that someone got a
<quote>free ride
</quote> on someone else's
4562 In
<emphasis>none
</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4563 Congress eliminate all free riding. In
<emphasis>none
</emphasis> of
4564 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4565 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4566 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of
<quote>piracy.
</quote>
4567 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4568 the behavior of the
<quote>pirates.
</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4569 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4571 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4573 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
4575 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4576 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4577 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4578 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4579 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4581 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4582 to $
15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4583 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4584 permission to record a song?
4586 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on balance of interests in copyright law
</secondary></indexterm>
4588 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4589 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4590 copyright
<quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4591 over all possible uses of his work.
</quote><footnote><para>
4593 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>.,
464 U.S.
417,
4596 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4597 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4598 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4599 balancing has historically been done
<emphasis>after
</emphasis> a
4600 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4601 facilitate the distribution of content.
4604 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4605 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4606 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4607 should not become a tool for
<quote>stealing
</quote> from artists. But neither
4608 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4609 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4610 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4611 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4612 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4613 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4614 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4615 public interest that innovation continue.
4619 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4620 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4621 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4622 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4623 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4624 efficient. Yet these
<quote>potential public benefits,
</quote> as John Schwartz
4625 writes in
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>,
<quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4626 fight.
</quote><footnote><para>
4628 John Schwartz,
<quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4629 Echoes Past Efforts,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
22 September
2003, C3.
4633 <emphasis role='strong'
>Yet when anyone
</emphasis> begins to talk
4634 about
<quote>balance,
</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4635 argument.
<quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4636 incentives,
</quote> they say,
<quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4637 content,
</quote> the warriors insist,
<quote>is our
4638 <emphasis>property
</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4639 `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4640 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4641 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether
4642 the car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?
</quote>
4645 <quote>It is
<emphasis>our property
</emphasis>,
</quote> the warriors
4646 insist.
<quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4647 is protected.
</quote>
4649 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4653 <part id=
"c-property">
4654 <title><quote>PROPERTY
</quote></title>
4658 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4659 <emphasis role='strong'
>The copyright warriors
</emphasis> are right: A
4660 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4661 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4662 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4663 that partially determine the price she can get.
4666 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a
<quote>property
</quote> right is a
4667 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4668 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4669 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4670 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4671 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4672 when I take the good
<emphasis>idea
</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4673 table in the backyard
—by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4674 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4677 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
4679 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4680 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4681 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4682 in the ordinary case
—indeed, in practically every case except for a
4684 range of exceptions
—ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4685 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress
—though I
4686 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4687 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4688 when I copy the way someone else dresses),
<quote>He who receives an idea
4689 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4690 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.
</quote><footnote><para>
4692 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (
13 August
1813) in
4693 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson
</citetitle>, vol.
6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4694 Ellery Bergh, eds.,
1903),
330,
333–34.
4697 <indexterm><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>intangibility of
</secondary></indexterm>
4699 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4700 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4701 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4703 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4707 But how, and to what extent, and in what form
—the details,
4708 in other words
—matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4709 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4710 <quote>property
</quote> in its proper context.
<footnote><para>
4712 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4713 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4714 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4715 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4716 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4717 Adam Mossoff,
<quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,
</quote>
4718 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review
</citetitle> 45 (
2003):
373,
429 n.
241.
4722 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4723 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4724 <quote>copyright material is property
</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4725 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4726 these stories, the significance of this true
4727 statement
—<quote>copyright material is property
</quote>— will be a bit
4728 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4729 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4733 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4734 <chapter label=
"6" id=
"founders">
4735 <title>CHAPTER SIX: Founders
</title>
4736 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for
</secondary></indexterm>
4737 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>development of
</secondary></indexterm>
4738 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>English
</secondary></indexterm>
4739 <indexterm id='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='startofrange'
><primary>England, copyright laws developed in
</primary></indexterm>
4740 <indexterm id='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='startofrange'
><primary>United Kingdom
</primary><secondary>history of copyright law in
</secondary></indexterm>
4741 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
4742 <indexterm><primary>Henry V
</primary></indexterm>
4743 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
4744 <indexterm id='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='startofrange'
><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)
</primary></indexterm>
4746 <emphasis role='strong'
>William Shakespeare
</emphasis> wrote
4747 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> in
1595. The play was first
4748 published in
1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4749 written. He would continue to write plays through
1613, and the plays
4750 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4751 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4752 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4753 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4754 Henry V:
<quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4757 <indexterm><primary>Conger
</primary></indexterm>
4758 <indexterm id='idxtonsonjacob' class='startofrange'
><primary>Tonson, Jacob
</primary></indexterm>
4760 In
1774, almost
180 years after
<citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> was written, the
4761 <quote>copy-right
</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4762 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.
<footnote><para>
4764 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben
</primary></indexterm>
4765 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John
</primary></indexterm>
4766 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4767 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4768 handsome
<quote>definitive editions
</quote> of classic works. In addition to
<citetitle>Romeo and
4769 Juliet
</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4770 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4771 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker,
<quote>Jacob Tonson,
4772 Bookseller,
</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar
</citetitle> 61:
3 (
1992):
424–31.
4774 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4775 the Conger
<footnote><para>
4777 Lyman Ray Patterson,
<citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective
</citetitle> (Nashville:
4778 Vanderbilt University Press,
1968),
151–52.
4780 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4781 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the
<quote>copy
</quote> of
4782 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4784 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4785 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4786 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4787 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4789 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
4790 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
4791 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>renewability of
</secondary></indexterm>
4792 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
4794 Now, there's something puzzling about the year
1774 to anyone who
4795 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4796 history of copyright is
1710, the year that the British Parliament
4797 adopted the first
<quote>copyright
</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4798 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4799 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4800 works already published by
1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4801 additional years.
<footnote><para>
4803 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
4804 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4805 <quote>copyright law.
</quote> See Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
40.
4806 </para></footnote> Under this law,
<citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> should have been
4807 free in
1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4808 Tonson's control in
1774?
4810 <indexterm startref='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='endofrange'
/>
4811 <indexterm startref='idxtonsonjacob' class='endofrange'
/>
4812 <indexterm id='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>common vs. positive
</secondary></indexterm>
4813 <indexterm><primary>positive law
</primary></indexterm>
4814 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (
1662)
</primary></indexterm>
4816 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a
<quote>copyright
</quote>
4817 was
—indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4818 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4819 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of
1662, had
4820 expired in
1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4821 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4822 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4823 that the publishers, or
<quote>Stationers,
</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4826 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='endofrange'
/>
4827 <indexterm><primary>common law
</primary></indexterm>
4829 There was no
<emphasis>positive
</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4830 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4831 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4832 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4833 from legislatures
<quote>positive law.
</quote> We call the words from judges
4834 <quote>common law.
</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4835 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4836 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4837 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4838 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4840 <indexterm startref='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='endofrange'
/>
4841 <indexterm><primary>Conger
</primary></indexterm>
4842 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'
><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
4843 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers
</primary></indexterm>
4844 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne' class='startofrange'
><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
4846 This question was important to the publishers, or
<quote>booksellers,
</quote> as
4847 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4848 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4849 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4851 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4852 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4853 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4855 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4857 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>as narrow monopoly right
</secondary></indexterm>
4859 The Statute of Anne granted the author or
<quote>proprietor
</quote> of a book an
4860 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4861 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4862 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4863 copyright
<quote>expired,
</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4864 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4867 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne' class='endofrange'
/>
4869 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4870 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4871 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4872 <emphasis>at all?
</emphasis>
4874 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'
/>
4875 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
4876 <indexterm><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)
</primary></indexterm>
4878 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4879 strong claim. Take
<citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> as an example: That play
4880 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4881 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4882 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4883 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4884 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4885 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4886 reason is there to allow someone else to
<quote>steal
</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4888 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
4890 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4891 about the notion of
<quote>copyright
</quote> that existed at the time of the
4892 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4893 <quote>booksellers.
</quote>
4895 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to
</secondary></indexterm>
4897 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4898 to apply the concept of
<quote>copyright
</quote> ever more broadly. But in
1710, it
4899 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4900 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4901 others from reprinting a book. In
1710, the
<quote>copy-right
</quote> was a right
4902 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4903 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4905 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4906 a work could be
<emphasis>used
</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4907 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4908 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4909 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4911 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
4912 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
4914 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4915 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4916 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4917 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4918 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4919 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4920 allowed to make his films. The
<quote>copy-right
</quote> was only an exclusive
4921 right to print
—no less, of course, but also no more.
4923 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England
</primary></indexterm>
4924 <indexterm id='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='startofrange'
><primary>monopoly, copyright as
</primary></indexterm>
4925 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (
1656)
</primary></indexterm>
4927 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4928 They had had a long and ugly experience with
<quote>exclusive rights,
</quote>
4929 especially
<quote>exclusive rights
</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4930 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4931 monopolies
—especially monopolies for works that already
4932 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4933 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4934 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In
1656, it passed the
4935 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4936 inventions. And by
1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4937 monopoly in publishing.
4940 Thus the
<quote>copy-right,
</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4941 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4942 claim that
<quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,
</quote> try
4943 sounding convincing when uttering,
<quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4944 have it forever.
</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4945 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4946 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4948 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John
</primary></indexterm>
4949 <indexterm id='idxbooksellersenglish' class='startofrange'
><primary>booksellers, English
</primary></indexterm>
4950 <indexterm><primary>Conger
</primary></indexterm>
4951 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
4953 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4954 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4955 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4956 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4957 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4959 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4960 kind
—tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4961 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4962 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as
<quote>old patentees
4963 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling
</quote>; they were
<quote>men who do
4964 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4965 indetted.
</quote><footnote><para>
4968 Philip Wittenberg,
<citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4969 Property
</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc.,
1937),
31.
4972 <indexterm><primary>Enlightenment
</primary></indexterm>
4973 <indexterm><primary>knowledge, freedom of
</primary></indexterm>
4975 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4976 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4977 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4978 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4979 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4982 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament2' class='startofrange'
><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
4984 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4985 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4986 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4987 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4988 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4989 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4991 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4992 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4993 construction and spread of culture.
4995 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
4996 </primary></indexterm>
4997 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>in perpetuity
</secondary></indexterm>
4999 When
1731 (
1710 +
21) came along, however, the booksellers were
5000 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
5001 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
5002 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
5003 to control publication. But in
1735 and
1737, they tried to persuade
5004 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
5005 they said; they needed more time.
5008 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
5009 words that echo today,
5013 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
5014 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
5015 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
5016 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
5017 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
5018 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
5019 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
5020 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
5021 Booksellers.
<footnote><para>
5023 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
5024 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
5025 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
5026 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
5027 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
5028 mentioned (London,
1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
5029 al.,
8,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618).
5033 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne2' class='endofrange'
/>
5034 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='endofrange'
/>
5035 <indexterm><primary>common law
</primary></indexterm>
5036 <indexterm><primary>law
</primary><secondary>common vs. positive
</secondary></indexterm>
5037 <indexterm><primary>positive law
</primary></indexterm>
5039 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
5040 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
5041 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
5042 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
5043 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
5044 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
5045 creative
<quote>property
</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
5046 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
5047 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
5048 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
5049 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
5050 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
5051 way to protect authors.
5053 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament2' class='endofrange'
/>
5055 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
5056 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
5057 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
5058 <quote>The publishers
… had as much concern for authors as a cattle
5059 rancher has for cattle.
</quote><footnote><para>
5061 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond
</primary></indexterm>
5062 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
5063 Lyman Ray Patterson,
<quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,
</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
5064 Law Review
</citetitle> 40 (
1987):
28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
5065 Vaidhyanathan,
37–48.
5067 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
5068 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
5070 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='startofrange'
><primary>Donaldson, Alexander
</primary></indexterm>
5071 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond
</primary></indexterm>
5072 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers' class='startofrange'
><primary>Scottish publishers
</primary></indexterm>
5074 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
5075 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
5076 Donaldson.
<footnote><para>
5078 For a compelling account, see David Saunders,
<citetitle>Authorship and Copyright
</citetitle>
5079 (London: Routledge,
1992),
62–69.
5082 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne3' class='startofrange'
><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
5083 <indexterm id='idxconger' class='startofrange'
><primary>Conger
</primary></indexterm>
5084 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James
</primary></indexterm>
5085 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew
</primary></indexterm>
5087 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
5088 career in Edinburgh in
1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
5089 reprints
<quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,
</quote> at least
5090 under the Statute of Anne.
<footnote><para>
5092 Mark Rose,
<citetitle>Authors and Owners
</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
5094 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark
</primary></indexterm>
5096 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
5097 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
5098 and became
<quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.
</quote> <quote>[A]mong
5099 them,
</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was
<quote>the young James Boswell
5100 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
5101 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.
</quote><footnote><para>
5106 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw' class='startofrange'
><primary>common law
</primary></indexterm>
5108 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
5109 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
5110 inexpensive editions
<quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
5111 of the supposed common law right of Literary
5112 Property.
</quote><footnote><para>
5114 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond
</primary></indexterm>
5115 Lyman Ray Patterson,
<citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective
</citetitle>,
167 (quoting
5118 His books undercut the Conger prices by
30 to
50 percent, and he
5119 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
5120 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
5122 <indexterm startref='idxconger' class='endofrange'
/>
5123 <indexterm id='idxmillarvtaylor' class='startofrange'
><primary>Millar v. Taylor
</primary></indexterm>
5125 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block
<quote>piracy
</quote> like
5126 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the
<quote>pirates,
</quote>
5127 the most important early victory being
<citetitle>Millar
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Taylor
</citetitle>.
5129 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='endofrange'
/>
5130 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers' class='endofrange'
/>
5131 <indexterm id='idxthomsonjames' class='startofrange'
><primary>Thomson, James
</primary></indexterm>
5132 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>in perpetuity
</secondary></indexterm>
5133 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)
</primary></indexterm>
5134 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert
</primary></indexterm>
5136 Millar was a bookseller who in
1729 had purchased the rights to James
5137 Thomson's poem
<quote>The Seasons.
</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
5138 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
5139 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
5140 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
5141 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.
<footnote><para>
5143 Howard B. Abrams,
<quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
5144 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,
</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review
</citetitle> 29
5148 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord
</primary></indexterm>
5150 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
5151 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
5152 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
5153 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
5154 law would protect the author against subsequent
<quote>pirates.
</quote>
5155 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
5156 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
5157 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
5158 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
5160 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw' class='endofrange'
/>
5161 <indexterm startref='idxthomsonjames' class='endofrange'
/>
5162 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='endofrange'
/>
5163 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament3' class='startofrange'
><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
5165 Considered as a matter of abstract justice
—reasoning as if
5166 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
5167 principles
—Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
5168 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
5169 with in
1710: How best to limit
5170 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
5171 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
5172 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in
1710, but
5173 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
5174 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
5175 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
5176 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
5178 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='endofrange'
/>
5179 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Donaldson, Alexander
</primary></indexterm>
5180 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Scottish publishers
</primary></indexterm>
5182 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
5183 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
5185 <indexterm><primary>Thomson, James
</primary></indexterm>
5186 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
5187 <indexterm id='idxhouseoflords' class='startofrange'
><primary>House of Lords
</primary></indexterm>
5188 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>House of Lords vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
5190 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
5191 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
5192 Thomas Beckett.
<footnote><para>
5196 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
5197 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in
<citetitle>Millar
</citetitle>,
5198 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
5199 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
5200 Court. In February of
1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
5201 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
5203 <indexterm startref='idxmillarvtaylor' class='endofrange'
/>
5204 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament3' class='endofrange'
/>
5205 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='startofrange'
><primary>Donaldson v. Beckett
</primary></indexterm>
5206 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw2' class='startofrange'
><primary>common law
</primary></indexterm>
5208 As few legal cases ever do,
<citetitle>Donaldson
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Beckett
</citetitle> drew an
5209 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
5210 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
5211 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
5212 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
5213 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
5214 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
5215 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
5217 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne3' class='endofrange'
/>
5219 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
5220 presented to the House and voted upon first by the
<quote>law lords,
</quote>
5221 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
5222 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
5223 House of Lords generally voted.
5225 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='endofrange'
/>
5226 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>in perpetuity
</secondary></indexterm>
5227 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of
</secondary></indexterm>
5229 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
5230 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
5231 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
5232 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
5233 (
22 to
11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
5234 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
5235 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
5236 passed into the public domain.
5238 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis
</primary></indexterm>
5239 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John
</primary></indexterm>
5240 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel
</primary></indexterm>
5241 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John
</primary></indexterm>
5242 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
5244 <quote>The public domain.
</quote> Before the case of
<citetitle>Donaldson
</citetitle>
5245 v.
<citetitle>Beckett
</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
5246 England. Before
1774, there was a strong argument that common law
5247 copyrights were perpetual. After
1774, the public domain was
5248 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
5249 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
5250 history
—including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
5251 and Bunyan
—were free of legal restraint.
5253 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='endofrange'
/>
5254 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers2' class='endofrange'
/>
5255 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw2' class='endofrange'
/>
5256 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='endofrange'
/>
5257 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='endofrange'
/>
5258 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers
</primary></indexterm>
5260 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
5261 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
5262 where most of the
<quote>pirate publishers
</quote> did their work, people
5263 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the
<citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser
</citetitle>
5264 reported,
<quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
5265 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
5266 decision of which so many individuals were interested.
</quote> <quote>Great
5267 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
5268 and illuminations.
</quote><footnote><para>
5273 <indexterm startref='idxhouseoflords' class='endofrange'
/>
5275 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
5276 equally strong in the opposite direction. The
<citetitle>Morning Chronicle
</citetitle>
5281 By the above decision
… near
200,
000 pounds worth of what was
5282 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
5283 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
5284 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
5285 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
5286 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
5287 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
5288 successors.
<footnote><para>
5294 <indexterm><primary>House of Lords
</primary></indexterm>
5295 <indexterm><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of
</secondary></indexterm>
5297 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
5298 <quote>Ruined
</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
5299 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
5300 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
5301 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
5302 <emphasis>free
</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
5303 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
5304 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
5305 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
5306 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
5307 book from someone. But
<emphasis>free
</emphasis> in the sense that the
5308 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
5309 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
5310 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
5311 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
5312 develop
— chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
5313 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a
<emphasis>competitive
5314 context
</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
5315 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
5316 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
5318 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellersenglish' class='endofrange'
/>
5319 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
5321 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
5322 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
5323 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
5326 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='endofrange'
/>
5327 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'
/>
5328 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='endofrange'
/>
5329 <indexterm startref='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='endofrange'
/>
5330 <indexterm startref='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='endofrange'
/>
5331 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='endofrange'
/>
5332 <indexterm startref='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='endofrange'
/>
5333 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='endofrange'
/>
5334 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='endofrange'
/>
5335 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
5337 <chapter label=
"7" id=
"recorders">
5338 <title>CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
</title>
5339 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>fair use and
</secondary></indexterm>
5340 <indexterm id='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'
><primary>documentary film
</primary></indexterm>
5341 <indexterm id='idxelsejon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Else, Jon
</primary></indexterm>
5342 <indexterm id='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>in documentary film
</secondary></indexterm>
5343 <indexterm id='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='startofrange'
><primary>films
</primary><secondary>fair use of copyrighted material in
</secondary></indexterm>
5345 <emphasis role='strong'
>Jon Else
</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5346 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5347 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5348 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5349 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5352 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5353 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5356 <indexterm id='idxwagnerrichard' class='startofrange'
><primary>Wagner, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
5357 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera
</primary></indexterm>
5359 In
1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5360 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5361 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5362 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5363 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5366 <indexterm id='idxsimpsonsthe' class='startofrange'
><primary>Simpsons, The
</primary></indexterm>
5368 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5369 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5370 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5371 and the opera company played Wagner, was
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>. As Else judged
5372 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5373 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5376 <indexterm startref='idxwagnerrichard' class='endofrange'
/>
5377 <indexterm><primary>films
</primary><secondary>multiple copyrights associated with
</secondary></indexterm>
5379 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5380 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>.
5381 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5382 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5383 unless
<quote>fair use
</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5385 <indexterm id='idxgraciefilms' class='startofrange'
><primary>Gracie Films
</primary></indexterm>
5386 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt' class='startofrange'
><primary>Groening, Matt
</primary></indexterm>
5388 Else called
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5389 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5390 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5391 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5392 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5394 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='startofrange'
><primary>Fox (film company)
</primary></indexterm>
5396 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5397 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5398 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5399 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5400 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5402 <indexterm startref='idxgraciefilms' class='endofrange'
/>
5404 Then, as Else told me,
<quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5405 … that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation
—or at
5406 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.
</quote>
5407 And second, Fox
<quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5408 to use this four-point-five seconds of
… entirely unsolicited
5409 <citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.
</quote>
5411 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt' class='endofrange'
/>
5412 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='endofrange'
/>
5413 <indexterm id='idxherrerarebecca' class='startofrange'
><primary>Herrera, Rebecca
</primary></indexterm>
5415 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5416 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5417 explained to her,
<quote>There must be some mistake here.
… We're
5418 asking for your educational rate on this.
</quote> That was the educational
5419 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5420 confirm what he had been told.
5422 <indexterm><primary>Wagner, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
5424 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,
</quote> he told me.
<quote>Yes, you
5425 have your facts straight,
</quote> she said. It would cost $
10,
000 to use the
5426 clip of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5429 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5430 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else,
<quote>And
5431 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.
</quote> As an assistant
5432 to Herrera told Else later on,
<quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5435 <indexterm startref='idxherrerarebecca' class='endofrange'
/>
5436 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera
</primary></indexterm>
5437 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The
</primary></indexterm>
5439 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5440 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5441 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5442 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5443 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5444 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity
</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5446 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Fox (film company)
</primary></indexterm>
5447 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Groening, Matt
</primary></indexterm>
5449 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5450 copyright to
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5451 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5452 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5453 <citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5454 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5455 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5456 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5457 says the owner gets to control.
5460 For example,
<quote>public performance
</quote> is a use of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle> that the
5461 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5462 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see
<quote>My
5463 Favorite
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle>,
</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5464 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5465 whatever she wants
—$
10 or $
1,
000,
000. That's her right, as set
5469 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5470 thought is
<quote>fair use.
</quote><footnote><para>
5472 For an excellent argument that such use is
<quote>fair use,
</quote> but that
5473 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is
<quote>fair use,
</quote> see Richard
5474 A. Posner with William F. Patry,
<quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5475 Wake of
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5476 Law School,
5 August
2003.
5478 Else's use of just
4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle>
5479 episode is clearly a fair use of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>—and fair use does
5480 not require the permission of anyone.
5482 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='endofrange'
/>
5483 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt2' class='endofrange'
/>
5485 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5486 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon
<quote>fair use.
</quote> Here's his reply:
5489 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against
</secondary></indexterm>
5491 The
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5492 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5493 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5494 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was
<quote>clearly
5495 fair use
</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5496 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5498 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
5500 <indexterm><primary>Errors and Omissions insurance
</primary></indexterm>
5503 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5504 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5505 <quote>visual cue sheet
</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5506 shot in the film. They take a dim view of
<quote>fair use,
</quote> and a claim of
5507 <quote>fair use
</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5510 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='startofrange'
><primary>Fox (film company)
</primary></indexterm>
5511 <indexterm><primary>Groening, Matt
</primary></indexterm>
5512 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George
</primary></indexterm>
5513 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars
</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5516 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5517 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5518 tracking down and stopping unlicensed
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> usage, just as George
5519 Lucas had a very high profile litigating
<citetitle>Star Wars
</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5520 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5521 license to four seconds of
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5522 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5523 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5528 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5529 School
… who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5530 that Fox would
<quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5531 life,
</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5532 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5533 pockets, me or them.
5534 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5536 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='endofrange'
/>
5540 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5541 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5546 <indexterm startref='idxsimpsonsthe' class='endofrange'
/>
5548 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5549 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5550 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5551 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5552 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5553 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5556 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5557 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5558 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5559 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5562 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='endofrange'
/>
5563 <indexterm startref='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'
/>
5564 <indexterm startref='idxelsejon' class='endofrange'
/>
5565 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'
/>
5566 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='endofrange'
/>
5567 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='endofrange'
/>
5568 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5570 <chapter label=
"8" id=
"transformers">
5571 <title>CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
</title>
5572 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
5573 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'
><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5574 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary></indexterm>
5576 <emphasis role='strong'
>In
1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5577 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5578 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5579 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5580 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5581 anticipation of the power of networks.
5583 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on
</secondary></indexterm>
5584 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'
><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in
</primary></indexterm>
5586 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5587 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology
—not to distribute
5588 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5589 difficult. In
1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5590 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5591 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5592 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5593 important to his career.
5596 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5597 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5598 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5599 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5602 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5603 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5604 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5605 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5606 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5607 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5610 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips.
<quote>Our
5611 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5612 Eastwood's films,
</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5613 arose.
<quote>No one had ever really done this before,
</quote> Alben explained.
<quote>No
5614 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5615 actor's career.
</quote>
5618 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5619 Slade asked,
<quote>Well, what will it take?
</quote>
5622 Alben replied,
<quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5623 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5624 else that we want to use in these film clips.
</quote> Slade said,
<quote>Great! Go
5625 for it.
</quote><footnote>
5628 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5629 publicity
—rights an artist has to control the commercial
5630 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden
<quote>Rip, Mix,
5631 Burn
</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5632 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of
</secondary></indexterm>
5633 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5637 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5638 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5639 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5640 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5641 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5644 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5645 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5646 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5650 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5651 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include
—of
5652 course we were going to use the
<quote>Make my day
</quote> clip from
<citetitle>Dirty
5653 Harry
</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5654 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5655 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5658 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5659 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5660 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5661 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5662 rate at the time was about $
600. So we had to identify the
5663 people
—some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5664 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5665 glass
—is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5666 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5667 started calling people.
5670 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald
</primary></indexterm>
5672 Some actors were glad to help
—Donald Sutherland, for example,
5673 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5674 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5675 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $
600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5676 know, $
1,
200?
</quote> And they would say,
<quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5677 to get $
1,
200.
</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5678 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5679 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5683 It was one
<emphasis>year
</emphasis> later
—<quote>and even then we
5684 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.
</quote>
5687 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5688 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5689 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5693 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5694 hands and said,
<quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5695 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5696 actors.
</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5697 constituent parts and said,
<quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5698 directors,
… this many musicians,
</quote> and we just went at it very
5699 systematically and cleared the rights.
5704 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5705 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5706 loved it, and it sold very well.
5708 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
5710 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5711 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5712 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped,
<quote>There is
5713 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5714 at all.
</quote><footnote><para>
5716 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management,
<citetitle>Seven
5717 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition
</citetitle>, available at
5718 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
22</ulink>.
5720 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5724 For, as he acknowledged,
<quote>very few
… have the time and resources,
5725 and the will to do this,
</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5726 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5727 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5728 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5732 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5733 he or she gets paid very well.
… And then when
30 seconds of
5734 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5735 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person
… should be
5736 compensated for that.
5740 Or at least, is this
<emphasis>how
</emphasis> the artist should be
5741 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5742 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5743 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5744 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5745 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5746 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5747 made to be more clean?
5751 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5752 mechanism
—where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5753 subject to estranged former spouses
—you'd see a lot more of this
5754 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5755 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5756 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5757 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5758 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5759 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5760 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5761 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5762 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5763 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5764 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say,
<quote>Oh, I
5765 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5766 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5767 money,
</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5771 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5772 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5773 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5774 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5775 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5777 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'
/>
5778 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'
/>
5780 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5781 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5782 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5783 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5784 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5785 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5786 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5787 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5788 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5789 <quote>Does this still make sense?
</quote>
5791 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'
/>
5793 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5794 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5795 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5796 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5798 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5799 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5800 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5803 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5804 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a
<citetitle>60 Minutes
</citetitle> episode.
5805 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5806 judges loved every minute of it.
5808 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David
</primary></indexterm>
5810 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5811 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5812 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5813 room of over
250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5814 began his talk with a question:
<quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5815 were just violated in this room?
</quote>
5817 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David
</primary></indexterm>
5818 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5820 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5821 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5822 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5823 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5824 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of
250 judges and a gaggle
5825 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5826 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5827 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5828 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5829 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5830 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5831 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5832 couldn't easily do them legally.
5835 We live in a
<quote>cut and paste
</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5836 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5837 and paste architecture of the Internet created
—in a second you can
5838 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5839 planted in your presentation.
5841 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos
</primary></indexterm>
5843 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5844 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5845 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5846 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5847 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5848 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5849 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5850 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5851 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5854 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5855 wanted to be
<quote>legal,
</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5856 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5857 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5858 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5861 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5862 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5863 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5864 necessarily requiring that the
<quote>free
</quote> use be free as in
<quote>free beer.
</quote>
5865 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5866 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5867 along: a rule, for example, that says
<quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5868 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5869 will be a flat
1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5870 copyright owner.
</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5871 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5872 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5876 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5877 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5878 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5879 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5882 <emphasis role='strong'
>In February
2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5883 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5884 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live
</citetitle> and
5885 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5886 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5887 would work together to form a
<quote>unique filmmaking pact.
</quote> Under the
5888 agreement, DreamWorks
<quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5889 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and
—with the use
5890 of stateof-the-art digital technology
—insert Myers and other
5891 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5892 entertainment.
</quote>
5895 The announcement called this
<quote>film sampling.
</quote> As Myers explained,
5896 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5897 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5898 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5899 to take that same concept and apply it to film.
</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5900 quoted as saying,
<quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5901 new audiences, it is Mike.
</quote>
5904 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5905 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5906 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5907 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5908 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5909 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5910 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5911 privilege reserved for the funny and famous
—and presumably rich.
5914 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5915 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of
<quote>fair use.
</quote>
5916 Much of
<quote>sampling
</quote> should be considered
<quote>fair use.
</quote> But few would
5917 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5918 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5919 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5920 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5921 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5922 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5923 process is a process of paying lawyers
—again a privilege, or perhaps a
5924 curse, reserved for the few.
5926 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5928 <chapter label=
"9" id=
"collectors">
5929 <title>CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
</title>
5930 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'
><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
5931 <indexterm><primary>bots
</primary></indexterm>
5933 <emphasis role='strong'
>In April
1996</emphasis>, millions of
5934 <quote>bots
</quote>—computer codes designed to
5935 <quote>spider,
</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5936 content
—began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5937 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5938 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5939 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5940 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5941 Internet and stored them.
5943 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine
</primary></indexterm>
5945 By October
2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5946 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5947 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5948 the world. Using a technology called
<quote>the Way Back Machine,
</quote> you could
5949 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to
1996, as
5950 well as when those pages changed.
5952 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'
><primary>Orwell, George
</primary></indexterm>
5954 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5955 appreciated. In the dystopia described in
<citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5956 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5957 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5961 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5962 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5963 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5964 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5967 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5968 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5969 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5970 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5971 library
—constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5973 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'
/>
5974 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine
</primary></indexterm>
5976 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5977 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5978 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5979 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5980 what others might prefer you forget.
<footnote><para>
5982 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war
</primary></indexterm>
5983 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases
</primary></indexterm>
5984 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5985 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May
13,
2003,
5986 press release stated,
<quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.
</quote> That was
5987 later changed, without notice, to
<quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5988 Have Ended.
</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle,
1 December
2003.
5991 <indexterm><primary>history, records of
</primary></indexterm>
5993 <emphasis role='strong'
>We take it
</emphasis> for granted that we can
5994 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5995 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5996 race riots in Watts in
1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in
1963,
5997 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5998 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5999 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
6000 remember
—not just what it is convenient to remember, but
6001 remember something close to the truth.
6004 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
6005 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We
<emphasis>all
</emphasis>
6006 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
6007 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
6008 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
6009 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
6010 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
6013 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
6014 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
6015 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
6016 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
6017 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
6018 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
6019 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
6020 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet
—the
6021 one kept by the Internet Archive.
6024 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
6025 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
6026 researcher. In the
1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
6027 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
6028 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
6029 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
6030 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of
2002, the archive had over
10
6031 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
6033 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress
</primary></indexterm>
6034 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive
</primary></indexterm>
6035 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University
</primary></indexterm>
6036 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine
</primary></indexterm>
6037 <indexterm><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>archival function of
</secondary></indexterm>
6038 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage2' class='startofrange'
><primary>news coverage
</primary></indexterm>
6040 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
6041 human history. At the end of
2002, it held
<quote>two hundred and thirty
6042 terabytes of material
</quote>—and was
<quote>ten times larger than the
6043 Library of Congress.
</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
6044 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
6045 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
6046 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
6047 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
6048 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
6049 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University
—thanks to a
6050 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
6051 is available to scholars for a very low fee.
<quote>But other than that,
6052 [television] is almost unavailable,
</quote> Kahle told me.
<quote>If you were
6053 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
6054 just a graduate student?
</quote> As Kahle put it,
6057 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan
</primary></indexterm>
6058 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes
</primary></indexterm>
6060 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
6061 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
6062 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
6063 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
6064 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
6066 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
6067 <citetitle>60 Minutes
</citetitle> episode that came out after it
… it would be almost
6068 impossible.
… Those materials are almost unfindable.
…
6071 <indexterm><primary>newspapers
</primary><secondary>archives of
</secondary></indexterm>
6073 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
6074 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
6075 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
6076 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
6077 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
6078 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
6081 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
6082 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
6083 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
6084 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
6085 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
6088 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress
</primary></indexterm>
6089 <indexterm><primary>films
</primary><secondary>archive of
</secondary></indexterm>
6091 These rules applied to film as well. But in
1915, the Library
6092 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
6093 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
6094 borrow back the deposits
—for an unlimited time at no cost. In
6095 1915 alone, there were more than
5,
475 films deposited and
<quote>borrowed
6096 back.
</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
6097 held by any library. The copy exists
—if it exists at
6098 all
—in the library archive of the film company.
<footnote><para>
6100 Doug Herrick,
<quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
6101 the Library of Congress,
</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly
</citetitle> 13 nos.
2–3
6102 (
1980):
5; Anthony Slide,
<citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
6103 Preservation in the United States
</citetitle> ( Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland
&
6108 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
6109 were originally not copyrighted
—there was no way to capture the
6110 broadcasts, so there was no fear of
<quote>theft.
</quote> But as technology enabled
6111 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
6112 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
6113 <quote>copyrighted.
</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
6114 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
6115 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
6116 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
6118 <indexterm><primary>September
11,
2001, terrorist attacks of
</primary></indexterm>
6120 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September
11,
2001, he and
6121 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
6122 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
6123 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
6124 September
11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
6125 stations from around the world and, beginning October
11,
2001, made
6126 their coverage during the week of September
11 available free on-line.
6127 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
6130 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive
</primary></indexterm>
6131 <indexterm><primary>archive.org
</primary><seealso>Internet Archive
</seealso></indexterm>
6132 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage2' class='endofrange'
/>
6133 <indexterm><primary>films
</primary><secondary>archive of
</secondary></indexterm>
6134 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive
</primary></indexterm>
6135 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film
</primary></indexterm>
6136 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films
</primary></indexterm>
6137 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick
</primary></indexterm>
6139 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
6140 archive of film includes close to
45,
000 <quote>ephemeral films
</quote> (meaning
6141 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
6142 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
6143 1,
300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
6144 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
6145 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
6146 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
6147 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
6148 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
6149 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
6150 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
6151 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the
<quote>Duck and Cover
</quote> film
6152 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
6153 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
6154 few minutes
—for free.
6157 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
6158 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
6159 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
6160 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
6161 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
6165 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
6166 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
6167 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
6168 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
6169 property, but during a second life that all creative property
6170 has
—a noncommercial life.
6173 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
6174 of creative property goes through different
<quote>lives.
</quote> In its first
6177 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
6178 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
6179 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
6180 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
6181 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
6182 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
6185 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
6186 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
6187 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
6188 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
6189 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
6190 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
6193 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
6195 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
6196 very quickly (the average today is after about a year
<footnote><para>
6198 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
6199 Dave Barns,
<quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
6200 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,
</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune
</citetitle>,
6201 5 September
1997, at Metro Lake
1L. Of books published between
1927
6202 and
1946, only
2.2 percent were in print in
2002. R. Anthony Reese,
6203 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,
</quote> <citetitle>Boston
6204 College Law Review
</citetitle> 44 (
2003):
593 n.
51.
6205 </para></footnote>). After
6206 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
6207 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
6208 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
6209 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
6210 important to the spread and stability of culture.
6213 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
6214 creative property does not hold true with the most important
6215 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
6216 centuries. For these
—television, movies, music, radio, the
6217 Internet
—there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
6218 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes
&
6219 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
6220 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
6224 <emphasis role='strong'
>For most of
</emphasis> the twentieth century,
6225 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
6226 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
6227 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
6228 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
6229 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
6230 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
6231 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
6232 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
6233 little practical effect.
6236 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
6237 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
6238 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
6239 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
6240 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
6241 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
6244 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
6245 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
6246 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
6250 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>total number of
</secondary></indexterm>
6252 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
6253 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
6254 movies,
… and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
6255 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
6256 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
6257 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
6258 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
6259 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
6260 … thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
6261 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
6262 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
6265 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
6267 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
6268 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
6269 libraries or archives could be.
<emphasis>When
</emphasis> the
6270 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
6271 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
6272 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
6273 will draw upon it to understand it;
6274 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
6275 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
6276 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
6277 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past
—a
6278 future
<emphasis>for
</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
6279 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
6282 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
6283 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
6284 call these
<quote>archives,
</quote> as warm as the idea of a
<quote>library
</quote> might seem,
6285 the
<quote>content
</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
6286 someone's
<quote>property.
</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
6287 that Kahle and others would exercise.
6289 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'
/>
6290 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
6292 <chapter label=
"10" id=
"property-i">
6293 <title>CHAPTER TEN:
<quote>Property
</quote></title>
6294 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon
</primary></indexterm>
6295 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.
</primary></indexterm>
6297 <emphasis role='strong'
>Jack Valenti
</emphasis> has been the president
6298 of the Motion Picture Association of America since
1966. He first came
6299 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
6300 administration
—literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
6301 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
6302 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
6303 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
6304 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
6306 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.
</primary></indexterm>
6307 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment
</primary></indexterm>
6308 <indexterm><primary>MGM
</primary></indexterm>
6309 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures
</primary></indexterm>
6310 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox
</primary></indexterm>
6311 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures
</primary></indexterm>
6312 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
6314 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
6315 Association. It was formed in
1922 as a trade association whose goal
6316 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
6317 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
6318 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
6319 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
6320 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
6321 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
6322 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
6326 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
6327 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
6328 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
6329 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
6330 political skill of a Southerner
—the ability to appear simple and
6331 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
6332 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
6333 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
6334 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
6335 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
6339 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
6340 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
6341 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
6342 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
6343 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
6344 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
6345 redefine the meaning of
<quote>creative property.
</quote>
6348 In
1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
6353 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
6354 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
6355 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
6356 theme which animates this entire debate:
<emphasis>Creative property
6357 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
6358 other property owners in the nation
</emphasis>. That is the issue.
6359 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
6360 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.
<footnote><para>
6362 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R.
4783, H.R.
6363 4794, H.R.
4808, H.R.
5250, H.R.
5488, and H.R.
5705 Before the
6364 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
6365 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
6366 Representatives,
97th Cong.,
2nd sess. (
1982):
65 (testimony of Jack
6372 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
6373 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
6374 <quote>central theme
</quote> to which
<quote>reasonable men and women
</quote> will return is
6376 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6377 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6378 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.
</quote>
6379 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6380 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6383 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6384 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6385 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6386 extreme a claim made by
<emphasis>anyone
</emphasis> who is serious in
6387 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6388 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6389 it comes to the nature and scope of
<quote>creative property.
</quote> His views
6390 have
<emphasis>no
</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6391 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6392 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6395 While
<quote>creative property
</quote> is certainly
<quote>property
</quote> in a nerdy and
6396 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,
<footnote><para>
6398 Lawyers speak of
<quote>property
</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6399 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6400 object. Thus, my
<quote>property right
</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6401 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at
150 miles an hour. For
6402 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of
<quote>property
</quote> to
6403 <quote>lawyer talk,
</quote> see Bruce Ackerman,
<citetitle>Private Property and the
6404 Constitution
</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1977),
26–27.
6405 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6406 <quote>creative property owners
</quote> have been
<quote>accorded the same rights and
6407 protection resident in all other property owners.
</quote> Indeed, if creative
6408 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6409 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6413 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6414 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6415 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6416 overturned in
1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6417 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6418 culture would develop.
6421 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6422 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6423 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6424 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6425 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6426 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6427 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6428 the same would be to
6430 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6431 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6432 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6436 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6437 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6438 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6439 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6440 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6441 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6442 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6445 <emphasis role='strong'
>To get
</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6446 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6447 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6450 The framers of our Constitution loved
<quote>property.
</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6451 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6452 important requirement. If the government takes your property
—if
6453 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6454 farm
—it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's
<quote>Takings
6455 Clause,
</quote> to pay you
<quote>just compensation
</quote> for that taking. The
6456 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6457 sacred. It cannot
<emphasis>ever
</emphasis> be taken from the property
6458 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6461 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6462 Valenti calls
<quote>creative property.
</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6463 power to create
<quote>creative property,
</quote> the Constitution
6464 <emphasis>requires
</emphasis> that after a
<quote>limited time,
</quote> Congress
6465 take back the rights that it has granted and set the
<quote>creative
6466 property
</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6467 the expiration of a copyright term
<quote>takes
</quote> your copyright and turns it
6468 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6469 pay
<quote>just compensation
</quote> for this
<quote>taking.
</quote> Instead, the same
6470 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6471 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6472 requires that you lose your
<quote>creative property
</quote> right without any
6473 compensation at all.
6476 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6477 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6478 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6479 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6480 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6481 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6484 <indexterm id='idxjeffersonthomas' class='startofrange'
><primary>Jefferson, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
6486 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6487 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6488 The Constitution of
1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6489 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6490 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6491 president (as it did in
1800). The framers were no doubt
6492 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6493 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6494 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6495 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6498 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6499 least try to understand
<emphasis>why
</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6500 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6501 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6502 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6505 <indexterm startref='idxjeffersonthomas' class='endofrange'
/>
6508 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6509 history of these
<quote>creative property
</quote> rights, and the control that they
6510 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6511 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6512 should be at the core of this war: Not
<emphasis>whether
</emphasis>
6513 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6514 <emphasis>whether
</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6515 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6516 ought to be. Not
<emphasis>whether
</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6517 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6518 also control how culture develops.
6520 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='startofrange'
><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary>four modalities of constraint on
</secondary></indexterm>
6521 <indexterm id='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>regulation
</primary><secondary>four modalities of
</secondary></indexterm>
6522 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>as ex post regulation modality
</secondary></indexterm>
6523 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>as constraint modality
</secondary></indexterm>
6526 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6527 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6528 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6529 than the narrow language of the law allows. In
<citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6530 Cyberspace
</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6531 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6532 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6533 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6535 <figure id=
"fig-1331">
6536 <title>How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.
</title>
6537 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.png"></graphic>
6539 <indexterm><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
6541 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6542 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6543 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6544 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6545 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6546 be regulated
— either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6547 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6548 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6549 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6550 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6551 Web, you can be punished
6552 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6553 with a $
150,
000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6554 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6555 <indexterm><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
6557 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of
</primary></indexterm>
6559 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6560 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6561 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6562 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6563 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6564 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6565 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6566 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6567 the source of the enforcement.
6569 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints' class='startofrange'
><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6571 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6572 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6573 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6574 norms
—it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6575 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6576 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6577 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6578 individual or group might behave.
6580 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6582 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6583 <quote>architecture
</quote>—the physical world as one finds it
—is a
6584 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6585 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6586 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6587 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6588 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6589 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6590 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6591 theft, but by nature, by
<quote>architecture.
</quote> If a
500-pound boulder
6592 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6593 constraint. If a $
500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6594 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6596 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='endofrange'
/>
6597 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='endofrange'
/>
6598 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints' class='endofrange'
/>
6599 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>as constraint modality
</secondary></indexterm>
6602 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6603 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6604 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6605 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6606 undermined by another.
6609 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6610 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6611 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6612 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6613 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6614 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6615 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6617 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6618 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6619 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of
</primary></indexterm>
6620 <indexterm id='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='startofrange'
><primary>driving speed, constraints on
</primary></indexterm>
6621 <indexterm id='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='startofrange'
><primary>speeding, constraints on
</primary></indexterm>
6623 So, for example, consider the
<quote>freedom
</quote> to drive a car at a high
6624 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6625 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6626 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6627 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6628 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6629 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6630 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6631 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6632 the freedom to speed. Drive at
50 mph by a school in your own
6633 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6634 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6637 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6638 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6639 special role in affecting the three.
<footnote><para>
6641 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6642 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6643 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6644 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6645 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig,
<citetitle>Code: And
6646 Other Laws of Cyberspace
</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books,
1999):
90–95;
6647 Lawrence Lessig,
<quote>The New Chicago School,
</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies
</citetitle>,
6650 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6651 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6652 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6653 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6654 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6655 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6656 used to require that other laws be more
6657 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6658 strict
—a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6659 limit, for example
—so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6662 <indexterm startref='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='endofrange'
/>
6663 <indexterm startref='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='endofrange'
/>
6664 <figure id=
"fig-1361">
6665 <title>Law has a special role in affecting the three.
</title>
6666 <graphic fileref=
"images/1361.png"></graphic>
6668 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6670 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6671 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6672 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6673 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6674 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6678 Some people object to this way of talking about
<quote>liberty.
</quote> They object
6679 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6680 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6681 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6682 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6683 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6684 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6685 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6686 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6687 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6688 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6689 of liberty. As I argued in
<citetitle>Code
</citetitle>, we come from a
6690 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6691 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6692 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6693 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6694 <citetitle>On Liberty
</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6695 1978),
19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6696 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons,
<quote>The
6697 Right to Work,
</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6698 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays
</citetitle> (London:
6699 Routledge:
1997),
62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6700 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6701 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6702 places easier;
42 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
6703 12101 (
2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6704 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6705 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6706 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6707 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (
1990)
</primary></indexterm>
6708 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.
</primary></indexterm>
6709 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6710 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6713 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='endofrange'
/>
6714 <section id=
"hollywood">
6715 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right
</title>
6716 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on
</secondary></indexterm>
6718 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6719 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6720 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6721 rallying makes sense.
6724 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6727 <figure id=
"fig-1371">
6728 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.
</title>
6729 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.png"></graphic>
6731 <indexterm id='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='startofrange'
><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6732 <indexterm><primary>law
</primary><secondary>as constraint modality
</secondary></indexterm>
6733 <indexterm id='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>norms, regulatory influence of
</primary></indexterm>
6735 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6736 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6737 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6738 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6739 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6740 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6741 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6742 recognize
—kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6743 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6744 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6745 this form of infringement.
6747 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>copyright regulatory balance lost with
</secondary></indexterm>
6748 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing
</primary><secondary>regulatory balance lost in
</secondary></indexterm>
6749 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6750 <indexterm><primary>MP3s
</primary></indexterm>
6752 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6753 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6754 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6755 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6756 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6757 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6759 <indexterm startref='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='endofrange'
/>
6760 <indexterm startref='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='endofrange'
/>
6761 <indexterm><primary>technology
</primary><secondary>established industries threatened by changes in
</secondary></indexterm>
6763 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6764 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6765 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6766 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6768 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6769 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6770 looting that results.
6772 <figure id=
"fig-1381">
6773 <title>effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
</title>
6774 <graphic fileref=
"images/1381.png"></graphic>
6776 <indexterm><primary>Commerce, U.S. Department of
</primary></indexterm>
6777 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='startofrange'
><primary>regulation
</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism
</secondary></indexterm>
6779 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6780 warriors. Indeed, in a
<quote>White Paper
</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6781 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in
1995,
6782 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6783 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6784 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (
1) Congress should
6785 strengthen intellectual property law, (
2) businesses should adopt
6786 innovative marketing techniques, (
3) technologists should push to
6787 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (
4) educators should
6788 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6790 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='endofrange'
/>
6791 <indexterm startref='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='endofrange'
/>
6792 <indexterm><primary>farming
</primary></indexterm>
6793 <indexterm><primary>steel industry
</primary></indexterm>
6795 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed
—if it was to
6796 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6797 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6798 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6799 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6800 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6801 life. Homeowners living in a
6803 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6804 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6805 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6806 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6807 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6808 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6809 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6811 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='endofrange'
/>
6812 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='endofrange'
/>
6813 <indexterm><primary>Brown, John Seely
</primary></indexterm>
6815 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6816 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6817 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6818 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6819 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6820 Brown describes it, its
<quote>architecture of revenue.
</quote>
6822 <indexterm><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
6823 <indexterm><primary>television
</primary><secondary>advertising on
</secondary></indexterm>
6824 <indexterm><primary>commercials
</primary></indexterm>
6825 <indexterm><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
6826 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras
</primary></indexterm>
6827 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras
</primary></indexterm>
6828 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry
</primary></indexterm>
6829 <indexterm><primary>remote channel changers
</primary></indexterm>
6831 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6832 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6833 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6834 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6835 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as
20
6836 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6837 of digital cameras.
<footnote><para>
6839 See Geoffrey Smith,
<quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?
</quote>
6840 BusinessWeek online,
2 August
1999, available at
6841 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
23</ulink>. For a more
6842 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6843 R. Schoenberger,
<quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?
</quote> Forbes.com,
6
6844 October
2003, available at
6845 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
24</ulink>.
6848 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6849 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6850 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6851 <emphasis>for the purpose of
</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6852 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6853 weakened the
<quote>stickiness
</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6854 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf ), and it
6855 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6856 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6857 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6858 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6860 <indexterm id='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='startofrange'
><primary>free market, technological changes in
</primary></indexterm>
6861 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid
</primary></indexterm>
6862 <indexterm><primary>FM radio
</primary></indexterm>
6863 <indexterm><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of
</secondary></indexterm>
6864 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
6865 <indexterm><primary>market competition
</primary></indexterm>
6866 <indexterm><primary>RCA
</primary></indexterm>
6868 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6869 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6870 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6871 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6872 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6873 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6874 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6875 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents,
<quote>established companies
6876 have an interest in excluding future competitors.
</quote><footnote><para>
6878 Fred Warshofsky,
<citetitle>The Patent Wars
</citetitle> (New York: Wiley,
1994),
170–71.
6881 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6882 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6883 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6884 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6885 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6889 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6890 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6891 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6892 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6893 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6894 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6895 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6896 opportunities for innovation and change.
6898 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>First Amendment to
</secondary></indexterm>
6899 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment
</primary></indexterm>
6900 <indexterm><primary>speech, freedom of
</primary><secondary>constitutional guarantee of
</secondary></indexterm>
6902 In the context of laws regulating speech
—which include,
6903 obviously, copyright law
—that duty is even stronger. When the
6904 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6905 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6906 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6907 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6908 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6909 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution:
<quote>Congress
6910 shall make no law
… abridging the freedom of speech.
</quote> So when
6911 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would
<quote>abridge
</quote> the freedom
6912 of speech, it should ask
— carefully
—whether such
6913 regulation is justified.
6915 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='endofrange'
/>
6916 <indexterm startref='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='endofrange'
/>
6918 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6919 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6920 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6921 <quote>justified.
</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6922 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6923 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6924 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6927 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6929 <indexterm id='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='startofrange'
><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann
</primary></indexterm>
6930 <indexterm id='idxddt' class='startofrange'
><primary>DDT
</primary></indexterm>
6931 <indexterm id='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>insecticide, environmental consequences of
</primary></indexterm>
6932 <indexterm id='idxfarming' class='startofrange'
><primary>farming
</primary></indexterm>
6934 In
1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In
1948, Swiss
6935 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6936 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the
1950s, the
6937 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6938 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6941 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6942 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6943 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6945 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel
</primary></indexterm>
6946 <indexterm><primary>Silent Spring (Carson)
</primary></indexterm>
6947 <indexterm id='idxenvironmentalism' class='startofrange'
><primary>environmentalism
</primary></indexterm>
6949 But in
1962, Rachel Carson published
<citetitle>Silent Spring
</citetitle>, which argued that
6950 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6951 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6952 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6955 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6956 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6957 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6958 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6959 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6960 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6961 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6963 <indexterm startref='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='endofrange'
/>
6964 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James
</primary></indexterm>
6965 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>innovative freedom balanced with fair compensation in
</secondary></indexterm>
6967 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6968 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an
<quote>environmentalism
</quote> for
6969 culture.
<footnote><para>
6971 See, for example, James Boyle,
<quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6972 Environmentalism for the Net?
</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal
</citetitle> 47 (
1997):
87.
6974 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6975 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6976 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6977 <quote>for free.
</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6978 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6979 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6980 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6981 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6982 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6983 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6984 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6985 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6987 <indexterm startref='idxfarming' class='endofrange'
/>
6989 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6990 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6991 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6992 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6993 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6994 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6995 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6996 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6997 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6999 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='endofrange'
/>
7001 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
7002 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
7005 <indexterm startref='idxddt' class='endofrange'
/>
7006 <indexterm startref='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='endofrange'
/>
7007 <indexterm startref='idxenvironmentalism' class='endofrange'
/>
7009 <section id=
"beginnings">
7010 <title>Beginnings
</title>
7011 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on creative property
</secondary></indexterm>
7012 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='startofrange'
><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in
</secondary></indexterm>
7013 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of
</secondary></indexterm>
7014 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of
</secondary></indexterm>
7015 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
7016 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='startofrange'
><primary>creative property
</primary><secondary>constitutional tradition on
</secondary></indexterm>
7017 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause' class='startofrange'
><primary>Progress Clause
</primary></indexterm>
7018 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
7020 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
7021 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of
<quote>creative
7022 property
</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
7023 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
7025 <indexterm id='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>in constitutional Progress Clause
</secondary></indexterm>
7027 The power to establish
<quote>creative property
</quote> rights is granted to
7028 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
7029 odd. Article I, section
8, clause
8 of our Constitution states that:
7032 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
7033 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
7034 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
7036 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
7037 We can call this the
<quote>Progress Clause,
</quote> for notice what this clause
7038 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
7039 <quote>creative property rights.
</quote> It says that Congress has the power
7040 <emphasis>to promote progress
</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
7041 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
7042 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
7044 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='endofrange'
/>
7045 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>as protection of creators
</secondary></indexterm>
7046 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>history of American
</secondary></indexterm>
7048 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
7049 in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"founders"/>,
7050 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
7051 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
7052 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
7053 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
7054 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
7055 copyrights extend
<quote>to Authors
</quote> only.
7057 <indexterm><primary>Senate, U.S.
</primary></indexterm>
7058 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>structural checks and balances of
</secondary></indexterm>
7059 <indexterm><primary>electoral college
</primary></indexterm>
7061 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
7062 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
7063 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
7064 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
7065 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
7066 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
7067 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
7068 to reinforce the power of the states
—including the Senate, whose
7069 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
7070 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
7071 case, a
<emphasis>structure
</emphasis> built checks and balances into
7072 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
7073 concentrations of power.
7075 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='endofrange'
/>
7076 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause' class='endofrange'
/>
7078 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call
<quote>copyright
</quote>
7079 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
7080 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
7081 <quote>copyright
</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the
210
7082 years since they first struck its design.
7084 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='endofrange'
/>
7085 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='endofrange'
/>
7086 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='endofrange'
/>
7087 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on
</secondary></indexterm>
7089 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
7090 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
7091 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
7092 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
7095 <figure id=
"fig-1441">
7096 <title>Copyright's regulation before the Internet.
</title>
7097 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.png"></graphic>
7102 <figure id=
"fig-1442">
7103 <title><quote>Copyright
</quote> today.
</title>
7104 <graphic fileref=
"images/1442.png"></graphic>
7108 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
7111 <section id=
"lawduration">
7112 <title>Law: Duration
</title>
7113 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
7114 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
7115 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact' class='startofrange'
><primary>Copyright Act (
1790)
</primary></indexterm>
7116 <indexterm><primary>creative property
</primary><secondary>common law protections of
</secondary></indexterm>
7117 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>balance of U.S. content in
</secondary></indexterm>
7119 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
7120 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
7121 the English had confronted in
1774. Many states had passed laws
7122 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
7123 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
7124 authorship.
<footnote>
7127 William W. Crosskey,
<citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
7128 the United States
</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press,
1953), vol.
1,
7129 485–86:
<quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
7130 Law of the Land,'
<emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
7131 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law
</emphasis></quote>
7133 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.
</primary></indexterm>
7135 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
7136 States in
1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
7137 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
7138 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
7139 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
7140 domain to reprint and distribute works.
7142 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
7143 <indexterm id='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>federal vs. state
</secondary></indexterm>
7145 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
7146 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
7147 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
7148 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
7149 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
7150 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
7152 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>renewability of
</secondary></indexterm>
7154 In
1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
7155 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
7156 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
7157 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
7158 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
7160 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='endofrange'
/>
7162 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
7163 ten years of the Republic, only
5 percent of the works were actually
7164 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
7165 in the United States both before
1790 and from
1790 through
1800,
95
7166 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
7167 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
7168 likely within fourteen years.
<footnote><para>
7170 Although
13,
000 titles were published in the United States from
1790
7171 to
1799, only
556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel,
<citetitle>A
7172 History of Book Publishing in the United States
</citetitle>, vol.
1,
<citetitle>The Creation
7173 of an Industry,
1630–1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker,
1972),
141. Of the
21,
000
7174 imprints recorded before
1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
7175 1790 act; William J. Maher,
<citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
7176 and the Copyright Law of
1790 in Historical Context
</citetitle>,
7–10 (
2002),
7177 available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
7178 #
25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
7179 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
7180 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
7181 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
7182 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
7183 Act of May
31,
1790, §
1,
1 stat.
124.
</para></footnote>
7185 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact' class='endofrange'
/>
7186 <indexterm startref='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='endofrange'
/>
7188 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
7189 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
7190 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
7191 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
7192 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
7193 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
7197 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
7198 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
7199 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
7200 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
7201 domain.
<footnote><para>
7203 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
7204 instance, of the
25,
006 copyrights registered in
1883, only
894 were
7205 renewed in
1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
7206 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer,
<quote>Study No.
31: Renewal of Copyright,
</quote>
7207 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright
</citetitle>, vol.
1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
7208 1963),
618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
7209 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner,
<quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,
</quote>
7210 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review
</citetitle> 70 (
2003):
471,
498–501, and
7211 accompanying figures.
</para></footnote>
7213 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='endofrange'
/>
7214 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
7215 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
7217 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
7218 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
7219 out of print after one year.
<footnote><para>
7221 See Ringer, ch.
9, n.
2.
</para></footnote> When that happens, the
7222 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
7223 no longer
<emphasis>effectively
</emphasis> controlled by
7224 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
7225 is to sell the books as used books; that use
—because it does not
7226 involve publication
—is effectively free.
7228 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
7229 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by
</secondary></indexterm>
7230 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>term extensions in
</secondary></indexterm>
7232 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
7233 changed once. In
1831, the term was increased from a maximum of
28
7234 years to a maximum of
42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
7235 from
14 years to
28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
7236 the term increased once again. In
1909, Congress extended the renewal
7237 term of
14 years to
28 years, setting a maximum term of
56 years.
7239 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='startofrange'
><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (
1998)
</primary></indexterm>
7240 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in
</secondary></indexterm>
7242 Then, beginning in
1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
7243 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
7244 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
7245 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
7246 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
7247 In
1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
7248 And in
1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
7249 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
7251 <indexterm><primary>patents
</primary><secondary>in public domain
</secondary></indexterm>
7253 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
7254 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
7255 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
7256 years, or
70 percent of the time since
1962. Thus, in the twenty years
7258 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
7259 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
7260 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
7261 of the expiration of a copyright term.
7263 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='endofrange'
/>
7265 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
7266 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
7267 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
7268 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
7269 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
7270 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
7271 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
7274 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (
1998)
</primary></indexterm>
7275 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>of natural authors vs. corporations
</secondary></indexterm>
7276 <indexterm><primary>corporations
</primary><secondary>copyright terms for
</secondary></indexterm>
7278 The United States abandoned this sensible system in
1976. For
7279 all works created after
1978, there was only one copyright term
—the
7280 maximum term. For
<quote>natural
</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
7281 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in
1992,
7282 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
7283 before
1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
7284 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
7285 was ninety-five years.
7288 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
7289 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
7290 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
7291 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
7292 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
7293 that terms be
<quote>limited,
</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
7296 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='endofrange'
/>
7297 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'
/>
7299 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
7300 dramatic. In
1973, more than
85 percent of copyright owners failed to
7301 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
7302 in
1973 was just
32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
7303 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
7304 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from
32.2 years to
95
7305 years.
<footnote><para>
7307 These statistics are understated. Between the years
1910 and
1962 (the
7308 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
7309 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
7310 Posner,
<quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,
</quote> loc. cit.
7313 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='endofrange'
/>
7314 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='endofrange'
/>
7315 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='endofrange'
/>
7316 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='endofrange'
/>
7317 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='endofrange'
/>
7318 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
7320 <section id=
"lawscope">
7321 <title>Law: Scope
</title>
7322 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>scope of
</secondary></indexterm>
7324 The
<quote>scope
</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
7325 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
7326 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
7327 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
7329 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
7330 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>historical shift in copyright coverage of
</secondary></indexterm>
7332 In
1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only
<quote>maps,
7333 charts, and books.
</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
7334 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
7335 the author the exclusive right to
<quote>publish
</quote> copyrighted works. That
7336 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
7337 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
7338 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
7339 did not extend to what lawyers call
<quote>derivative works.
</quote> It would not,
7340 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
7341 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
7342 (such as a drama based on a published book).
7345 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
7346 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
7347 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
7348 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
7349 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
7350 work not only the exclusive right to
<quote>publish
</quote> the work, but also the
7351 exclusive right of control over any
<quote>copies
</quote> of that work. And most
7352 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
7353 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
7354 <quote>derivative work
</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
7355 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
7356 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
7357 on the initial creative work.
7359 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>marking of
</secondary></indexterm>
7360 <indexterm id='idxformalities' class='startofrange'
><primary>formalities
</primary></indexterm>
7361 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>registration requirement of
</secondary></indexterm>
7363 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
7364 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
7365 complete removal of the renewal requirement in
1992. In addition
7366 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
7367 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
7368 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
7369 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
7370 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
7371 famous
© or the word
<emphasis>copyright
</emphasis>. And for most
7372 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
7373 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
7376 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='endofrange'
/>
7378 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
7379 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
7380 in the first ten years of the Republic,
95 percent of works eligible
7381 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
7382 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
7383 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
7384 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
7385 copyrighted
—that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
7386 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
7387 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
7388 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
7391 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>European
</secondary></indexterm>
7393 All of these
<quote>formalities
</quote> were abolished in the American system when
7394 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
7395 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
7396 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
7397 a
©; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
7398 copy available for others to copy.
7400 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='endofrange'
/>
7401 <indexterm startref='idxformalities' class='endofrange'
/>
7402 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='endofrange'
/>
7404 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
7407 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Copyright Act (
1790)
</primary></indexterm>
7409 If, in
1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the
5 percent who
7410 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
7411 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
7412 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
7413 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In
1790, there were
7414 174 publishers in the United States.
<footnote><para>
7416 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner,
<quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
7417 Creation of American Literature,
</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
7418 International Law and Politics
</citetitle> 255 (
1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
7419 Federal Copyright Records,
1790–1800 (U.S. G.P.O.,
1987).
7422 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
7423 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
7424 the United States
—publishers.
7426 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
7427 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7428 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7430 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
7431 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
7432 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
7433 was totally unregulated by the
1790 act. If I took your novel and made
7434 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
7435 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
7436 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
7439 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact2' class='endofrange'
/>
7441 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
7442 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
7443 every note to your spouse, every doodle,
<emphasis>every
</emphasis>
7444 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form
—all of this is
7445 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
7446 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
7450 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
7451 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
7452 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
7455 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
7457 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
7458 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of
<quote>derivative
7459 rights.
</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
7460 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
7461 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
7462 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
7463 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
7465 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
7466 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
7468 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='endofrange'
/>
7470 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
7471 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
7473 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
7475 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
7476 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
7477 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
7478 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
7481 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
7482 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
7483 within a free culture
—at least, it's astonishing when you
7484 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
7485 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
7486 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
7487 <emphasis>that
</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
7488 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
7489 all
—they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
7490 not protect derivative rights at all.
<footnote><para>
7492 Jonathan Zittrain,
<quote>The Copyright Cage,
</quote> <citetitle>Legal
7493 Affairs
</citetitle>, July/August
2003, available at
7494 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
26</ulink>.
7495 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
7497 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
7498 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7499 the wrong of direct piracy.
7502 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7503 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7504 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7505 of my book.
<footnote><para>
7507 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7508 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7509 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere
<quote>copies
</quote> and
7510 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld,
<quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7511 Copyright's Constitutionality,
</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7512 Journal
</citetitle> 112 (
2002):
1–60 (see especially
7514 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb
</primary></indexterm>
7516 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7518 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='endofrange'
/>
7519 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
7520 <indexterm><primary>Mickey Mouse
</primary></indexterm>
7522 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7523 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7524 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7525 called
<quote>Mickey Mouse,
</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7526 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7530 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7531 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7532 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7533 the rights originally granted.
7535 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='endofrange'
/>
7536 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='endofrange'
/>
7538 <section id=
"lawreach">
7539 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach
</title>
7540 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of
</secondary></indexterm>
7541 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>scope of
</secondary></indexterm>
7543 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7544 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7545 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7546 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.
<footnote><para>
7548 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7549 certainly regulates more than
<quote>copies
</quote>—a public performance of a
7550 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7551 per se doesn't make a copy;
17 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
7552 106(
4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a
<quote>copy
</quote>;
17
7553 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
112(a). But the presumption under the
7554 existing law (which regulates
<quote>copies;
</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
7555 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7558 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack
</primary><secondary>on creative property rights
</secondary></indexterm>
7559 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>creative property
</primary><secondary>other property rights vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7561 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7562 <quote>Copies.
</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7563 <emphasis>copy
</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7564 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that
<quote>creative
7565 property
</quote> deserves the
<quote>same rights
</quote> as all other property, it is the
7566 <emphasis>obvious
</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7567 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7568 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7569 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7570 copies should
<emphasis>not
</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7571 law. More precisely, they should not
<emphasis>always
</emphasis> be
7572 the trigger for copyright law.
7574 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='endofrange'
/>
7576 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7577 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7578 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7579 the law of copyright automatically applies,
<footnote><para>
7581 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7582 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7583 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7584 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7587 because it is clear that the
7588 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7589 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7591 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='endofrange'
/>
7592 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='endofrange'
/>
7594 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7597 <figure id=
"fig-1521">
7598 <title>All potential uses of a book.
</title>
7599 <graphic fileref=
"images/1521.png"></graphic>
7601 <indexterm id='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>three types of uses of
</secondary></indexterm>
7602 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of
</secondary></indexterm>
7603 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>copyright applicability altered by technology of
</secondary></indexterm>
7604 <indexterm id='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='startofrange'
><primary>technology
</primary><secondary>copyright intent altered by
</secondary></indexterm>
7605 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7606 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7608 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7609 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7610 all its potential
<emphasis>uses
</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7611 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7612 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7613 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7614 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7615 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7616 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7617 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7618 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7619 acts do not make a copy.
7621 <figure id=
"fig-1531">
7622 <title>Examples of unregulated uses of a book.
</title>
7623 <graphic fileref=
"images/1531.png"></graphic>
7626 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7627 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7628 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7629 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7630 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see first
7631 diagram on next page).
7633 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='endofrange'
/>
7634 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='endofrange'
/>
7635 <indexterm id='idxfairuse' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary></indexterm>
7636 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>fair use and
</secondary></indexterm>
7638 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7639 that remain unregulated because the law considers these
<quote>fair uses.
</quote>
7641 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7642 <figure id=
"fig-1541">
7643 <title>Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.
</title>
7644 <graphic fileref=
"images/1541.png"></graphic>
7646 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>First Amendment to
</secondary></indexterm>
7647 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment
</primary></indexterm>
7649 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7650 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7651 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7652 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7653 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7654 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7655 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such
<quote>fair uses
</quote>
7656 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7658 <figure id=
"fig-1542">
7659 <title>Unregulated copying considered
<quote>fair uses.
</quote></title>
7660 <graphic fileref=
"images/1542.png"></graphic>
7663 <figure id=
"fig-1551">
7664 <title>Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.
</title>
7665 <graphic fileref=
"images/1551.png"></graphic>
7667 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to
</secondary></indexterm>
7669 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7670 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7671 sorts: (
1) unregulated uses, (
2) regulated uses, and (
3) regulated uses that
7672 are nonetheless deemed
<quote>fair
</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7674 <indexterm startref='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='endofrange'
/>
7675 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>on Internet
</secondary></indexterm>
7676 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>books on
</secondary></indexterm>
7677 <indexterm><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on
</secondary></indexterm>
7679 Enter the Internet
—a distributed, digital network where every use
7680 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.
<footnote><para>
7682 I don't mean
<quote>nature
</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7683 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7684 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7685 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7688 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7689 digital network, the scope of category
1 changes dramatically. Uses
7690 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7691 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7692 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7693 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7694 a copy
—category
1 gets sucked into category
2. And those who
7695 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7696 exclusively to category
3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7699 <indexterm startref='idxfairuse' class='endofrange'
/>
7700 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='endofrange'
/>
7702 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7703 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7704 be no plausible
<emphasis>copyright
</emphasis>-related argument that
7705 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7706 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7707 the book once, ten times, or every
7708 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7709 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7710 use
—reading
— could be regulated by copyright law because
7711 none of those uses produced a copy.
7713 <indexterm id='idxebooks' class='startofrange'
><primary>e-books
</primary></indexterm>
7714 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>technological developments and
</secondary></indexterm>
7716 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7717 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7718 only once or only once a month, then
<emphasis>copyright
7719 law
</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7720 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7721 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7722 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7723 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7724 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7725 copyright owner's wish.
7728 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7729 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7730 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7731 points also become clear:
7734 First, making category
1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7735 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7736 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7737 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7738 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7739 part of free culture before the Internet.
7741 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
7743 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7744 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7745 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7746 <emphasis>any
</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7747 using a machine.
<quote>Copy and paste
</quote> and
<quote>cut and paste
</quote> become
7748 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7749 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7750 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7751 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7754 <indexterm id='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on
</secondary></indexterm>
7755 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>fair use and
</secondary></indexterm>
7756 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>fair use vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7758 Third, this shift from category
1 to category
2 puts an extraordinary
7760 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7761 burden on category
3 (
<quote>fair use
</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7762 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7763 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7764 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7765 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7766 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7767 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7768 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7771 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='endofrange'
/>
7772 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='endofrange'
/>
7773 <indexterm startref='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='endofrange'
/>
7774 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='endofrange'
/>
7775 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='endofrange'
/>
7777 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7778 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7779 depend upon fair use
—never even addressing the earlier question
7780 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7781 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7782 <emphasis>unregulated
</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7783 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7786 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='endofrange'
/>
7787 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'
/>
7788 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson2' class='endofrange'
/>
7789 <indexterm startref='idxebooks' class='endofrange'
/>
7790 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='endofrange'
/>
7791 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='endofrange'
/>
7792 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='endofrange'
/>
7793 <indexterm id='idxvideopipeline' class='startofrange'
><primary>Video Pipeline
</primary></indexterm>
7794 <indexterm id='idxadvertising' class='startofrange'
><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
7795 <indexterm id='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='startofrange'
><primary>film industry
</primary><secondary>trailer advertisements of
</secondary></indexterm>
7797 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7798 in the business of making
<quote>trailer
</quote> advertisements for movies available
7799 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7800 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7801 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7803 <indexterm><primary>browsing
</primary></indexterm>
7805 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in
1997, it began
7806 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7807 previews. The idea was to expand their
<quote>selling by sampling
</quote>
7808 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7809 <quote>browsing.
</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7810 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7811 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7813 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Inc.
</primary></indexterm>
7814 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>fair use and
</secondary></indexterm>
7815 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of
</secondary></indexterm>
7816 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against
</secondary></indexterm>
7818 In
1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7819 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7820 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7821 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7822 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7823 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter
—he had built a
7824 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7825 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7826 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7827 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7828 <quote>fair use
</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7829 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7832 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising' class='endofrange'
/>
7833 <indexterm startref='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='endofrange'
/>
7834 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to
</secondary></indexterm>
7835 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>willful infringement findings in
</secondary></indexterm>
7836 <indexterm><primary>willful infringement
</primary></indexterm>
7838 Disney countersued
—for $
100 million in damages. Those damages
7839 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had
<quote>willfully
7840 infringed
</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7841 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7842 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7843 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7844 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7845 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $
100 million.
7848 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7849 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7850 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7851 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7852 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7853 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7854 Disney's permission.
7856 <indexterm><primary>first-sale doctrine
</primary></indexterm>
7858 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7859 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7860 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7861 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7862 was in the marketplace, the
<quote>first-sale doctrine
</quote> would free the
7863 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7864 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7865 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7866 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7867 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7868 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7869 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7871 <indexterm startref='idxvideopipeline' class='endofrange'
/>
7872 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc2' class='endofrange'
/>
7873 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='endofrange'
/>
7874 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='endofrange'
/>
7875 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='endofrange'
/>
7876 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='endofrange'
/>
7877 <indexterm><primary>Barnes
& Noble
</primary></indexterm>
7878 <indexterm><primary>browsing
</primary></indexterm>
7879 <indexterm><primary>market competition
</primary></indexterm>
7881 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7882 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7883 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes
& Noble has the
7884 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7885 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7886 abuse. If Barnes
& Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7887 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7888 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7889 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7890 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7891 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7892 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7893 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7894 happening are quite slight.
7897 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7898 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7899 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7900 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7901 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7902 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7905 <section id=
"lawforce">
7906 <title>Architecture and Law: Force
</title>
7908 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7909 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7910 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7911 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7913 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>technology as automatic enforcer of
</secondary></indexterm>
7914 <indexterm><primary>technology
</primary><secondary>copyright enforcement controlled by
</secondary></indexterm>
7916 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7917 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7918 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7919 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7920 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7923 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca
</primary></indexterm>
7924 <indexterm id='idxmarxbrothers' class='startofrange'
><primary>Marx Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
7925 <indexterm id='idxwarnerbrothers' class='startofrange'
><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
7927 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7928 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7929 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7930 <citetitle>Casablanca
</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7931 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7932 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7933 plan.
<footnote><para>
7935 See David Lange,
<quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,
</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7936 Contemporary Problems
</citetitle> 44 (
1981):
172–73.
7940 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7941 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers
<quote>were brothers long before
7942 you were.
</quote><footnote><para>
7944 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
7945 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and
7946 Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
1–3.
7948 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7949 <citetitle>brothers
</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7950 trying to control
<citetitle>Casablanca
</citetitle>, then the Marx
7951 Brothers would insist on control over
<citetitle>brothers
</citetitle>.
7954 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7955 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7956 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7957 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7959 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet2' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>on Internet
</secondary></indexterm>
7961 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7962 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7963 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7964 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7965 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7966 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7967 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7968 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7970 <indexterm startref='idxwarnerbrothers' class='endofrange'
/>
7971 <indexterm startref='idxmarxbrothers' class='endofrange'
/>
7973 <indexterm id='idxadobeebookreader' class='startofrange'
><primary>Adobe eBook Reader
</primary></indexterm>
7975 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7978 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7979 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7980 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7981 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7985 On the next page is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook
7989 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7990 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7991 public domain:
<citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle>, for example, is in
7992 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7993 public domain: My own book
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle>
7994 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7995 <citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7997 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7998 <citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7999 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
8001 <figure id=
"fig-1611">
8002 <title>Picture of an old version of Adobe eBook Reader
</title>
8003 <graphic fileref=
"images/1611.png"></graphic>
8006 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
8007 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
8009 <figure id=
"fig-1612">
8010 <title>List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.
</title>
8011 <graphic fileref=
"images/1612.png"></graphic>
8014 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
8015 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
8016 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
8017 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
8018 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
8019 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear
<citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle>
8020 read aloud through the computer.
8022 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle
</primary></indexterm>
8023 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics
</citetitle>, (Aristotle)
</primary></indexterm>
8025 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
8026 translation): Aristotle's
<citetitle>Politics
</citetitle>.
8028 <figure id=
"fig-1621">
8029 <title>E-book of Aristotle;s
<quote>Politics
</quote></title>
8030 <graphic fileref=
"images/1621.png"></graphic>
8033 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
8034 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
8037 <figure id=
"fig-1622">
8038 <title>List of the permissions for Aristotle;s
<quote>Politics
</quote>.
</title>
8039 <graphic fileref=
"images/1622.png"></graphic>
8041 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)
</primary></indexterm>
8042 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence
</primary></indexterm>
8044 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
8045 original e-book version of my last book,
<citetitle>The Future of
8048 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
8049 <figure id=
"fig-1631">
8050 <title>List of the permissions for
<quote>The Future of Ideas
</quote>.
</title>
8051 <graphic fileref=
"images/1631.png"></graphic>
8054 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
8057 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
8058 <quote>permissions
</quote>— as if the publisher has the power to control how
8059 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
8060 certainly does have the power
—up to the limits of the copyright
8061 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
8062 power.
<footnote><para>
8064 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
8065 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
8066 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
8067 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
8068 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
8069 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
8070 subsequently acquired the book.
8072 When my e-book of
<citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle> says I have the
8073 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
8074 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
8075 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
8076 control that the law would enable.
8079 The control comes instead from the code
—from the technology
8080 within which the e-book
<quote>lives.
</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
8081 permissions, they are not the sort of
<quote>permissions
</quote> that most of us
8082 deal with. When a teenager gets
<quote>permission
</quote> to stay out till
8083 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
8084 till
2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
8085 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
8086 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
8087 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
8088 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
8089 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
8090 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
8091 aloud
—it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
8092 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
8095 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
8096 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
8098 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
8099 These are
<emphasis>controls
</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
8100 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
8101 you tried to type
<quote>Warner Brothers,
</quote> erased
<quote>Brothers
</quote> from the
8105 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
8106 <emphasis>law
</emphasis> as copyright
<emphasis>code
</emphasis>. The
8107 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
8108 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
8109 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
8110 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
8111 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
8114 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
8115 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
8116 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
8117 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
8118 to defeat these protections as well?
8121 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
8124 <indexterm id='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='startofrange'
><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)
</primary></indexterm>
8125 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>e-book restrictions on
</secondary></indexterm>
8127 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
8128 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
8129 on the Adobe site was a copy of
<citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
8130 Wonderland
</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
8131 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
8134 <figure id=
"fig-1641">
8135 <title>List of the permissions for
<quote>Alice's Adventures in
8136 Wonderland
</quote>.
</title>
8137 <graphic fileref=
"images/1641.png"></graphic>
8139 <!-- PAGE BREAK 164-->
8141 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
8142 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
8143 <quote>permissions
</quote> indicated, not allowed to
<quote>read aloud
</quote>!
8146 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
8147 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
8148 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
8149 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
8150 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
8151 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
8154 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
8155 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
8156 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
8157 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
8158 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
8159 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
8160 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
8161 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
8162 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
8163 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
8164 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
8166 <indexterm startref='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='endofrange'
/>
8167 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='endofrange'
/>
8169 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
8170 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
8171 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
8172 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
8173 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
8176 <indexterm startref='idxadobeebookreader' class='endofrange'
/>
8177 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet2' class='endofrange'
/>
8179 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
8180 story of mine that makes the same point.
8182 <indexterm id='idxaibo1' class='startofrange'
><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8183 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog1' class='startofrange'
><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8184 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo1' class='startofrange'
><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8186 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named
<quote>Aibo.
</quote> The Aibo
8187 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
8188 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
8191 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
8192 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
8193 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
8194 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
8195 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
8196 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
8197 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
8200 <quote>Teach
</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
8201 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
8202 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
8203 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
8204 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
8205 their computer
<quote>dog
</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
8207 <indexterm><primary>hacks
</primary></indexterm>
8209 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
8210 <citetitle>hack
</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
8211 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
8212 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
8213 them,
<citetitle>hack
</citetitle> is a much more positive
8214 term.
<citetitle>Hack
</citetitle> just means code that enables the
8215 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
8216 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
8217 old computer doesn't run, or
<quote>drive,
</quote> the printer. If you discovered
8218 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
8219 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
8223 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
8224 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
8225 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
8226 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
8230 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
8231 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
8232 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
8233 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
8234 than Sony had built.
8236 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo1' class='endofrange'
/>
8237 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog1' class='endofrange'
/>
8238 <indexterm startref='idxaibo1' class='endofrange'
/>
8240 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
8241 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
8242 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
8243 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
8246 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
8247 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
8248 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
8249 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
8250 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
8251 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
8252 thought,
<emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
8253 a robot dog to dance?
</emphasis>
8255 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>government case against
</secondary></indexterm>
8257 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show
—
8258 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
8259 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
8260 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
8261 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
8262 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
8263 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
8264 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
8265 into being silent about something he knew very well.
8268 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April
2001.
<footnote><para>
8270 See Pamela Samuelson,
<quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,
</quote>
8271 <citetitle>Science
</citetitle> 293 (
2001):
2028; Brendan I. Koerner,
<quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
8272 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,
</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect
</citetitle>,
8273 January
2002;
<quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
8274 DMCA,
</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter
</citetitle>,
11 December
2001; Bill
8275 Holland,
<quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,
</quote> <citetitle>Billboard
</citetitle>,
8276 May
2001; Janelle Brown,
<quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?
</quote> Salon.com,
8277 April
2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation,
<quote>Frequently Asked
8278 Questions about
<citetitle>Felten and USENIX
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>RIAA
</citetitle> Legal Case,
</quote> available at
8279 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
27</ulink>.
8280 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation
</primary></indexterm>
8282 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
8283 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
8284 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
8285 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
8288 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
8289 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
8290 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
8291 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
8292 <quote>this music cannot be copied,
</quote> and have a computer respect that
8293 command. The technology was to be part of a
<quote>trusted system
</quote> of
8294 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
8298 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
8299 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
8300 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
8301 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
8304 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
8305 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
8306 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
8307 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
8308 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
8311 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
8312 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
8313 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
8314 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
8315 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
8316 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
8319 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
8320 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
8321 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
8322 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
8323 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
8324 constituted, succeed.
8326 <indexterm id='idxaibo2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8327 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog2' class='startofrange'
><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8328 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8330 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
8331 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
8332 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
8337 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
8338 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
8339 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
8342 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo2' class='endofrange'
/>
8343 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog2' class='endofrange'
/>
8344 <indexterm startref='idxaibo2' class='endofrange'
/>
8346 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
8347 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
8348 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
8352 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
8353 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
8354 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
8355 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
8356 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (
<quote>DMCA
</quote>).
8360 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
8361 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
8362 spreading such information an offense.
8365 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
8366 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
8367 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
8368 These new technologies would be copyright protection
8369 technologies
— technologies to control the replication and
8370 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
8371 <emphasis>code
</emphasis> to modify the original
8372 <emphasis>code
</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
8373 protection for copyright owners.
8376 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
8377 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
8378 <emphasis>legal code
</emphasis> intended to buttress
8379 <emphasis>software code
</emphasis> which itself was intended to
8380 support the
<emphasis>legal code of copyright
</emphasis>.
8383 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
8384 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
8385 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
8386 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
8387 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
8388 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
8389 have been a copyright violation.
8391 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8392 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8393 <indexterm><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8395 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
8396 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
8397 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
8398 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
8399 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
8400 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
8401 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
8402 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
8403 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
8404 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
8407 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
8408 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
8409 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
8410 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
8411 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
8412 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
8414 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
8415 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
8417 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
8418 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
8419 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
8420 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
8421 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
8422 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka
<quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers
</citetitle>,
</quote>
8423 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
8424 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
8425 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
8429 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
8430 <quote>Neighborhood
</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
8431 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
8432 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
8433 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
8434 <quote>Neighborhood
</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the
<quote>Neighborhood
</quote>
8435 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
8436 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
8437 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
8438 broadcasting has always been
<quote>You are an important person just the way
8439 you are. You can make healthy decisions.
</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
8440 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
8441 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
8442 important.
<footnote><para>
8444 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
8445 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>.,
464 U.S.
417,
8446 455 fn.
27 (
1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
8447 James Lardner,
<citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
8448 the VCR
</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton,
1987),
270–71.
8449 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
8454 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
8455 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
8456 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
8457 the VCR responsible.
8460 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to
8462 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
8465 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
8468 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
8469 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
8470 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
8471 pirating of copyrighted material
—a bad end. Or they can be used
8472 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
8473 would be considered fair use
—a good end.
8475 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'
><primary>handguns
</primary></indexterm>
8477 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
8478 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
8479 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
8480 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
8481 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
8484 <figure id=
"fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig">
8485 <title>VCR/handgun cartoon.
</title>
8486 <graphic fileref=
"images/1711.png"></graphic>
8488 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
8490 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
8491 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
8492 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash:
<emphasis>No one ever
8493 died from copyright circumvention
</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
8494 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
8495 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
8497 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'
/>
8498 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'
/>
8499 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8500 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8501 <indexterm><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8503 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
8504 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
8505 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
8506 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
8507 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
8508 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
8511 This is how
<emphasis>code
</emphasis> becomes
8512 <emphasis>law
</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
8513 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
8514 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
8515 law
—increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
8516 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
8517 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
8518 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect
—at
8519 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
8520 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
8523 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
8524 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
8525 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
8526 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
8527 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
8528 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
8529 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
8530 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
8531 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
8535 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
8536 For example, imagine you were part of a
<citetitle>Star Trek
</citetitle> fan club. You
8537 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
8538 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
8539 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
8540 simply continue it.
<footnote><para>
8542 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet,
<quote>Legal Fictions,
8543 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,
</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
8544 Entertainment Law Journal
</citetitle> 17 (
1997):
651.
8548 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
8549 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
8550 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
8551 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
8552 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
8554 <indexterm><primary>bots
</primary></indexterm>
8556 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
8557 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
8558 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
8559 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
8560 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
8561 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
8562 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
8563 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
8566 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
8567 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
8568 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
8569 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8570 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8571 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8574 <section id=
"marketconcentration">
8575 <title>Market: Concentration
</title>
8577 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically
—tripled in
8578 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8579 well
—from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8580 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8581 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8583 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8584 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8585 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8586 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8587 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8588 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8589 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8590 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8591 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8595 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8596 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8597 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8598 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8599 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8602 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8603 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8604 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8605 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8606 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8607 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8608 announced in June
2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8609 live in a world where just three companies control more than percent
8613 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8616 <indexterm><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
8617 <indexterm><primary>BMG
</primary></indexterm>
8618 <indexterm><primary>EMI
</primary></indexterm>
8619 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John
</primary></indexterm>
8620 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group
</primary></indexterm>
8621 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group
</primary></indexterm>
8623 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8624 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8625 ownership,
<quote>five companies control
85 percent of our media sources.
</quote><footnote><para>
8627 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8628 Transportation Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st sess. (
22 May
2003)
8629 (statement of Senator John McCain).
</para></footnote>
8630 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8631 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control
84.8 percent of the
8632 U.S. music market.
<footnote><para>
8634 Lynette Holloway,
<quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8635 Slide,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
23 December
2002.
8637 The
<quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8638 programming to
74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.
</quote><footnote><para>
8640 Molly Ivins,
<quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,
</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette
</citetitle>,
8645 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8646 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8647 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8648 seventy-five stations. Today
<emphasis>one
</emphasis> company owns
8649 more than
1,
200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8650 total number of radio owners dropped by
34 percent. Today, in most
8651 markets, the two largest broadcasters control
74 percent of that
8652 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control
90 percent of
8653 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8655 <indexterm><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
8657 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8658 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8659 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8660 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8661 the United States. The top ten film studios receive
99 percent of all
8662 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for
85 percent
8663 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8664 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8665 protected
— by the market.
8668 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8669 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8670 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8671 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James
</primary></indexterm>
8675 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8676 unmatched in its integration. They supply content
—Fox movies
8677 … Fox TV shows
… Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8678 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8679 advertisers
—in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8680 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8681 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8682 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8683 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8684 the same function in the United States.
<footnote><para>
8686 James Fallows,
<quote>The Age of Murdoch,
</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly
</citetitle> (September
8688 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James
</primary></indexterm>
8693 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8694 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8695 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8696 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8698 <figure id=
"fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership">
8699 <title>Pattern of modern media ownership.
</title>
8700 <graphic fileref=
"images/1761.png"></graphic>
8703 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8704 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8705 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8709 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8710 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8711 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8712 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8715 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8716 integration may matter.
8718 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman
</primary></indexterm>
8719 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
8720 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family
</primary></indexterm>
8722 In
1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for
<citetitle>All in the Family
</citetitle>. He took
8723 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8724 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8725 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8726 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8729 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8730 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8731 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8732 control.
<footnote><para>
8734 Leonard Hill,
<quote>The Axis of Access,
</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8735 Forum,
<quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,
</quote> St. Louis,
8736 Missouri,
3 April
2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8737 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
28</ulink>;
8738 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8739 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
29</ulink>).
8744 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8745 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8746 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8747 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8748 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as
1992,
8749 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8750 television
—75 percent of it
—was
<quote>independent
</quote> of the
8754 In
1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8755 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In
1985,
8756 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8757 2002, only five independent television studios remained.
<quote>In
1992,
8758 only
15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8759 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8760 controlled companies more than quintupled to
77 percent.
</quote> <quote>In
1992,
16
8761 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8762 year there was one.
</quote><footnote><para>
8764 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8765 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st
8766 sess. (
2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8767 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8768 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8769 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8770 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia,
27 February
8773 In
2002,
75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8774 that ran it.
<quote>In the ten-year period between
1992 and
2002, the number
8775 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8776 increased over
200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8777 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8778 63%.
</quote><footnote><para>
8783 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family
</primary></indexterm>
8785 Today, another Norman Lear with another
<citetitle>All in the Family
</citetitle> would
8786 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8787 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8788 owned by the network.
8790 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry
</primary></indexterm>
8791 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
8793 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8794 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8795 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8799 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8800 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8801 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8802 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8803 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8804 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8805 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8806 handful.
<footnote><para>
8808 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,
</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers
</citetitle>, Bill
8809 Moyers,
25 April
2003, edited transcript available at
8810 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
31</ulink>.
8815 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8816 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8817 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8818 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8819 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8820 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8821 question without risk of consequence
—not necessarily banishment
8822 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8823 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8826 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.
</primary></indexterm>
8828 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8829 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the
<quote>Innovator's
8830 Dilemma
</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8831 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8832 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8833 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.
<footnote><para>
8835 Clayton M. Christensen,
<citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8836 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business
</citetitle>
8837 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press,
1997). Christensen
8838 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8839 Kim B. Clark,
<quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8840 Concepts in Technological Evolution,
</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy
</citetitle> 14 (
1985):
8841 235–51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8842 Kaplan,
<citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8843 Underperform the Market
—and How to Successfully Transform Them
</citetitle>
8844 (New York: Currency/Doubleday,
2001).
</para></footnote>
8846 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8847 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8849 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.
</primary></indexterm>
8852 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8853 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8854 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8858 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8859 suggest the concern.
8862 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8863 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8864 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8867 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8868 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8869 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8871 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8872 wrecked by drugs
—though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8873 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8874 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8875 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8876 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8877 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8878 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8879 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8880 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8881 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8882 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8883 outweigh these costs.
8886 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8887 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8888 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8891 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'
><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
8893 Beginning in
1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8894 a media campaign as part of the
<quote>war on drugs.
</quote> The campaign produced
8895 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8896 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8897 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8898 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8899 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8900 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8901 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8902 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8905 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8906 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8909 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8910 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8911 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8915 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8916 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8917 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8918 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8919 message will be heard then?
8922 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8923 <quote>controversial
</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8924 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8925 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8926 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8927 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8928 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8929 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8930 rights of the stations to be this biased.
<footnote><para>
8932 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February
2003, sought to place ads
8933 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8934 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as
<quote>against
8935 [their] policy.
</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8936 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8937 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8938 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8939 Neal Levine,
15 October
2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8940 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives,
<quote>On the Issue of
8941 an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV Networks,
</quote> <citetitle>New
8942 York Times
</citetitle>,
13 March
2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time
8943 there is very little that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to
8944 even the playing field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown,
<quote>Ad
8945 Hoc Access: The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8946 Radio,
</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review
</citetitle> 6 (
1988):
449–79, and for a
8947 more recent summary of the stance of the FCC and the courts, see
8948 <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors Association
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>FCC
</citetitle>,
184 F.
3d
872
8949 (D.C. Cir.
1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8950 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8951 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8952 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross,
<quote>Antidiesel Group Fuming
8953 After Muni Rejects Ad,
</quote> SFGate.com,
16 June
2003, available at
8954 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
32</ulink>. The ground
8955 was that the criticism was
<quote>too controversial.
</quote>
8956 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
8957 <indexterm><primary>Comcast
</primary></indexterm>
8958 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project
</primary></indexterm>
8959 <indexterm><primary>NBC
</primary></indexterm>
8960 <indexterm><primary>WJOA
</primary></indexterm>
8961 <indexterm><primary>WRC
</primary></indexterm>
8962 <indexterm><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
8966 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well
—if we lived
8967 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8968 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8969 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8970 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8971 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8972 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8973 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8974 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8976 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'
/>
8978 <section id=
"together">
8979 <title>Together
</title>
8981 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8982 copyright warriors that the government should
<quote>protect my property.
</quote>
8983 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8984 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8987 But when we see how dramatically this
<quote>property
</quote> has changed
—
8988 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8989 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8990 cultivate our culture is dramatically different
—the claim begins
8993 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8994 less innocent and obvious. Given (
1) the power of technology to
8995 supplement the law's control, and (
2) the power of concentrated
8996 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8997 the massively expanded
<quote>property
</quote> rights granted by copyright
8998 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8999 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
9003 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
9004 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
9005 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
9009 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
9010 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
9011 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
9012 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
9013 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
9014 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
9015 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
9016 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
9017 traditionally defined copyright's regulation
—a weakening of that
9018 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
9021 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
9022 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
9023 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
9024 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
9025 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
9026 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
9027 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
9028 future. And these changes have to be
<emphasis>reductions
</emphasis>
9029 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
9030 in control that technology and the market enable.
9033 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
9034 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
9035 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
9036 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
9037 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
9038 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
9039 more of the development of our culture than now
</emphasis>.
9042 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
9043 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
9044 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
9045 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
9046 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
9047 were independent of the networks.
<emphasis>Never
</emphasis> has
9048 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
9049 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
9050 regulation
—a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
9051 energy of a nation at the founding
—is now a massive regulation
9052 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
9053 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
9054 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
9055 known.
<footnote><para>
9057 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
9058 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his
<quote>four surrenders
</quote> of
9059 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan,
159–60.
9063 <emphasis role='strong'
>This has been
</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
9064 point can now be briefly stated.
9067 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
9068 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
9069 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
9070 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
9071 that copyright law has undergone. In
1790, the law looked like this:
9074 <informaltable id=
"t2">
9075 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
9079 <entry>PUBLISH
</entry>
9080 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
9085 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
9086 <entry>©</entry>
9090 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
9099 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
9100 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
9101 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
9103 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
9104 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
9105 noncommercial work was also free.
9108 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
9111 <informaltable id=
"t3">
9112 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
9116 <entry>PUBLISH
</entry>
9117 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
9122 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
9123 <entry>©</entry>
9124 <entry>©</entry>
9127 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
9136 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law
—if
9137 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
9138 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
9139 transformation were still essentially free.
9142 In
1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
9143 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
9144 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
9145 expanded. Thus by
1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
9146 we could say the law began to look like this:
9149 <informaltable id=
"t4">
9150 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
9155 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
9160 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
9161 <entry>©</entry>
9162 <entry>©</entry>
9165 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
9166 <entry>©/Free
</entry>
9174 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
9175 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
9176 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
9177 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
9178 that the law now looks like this:
9181 <informaltable id=
"t5">
9182 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
9187 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
9192 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
9193 <entry>©</entry>
9194 <entry>©</entry>
9197 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
9198 <entry>©</entry>
9199 <entry>©</entry>
9206 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
9207 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
9209 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
9210 commercial or not, transformative or not
—with the same rules
9211 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
9214 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
9215 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
9216 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
9217 these domains actually does any good.
9220 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
9221 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
9222 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
9223 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
9224 reasons sketched especially in chapters
9225 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"recorders"/> and
9226 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"transformers"/>, one
9227 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
9228 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
9229 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
9232 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
9233 course copyright is a kind of
<quote>property,
</quote> and of course, as with any
9234 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
9235 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
9236 property rights
<footnote><para>
9238 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
9239 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
9240 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey,
<quote>The
9241 Disintegration of Property,
</quote> in
<citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property
</citetitle>, J. Roland
9242 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
9244 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement
</primary></indexterm>
9246 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
9247 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
9248 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
9249 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the
<quote>copyright
</quote>
9250 did not control
<emphasis>at all
</emphasis> the freedom of others to
9251 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
9252 free, and for almost
180 years our country consistently protected a
9253 vibrant and rich free culture.
9255 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
9257 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
9258 limits on the scope of the interests protected by
<quote>property.
</quote> The very
9259 birth of
<quote>copyright
</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
9260 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
9261 story of chapter
6). The tradition of
<quote>fair use
</quote> is animated by a
9262 similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the costs of
9263 exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the story of
9265 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
9266 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
9267 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter
9268 8). And granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect,
9269 claims of property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing
9270 the soul of a culture (chapter
9). Free cultures, like free markets,
9271 are built with property. But the nature of the property that builds a
9272 free culture is very different from the extremist vision that
9273 dominates the debate today.
9276 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
9277 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
9278 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
9279 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
9280 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
9281 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
9282 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
9283 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
9284 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
9285 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
9288 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
9292 <part id=
"c-puzzles">
9293 <title>PUZZLES
</title>
9295 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
9296 <chapter label=
"11" id=
"chimera">
9297 <title>CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
</title>
9298 <indexterm id='idxchimera' class='startofrange'
><primary>chimeras
</primary></indexterm>
9299 <indexterm id='idxwells' class='startofrange'
><primary>Wells, H. G.
</primary></indexterm>
9300 <indexterm id='idxtcotb' class='startofrange'
><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The
</quote> (Wells)
</primary></indexterm>
9303 <emphasis role='strong'
>In a well-known
</emphasis> short story by
9304 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
9305 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
9306 Andes.
<footnote><para>
9308 H. G. Wells,
<quote>The Country of the Blind
</quote> (
1904,
1911). See H. G. Wells,
9309 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories
</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
9310 York: Oxford University Press,
1996).
9312 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with
<quote>sweet water, pasture,
9313 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
9314 that bore an excellent fruit.
</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
9315 takes this as an opportunity.
<quote>In the Country of the Blind,
</quote> he tells
9316 himself,
<quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.
</quote> So he resolves to live with the
9317 villagers to explore life as a king.
9320 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
9321 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
9322 <quote>blind.
</quote> They don't have the word
<citetitle>blind
</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
9323 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
9324 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
9325 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated.
<quote>`You
9326 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
9327 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
9331 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
9332 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
9333 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
9334 affection, a young woman who to him seems
<quote>the most beautiful thing in
9335 the whole of creation,
</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
9336 description of what he sees
<quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
9337 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
9338 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
9339 indulgence.
</quote> <quote>She did not believe,
</quote> Wells tells us, and
<quote>she could
9340 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.
</quote>
9343 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his
<quote>mysteriously delighted
</quote>
9344 love, the father and the village object.
<quote>You see, my dear,
</quote> her
9345 father instructs,
<quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
9346 anything right.
</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
9349 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion.
<quote>His brain
9350 is affected,
</quote> he reports.
9353 <quote>What affects it?
</quote> the father asks.
<quote>Those queer things that are
9354 called the eyes
… are diseased
… in such a way as to affect
9358 The doctor continues:
<quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
9359 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
9360 simple and easy surgical operation
—namely, to remove these
9361 irritant bodies [the eyes].
</quote>
9364 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!
</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
9365 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
9366 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
9367 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
9370 <emphasis role='strong'
>It sometimes
</emphasis> happens that the eggs
9371 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
9372 <quote>chimera.
</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
9373 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
9374 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
9376 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
9377 plot for murder mysteries.
<quote>But the DNA shows with
100 percent
9378 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
9379 scene.
…</quote>
9381 <indexterm startref='idxtcotb' class='endofrange'
/>
9382 <indexterm startref='idxwells'
class=
"endofrange"/>
9384 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
9385 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
9386 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
9387 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
9388 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
9389 understanding of a
<quote>person
</quote> should reflect this reality.
9392 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
9393 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
9394 unfairly enough,
<quote>the copyright wars,
</quote> the more I think we're dealing
9395 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question
<quote>What is
9396 p2p file sharing?
</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
9397 wrong. One side says,
<quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
9398 others' records
—the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
9399 thirty years without any question at all.
</quote> That's true, at least in
9400 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
9401 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
9402 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
9403 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
9406 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
9407 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
9408 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
9409 <quote>friends
</quote> beyond recognition to say
<quote>my ten thousand best friends
</quote> can
9410 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
9411 what
<quote>we have always been allowed to do,
</quote> we have not always been
9412 allowed to share music with
<quote>our ten thousand best friends.
</quote>
9415 Likewise, when the other side says,
<quote>File sharing is just like walking
9416 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
9417 with it,
</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
9418 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
9419 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
9421 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
9425 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
9426 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
9427 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
9428 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
9429 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
9430 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
9431 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
9432 $
1,
000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
9433 CD, I'm liable for $
1,
500,
000 in damages.)
9436 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
9437 that it is both
—both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
9438 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
9439 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
9440 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
9443 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
9444 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
9445 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
9446 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
9447 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
9448 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
9449 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
9450 implemented.
<footnote><para>
9452 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by
</primary></indexterm>
9453 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
9454 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
9455 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,
</quote> 27 June
2003,
9457 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9458 #
33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
9459 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
9460 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
9461 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey,
<quote>House Bill Aims to Up
9462 Stakes on Piracy,
</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times
</citetitle>,
17 July
2003, available at
9463 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
34</ulink>. Civil
9464 penalties are currently set at $
150,
000 per copied song. For a recent
9465 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
9466 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than
600 songs
9467 through a family computer, see
<citetitle>RIAA
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
9468 re. Verizon Internet Services)
</citetitle>,
240 F. Supp.
2d
24
9469 (D.D.C.
2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $
90
9470 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
9471 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
9472 $
12,
000 to $
17,
500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
9473 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $
98
9474 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
9475 Elizabeth Young,
<quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,
</quote> redandblack.com,
9476 August
2003, available at
9477 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
35</ulink>. For an
9478 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
9479 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
9480 identities, see James Collins,
<quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
9481 Name Students,
</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe
</citetitle>,
8 August
2003, D3, available at
9482 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
36</ulink>.
9483 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
9484 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.
</primary></indexterm>
9488 <indexterm startref='idxchimera' class='endofrange'
/>
9490 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
9491 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
9492 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
9493 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
9494 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
9497 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
9498 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
9499 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
9500 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
9501 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
9502 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe
<emphasis>either
</emphasis> extreme
9503 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
9504 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
9508 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
9509 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
9510 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
9511 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
9512 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
9513 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
9514 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
9517 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to
<quote>steal
</quote> music. My
9518 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
9519 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
9520 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
9521 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
9522 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
9523 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
9524 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
9525 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
9526 protection for copyrighted material,
9530 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
9531 material, and we want to protect those rights.
9534 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
9535 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
9536 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
9537 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
9538 produce a totally different industry model.
9541 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
9542 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
9543 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
9544 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
9545 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
9546 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
9547 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
9548 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
9549 interests.
<footnote><para>
9551 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
9552 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
9553 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
9554 House Committee on Commerce,
106th Cong.
29 (
1999) (statement of Peter
9555 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
9556 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
9557 Congressional Testimony File.
</para></footnote>
9560 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
9562 In April
2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
9563 one of
<quote>the major labels.
</quote> Its position on these matters has now
9565 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal
</primary></indexterm>
9568 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
9569 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9570 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9573 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9575 <chapter label=
"12" id=
"harms">
9576 <title>CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
</title>
9578 <emphasis role='strong'
>To fight
</emphasis> <quote>piracy,
</quote> to
9579 protect
<quote>property,
</quote> the content industry has launched a
9580 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9581 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9582 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9583 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9586 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9587 particular, the consequences for
<quote>free culture.
</quote> But my aim now is to
9588 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9592 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9593 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9594 power of the property called
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> is at its greatest in
9597 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
9598 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
9600 Yet
<quote>common sense
</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9601 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9602 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9603 rejection of
<quote>piracy
</quote> still has play.
9605 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard
</primary></indexterm>
9607 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9608 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9609 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9610 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9611 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9612 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9614 <section id=
"constrain">
9615 <title>Constraining Creators
</title>
9617 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9618 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9619 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9620 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9621 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9622 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9623 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9624 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9625 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9626 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9627 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9628 weave together a string
—a mash-up
— of songs from your
9629 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9632 This digital
<quote>capturing and sharing
</quote> is in part an extension of the
9633 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9634 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9635 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9636 of digital
<quote>capturing and sharing
</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9637 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9638 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9639 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9640 the culture all around.
9643 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9644 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9646 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9648 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9649 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9650 storytelling extended across the globe.
9653 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9654 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9655 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9656 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9657 that catalog cartoons from the
1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9658 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9659 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9660 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9661 work is presumptively illegal.
9663 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom
</primary></indexterm>
9664 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of
</secondary></indexterm>
9665 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>in recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
9666 <indexterm><primary>doctors malpractice claims against
</primary></indexterm>
9667 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse
</primary></indexterm>
9669 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9670 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9671 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9672 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9673 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9674 by the RIAA ( Jesse Jordan of chapter
3 was just one) were threatened
9675 with a $
98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted
9676 songs to be copied. Yet World-Com
—which defrauded investors of
9677 $
11 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization
9678 of over $
200 billion
—received a fine of a mere $
750
9679 million.
<footnote><para>
9681 See Lynne W. Jeter,
<citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom
</citetitle>
9682 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley
& Sons,
2003),
176,
204; for details of
9683 the settlement, see MCI press release,
<quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9684 Approval for SEC Settlement
</quote> (
7 July
2003), available at
9685 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
37</ulink>.
9686 <indexterm><primary>Worldcom
</primary></indexterm>
9688 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9689 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9690 no more than $
250,
000 in damages for pain and
9691 suffering.
<footnote>
9693 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9694 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July
2003. For
9695 an overview, see Tanya Albert,
<quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9696 Say Tort Reformers,
</quote> amednews.com,
28 July
2003, available at
9697 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
38</ulink>,
9698 and
<quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,
</quote> CBSNews.com,
9 July
2003,
9700 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9702 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.
</primary></indexterm>
9704 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9705 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9706 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9708 <indexterm><primary>art, underground
</primary></indexterm>
9710 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9711 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9712 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9713 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9714 Disneys
<quote>pirates.
</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9715 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9718 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9719 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9720 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9721 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9722 we will begin to see a world of underground art
—not because the
9723 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9724 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9725 fraught. Already, exhibits of
<quote>illegal art
</quote> tour the United
9726 States.
<footnote><para>
9729 See Danit Lidor,
<quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,
</quote> <citetitle>Wired
</citetitle>,
7 July
9731 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9732 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
41</ulink>.
9734 In what does their
<quote>illegality
</quote> consist?
9735 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9736 critical or reflective.
9738 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by
</primary></indexterm>
9740 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9741 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9742 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>. But an
9743 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9744 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9745 discovered in
2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9746 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9747 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9748 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9749 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9751 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of
</primary></indexterm>
9753 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9754 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9755 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9756 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9757 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9758 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9759 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9760 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9761 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9764 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9765 described in chapter
9766 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"recorders"/>, in
9767 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9768 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9769 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9774 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9775 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9776 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9777 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad
—in
9778 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9779 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9780 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9781 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9782 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9785 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9786 <quote>breathing room
</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9787 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9788 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9789 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9790 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9791 journalists
— these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9792 these rules have little relationship to the
<quote>law
</quote> with which judges
9796 For in a world that threatens $
150,
000 for a single willful
9797 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9798 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9799 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9800 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak
—in that
9801 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9802 <quote>copyright
</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9803 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9804 culture that is free.
9807 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9811 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9812 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9813 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9814 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made
… you're not
9815 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9816 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9817 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying,
<quote>This has been
9818 cleared.
</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9819 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9823 <section id=
"innovators">
9824 <title>Constraining Innovators
</title>
9825 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>innovation hampered by
</secondary></indexterm>
9826 <indexterm id='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='startofrange'
><primary>innovation
</primary><secondary>industry establishment opposed to
</secondary></indexterm>
9827 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='startofrange'
><primary>regulation
</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism
</secondary></indexterm>
9829 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9830 story
—creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9831 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9832 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9833 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9834 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9836 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints2' class='startofrange'
><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
9838 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9839 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9840 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9841 one at that,
188 pages into a book like this), then you can see this
9842 other aspect by substituting
<quote>free market
</quote> every place I've spoken of
9843 <quote>free culture.
</quote> The point is the same, even if the interests
9844 affecting culture are more fundamental.
9847 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9848 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9849 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary
—at
9850 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9851 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9852 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9853 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9854 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9855 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9856 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9857 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9859 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints2' class='endofrange'
/>
9860 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
9861 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists
</primary></indexterm>
9863 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9864 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9865 strategy that I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select:
9866 labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9867 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9868 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9869 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9870 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9871 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9872 lesson. That lesson
—what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9873 <quote>nuclear pall
</quote> that has fallen over the Valley
—has been learned.
9875 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)
</primary></indexterm>
9876 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence
</primary></indexterm>
9878 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9879 I told in
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9880 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9882 <indexterm id='idxmpcom' class='startofrange'
><primary>MP3.com
</primary></indexterm>
9883 <indexterm id='idxmympcom' class='startofrange'
><primary>my.mp3.com
</primary></indexterm>
9884 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
9886 In
1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9887 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9888 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9889 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9890 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9891 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9893 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
9894 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>preference data on
</secondary></indexterm>
9896 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9897 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9898 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9899 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9903 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9904 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9905 preference data. In January
2000, the company launched a service
9906 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9907 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9908 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9909 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9910 wherever you were
—at work or at home
—you could get access
9911 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9912 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9915 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9916 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9918 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9919 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9920 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9921 the kind of content the users liked.
9923 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'
/>
9925 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy
50,
000
9926 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9927 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9928 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9929 therefore purchased
50,
000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9930 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9931 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9932 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was
50,
000
9933 copies, it was
50,
000 copies directed at giving customers something
9934 they had already bought.
9936 <indexterm id='idxvivendiuniversal' class='startofrange'
><primary>Vivendi Universal
</primary></indexterm>
9937 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in
</secondary></indexterm>
9938 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of
</secondary></indexterm>
9939 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>in recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
9940 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of
</secondary></indexterm>
9941 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by
</secondary></indexterm>
9942 <indexterm><primary>regulation
</primary><secondary>outsize penalties of
</secondary></indexterm>
9944 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9945 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9946 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9947 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9948 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9949 MP3.com of $
118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9950 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $
54 million. Vivendi
9951 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9954 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9957 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9958 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9959 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9960 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9961 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9962 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9963 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9966 <indexterm startref='idxvivendiuniversal' class='endofrange'
/>
9968 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9969 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9970 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9972 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9973 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9974 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9975 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9976 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9978 <indexterm startref='idxmpcom' class='endofrange'
/>
9979 <indexterm startref='idxmympcom' class='endofrange'
/>
9980 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='endofrange'
/>
9981 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
9982 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in
</secondary></indexterm>
9983 <indexterm id='idxbmw' class='startofrange'
><primary>BMW
</primary></indexterm>
9984 <indexterm id='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>cars, MP3 sound systems in
</primary></indexterm>
9985 <indexterm><primary>EMI
</primary></indexterm>
9986 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John
</primary></indexterm>
9987 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
9988 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad
</primary></indexterm>
9989 <indexterm><primary>MP3 players
</primary></indexterm>
9990 <indexterm><primary>Napster
</primary><secondary>venture capital for
</secondary></indexterm>
9991 <indexterm id='idxneedlemanrafe' class='startofrange'
><primary>Needleman, Rafe
</primary></indexterm>
9992 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group
</primary></indexterm>
9993 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists
</primary></indexterm>
9995 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April
2003,
9996 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9997 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9998 its development, its cofounder ( John Hummer), and general partner
9999 (Hank Barry).
<footnote><para>
10001 See Joseph Menn,
<quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,
</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
10002 Times
</citetitle>,
23 April
2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
10003 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown,
<quote>The Music
10004 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,
</quote> Salon.com,
1 June
2001, available
10005 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
42</ulink>.
10006 See also Jon Healey,
<quote>Online Music Services Besieged,
</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
10007 Times
</citetitle>,
28 May
2001.
10009 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
10010 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
10011 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
10012 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
10013 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
10014 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
10015 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
10016 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
10017 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
10018 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
10019 <citetitle>Business
2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
10020 discussion with BMW:
10024 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
10025 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
10026 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
10027 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
10028 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
10029 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
10030 United States with bona fide MP3 players.
… <footnote>
10033 Rafe Needleman,
<quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,
</quote> <citetitle>Business
2.0</citetitle>,
16 June
10035 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
43</ulink>. I am grateful
10036 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
10037 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe
</primary></indexterm>
10041 <indexterm startref='idxbmw' class='endofrange'
/>
10042 <indexterm startref='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='endofrange'
/>
10043 <indexterm startref='idxneedlemanrafe' class='endofrange'
/>
10045 This is the world of the mafia
—filled with
<quote>your money or your
10046 life
</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
10047 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
10048 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
10049 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
10050 constantly threatened by litigation.
10054 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
10055 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
10056 enterprises. The point is the definition of
<quote>illegal.
</quote> The law is a
10057 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
10058 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
10059 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
10060 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
10061 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
10062 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
10063 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
10064 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
10065 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
10066 much less creativity.
10068 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
10070 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
10071 use. Whatever the
<quote>real
</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
10072 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
10073 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
10074 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
10075 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
10076 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
10077 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
10078 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
10079 produce an overregulatedregulated market.
10082 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
10083 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
10084 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
10085 culture
—a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
10086 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
10087 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
10088 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
10089 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
10090 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
10091 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
10092 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
10093 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
10094 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
10095 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
10096 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
10097 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
10101 <emphasis role='strong'
>The uncertainty
</emphasis> of the law is one
10102 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
10103 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
10104 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
10105 better protects their content.
10108 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
10109 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
10110 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
10111 this feature is a
<quote>bug.
</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
10112 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
10113 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
10114 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables
<quote>piracy,
</quote> then,
10115 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
10117 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
10119 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
10120 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
10121 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
10122 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.
<footnote><para>
10123 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,
</quote> GartnerG2 and
10124 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
10125 (
2003),
33–35, available at
10126 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
44</ulink>.
10128 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
10129 <quote>broadcast flag
</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
10130 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
10131 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
10132 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
10133 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
10134 copyright violators and disable their machines.
<footnote><para>
10136 GartnerG2,
26–27.
10140 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
10141 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
10142 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
10143 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
10145 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
10146 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
10147 those requirements.
10149 <indexterm><primary>Intel
</primary></indexterm>
10151 In March
2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
10152 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
10153 would impose.
<footnote><para>
10155 See David McGuire,
<quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,
</quote> Newsbytes,
10156 February
2002 (Entertainment).
10158 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
10159 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
10163 <emphasis role='strong'
>There is one
</emphasis> more obvious way in
10164 which this war has harmed innovation
—again, a story that will be
10165 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
10168 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
10169 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
10170 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
10171 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
10173 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
10174 <indexterm><primary>VCRs
</primary></indexterm>
10175 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses
</primary></indexterm>
10176 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in
</secondary></indexterm>
10178 As I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
10179 linkend=
"property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
10180 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
10181 Jessica Litman in her book
<citetitle>Digital
10182 Copyright
</citetitle>,
<footnote><para>
10184 Jessica Litman,
<citetitle>Digital Copyright
</citetitle> (Amherst,
10185 N.Y.: Prometheus Books,
2001).
10186 <indexterm><primary>Digital Copyright (Litman)
</primary></indexterm>
10187 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica
</primary></indexterm>
10189 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter
10 details,
10190 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
10191 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
10192 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
10193 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
10196 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
10197 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
10198 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
10199 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
10200 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
10202 <indexterm id='idxinternetradioon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>radio on
</secondary></indexterm>
10203 <indexterm id='idxradiooninternet' class='startofrange'
><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>on Internet
</secondary></indexterm>
10205 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.
<footnote><para>
10207 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.
</primary></indexterm>
10208 The only circuit court exception is found in
<citetitle>Recording Industry
10209 Association of America (RIAA)
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems
</citetitle>,
180 F.
3d
10210 1072 (
9th Cir.
1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
10211 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
10212 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
10213 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
10214 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
10215 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
10216 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Grokster, Ltd
</citetitle>.,
259 F. Supp.
2d
10217 1029 (C.D. Cal.,
2003), where the court found the link between the
10218 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
10219 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
10222 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
10223 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
10224 here.
<footnote><para>
10226 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy
</primary></indexterm>
10227 For example, in July
2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
10228 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R.
5211), which would immunize
10229 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
10230 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
10231 August
2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
10232 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
10233 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a
<quote>broadcast flag
</quote> that
10234 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
10235 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
10236 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
10237 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2,
<quote>Copyright and
10238 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,
</quote> 27 June
2003,
33–34,
10240 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
44</ulink>.
10241 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.
</primary></indexterm>
10242 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz
</primary></indexterm>
10243 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
10245 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
10246 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
10248 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
10249 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.
</primary></indexterm>
10252 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
10253 As I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
10254 linkend=
"pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
10255 artist doesn't get paid for that
<quote>radio performance
</quote> unless he or she
10256 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
10257 version of
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote>—to memorialize her famous
10258 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden
—
10259 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
10260 copyright owners of
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote> would get some money, whereas
10261 Marilyn Monroe would not.
10264 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
10265 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
10266 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
10267 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
10268 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
10269 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
10270 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
10271 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
10275 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
10276 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
10277 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
10278 spectrum. Thus, I can
<quote>tune in
</quote> to an Internet radio station in
10279 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
10280 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
10284 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
10285 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
10286 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
10287 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
10288 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
10289 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
10290 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
10291 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
10292 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
10293 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
10294 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
10296 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard
</primary></indexterm>
10299 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
10300 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
10301 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
10302 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
10303 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
10304 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
10305 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
10310 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
10311 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
10312 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
10313 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
10314 than by technical restrictions.
… Armstrong likened the situation
10315 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
10316 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
10317 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
10318 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
10319 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
10320 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
10321 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
10322 shackles.
<footnote><para>
10329 This potential for FM radio was never realized
—not
10330 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
10331 underestimated the power of
<quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
10332 legislation
</quote><footnote><para>
10336 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
10339 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
10340 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
10341 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
10342 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
10343 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
10346 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
10347 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
10348 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on radio
</secondary></indexterm>
10349 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
10350 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in
</secondary></indexterm>
10351 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and
</secondary></indexterm>
10352 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>Internet radio hampered by
</secondary></indexterm>
10353 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees
</secondary></indexterm>
10354 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>lobbying power of
</secondary></indexterm>
10356 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
10357 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
10359 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
10360 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
10361 of Internet radio in
1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
10362 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
10363 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
10364 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
10365 of
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote> on the air,
<emphasis>Internet radio
10366 does
</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
10367 radio
—the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
10368 burdens terrestrial radio.
10371 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
10372 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
10373 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
10374 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
10375 over $
1 million a year.
<footnote>
10378 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
10379 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
10380 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
10381 iLaw (Stanford),
3 July
2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
10382 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
10383 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
10384 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No.
2000-
9, CARP
10385 DTRA
1 and
2, available at
10386 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
45</ulink>.
10387 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
10388 C. Picker,
<quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
10389 Distribution,
</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin
</citetitle> (Summer/Fall
2002):
461:
<quote>This was
10390 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
10391 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
10392 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
10393 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
10394 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.
</quote>
10395 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)
</primary></indexterm>
10396 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
10398 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
10401 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='endofrange'
/>
10402 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='endofrange'
/>
10403 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='endofrange'
/>
10404 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='endofrange'
/>
10405 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='endofrange'
/>
10407 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
10408 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
10409 station) would have to collect the following data from
<emphasis>every
10410 listening transaction
</emphasis>:
10412 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
10413 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
10415 name of the service;
10418 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
10421 type of program (archived/looped/live);
10424 date of transmission;
10427 time of transmission;
10430 time zone of origination of transmission;
10433 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
10436 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
10439 sound recording title;
10442 ISRC code of the recording;
10445 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
10448 featured recording artist;
10451 retail album title;
10457 UPC code of the retail album;
10463 copyright owner information;
10466 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
10469 name of the service or entity;
10472 channel or program;
10475 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
10478 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
10481 time zone where the signal was received (user);
10484 unique user identifier;
10487 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
10490 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress
</primary></indexterm>
10492 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
10493 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
10494 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
10495 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
10496 Internet radio has to pay a
<emphasis>type of copyright fee
</emphasis>
10497 that terrestrial radio does not.
10500 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
10501 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
10502 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
10504 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks
</primary></indexterm>
10505 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
10506 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees
</secondary></indexterm>
10507 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
10508 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in
</secondary></indexterm>
10510 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
10511 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
10512 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
10516 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
10517 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
10518 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
10519 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
10520 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
10521 webcasters asked the RIAA,
… <quote>How do you come up with a
10523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
10524 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
10525 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
10526 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
10527 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
10528 business.
…</quote>
10530 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
10532 And the RIAA experts said,
<quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
10533 industry with thousands of webcasters,
<emphasis>we think it should be
10534 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
10535 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market
</emphasis>.
</quote> (Emphasis
10539 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'
/>
10540 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='endofrange'
/>
10541 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='endofrange'
/>
10542 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='endofrange'
/>
10544 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
10545 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
10546 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
10547 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
10548 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
10549 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
10550 effective to prevent it.
10552 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='endofrange'
/>
10553 <indexterm startref='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='endofrange'
/>
10554 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='endofrange'
/>
10555 <indexterm startref='idxinternetradioon' class='endofrange'
/>
10556 <indexterm startref='idxradiooninternet' class='endofrange'
/>
10557 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='endofrange'
/>
10559 <section id=
"corruptingcitizens">
10560 <title>Corrupting Citizens
</title>
10562 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
10564 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
10565 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
10568 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
10569 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
10570 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
10573 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
10574 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
10575 large number of citizens. According to
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>,
43 million
10576 Americans downloaded music in May
2002.
<footnote><para>
10577 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie,
<quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,
</quote> Pew
10578 Internet and American Life Project (
24 April
2001), available at
10579 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
46</ulink>.
10580 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that
37 million
10581 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early
2001.
10583 According to the RIAA,
10584 the behavior of those
43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
10585 set of rules that transform
20 percent of America into criminals. As the
10587 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
10588 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
10589 the world, but against students building search engines, and
10591 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
10592 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
10593 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
10595 response by the other.
10598 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
10599 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
10600 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
10601 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
10602 ($
15,
000,
000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
10603 paying all the money in the world in damages ($
250,
000 in legal fees)
10604 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
10605 ($
12,
000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
10606 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September
2003, the RIAA
10607 sued
261 individuals
—including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
10608 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
10609 was.
<footnote><para>
10611 Alex Pham,
<quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,
</quote> <citetitle>Los
10612 Angeles Times
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, Business.
10614 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
10615 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
10616 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $
2,
000
10617 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
10618 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
10619 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
10622 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition
</primary></indexterm>
10624 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
10625 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
10626 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
10627 consumption of alcohol was
1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
10628 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just
30 percent
10629 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10630 consumption was up to
70 percent of the preprohibition
10631 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10632 number were criminals.
<footnote><para>
10634 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel,
<quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10635 Prohibition,
</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review
</citetitle> 81, no.
2 (
1991):
242.
10638 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10639 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10640 narcotics that
7 percent (or
16 million) Americans now use.
<footnote><para>
10642 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10643 Reform Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st sess. (
5 March
2003) (statement of
10644 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10646 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in
1979 of
14 percent of
10647 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10648 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10649 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10650 cheat.
<footnote><para>
10652 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein,
<quote>Tax
10653 Compliance,
</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature
</citetitle> 36 (
1998):
818 (survey of
10654 compliance literature).
10656 We pride ourselves on our
<quote>free society,
</quote> but an endless array of
10657 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10658 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10660 <indexterm><primary>law schools
</primary></indexterm>
10662 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10663 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10664 students about the importance of
<quote>ethics.
</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10665 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10666 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10667 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10668 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10669 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10670 teach them how to behave ethically
—how to say no to bribes, or
10671 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10672 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10673 Americans
—more significantly in some parts of America than in
10674 others, but still, everywhere in America today
—can't live their
10675 lives both normally and legally, since
<quote>normally
</quote> entails a certain
10676 degree of illegality.
10679 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10680 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10681 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10682 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10683 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10684 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10685 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10686 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10687 to consider the alternative.
10691 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10692 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10693 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10694 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10695 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10696 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10699 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10700 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10701 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10702 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10703 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10704 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10705 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10706 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10707 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10708 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10709 introduced this different idea of
<quote>sharing.
</quote> We need to be able to
10710 call these twenty million Americans
<quote>citizens,
</quote> not
<quote>felons.
</quote>
10713 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10714 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10715 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10716 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10717 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10718 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10719 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10720 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10721 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10722 a nation of felons?
10725 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10728 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10729 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10730 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10731 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10734 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10735 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That
<quote>use
</quote> of the
10736 recordings is free.
10739 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10740 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10741 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am
<quote>free
</quote> to copy,
10742 or
<quote>rip,
</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10743 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that
<quote>freedom
</quote> was a
10744 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the
<quote>Rip, Mix, Burn
</quote>
10745 capacities of digital technologies.
10747 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda
</primary></indexterm>
10748 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>mix technology and
</secondary></indexterm>
10750 This
<quote>use
</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10751 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10752 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10753 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10754 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10755 Others
—the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10756 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10757 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10758 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10761 This use is enabled by unprotected media
—either CDs or records.
10762 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10763 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10764 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10765 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10766 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10767 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10768 on people's machines.
10771 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10772 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10773 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10774 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10775 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10776 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10778 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10779 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10780 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10781 plastic or were part of a massively complex
<quote>digital rights
10782 management
</quote> system.
10784 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'
/>
10786 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10787 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10788 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10789 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10790 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10791 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10792 freedom to move content easily?
10795 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10796 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10797 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10798 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10799 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10800 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10801 alternative
—namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10802 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10803 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10806 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10807 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10808 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10809 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10810 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10811 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10812 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10815 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10816 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10817 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10818 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10821 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10822 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10824 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10826 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10827 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10829 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation
</primary></indexterm>
10830 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'
><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by
</primary></indexterm>
10832 <emphasis role='strong'
>There's one more
</emphasis> aspect to this
10833 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10834 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10835 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10836 <quote>collateral damage
</quote> that
<quote>arises whenever you turn
10837 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.
</quote> This
10838 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10840 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
10842 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,
</quote> von Lohmann
10847 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10848 evaporate to one degree or another.
… If you're a copyright
10849 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10850 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10851 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10852 access?
… Our sensibilities change as soon as we think,
<quote>Oh, well,
10853 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.
</quote> Well, what this campaign
10854 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10855 American Internet-using population into
<quote>lawbreakers.
</quote>
10859 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10860 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10861 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10864 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in
2003 as the RIAA
10865 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10866 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10867 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10868 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10869 an Internet user is revealed.
10872 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10873 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10874 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10875 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10876 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10877 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10878 the family could be liable for $
2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10879 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10880 Jesse Jordan.
<footnote><para>
10882 See Frank Ahrens,
<quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10883 Mother in Calif.,
12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,
</quote>
10884 <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, E1; Chris Cobbs,
<quote>Worried Parents
10885 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10886 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10887 Being Sued,
</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune
</citetitle>,
30 August
2003, C1; Jefferson
10888 Graham,
<quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,
</quote> <citetitle>USA Today
</citetitle>,
15 September
10889 2003,
4D; John Schwartz,
<quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10890 Fan, Either,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
25 September
2003, C1; Margo Varadi,
<quote>Is
10891 Brianna a Criminal?
</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star
</citetitle>,
18 September
2003, P7.
10896 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10897 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10898 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.
<footnote><para>
10900 See
<quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10901 Some Methods Used,
</quote> CNN.com, available at
10902 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
47</ulink>.
10904 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10905 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10906 one of those MP3s will have the same
<quote>fingerprint.
</quote>
10909 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10910 friend gives a CD to your daughter
—a collection of songs just
10911 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10912 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10913 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10914 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10915 network is
<quote>cooperating
</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10916 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10917 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10918 as a
<quote>criminal.
</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10919 to deploy,
<footnote><para>
10921 See Jeff Adler,
<quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,
</quote>
10922 <citetitle>Boston Globe
</citetitle>,
18 May
2003, City Weekly,
1; Frank Ahrens,
<quote>Four
10923 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10924 Colleges,
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
4 April
2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10925 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,
</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10926 Monitor
</citetitle>,
2 September
2003,
20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas,
<quote>Music
10927 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10928 Lawsuit Possible,
</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune
</citetitle>,
16 July
2003,
1C; Beth Cox,
<quote>RIAA
10929 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,
</quote> <citetitle>Internet News
</citetitle>,
30 January
10930 2003, available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10931 #
48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista,
<quote>Download Warning
101: Freshman
10932 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10933 Sharing,
</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
11 August
2003, E11;
<quote>Raid, Letters
10934 Are Weapons at Universities,
</quote> <citetitle>USA Today
</citetitle>,
26 September
2000,
3D.
10936 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10937 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10939 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'
/>
10940 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
10942 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10943 a lawyer for her (at $
300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10944 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10945 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10946 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10947 this
<quote>contraband
</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10950 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10951 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10952 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10957 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10958 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10959 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10960 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10961 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10962 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10963 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10964 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10965 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10966 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10967 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10968 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10969 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10970 larger number of Americans than drug use.
… If forty to sixty
10971 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10972 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10977 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered
<quote>criminals
</quote> under
10978 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective
—
10979 securing rights to authors
—without these millions being
10980 considered
<quote>criminals,
</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10981 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10982 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10985 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10989 <part id=
"c-balances">
10990 <title>BALANCES
</title>
10993 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10995 <emphasis role='strong'
>So here's
</emphasis> the picture: You're
10996 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
10997 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
10998 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
10999 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
11002 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
11003 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
11004 stop
—or before she understands just why she should
11005 stop
—the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
11006 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
11010 <emphasis role='strong'
>A war
</emphasis> about copyright rages all
11011 around
—and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
11012 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
11013 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
11014 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
11015 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
11016 that if let alone would burn itself out.
11019 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
11020 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
11021 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
11022 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
11023 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
11024 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
11025 made that is happening all around.
11028 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
11029 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
11030 gasoline onto this fire.
11033 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
11034 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
11035 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
11036 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
11039 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
11040 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
11041 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
11042 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
11043 success will require.
11047 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
11048 <chapter label=
"13" id=
"eldred">
11049 <title>CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
</title>
11050 <indexterm id='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='startofrange'
><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel
</primary></indexterm>
11052 <emphasis role='strong'
>In
1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
11053 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
11054 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
11055 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
11056 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
11057 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
11058 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
11061 It didn't work
—at least for his daughters. They didn't find
11062 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
11063 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
11064 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
11065 them available for free.
11067 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt5' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
11068 <indexterm><primary>Grimm fairy tales
</primary></indexterm>
11070 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
11071 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
11072 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
11073 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
11074 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
11075 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
11076 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
11077 many others, into a form more accessible
—technically
11078 accessible
—today.
11081 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
11082 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's
<citetitle>Scarlet Letter
</citetitle> had passed into the
11083 public domain in
1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
11084 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
11085 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
11086 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
11087 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
11088 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (
<citetitle>Cinderella
</citetitle>), sometimes not
11089 (
<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame
</citetitle>,
<citetitle>Treasure Planet
</citetitle>). These are all
11090 commercial publications of public domain works.
11092 <indexterm startref='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='endofrange'
/>
11093 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt5' class='endofrange'
/>
11095 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
11096 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
11097 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
11098 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
11099 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
11100 call the
<quote>noncommercial publishing industry,
</quote> which before the
11101 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
11102 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
11103 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
11104 generally.
<footnote><para>
11106 <indexterm><primary>pornography
</primary></indexterm>
11107 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
11108 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
11109 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers
—people who
11110 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
11111 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
11112 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
11113 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
11114 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
11115 Decency Act of
1996. It was partly because of the burden on
11116 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
11117 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
11118 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
11119 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
11120 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
11121 protect noncommercial pornographers.
</para></footnote>
11124 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In
1998, Robert Frost's
11125 collection of poems
<citetitle>New Hampshire
</citetitle> was slated to
11126 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
11127 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
11128 in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
11129 linkend=
"property-i"/>, in
1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
11130 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights
—this time by
11131 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
11132 than
1923 to his collection until
2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
11133 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
11134 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
11135 more than
1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
11137 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary
</primary></indexterm>
11138 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny
</primary></indexterm>
11141 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
11142 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
11143 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
11144 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
11145 <quote>copyrights should be forever.
</quote><footnote><para>
11147 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary
</primary></indexterm>
11148 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny
</primary></indexterm>
11149 The full text is:
<quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
11150 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
11151 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
11152 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
11153 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
11154 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
11155 Congress,
</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946,
9951-
2 (October
7,
1998).
11160 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
11161 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
11162 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
11163 second law passed in
1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
11164 of publishing would make Eldred a felon
—whether or not anyone
11165 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
11169 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
11171 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
11173 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
11174 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
11176 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
11180 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science
…
11181 by securing for limited Times to Authors
… exclusive Right to
11182 their
… Writings.
…
11186 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
11187 clause of Article I, section
8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
11188 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
11189 something
—for example, to regulate
<quote>commerce among the several
11190 states
</quote> or
<quote>declare War.
</quote> But here, the
<quote>something
</quote> is something quite
11191 specific
—to
<quote>promote
… Progress
</quote>—through means that
11192 are also specific
— by
<quote>securing
</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights
</quote> (i.e.,
11193 copyrights)
<quote>for limited Times.
</quote>
11195 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
11197 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
11198 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
11199 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
11200 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be
<quote>limited
</quote> will have
11201 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
11202 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
11203 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
11204 what the Constitution plainly forbids
—perpetual terms
<quote>on the
11205 installment plan,
</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
11208 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
11209 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
11210 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
11211 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
11212 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
11213 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
11214 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
11215 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
11216 this gravy train going.
11219 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
11220 government.
<quote>Corruption
</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
11221 bribed. Rather,
<quote>corruption
</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
11222 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
11223 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
11224 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
11225 do
—and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
11228 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
11229 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
11230 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
11231 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in
1963. His poetry
11232 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
11233 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
11234 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
11235 published by anyone for free.
11238 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $
100,
000 a year from
11239 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
11240 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
11241 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
11245 <quote>Next year,
</quote> the adviser announces,
<quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
11247 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
11248 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
11249 receiving the annual royalty check of $
100,
000 from the publishers of
11250 those works.
</quote>
11253 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,
</quote> she continues,
<quote>that
11254 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
11255 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
11256 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.
</quote>
11259 <quote>Hope?
</quote> a fellow board member says.
<quote>Can't we be doing something
11263 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,
</quote> the adviser responds.
<quote>We could contribute
11264 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
11265 they support the bill.
</quote>
11268 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
11269 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it.
<quote>How much
11270 would we get if this extension were passed?
</quote> you ask the adviser.
<quote>How
11271 much is it worth?
</quote>
11274 <quote>Well,
</quote> the adviser says,
<quote>if you're confident that you will continue
11275 to get at least $
100,
000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
11276 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (
6 percent),
11277 then this law would be worth $
1,
146,
000 to the estate.
</quote>
11280 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
11281 correct conclusion:
11284 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
11285 $
1,
000,
000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
11287 would assure that the bill was passed?
</quote>
11290 <quote>Absolutely,
</quote> the adviser responds.
<quote>It is worth it to you to
11292 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
11293 copyrights. Which for us means over $
1,
000,
000.
</quote>
11296 You quickly get the point
—you as the member of the board and, I
11297 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
11298 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
11299 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
11300 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
11301 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
11303 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
11304 the copyright term extended.
11307 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
11308 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
11309 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
11312 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
11314 Term Extension Act, this
<quote>theory
</quote> about incentives was proved
11315 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
11316 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
11317 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
11318 contributions.
<footnote><para>
11319 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press,
<quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
11320 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators
20 More Years,
</quote>
11321 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune
</citetitle>,
17 October
1998,
22.
11323 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
11324 $
1.5 million lobbying in the
1998 election cycle. They paid out more
11325 than $
200,
000 in campaign contributions.
<footnote><para>
11326 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown,
<quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
11327 Age,
</quote> available at
11328 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
49</ulink>.
11330 Disney is estimated to have
11331 contributed more than $
800,
000 to reelection campaigns in the
11332 cycle.
<footnote><para>
11334 Alan K. Ota,
<quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,
</quote>
11335 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week
</citetitle>,
8 August
1990, available at
11336 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
50</ulink>.
11341 <emphasis role='strong'
>Constitutional law
</emphasis> is not oblivious
11342 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
11343 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
11344 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
11345 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
11346 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
11347 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
11348 constitutional requirement that terms be
<quote>limited.
</quote> If
11349 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
11353 It was also my judgment that
<emphasis>this
</emphasis> Supreme Court
11354 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
11355 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
11356 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
11357 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
11358 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
11361 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
11362 decision in
1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
11366 Since
1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
11367 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
11368 power to regulate only
<quote>commerce among the several states
</quote> (aka
11370 commerce
</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
11371 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
11376 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
11377 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
11378 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
11379 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
11380 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
11382 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.
</primary></indexterm>
11384 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
11385 that in
<citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>. The government had
11386 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
11387 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
11388 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
11389 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
11390 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
11391 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
11392 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
11393 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
11394 position to second-guess Congress.
11397 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,
</quote>
11398 the Chief Justice wrote.
<footnote><para>
11399 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>,
514 U.S.
549,
564 (
1995).
11401 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
11402 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
11403 Congress's power. The decision in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
11404 later in
<citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Morrison
</citetitle>.
<footnote><para>
11406 <citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Morrison
</citetitle>,
529 U.S.
598 (
2000).
11410 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
11411 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.
<footnote><para>
11413 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
11414 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
11415 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
11416 by the government would allow the government unending power to
11417 regulate commerce
—the limitation to interstate commerce
11418 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
11419 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
11420 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights
—the
11421 limitation to
<quote>limited times
</quote> notwithstanding.
11423 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
11424 yield the conclusion that Congress
11425 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
11426 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
11427 term, then there would be no
<quote>stopping point
</quote> to Congress's power over
11428 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
11429 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
11430 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
11431 term of existing copyrights.
11434 <emphasis>If
</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>
11435 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> stood for
11436 politics
—a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
11437 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
11438 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
11439 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
11440 demonstrating the
<quote>fidelity
</quote> in such an interpretation of the
11441 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
11442 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
11443 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
11444 were going to be petty politicians.
11446 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in
</secondary></indexterm>
11447 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of
</secondary></indexterm>
11448 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
11449 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
11451 <emphasis role='strong'
>Now let's pause
</emphasis> for a moment to
11452 make sure we understand what the argument in
11453 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
11454 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
11455 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
11456 piracy
—piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
11457 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
11458 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
11459 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
11460 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
11461 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
11462 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
11463 power
—expressed through the power of lobbyists' money
—to
11464 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
11465 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
11466 piracy that affects us all.
11468 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association
</primary></indexterm>
11470 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
11472 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
11473 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
11474 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than
<quote>legal piracy.
</quote><footnote><para>
11476 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle>
11477 v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618), n
.10, available
11478 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
51</ulink>.
11480 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
11481 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
11482 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
11486 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
11488 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
11490 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
11491 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
11492 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
11493 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
11494 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
11495 bought to extend them again.
11498 <emphasis role='strong'
>It is valuable
</emphasis> copyrights that are
11499 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
11500 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.
</quote> These works are too valuable for
11501 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
11502 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
11503 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
11504 the
1920s and
1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
11505 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
11506 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
11507 and no longer available as a result.
11510 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (
1923 to
11511 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
11512 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
11513 copyright holders for that
2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
11514 But the law and its effect were not limited to that
2 percent. The law
11515 extended the terms of copyright generally.
<footnote><para>
11516 <!-- f10. --> The figure of
2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
11518 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
11519 of Petitioners,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
7, available at
11520 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
52</ulink>.
11525 Think practically about the consequence of this
11526 extension
—practically,
11527 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
11529 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
11530 work. In
1930,
10,
047 books were published. In
2000,
174 of those
11531 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
11532 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
11534 9,
873. What would you have to do?
11536 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
11538 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the
9,
873 books were
11539 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
11540 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
11541 titles and authors of the
9,
873 books with the copyright registration
11542 and renewal records for works published in
1930. That will produce a
11543 list of books still under copyright.
11546 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
11547 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
11550 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
11552 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
11553 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
11554 being at least a list?
11557 But there is no list. There may be a name from
1930, and then in
11558 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
11560 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
11562 of such records
—especially since the person who registered is
11563 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about
1930!
11566 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,
</quote> the
11567 apologists for the system respond.
<quote>Why should there be a list of
11568 copyright owners?
</quote>
11571 Well, actually, if you think about it, there
<emphasis>are
</emphasis>
11572 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
11573 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
11574 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
11575 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
11576 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
11577 what tangible property.
11580 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
11581 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
11582 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
11584 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
11585 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
11586 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
11588 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
11589 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
11590 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
11591 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
11592 know quite well who owns what property.
11595 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
11596 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
11598 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
11599 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
11600 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
11601 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
11602 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
11603 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
11604 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
11607 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
11608 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
11610 for other creative works is much more dire.
11612 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'
><primary>Agee, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
11613 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios
</primary></indexterm>
11614 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films
</primary></indexterm>
11615 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The
</primary></indexterm>
11617 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
11618 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
11619 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
11620 made between
1921 and
1951. Only one of these films,
<citetitle>The Lucky Dog
</citetitle>, is
11621 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after
1923
11622 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
11623 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
11624 money. According to one estimate,
<quote>Roach has sold about
60,
000
11625 videocassettes and
50,
000 DVDs of the duo's silent
11626 films.
</quote><footnote><para>
11628 See David G. Savage,
<quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,
</quote>
11629 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times
</citetitle>,
6 October
2002; David Streitfeld,
<quote>Classic Movies,
11630 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
11631 Down Copyright Extension,
</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune
</citetitle>,
9 October
2002.
11635 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
11636 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
11637 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11638 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11641 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11643 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11644 any continuing commercial value. The rest
—to the extent it
11645 survives at all
—sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11646 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11647 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11648 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11649 work available for distribution.
11652 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11653 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11654 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11655 it cost more than $
10,
000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11656 film in
1993, it can now cost as little as $
100 to digitize one hour of
11657 mm film.
<footnote><para>
11659 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11660 Supporting the Petitoners,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537
11661 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618),
12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11662 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle>
11663 v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>, available at
11664 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
53</ulink>.
11669 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11671 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11672 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11673 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11674 locate the copyright owner.
11677 Or more accurately,
<emphasis>owners
</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11678 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11679 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11680 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11681 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11682 to these films is exceptionally high.
11685 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11686 copyright owner when she shows up?
</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11687 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11688 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11689 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11690 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11691 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11692 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11693 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11696 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11698 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11699 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11701 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11702 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11703 the copyright expires.
11705 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'
/>
11707 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11708 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11709 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11711 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11715 <emphasis role='strong'
>Of all the
</emphasis> creative work produced
11716 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11717 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11718 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11719 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11720 the copyright acts as an
<quote>engine of free expression.
</quote>
11723 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11724 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11726 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11727 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11728 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11730 the commercial life ends.
11733 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11734 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes
& Noble, and
11735 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11737 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11739 night watching a
1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11740 of culture is important and valuable
—for entertainment but also, and
11741 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11742 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11743 have, we need to have access to this history.
11746 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11748 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11749 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11750 this context do no good.
11753 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11754 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11755 <emphasis>copyright-related use
</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11756 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11757 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11758 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11759 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11760 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11761 was independent of copyright law.
11764 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11765 a film
—the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs
—were
11766 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11767 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11768 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11769 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11770 market didn't have more to offer.
11773 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11774 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11775 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11776 would not have interfered with anything.
11779 But this situation has now changed.
11781 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'
><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
11783 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11784 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11785 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11786 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11787 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11788 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11789 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11790 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11791 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11792 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11795 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11796 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11797 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11798 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11799 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11800 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11801 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11802 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11803 written for a radically different context.
11806 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11807 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11808 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11809 <emphasis>copyright
</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11810 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11811 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11812 context, copyright is serving no purpose
<emphasis>at all
</emphasis>
11813 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11814 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11817 You may well ask,
<quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11818 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11819 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11820 culture widely?
</quote>
11823 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11824 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes
& Noble
11825 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11826 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11827 of a library is to serve what
<quote>the market
</quote> would demand. But if you
11828 think the role of a library is bigger than this
—if you think its
11829 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11830 particular bit of that culture or not
—then we can't count on the
11831 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11833 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'
/>
11835 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11836 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11837 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11838 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11840 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11841 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11842 culture,
94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11843 and
1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11844 commercial market, if access is a value, then
6 percent is a failure
11845 to provide that value.
<footnote><para>
11847 Jason Schultz,
<quote>The Myth of the
1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,
</quote> 20
11848 December
2002, available at
11849 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
54</ulink>.
11854 <emphasis role='strong'
>In January
1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11855 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11856 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11857 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (
1)
11858 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11859 <quote>limited Times
</quote> requirement, and (
2) that extending terms
11860 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11863 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11864 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11865 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11866 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11867 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11870 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11871 copyrights be for
<quote>limited Times
</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11872 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11873 <quote>stopping point
</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11874 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11875 terms that are
<quote>limited.
</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11876 to interpret the term
<quote>limited Times
</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11877 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11878 power to extend existing terms.
11881 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11882 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11883 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11884 whole, where the court will sit
<quote>en banc
</quote> to hear the case.
11886 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David
</primary></indexterm>
11888 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11889 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11891 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11892 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11893 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11894 overstepped its bounds.
11897 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11898 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11899 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11900 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11901 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11904 But in February
2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11905 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11906 was set for October of
2002. The summer would be spent writing
11907 briefs and preparing for argument.
11910 <emphasis role='strong'
>It is over
</emphasis> a year later as I write
11911 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
11912 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
11913 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
11914 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
11915 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
11916 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
11917 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
11918 client, Eric Eldred.
11921 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11922 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11923 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11926 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey
</primary></indexterm>
11928 <emphasis role='strong'
>The mistake
</emphasis> was made early, though
11929 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
11930 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
11931 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
11932 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
11933 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11934 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11935 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11936 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11938 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11939 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan
</primary></indexterm>
11940 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey
</primary></indexterm>
11942 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11943 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11944 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11945 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11946 told me, if we could make the issue seem
<quote>important
</quote> to the Supreme
11947 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11948 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against
<quote>the
11949 most powerful media companies in the world.
</quote>
11952 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
11953 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
11954 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
11955 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
11956 <quote>right
</quote> as in
<quote>true,
</quote> I thought, but it is
<quote>wrong
</quote> as in
<quote>it just shouldn't be
11957 that way.
</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
11958 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
11959 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
11961 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
11962 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
11964 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
11965 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
11966 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
11968 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
11969 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
11970 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
11973 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
11974 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
11975 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
11976 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
11977 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
11978 why it was unconstitutional.
11981 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
11983 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
11984 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
11985 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
11986 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
11987 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
11988 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
11989 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
11990 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
11991 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
11992 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
11993 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
11994 <emphasis>law
</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
11995 the widest range of credible critics
—credible not because they
11996 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
11997 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
11999 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum
</primary></indexterm>
12000 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis
</primary></indexterm>
12002 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
12003 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
12004 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
12005 Congress. In November
1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
12006 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
12007 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
12008 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
12009 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
12010 to get bogged down?
</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
12011 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
12012 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
12013 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
12016 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
12017 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
12018 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
12019 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
12020 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
12021 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
12023 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
12024 <indexterm><primary>Intel
</primary></indexterm>
12025 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
12026 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum
</primary></indexterm>
12028 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
12029 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
12031 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
12032 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/ Linux
12033 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
12034 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
12035 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
12036 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
12037 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
12038 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
12040 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries
</primary></indexterm>
12041 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union
</primary></indexterm>
12043 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
12044 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
12045 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
12046 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
12048 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios
</primary></indexterm>
12050 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
12051 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
12052 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
12053 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
12056 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George
</primary></indexterm>
12057 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
12058 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James
</primary></indexterm>
12059 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
12060 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton
</primary></indexterm>
12062 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
12063 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
12064 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
12065 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
12066 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
12067 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
12068 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
12069 nothing more than
<quote>rent-seeking
</quote>—the fancy term economists use
12070 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
12072 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
12073 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan
</primary></indexterm>
12074 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen
</primary></indexterm>
12075 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
12077 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
12078 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
12079 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
12080 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
12081 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
12082 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
12083 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
12084 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
12086 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
12087 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
12088 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
12090 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
12091 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of
</secondary></indexterm>
12092 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>Commerce Clause of
</secondary></indexterm>
12094 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
12095 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
12096 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
12097 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
12098 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
12099 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
12100 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
12101 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
12102 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
12103 confidence in our argument.
12106 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
12107 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these
<quote>friends
</quote> included
12108 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
12109 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
12113 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
12114 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either
—they
12115 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
12116 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
12117 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
12118 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
12121 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George
</primary></indexterm>
12122 <indexterm><primary>Porgy and Bess
</primary></indexterm>
12123 <indexterm><primary>pornography
</primary></indexterm>
12125 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
12126 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
12127 Dr. Seuss's work
— better than allowing it to fall into the
12128 public domain
—because if this creativity were in the public
12129 domain, then people could use it to
<quote>glorify drugs or to create
12130 pornography.
</quote><footnote><para>
12132 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al.,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537
12133 U.S. (
2003) (No.
01-
618),
19.
12135 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
12136 <quote>protection
</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
12137 to license
<citetitle>Porgy and Bess
</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
12138 Americans in the cast.
<footnote><para>
12140 Dinitia Smith,
<quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
12141 Mouse Joins the Fray,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
28 March
1998, B7.
12144 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
12145 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
12146 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
12149 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
12150 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
12151 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
12152 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
12153 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say,
<quote>Give us twenty years
12154 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
12155 better with them than anyone else.
</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
12156 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
12157 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
12158 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
12161 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
12162 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
12163 copyrights
—extensions that would further concentrate the market;
12164 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
12165 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
12168 <emphasis role='strong'
>Between February
</emphasis> and October, there
12169 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
12170 I set the strategy.
12172 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.
</primary></indexterm>
12173 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day
</primary></indexterm>
12175 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
12176 called
<quote>the Conservatives.
</quote> The other we called
<quote>the Rest.
</quote> The
12177 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
12178 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
12179 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
12180 five who had supported the
<citetitle>Lopez/Morrison
</citetitle> line
12181 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
12182 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
12184 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12185 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'
><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader
</primary></indexterm>
12187 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
12188 Congress's power. These four
—Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
12189 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer
—had repeatedly argued that
12191 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
12192 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
12193 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
12194 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
12195 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
12196 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
12199 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
12200 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
12201 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
12202 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
12203 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
12204 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
12205 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
12206 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
12209 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12211 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
12212 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
12213 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
12214 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
12215 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
12216 these retrospective extensions.
12218 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'
/>
12220 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
12221 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
12222 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
12223 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
12224 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
12225 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
12228 This analysis of
<quote>the Rest
</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
12229 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
12230 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
12231 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
12232 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation
—the
12233 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
12234 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
12235 powers have limits.
12238 This then was the core of our strategy
—a strategy for which I am
12239 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
12240 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>
12241 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
12242 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
12243 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
12244 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
12245 supposed to be
<quote>limited.
</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
12246 reconcile
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> with
12247 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
12248 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
12252 <emphasis role='strong'
>The argument
</emphasis> on the government's
12253 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
12254 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
12255 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
12256 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
12257 that practice is unconstitutional.
12260 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
12261 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in
1831
12262 and in
1909. And of course, in
1962, Congress began extending
12264 terms regularly
—eleven times in forty years.
12267 But this
<quote>consistency
</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
12269 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
12270 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
12271 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
12273 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
12275 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
12276 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
12278 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
12279 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
12282 <emphasis role='strong'
>Oral argument
</emphasis> was scheduled for the
12283 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
12284 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
12285 <quote>mooted
</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
12287 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
12288 help in the case. Such
<quote>moots
</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
12289 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
12292 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
12293 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
12294 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
12295 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
12297 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
12298 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
12301 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12302 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
12303 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
12305 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
12306 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
12307 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
12308 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
12311 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
12312 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
12313 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
12314 the harm
—passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
12315 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.
</quote>
12317 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12319 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
12320 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
12321 right thing
—not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
12322 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
12323 does the right thing
—not because of politics but because it is right. As
12324 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
12325 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
12326 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
12329 <emphasis role='strong'
>The night before
</emphasis> the argument, a
12330 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
12331 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
12332 culture. Hundreds stood in line
12334 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
12335 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
12336 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
12339 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
12340 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
12341 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
12342 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
12344 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
12345 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
12346 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
12347 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
12348 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
12349 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
12350 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
12351 family of the Justices.
12354 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
12355 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
12356 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
12357 those enumerated powers had any limit.
12359 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day
</primary></indexterm>
12361 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
12362 The history was bothering her.
12366 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
12367 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
12368 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
12369 practice that began with the very first act.
12373 She was quite willing to concede
<quote>that this flies directly in the face
12374 of what the framers had in mind.
</quote> But my response again and again
12375 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
12379 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
12380 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
12381 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
12382 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
12387 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
12388 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
12389 Kennedy, who observed,
12393 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
12394 the '
76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
12395 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
12396 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
12397 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
12401 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
12407 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
12408 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
12409 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
12410 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
12411 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
12414 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12416 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
12417 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
12418 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
12419 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
12420 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
12423 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
12424 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> ruling,
12425 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
12428 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
12429 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
12431 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
12435 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
12436 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
12439 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
12440 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
12442 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
12443 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
12444 into the Copyright Clause.
12447 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.
</primary></indexterm>
12449 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
12450 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
12451 asked Solicitor General Olson,
12455 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12456 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
12457 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
12458 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12463 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
12464 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
12465 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
12466 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
12467 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
12468 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
12469 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
12470 Patent Clause
— indeed, the very first case striking a law of
12471 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
12472 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
12476 <emphasis role='strong'
>As I left
</emphasis> the court that day, I
12477 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
12478 hundred questions I wished I had
12480 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
12481 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
12485 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
12486 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
12487 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
12488 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
12489 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
12490 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
12491 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
12492 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
12493 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
12494 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
12495 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court
—in particular,
12496 the Conservatives
—would feel itself constrained by the rule of
12497 law that it had established elsewhere.
12500 <emphasis role='strong'
>The morning
</emphasis> of January
15,
2003, I
12501 was five minutes late to the office and missed the
7:
00 A.M. call from
12502 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
12503 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
12504 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
12505 majority. There were two dissents.
12508 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
12509 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
12510 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
12513 My
<emphasis>reasoning
</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
12514 money in the world against
<emphasis>reasoning
</emphasis>. And here
12515 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
12519 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
12520 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
12521 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
12522 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
12523 even appear in the Court's opinion.
12525 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader
</primary></indexterm>
12528 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
12529 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
12530 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
12531 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
12534 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable
—for her, and for Justice
12535 Souter. Neither believes in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
12536 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
12537 they had worked so hard to defeat.
12540 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
12541 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
12542 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
12543 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
12544 reconcile the two simply
<emphasis>by not addressing the
12545 argument
</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
12546 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
12547 followed from the
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
12548 be limited, but in this context it would not.
12551 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
12552 they would respect? By what right did they
—the silent
12553 five
—get to select the part of the Constitution they would
12554 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
12555 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
12556 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
12557 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
12558 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
12559 the system we have.
12561 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12563 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
12564 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
12565 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
12566 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
12567 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
12568 the Court discounted the parallel
—without explaining how the
12569 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
12570 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
12571 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
12573 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12575 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
12576 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
12577 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
12578 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
12579 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author
99.8
12580 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
12581 that the actual number was
99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
12582 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
12583 <quote>limited,
</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
12584 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
12587 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
12588 because neither believed in the
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
12589 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
12590 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
12591 Sentelle. It was
<citetitle>Hamlet
</citetitle> without the Prince.
12594 <emphasis role='strong'
>Defeat brings depression
</emphasis>. They say
12595 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
12596 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
12599 <indexterm><primary>originalism
</primary></indexterm>
12601 It was first anger with the five
<quote>Conservatives.
</quote> It would have been
12602 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> didn't
12603 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
12604 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
12605 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
12606 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
12607 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is
<quote>originalism
</quote>—to
12608 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
12609 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
12610 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> and many other
<quote>originalist
</quote> rulings. Where was their
12611 <quote>originalism
</quote> now?
12614 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
12615 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
12616 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
12617 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
12619 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
12620 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
12621 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
12622 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
12623 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
12624 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
12625 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
12629 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
12631 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
12634 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12636 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
12637 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
12638 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
12639 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
12640 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
12641 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12642 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12643 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12644 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12647 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12648 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12649 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12650 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12651 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12652 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12653 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12654 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12655 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12656 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12657 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12658 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12659 effort to persuade; but I
12660 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12661 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12662 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12663 should decide the issue.
12665 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12666 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
12668 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12669 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12673 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12674 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12675 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12676 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12679 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12680 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12681 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12682 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12685 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
12687 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12688 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12689 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12690 case was a mistake.
<quote>The Court is not ready,
</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12691 issue should not be raised until it is.
12694 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12695 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12696 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12697 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12698 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12699 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12700 this case
—a decision I had made four years before
—was wrong.
12703 <emphasis role='strong'
>While the reaction
</emphasis> to the Sonny
12704 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12705 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12706 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12707 that battle over ideas. Where
12709 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12710 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12711 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12712 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12713 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12714 harmful law.
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12718 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12719 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12720 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12721 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12722 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12723 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12727 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12728 hilarious images
—of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12729 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced on the next page
12730 (
<xref linkend=
"fig-18"/>). The
<quote>powerful and wealthy
</quote> line is a bit
12731 unfair. But the punch in the face felt exactly like that.
12732 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben
</primary></indexterm>
12734 <figure id=
"fig-18">
12735 <title>Tom the Dancing Bug cartoon
</title>
12736 <graphic fileref=
"images/18.png"></graphic>
12737 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben
</primary></indexterm>
12740 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12741 quote from
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>. That
<quote>grand experiment
</quote> we call the
12742 <quote>public domain
</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think,
<quote>Honey,
12743 I shrunk the Constitution.
</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12744 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12745 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12746 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12748 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12750 <chapter label=
"14" id=
"eldred-ii">
12751 <title>CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
</title>
12753 <emphasis role='strong'
>The day
</emphasis>
12754 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12755 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12756 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> was denied
—meaning the case was
12757 really finally over
—fate would have it that I was giving a
12758 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12759 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12760 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12761 wrote an op-ed piece.
12763 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12765 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12766 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12767 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12768 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12769 Justice Kennedy:
<quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12770 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12771 that.
</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12772 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12775 <citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12776 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12777 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12778 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12779 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12780 the work passed into the public domain.
12783 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12784 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12785 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12788 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12789 is either the
<quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act
</quote> or the
<quote>Copyright
12790 Term Deregulation Act.
</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12791 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12792 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12793 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $
1. But for
12794 everything else, let the content go.
12796 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
12798 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12799 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12800 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12801 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12802 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12803 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12804 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12805 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12806 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12807 the stupid harm of the present system.
12810 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12811 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12812 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12813 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12814 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12815 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12816 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12817 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12818 where copyright owners could be identified.
12820 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
12821 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
12823 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12824 As I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
12825 linkend=
"property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12826 removed in
1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12827 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.
<footnote><para>
12829 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law
</primary></indexterm>
12830 Until the
1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12831 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12832 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12833 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the
1908 act,
12834 every text of the Convention has provided that
<quote>the enjoyment and the
12835 exercise
</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention
<quote>shall not be subject
12836 to any formality.
</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12837 embodied in Article
5(
2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12838 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12839 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12840 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12841 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12842 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12843 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12844 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12845 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein,
<citetitle>International
12846 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials
</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12847 Press,
2001),
153–54.
</para></footnote>
12848 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a
<quote>natural right.
</quote> Natural
12849 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12850 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12851 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12852 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12853 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12856 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12857 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12858 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12859 <quote>Walt Disney creativity
</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12860 know what's protected and what's not.
12862 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
12864 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12865 Berlin in
1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12866 Convention in
1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12867 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12868 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12869 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12870 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an
<citetitle>i
</citetitle> or cross a
12871 <citetitle>t
</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12874 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12875 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12876 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12877 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12878 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12879 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12882 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12883 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12884 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12885 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12887 imposed upon creators.
12890 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in
1908, there was
12891 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12893 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12894 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12895 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12896 the government. He has a property right over the table
<quote>naturally,
</quote>
12897 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12898 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12902 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12903 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12904 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12905 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12906 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12907 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12911 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12912 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12913 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12914 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12915 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12916 important reason to secure registration
—both because it makes
12917 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12918 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12919 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12920 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12921 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12922 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12923 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12924 system of protection for property generally.
12927 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12928 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12929 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12930 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12931 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12932 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12933 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12934 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12936 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12937 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12938 <emphasis>lawyer
</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12939 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
12942 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12943 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12944 didn't
<quote>get.
</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
12945 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
12946 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be,
<quote>short,
</quote> then this
12947 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
12948 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
12949 be presumptively uncontrolled.
12952 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
12953 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
12954 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
12955 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
12956 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
12957 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
12958 seen before
<emphasis>because there are no formalities
</emphasis>.
12961 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
12962 it is worth $
1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
12963 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
12964 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
12965 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
12968 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
12969 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
12970 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
12971 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
12972 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $
1 to you.
12975 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
12976 registering the work mean that the $
1 is really misleading? Isn't the
12977 hassle worth more than $
1? Isn't that the real problem with
12981 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
12982 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
12983 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
12985 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
12986 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
12987 address the real problem of
<emphasis>governments
</emphasis> standing
12988 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
12989 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
12990 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
12991 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
12992 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
12993 upon historical data, that system would move up to
98 percent of
12994 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
12995 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
12997 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
12999 <emphasis role='strong'
>When Steve Forbes
</emphasis> endorsed the
13000 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
13001 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
13002 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
13003 willing to take the first step.
13005 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe
</primary></indexterm>
13007 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
13008 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
13009 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
13010 possible. In May
2003, it looked as if the bill would be
13011 introduced. On May
16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog,
<quote>we are
13012 close.
</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
13013 something good might happen here.
13016 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
13017 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
13018 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
13019 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
13020 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
13021 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
13024 The MPAA argued first that Congress had
<quote>firmly rejected the central
13025 concept in the proposed bill
</quote>—that copyrights be renewed. That
13026 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's
<quote>firm rejection
</quote> had occurred
13027 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
13028 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
13029 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
13030 owners
—apparently those who could not afford the $
1 fee. Third,
13031 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
13032 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
13033 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
13034 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
13035 off the extended term unless the $
1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
13036 argued that the bill would impose
<quote>enormous
</quote> costs, since a
13037 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
13038 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
13039 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
13040 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
13041 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
13042 film is a valid derivative use.
13045 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
13046 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
13047 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
13048 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
13049 or not
—a controversial claim in any case
—unless they know
13050 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
13053 <emphasis role='strong'
>At the beginning
</emphasis> of this book, I
13054 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
13055 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
13056 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
13057 opposition
—the power of the side that fought to defend the
13058 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
13059 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
13060 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
13063 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
13064 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
13065 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
13066 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
13071 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
13072 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
13073 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
13074 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
13075 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
13076 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
13077 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
13078 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
13079 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
13080 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
13082 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin
</primary></indexterm>
13084 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
13085 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
13086 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
13087 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
13088 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
13089 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the
<quote>Dark
13090 Content
</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
13091 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
13094 What does this industry really want?
13097 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
13098 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
13099 protecting
<emphasis>their
</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
13100 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
13101 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
13102 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
13103 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
13104 content that doesn't require
<emphasis>their
</emphasis> permission
13108 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
13109 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
13110 its aim not the protection of
<quote>property
</quote> but the rejection of a
13111 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
13112 theirs.
<emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
13116 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
13117 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
13119 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
13120 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
13121 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
13122 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
13123 and to share its own creation.
13125 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
13126 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
13128 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
13129 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
13130 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
13131 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
13132 block the progress of others.
13135 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
13136 <quote>property
</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
13137 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
13138 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing
<quote>permission
13139 society.
</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
13140 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
13141 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
13143 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
13146 <chapter label=
"15" id=
"c-conclusion">
13147 <title>CONCLUSION
</title>
13148 <indexterm id='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in
</primary></indexterm>
13149 <indexterm id='idxaidsmedications' class='startofrange'
><primary>AIDS medications
</primary></indexterm>
13150 <indexterm id='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='startofrange'
><primary>antiretroviral drugs
</primary></indexterm>
13151 <indexterm id='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='startofrange'
><primary>developing countries, foreign patent costs in
</primary></indexterm>
13152 <indexterm id='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='startofrange'
><primary>drugs
</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical
</secondary></indexterm>
13153 <indexterm id='idxhivaidstherapies' class='startofrange'
><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies
</primary></indexterm>
13155 <emphasis role='strong'
>There are more
</emphasis> than
35 million
13156 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
13157 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
13158 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
13159 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
13162 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
13163 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
13164 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
13165 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
13166 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
13167 the disease almost invisible.
13170 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
13171 United States, they cost between $
10,
000 and $
15,
000 per person per
13172 year. Today, some cost $
25,
000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
13173 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
13175 $
15,
000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
13176 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.
<footnote><para>
13177 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights,
<quote>Final Report: Integrating
13178 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy
</quote> (London,
2002),
13180 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
13182 issued
9 July
2002, only
230,
000 of the
6 million who need drugs in
13183 the developing world receive them
—and half of them are in Brazil.
13186 <indexterm id='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='startofrange'
><primary>patents
</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals
</secondary></indexterm>
13187 <indexterm id='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='startofrange'
><primary>pharmaceutical patents
</primary></indexterm>
13189 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
13190 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
13191 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
13192 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
13193 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
13194 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
13195 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
13198 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
13199 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
13200 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
13201 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
13202 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
13203 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
13204 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
13205 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
13209 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
13210 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
13211 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
13212 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
13213 costs significantly below the market price.
13215 <indexterm id='idxinternationallaw2' class='startofrange'
><primary>international law
</primary></indexterm>
13216 <indexterm id='idxparallelimportation' class='startofrange'
><primary>parallel importation
</primary></indexterm>
13217 <indexterm id='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='startofrange'
><primary>South Africa, Republic of, pharmaceutical imports by
</primary></indexterm>
13219 In
1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
13220 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
13221 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
13222 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
13223 Africa from India. This is called
<quote>parallel importation,
</quote> and it is
13224 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
13225 permitted within the European Union.
<footnote>
13228 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite,
<citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
13229 Owns the Knowledge Economy?
</citetitle> (New York: The New Press,
2003),
37.
13230 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John
</primary></indexterm>
13231 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
13234 <indexterm><primary>United States Trade Representative (USTR)
</primary></indexterm>
13236 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
13237 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
13238 characterized it,
<quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa
…
13239 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
13240 imports.
</quote><footnote><para>
13242 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI),
<citetitle>Patent
13243 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13244 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13245 Organization
</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.,
2000),
14, available at
13246 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
56</ulink>. For a
13247 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
13248 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
13249 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep.,
1st sess.,
13250 Ser. No.
106-
126 (
22 July
1999),
150–57 (statement of James
13253 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
13254 government asked South Africa to change the law
—and to add
13255 pressure to that request, in
1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
13256 possible trade sanctions.
13257 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
13258 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
13259 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
13260 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
13261 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
13262 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
13263 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
13264 patent
— pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
13265 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
13266 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
13267 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.
<footnote><para>
13269 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI),
<citetitle>Patent
13270 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13271 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13272 Organization
</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.,
2000),
15.
</para></footnote>
13274 <indexterm startref='idxparallelimportation' class='endofrange'
/>
13276 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
13277 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
13278 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
13279 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
13280 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
13281 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
13282 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
13283 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
13286 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
13287 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
13288 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
13289 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
13290 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
13291 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save
15 to
30 million lives.
13294 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
13295 profits of United States drug companies
—at least, not substantially. It
13296 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
13297 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
13298 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
13299 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
13303 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
13304 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
13306 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
13307 about the sanctity of property.
<footnote><para>
13309 See Sabin Russell,
<quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
13310 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,
</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
24
13311 May
1999, A1, available at
13312 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
57</ulink>
13313 (
<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
13314 system of intellectual property protection
</quote>); Robert Weissman,
<quote>AIDS
13315 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
13316 Medicines,
</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus
</citetitle> 4:
23 (August
1999), available at
13317 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
58</ulink>
13318 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson,
<quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
13319 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
13320 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,
</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
13321 Symposium Journal
</citetitle> (Spring
2001):
175.
13322 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
13324 It was because
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> would be violated that these
13325 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
13326 importance of
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> that led these government actors
13327 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
13329 <indexterm startref='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='endofrange'
/>
13331 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
13332 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
13333 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
13334 direct cost would be to speed the death of
15 to
30 million Africans,
13335 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the
<quote>sanctity
</quote> of an
13336 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
13337 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
13338 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
13340 <indexterm id='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='startofrange'
><primary>corporations
</primary><secondary>in pharmaceutical industry
</secondary></indexterm>
13342 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
13343 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
13344 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
13345 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
13346 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system
—
13347 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
13350 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
13351 drug companies would love
—they say, and I believe them
—to
13352 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
13353 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
13354 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
13355 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
13357 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='startofrange'
><primary>intellectual property rights
</primary><secondary>of drug patents
</secondary></indexterm>
13359 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
13360 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
13361 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask,
<quote>How
13362 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $
1 a pill, but the same
13363 drug would cost an American $
1,
500?
</quote> Because there is no
<quote>sound
13364 bite
</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
13365 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
13366 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
13367 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
13368 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
13369 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
13370 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal
—the sanctity of an
13371 idea called
<quote>intellectual property.
</quote>
13373 <indexterm startref='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='endofrange'
/>
13374 <indexterm startref='idxaidsmedications' class='endofrange'
/>
13375 <indexterm startref='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='endofrange'
/>
13376 <indexterm startref='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='endofrange'
/>
13377 <indexterm startref='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='endofrange'
/>
13378 <indexterm startref='idxhivaidstherapies' class='endofrange'
/>
13379 <indexterm startref='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='endofrange'
/>
13381 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
13382 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
13383 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
13384 What is the argument?
13387 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
13388 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
13389 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
13390 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
13391 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
13392 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
13393 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
13394 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
13395 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
13396 were balanced in just this sense.
13398 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='endofrange'
/>
13399 <indexterm startref='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='endofrange'
/>
13400 <indexterm startref='idxinternationallaw2' class='endofrange'
/>
13402 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
13403 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
13404 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
13405 our tradition, now reigns in this culture
—bizarrely, and with
13406 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
13407 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
13409 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='endofrange'
/>
13411 <emphasis role='strong'
>A simple idea
</emphasis> blinds us, and under
13412 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
13413 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
13414 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
13415 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
13416 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
13417 control of that property removes our
13418 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
13419 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
13420 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
13421 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
13422 this common sense open its eyes.
13425 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
13426 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
13427 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
13428 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
13429 to fight
<quote>piracy,
</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
13430 the idea of
<quote>creative property,
</quote> while transforming real creators into
13431 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
13432 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
13433 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
13434 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
13435 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
13436 produce the
<quote>perfect storm
</quote> for free culture.
13438 <indexterm><primary>academic journals
</primary></indexterm>
13439 <indexterm><primary>biomedical research
</primary></indexterm>
13440 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>intellectual property rights
</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of
</secondary></indexterm>
13441 <indexterm><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>development of
</secondary></indexterm>
13442 <indexterm><primary>IBM
</primary></indexterm>
13443 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)
</primary></indexterm>
13444 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)
</primary></indexterm>
13445 <indexterm><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>public projects in
</secondary></indexterm>
13446 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)
</primary></indexterm>
13447 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust
</primary></indexterm>
13448 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='startofrange'
><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)
</primary></indexterm>
13449 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web
</primary></indexterm>
13450 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System
</primary></indexterm>
13451 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
13452 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'
><primary>biomedical research
</primary></indexterm>
13454 <emphasis role='strong'
>In August
2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
13455 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
13456 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.
<footnote><para>
13457 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim,
<quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
13458 August
2003, E1, available at
13459 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
59</ulink>; William New,
<quote>Global Group's
13460 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,
</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13461 Daily
</citetitle>,
19 August
2003, available at
13462 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
60</ulink>; William New,
<quote>U.S. Official
13463 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,
</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13464 Daily
</citetitle>,
19 August
2003, available at
13465 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
61</ulink>.
13467 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
13468 a meeting to discuss
<quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
13469 goods.
</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
13470 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
13471 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
13472 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
13473 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
13474 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
13475 that I describe in chapter
13476 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"c-afterword"/>. It
13477 included a project to develop single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs),
13478 which are thought to have great significance in biomedical
13479 research. (That nonprofit project comprised a consortium of the
13480 Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and technological companies,
13481 including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
13482 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
13483 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
13484 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
13485 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
13486 in the early
1980s. And it included
<quote>open source and free software.
</quote>
13488 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'
/>
13490 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
13491 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
13492 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
13493 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
13494 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
13496 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='startofrange'
><primary>Lessig, Lawrence
</primary><secondary>in international debate on intellectual property
</secondary></indexterm>
13498 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.
<footnote><para>
13499 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
13502 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
13503 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
13504 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
13505 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
13508 <indexterm id='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='startofrange'
><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)
</primary></indexterm>
13510 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
13511 about WIPO. In February
2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
13512 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
13513 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
13514 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
13515 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
13516 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
13517 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
13518 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
13519 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
13520 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
13521 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
13522 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
13523 talk about an
<quote>Information Society
</quote> unless one also talked about the
13524 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
13525 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
13526 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
13528 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
13529 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
13530 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
13531 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
13534 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
13535 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
13536 thus the meeting about
<quote>open and collaborative projects to create
13537 public goods
</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
13539 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='endofrange'
/>
13540 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='endofrange'
/>
13541 <indexterm startref='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='endofrange'
/>
13542 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='startofrange'
><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)
</primary></indexterm>
13543 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation
</primary></indexterm>
13544 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='startofrange'
><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>on free software
</secondary></indexterm>
13546 But there is one project within that list that is highly
13547 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is
<quote>open source
13548 and free software.
</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
13549 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
13550 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
13551 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
13552 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
13553 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
13554 rather than
<quote>proprietary software,
</quote> for their own internal uses.
13556 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft
</quote> licenses
</primary></indexterm>
13557 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
13558 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
13559 <indexterm><primary>IBM
</primary></indexterm>
13561 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
13562 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
13563 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
13564 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
13565 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
13566 operating system, the most famous bit of
<quote>free software
</quote>—and IBM
13567 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support
<quote>open source and
13568 free software
</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
13569 to support a mode of software development that is different from
13570 Microsoft's.
<footnote><para>
13572 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
13573 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
13574 <quote>open source
</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
13575 principal opposition is to
<quote>free software
</quote> licensed under a
<quote>copyleft
</quote>
13576 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
13577 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith,
<quote>The Future
13578 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,
</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
13579 Toward Open Source Software
</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
13580 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
13581 Public Policy Research,
2002),
69, available at
13582 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
62</ulink>. See also
13583 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president,
<citetitle>The Commercial Software
13584 Model
</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (
3
13585 May
2001), available at
13586 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
63</ulink>.
13589 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='endofrange'
/>
13590 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)
</primary></indexterm>
13591 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)
</primary></indexterm>
13593 More important for our purposes, to support
<quote>open source and free
13594 software
</quote> is not to oppose copyright.
<quote>Open source and free software
</quote>
13595 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
13596 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
13597 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
13599 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
13600 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
13601 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
13602 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
13603 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
13604 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
13605 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
13606 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
13607 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
13608 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
13610 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>intellectual property rights
</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of
</secondary></indexterm>
13611 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='startofrange'
><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)
</primary></indexterm>
13612 <indexterm id='idxkrimjonathan' class='startofrange'
><primary>Krim, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
13613 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by
</secondary></indexterm>
13615 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
13616 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
13617 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
13618 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
13619 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
13620 <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
13621 States government to veto the meeting.
<footnote><para>
13623 Krim,
<quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,
</quote> available at
<ulink
13624 url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
64</ulink>.
13626 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
13629 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
13630 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
13631 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
13632 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
13633 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
13634 its lobbying efforts.
13636 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='endofrange'
/>
13637 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois
</primary></indexterm>
13639 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
13640 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
13641 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
13642 Office, explained that
<quote>open-source software runs counter to the
13643 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.
</quote>
13644 She is quoted as saying,
<quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
13645 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
13646 goals of WIPO.
</quote>
13648 <indexterm startref='idxkrimjonathan' class='endofrange'
/>
13650 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
13652 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='endofrange'
/>
13653 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
13655 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
13656 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
13657 right called
<quote>copyright
</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
13658 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it
<quote>runs counter
</quote> to the mission
13659 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
13660 in understanding
—the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
13661 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
13662 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
13664 <indexterm><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)
</primary></indexterm>
13665 <indexterm><primary>drugs
</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical
</secondary></indexterm>
13666 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs
</primary></indexterm>
13667 <indexterm><primary>patents
</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals
</secondary></indexterm>
13669 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to
<quote>promote
</quote>
13670 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
13671 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
13672 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
13673 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
13674 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
13675 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
13676 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
13677 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
13678 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
13679 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
13681 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
13683 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
13684 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
13685 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13686 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13687 <emphasis>their
</emphasis> rights. If they want to
<quote>waive
</quote> or
13688 <quote>disclaim
</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13689 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $
20 billion to do
13690 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13691 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13692 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13693 to do with
<emphasis>their
</emphasis> property.
13695 <indexterm id='idxboland' class='startofrange'
><primary>Boland, Lois
</primary></indexterm>
13697 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13698 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,
</quote> she's
13699 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13700 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13701 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13702 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from
<quote>waiving
</quote> or
13703 <quote>disclaiming
</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13704 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13705 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13708 <indexterm id='idxfeudalsystem' class='startofrange'
><primary>feudal system
</primary></indexterm>
13709 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='startofrange'
><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>feudal system of
</secondary></indexterm>
13711 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13712 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called
<quote>feudalism.
</quote> Under
13713 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13714 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13715 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13716 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13717 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13718 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13719 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13722 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
13723 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John
</primary></indexterm>
13725 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13726 choice we are now making about intellectual property.
<footnote><para>
13728 See Drahos with Braithwaite,
<citetitle>Information Feudalism
</citetitle>,
210–20.
13729 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
13731 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13732 choice now is whether that information society will be
13733 <emphasis>free
</emphasis> or
<emphasis>feudal
</emphasis>. The trend is
13736 <indexterm startref='idxfeudalsystem' class='endofrange'
/>
13737 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='endofrange'
/>
13739 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13740 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13741 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13742 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13745 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='endofrange'
/>
13746 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='endofrange'
/>
13748 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13749 it should be (
<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13750 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13751 not simply to promote intellectual property rights
</quote>), not as it is. If
13752 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13753 say anything wrong. But in the world
13754 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13755 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13756 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13760 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13761 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13762 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13763 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13764 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13765 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13766 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13767 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13769 <indexterm startref='idxboland' class='endofrange'
/>
13771 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13772 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13773 <quote>goal
</quote> of a government should be
<quote>to promote the right balance
</quote> of
13774 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13775 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism.
<quote>Typical for
13776 an academic,
</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13779 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13780 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13781 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13782 our own country's history).
13785 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13786 government should be to
<quote>seek balance,
</quote> then count me with the silly,
13787 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13788 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13789 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13790 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13791 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13792 not lies is just na
ïve, then who have we, the most powerful
13793 democracy in the world, become?
13796 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13797 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13798 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13799 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13800 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13801 been part of our tradition for most of our history
—free culture.
13804 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13806 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace
</primary></indexterm>
13807 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
13808 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted
</primary></indexterm>
13810 <emphasis role='strong'
>There are moments
</emphasis> of hope in this
13811 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13812 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13813 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13814 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13815 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13816 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13817 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing
700,
000 letters were
13818 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13821 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13822 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13823 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13824 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13825 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13826 concentration in the media.
13829 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13830 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13831 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13832 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13833 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13836 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13837 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13838 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13839 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13840 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13841 range of rights
—property rights of a historically extreme
13842 form
—that makes their bigness bad.
13844 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13846 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13847 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13848 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13849 Americans have a long history of fighting
<quote>big,
</quote> wisely or not. That
13850 we could be motivated to fight
<quote>big
</quote> again is not something new.
13853 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13854 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13855 the idea of
<quote>intellectual property.
</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13856 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13857 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13858 called
<quote>property
</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13861 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13864 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob
</primary></indexterm>
13866 <emphasis role='strong'
>As I write
</emphasis> these final words, the
13867 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
13868 three hundred individuals.
<footnote><para>
13870 John Borland,
<quote>RIAA Sues
261 File Swappers,
</quote> CNET News.com, September
13872 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
65</ulink>; Paul
13873 R. La Monica,
<quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,
</quote> CNN/Money,
8 September
13875 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
66</ulink>; Soni
13876 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty,
<quote>Sued for a Song,
13877 N.Y.C.
12-Yr-Old Among
261 Cited as Sharers,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News
</citetitle>,
9
13878 September
2003,
3; Frank Ahrens,
<quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13879 Targets; Single Mother in Calif.,
12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13880 Defendants,
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13881 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,
</quote> <citetitle>Wired News
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003,
13883 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
67</ulink>.
13885 Eminem has just been sued for
<quote>sampling
</quote> someone else's
13886 music.
<footnote><para>
13888 Jon Wiederhorn,
<quote>Eminem Gets Sued
… by a Little Old Lady,
</quote>
13889 mtv.com,
17 September
2003, available at
13890 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
68</ulink>.
13892 The story about Bob Dylan
<quote>stealing
</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13893 finished making the rounds.
<footnote><para>
13895 Kenji Hall, Associated Press,
<quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13896 Dylan Songs,
</quote> Kansascity.com,
9 July
2003, available at
13897 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
69</ulink>.
13898 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13900 An insider from Hollywood
—who insists he must remain
13901 anonymous
—reports
<quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13902 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13903 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13904 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13905 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.
</quote> Congressmen are
13906 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13907 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13908 kids who use a computer to share content.
13910 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
13911 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
13912 <indexterm><primary>BBC
</primary></indexterm>
13913 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in
</primary></indexterm>
13914 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons
</primary></indexterm>
13915 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto
</primary></indexterm>
13916 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom
</primary><secondary>public creative archive in
</secondary></indexterm>
13918 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13919 that it will build a
<quote>Creative Archive,
</quote> from which British citizens can
13920 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.
<footnote><para>
13921 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,
</quote> BBC press release,
13922 24 August
2003, available at
13923 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
70</ulink>.
13925 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13926 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13927 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13928 country.
<footnote><para>
13930 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,
</quote> Creative Commons Weblog,
6 August
2003,
13932 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
71</ulink>.
13934 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13935 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13936 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13937 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13938 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13939 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13940 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13941 day into the Causbys.
13944 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
13945 potential is ever to be realized.
13947 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
13951 <chapter label=
"16" id=
"c-afterword">
13952 <title>AFTERWORD
</title>
13955 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
13956 <emphasis role='strong'
>At least some
</emphasis> who have read this
13957 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
13958 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
13961 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
13962 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
13963 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
13964 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
13967 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
13968 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
13969 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists
—all to tell this
13970 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
13974 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
13975 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
13976 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
13977 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
13978 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
13980 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
13982 <section id=
"usnow">
13983 <title>US, NOW
</title>
13985 <emphasis role='strong'
>Common sense
</emphasis> is with the copyright
13986 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
13987 extremes
—as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
13988 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
13989 choice, then the warriors should win.
13992 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
13993 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
13994 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright
—<quote>All Rights
13995 Reserved
</quote>— and those who reject copyright
—<quote>No Rights
13996 Reserved.
</quote> The
<quote>All Rights Reserved
</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
13997 permission before you
<quote>use
</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The
<quote>No
13998 Rights Reserved
</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
13999 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
14001 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>development of
</secondary></indexterm>
14002 <indexterm id='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>initial free character of
</secondary></indexterm>
14004 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
14005 tilted in the
<quote>no rights reserved
</quote> direction. Content could be copied
14006 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
14007 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
14010 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
14011 original design of the Internet was
<quote>no rights reserved.
</quote> Content was
14012 <quote>taken
</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
14016 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
14017 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
14018 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
14019 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
14020 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
14021 architecture made the effective default
<quote>no rights reserved,
</quote> the
14022 future architecture will make the effective default
<quote>all rights
14023 reserved.
</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
14024 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
14025 content requires permission. The
<quote>cut and paste
</quote> world that defines
14026 the Internet today will become a
<quote>get permission to cut and paste
</quote>
14027 world that is a creator's nightmare.
14029 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='endofrange'
/>
14030 <indexterm startref='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='endofrange'
/>
14032 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle
—neither
14033 <quote>all rights reserved
</quote> nor
<quote>no rights reserved
</quote> but
<quote>some rights
14034 reserved
</quote>— and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
14035 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
14036 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
14039 <section id=
"examples">
14040 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
</title>
14041 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='startofrange'
><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary>restoration efforts on previous aspects of
</secondary></indexterm>
14042 <indexterm id='idxbrowsing' class='startofrange'
><primary>browsing
</primary></indexterm>
14043 <indexterm id='idxprivacyrights2' class='startofrange'
><primary>privacy rights
</primary></indexterm>
14045 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
14046 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
14047 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
14048 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
14049 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
14050 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
14051 to your neighbors or boss. The
<quote>privacy
</quote> of your browsing habits was
14055 What made it assured?
14057 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
14059 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
14060 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>, your
14061 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
14062 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
14063 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
14064 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
14065 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
14066 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
14067 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
14068 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
14069 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
14070 (there is no law protecting
<quote>privacy
</quote> in public places), and in many
14071 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
14072 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
14074 <indexterm id='idxamazon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Amazon
</primary></indexterm>
14075 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet
</primary></indexterm>
14076 <indexterm id='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>privacy protection on
</secondary></indexterm>
14078 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
14079 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
14080 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
14081 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
14082 <quote>recently viewed
</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
14083 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
14084 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any
<quote>privacy
</quote>
14085 protected by the friction disappears, too.
14087 <indexterm><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>privacy rights in use of
</secondary></indexterm>
14089 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
14090 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
14091 people should have the
<quote>right
</quote> to browse in a library without the
14092 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
14093 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
14094 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
14095 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
14098 <indexterm startref='idxbrowsing' class='endofrange'
/>
14099 <indexterm startref='idxamazon' class='endofrange'
/>
14101 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define
<quote>privacy
</quote>
14102 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
14103 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
14104 friction did.
<footnote><para>
14107 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg,
<quote>Fair Information Practices and the
14108 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),
</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
14109 Law Review
</citetitle> 1 (
2001): par.
6–18, available at
14111 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
72</ulink>
14112 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
14113 also Jeffrey Rosen,
<citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
14114 in an Anxious Age
</citetitle> (New York: Random House,
2004) (mapping tradeoffs
14115 between technology and privacy).
</para></footnote>
14116 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
14117 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
14119 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
14120 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
14121 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
14122 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
14124 <indexterm startref='idxprivacyrights2' class='endofrange'
/>
14125 <indexterm startref='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='endofrange'
/>
14126 <indexterm><primary>Data General
</primary></indexterm>
14127 <indexterm><primary>IBM
</primary></indexterm>
14128 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='startofrange'
><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)
</primary></indexterm>
14130 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
14131 movement. When computers with software were first made available
14132 commercially, the software
—both the source code and the
14133 binaries
— was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
14134 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
14135 care much about controlling their software.
14137 <indexterm id='idxstallmanrichard' class='startofrange'
><primary>Stallman, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
14139 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
14140 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
14141 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
14142 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
14143 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
14147 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
14148 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
14149 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
14150 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
14151 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
14152 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
14153 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
14154 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
14155 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
14158 <indexterm id='idxproprietarycode' class='startofrange'
><primary>proprietary code
</primary></indexterm>
14160 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
14161 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
14162 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
14163 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
14164 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
14165 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
14166 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
14169 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
14170 early
1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
14171 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
14172 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
14173 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
14174 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
14175 fundamentally weakened.
14177 <indexterm startref='idxproprietarycode' class='endofrange'
/>
14178 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus
</primary></indexterm>
14180 Therefore, in
1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
14181 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
14182 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's
<quote>Linux
</quote>
14183 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
14184 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
14185 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
14188 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
14189 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
14190 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
14191 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
14192 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
14193 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
14194 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
14195 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
14199 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
14200 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
14201 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
14202 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
14203 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
14204 what before had been passively guaranteed.
14206 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='endofrange'
/>
14207 <indexterm startref='idxstallmanrichard' class='endofrange'
/>
14208 <indexterm id='idxacademicjournals' class='startofrange'
><primary>academic journals
</primary></indexterm>
14209 <indexterm id='idxscientificjournals' class='startofrange'
><primary>scientific journals
</primary></indexterm>
14211 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
14212 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
14213 scientific journals are produced.
14215 <indexterm id='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='startofrange'
><primary>Lexis and Westlaw
</primary></indexterm>
14216 <indexterm id='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in
</secondary></indexterm>
14217 <indexterm><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>journals in
</secondary></indexterm>
14218 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>access to opinions of
</secondary></indexterm>
14220 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
14221 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
14222 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
14223 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
14224 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
14225 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
14226 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
14227 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
14228 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
14229 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
14230 and Westlaw are also free
14231 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
14232 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
14233 Court opinion through their respective services.
14235 <indexterm><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>access fees for material in
</secondary></indexterm>
14236 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>license system for rebuilding of
</secondary></indexterm>
14238 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
14239 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
14240 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
14241 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
14242 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
14243 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
14244 access to material that is not in the public domain.
14246 <indexterm startref='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='endofrange'
/>
14247 <indexterm startref='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='endofrange'
/>
14249 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
14250 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
14251 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
14253 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>journals in
</secondary></indexterm>
14255 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
14256 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
14257 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
14258 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
14259 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
14260 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
14261 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
14262 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
14263 the technology of paper journals (architecture)
—namely, that it
14264 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
14267 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
14268 that libraries not give the general public access to the
14269 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
14270 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
14271 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
14274 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)
</primary></indexterm>
14275 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)
</primary></indexterm>
14277 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
14278 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
14279 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
14280 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
14281 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
14282 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
14283 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
14284 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
14285 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
14286 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
14287 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
14289 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='endofrange'
/>
14291 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
14292 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
14293 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
14294 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
14295 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
14296 presumptively a good
—especially when it helps spread knowledge
14299 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='endofrange'
/>
14300 <indexterm startref='idxacademicjournals' class='endofrange'
/>
14301 <indexterm startref='idxscientificjournals' class='endofrange'
/>
14303 <section id=
"oneidea">
14304 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
</title>
14305 <indexterm id='idxcreativecommons' class='startofrange'
><primary>Creative Commons
</primary></indexterm>
14307 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
14308 increasing control effected through law and technology.
14310 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University
</primary></indexterm>
14312 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
14313 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
14314 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
14315 <emphasis>reasonable
</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
14316 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
14317 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
14318 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
14319 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
14320 make this possible.
14323 <emphasis>Simple
</emphasis>—which means without a middleman, or
14324 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
14325 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
14326 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
14327 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
14328 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
14329 shared. These three expressions together
—a legal license, a
14330 human-readable description, and
14331 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
14332 machine-readable tags
—constitute a Creative Commons license. A
14333 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
14334 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
14335 that the person associated with the license believes in something
14336 different than the
<quote>All
</quote> or
<quote>No
</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
14337 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
14338 certain freedoms are given.
14341 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
14342 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
14343 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
14344 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
14345 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
14346 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (
<quote>share and share
14347 alike
</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
14348 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
14349 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
14352 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
14353 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
14354 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
14355 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
14356 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
14357 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
14358 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
14359 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
14362 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia
</primary></indexterm>
14364 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
14365 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
14366 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
14367 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
14368 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
14369 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
14370 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
14371 of content (
<quote>content conducers,
</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
14372 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
14373 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
14375 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
14377 The aim is not to fight the
<quote>All Rights Reserved
</quote> sorts. The aim is to
14378 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
14379 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
14380 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
14381 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
14382 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
14383 the background of digital technologies. New rules
—with different
14384 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
14385 them
—are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
14386 to begin to build those rules.
14388 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of
</secondary></indexterm>
14390 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
14391 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
14392 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel,
<citetitle>Down and Out in
14393 the Magic Kingdom
</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
14394 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
14397 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
14398 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (
1)
14399 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
14400 and (
2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
14401 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (
1) will download
14402 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(
1)s. Some part of (
2)
14403 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
14404 them (
2)-goods. If there are more (
2)-goods than bad-(
1)s, the
14405 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
14406 <emphasis>increase
</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
14409 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
14410 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
14411 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
14412 was a total success.
14414 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)
</primary></indexterm>
14415 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
14417 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
14418 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
14419 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
14420 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled
<citetitle>Free for All
</citetitle>,
14421 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
14422 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
14423 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
14424 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
14427 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'
/>
14428 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy
</primary></indexterm>
14429 <indexterm><primary>rap music
</primary></indexterm>
14430 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter
</primary></indexterm>
14432 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
14433 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
14434 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
14435 reasons. Many who use the
<quote>sampling license
</quote> do so because anything
14436 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
14437 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
14438 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
14439 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
14440 art
—they, too, sample from others. Because the
14441 <emphasis>legal
</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
14442 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
14443 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not
<quote>allow
</quote>
14444 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
14445 high
<footnote><para>
14447 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
14448 Culture Wars
</citetitle> (
2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
14449 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
14450 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
72</ulink>.
14451 </para></footnote>),
14452 these artists release into the creative environment content
14453 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
14456 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
14457 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
14458 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
14459 you are effectively saying you believe in the
<quote>All Rights Reserved
</quote>
14460 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
14461 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
14462 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
14463 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
14464 this notion of
<quote>Some Rights Reserved,
</quote> and gives many the chance to
14468 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
14469 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
14470 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
14471 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
14473 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
14474 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
14475 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
14478 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
14479 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
14480 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
14481 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
14482 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
14483 steps are possible.
14486 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
14487 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
14488 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
14489 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
14490 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
14491 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
14492 creativity to spread more easily.
14494 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='endofrange'
/>
14495 <indexterm startref='idxcreativecommons' class='endofrange'
/>
14496 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
14499 <section id=
"themsoon">
14500 <title>THEM, SOON
</title>
14502 <emphasis role='strong'
>We will
</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
14503 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
14504 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
14505 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
14506 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
14509 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
14510 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
14511 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
14515 <section id=
"formalities">
14516 <title>1. More Formalities
</title>
14518 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
14519 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
14520 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
14521 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
14524 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
14525 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
14526 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
14530 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
14531 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
14532 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
14533 default is control, and
<quote>formalities
</quote> are banished.
14539 As I suggested in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
14540 linkend=
"property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
14541 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
14542 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
14543 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
14544 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
14545 formalities were getting in the way.
14548 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
14549 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
14550 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
14551 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
14552 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
14553 trace
— there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
14554 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
14555 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
14556 past. And thus, the
<emphasis>lack
</emphasis> of formalities forces
14557 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
14560 The law should therefore change this requirement
<footnote><para>
14562 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
14563 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
14564 adopted by other countries as well.
</para></footnote>—but it
14565 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
14566 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
14567 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
14570 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
14571 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
14572 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
14573 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
14574 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
14575 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
14576 developed by others.
14579 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
14581 <section id=
"registration">
14582 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL
</title>
14584 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
14585 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
14586 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
14587 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
14588 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
14589 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
14590 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
14591 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
14592 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
14593 panic
—nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
14594 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
14597 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
14598 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
14599 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
14600 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
14601 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
14602 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
14603 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
14606 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
14607 There are at least
32 million Web sites registered around the world.
14608 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
14609 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
14610 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
14611 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
14612 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
14613 with which registration occurs up.
14616 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
14617 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
14618 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
14619 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
14620 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
14621 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
14622 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
14623 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
14624 formality
—while producing a database
14625 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
14626 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
14630 <section id=
"marking">
14631 <title>MARKING
</title>
14633 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
14634 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
14635 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule
—akin to
14636 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
14637 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
14638 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
14639 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
14640 uniformly across all media.
14643 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
14644 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
14645 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
14649 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
14650 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
14651 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
14652 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
14653 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
14654 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
14655 signal from the failure to mark
—not the loss of the copyright, but the
14656 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
14659 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
14660 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
14661 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
14662 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
14663 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
14664 doesn't give permission.
<footnote><para>
14666 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
14667 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
14668 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
14670 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be
<quote>use unless someone
14671 complains.
</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
14672 stop using the work in any new
14673 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
14674 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
14675 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
14679 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
14680 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
14681 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
14682 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
14683 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
14685 <indexterm><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>copyright marking of
</secondary></indexterm>
14687 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
14688 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
14689 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
14690 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
14691 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
14692 <emphasis>solely
</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
14693 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
14694 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
14695 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
14696 other important functions.
14699 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
14700 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
14701 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
14702 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
14703 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
14704 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
14707 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
14708 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
14709 make things unclear.
14712 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
14713 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
14714 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
14715 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
14716 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
14717 that assertion at the appropriate time.
14720 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
14723 <section id=
"shortterms">
14724 <title>2. Shorter Terms
</title>
14726 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14727 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14731 In
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14732 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14733 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14734 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14735 radical.
<citetitle>The Economist
</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14736 copyright term.
<footnote><para>
14739 <quote>A Radical Rethink,
</quote> <citetitle>Economist
</citetitle>,
366:
8308 (
25 January
2003):
15,
14741 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
74</ulink>.
14743 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14746 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14747 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14748 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14751 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
14754 <emphasis>Keep it short:
</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14755 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14756 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14757 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14758 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14759 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14763 <emphasis>Keep it simple:
</emphasis> The line between the public
14764 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14765 fuzziness of
<quote>fair use,
</quote> and the distinction between
<quote>ideas
</quote> and
14766 <quote>expression.
</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14767 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14768 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14769 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14770 <quote>lawyer-free zone
</quote> makes the complexities of
<quote>fair use
</quote> and
14771 <quote>idea/expression
</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14772 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14775 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions
</primary></indexterm>
14778 <emphasis>Keep it alive:
</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14779 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14780 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14781 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14782 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14783 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14784 pension.
<footnote><para>
14786 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14787 and/or Pension, VA Form
21-
526 (OMB Approved No.
2900-
0001),
14789 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
75</ulink>.
14791 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14792 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14797 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:
</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14798 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14799 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14800 in
1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14801 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14802 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in
1923 than we
14803 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14804 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14805 the number of authors who wrote in
1923. Of course, we can increase
14806 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14807 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14808 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14809 creativity in
1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14810 we can do about that now.
</para></listitem>
14813 These changes together should produce an
<emphasis>average
</emphasis>
14814 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until
1976,
14815 the average term was just
32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14819 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas
<quote>radical.
</quote> (After all, I
14820 call them
<quote>extremists.
</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14821 than the term under Richard Nixon. How
<quote>radical
</quote> can it be to ask for
14822 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14825 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14828 <section id=
"freefairuse">
14829 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
</title>
14830 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and
</primary></indexterm>
14831 <indexterm><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
14833 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14834 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14835 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14836 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14837 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14838 the emergence of that new technology.
14841 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors
<quote>exclusive
14842 right
</quote> to
<quote>their writings.
</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14843 right to
<quote>their writings
</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14844 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14845 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14846 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14847 though that movie is not
<quote>my writing.
</quote>
14849 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin
</primary></indexterm>
14851 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in
1870, when it
14852 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14853 control translations and dramatizations of a work.
<footnote><para>
14855 Benjamin Kaplan,
<citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright
</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14856 University Press,
1967),
32.
14858 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14859 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14860 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14864 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14865 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14866 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14867 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.
<footnote><para>
14868 <!-- f6. --> Ibid.,
56.
14873 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14874 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14875 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14876 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14877 Consider each limitation in turn.
14880 <emphasis>Term:
</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14881 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14882 sense to protect John
14884 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14885 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14886 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14887 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14888 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14889 after the creative work is done.
14890 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John
</primary></indexterm>
14893 <emphasis>Scope:
</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14894 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14895 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14896 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14897 material. When all
<quote>reuse
</quote> of creative material was within the control
14898 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14899 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14900 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14901 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14902 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14903 the creative process. Smothers it.
14905 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
14907 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14908 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14909 foreseeable derivative rights
—turning a book into a movie, or a
14910 poem into a musical score
—it doesn't make sense to require
14911 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14915 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14916 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14917 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14918 Paul Goldstein.
<footnote>
14921 Paul Goldstein,
<citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14922 Jukebox
</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
2003),
187–216.
14923 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
14925 His view is that the law should be written so that
14926 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14929 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14930 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14931 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14932 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14933 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14936 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14937 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
14938 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
14939 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
14940 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
14941 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
14945 <section id=
"liberatemusic">
14946 <title>4. Liberate the Music
—Again
</title>
14948 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
14949 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
14950 is, to most people, most pressing
—music. There is no other
14951 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
14952 battles around the sharing of music.
14955 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
14956 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
14957 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
14958 killer app
—possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
14959 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
14960 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
14961 innovation on the network.
14964 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
14965 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
14966 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
14967 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
14968 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
14971 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
14972 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
14973 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
14974 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"piracy"/>, they enable
14975 four different kinds of sharing:
14977 <orderedlist numeration=
"upperalpha">
14980 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
14981 for purchasing CDs.
14985 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
14986 on the way to purchasing CDs.
14989 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
14991 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14992 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
14993 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
14997 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
14998 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
14999 owner plainly endorses.
15002 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
15003 <indexterm><primary>VCRs
</primary></indexterm>
15005 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
15006 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
15007 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
15008 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
15009 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
15010 significantly weakened.
15013 As I said in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
15014 linkend=
"piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
15015 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
15016 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
15017 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
15021 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
15022 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
15026 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
15027 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
15028 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
15029 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
15030 is cumbersome and slow
—we in the United States are lucky to have
15031 broadband service at
1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
15032 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
15033 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
15034 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
15035 Internet is mainly just an idea.
15038 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
15039 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
15040 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
15041 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
15042 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
15043 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
15044 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
15045 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
15046 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
15047 where everywhere you are
—except maybe the desert or the
15048 Rockies
—you can instantaneously be connected to the
15049 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
15050 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
15052 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over
</primary></indexterm>
15054 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
15055 give you access to content on the fly
—such as Internet radio,
15056 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
15057 then, is the critical point: When it is
<emphasis>extremely
</emphasis>
15058 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
15059 <emphasis>easier
</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
15060 access to content than it will be to download and store content
15061 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
15062 content
</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
15063 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
15064 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
15065 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
15066 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
15067 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
15068 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
15069 paying for this content even though
<quote>free
</quote> content is available in the
15070 form of MP3s across the Web.
<footnote><para>
15072 See, for example,
<quote>Music Media Watch,
</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter,
3
15073 April
2002, available at
15074 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
76</ulink>.
15079 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
15080 present: It is emphatically temporary. The
<quote>problem
</quote> with file
15081 sharing
—to the extent there is a real problem
—is a problem
15082 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
15083 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
15084 makers today to be
<quote>solving
</quote> this problem in light of a technology
15085 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
15086 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
15087 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
15088 artists get paid, during
15090 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
15091 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
15092 and twenty-first-century technologies.
15095 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different
<quote>problems
</quote>
15096 here to solve. Let's start with type D content
—uncopyrighted
15097 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
15098 <quote>problem
</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
15099 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
15100 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
15101 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
15102 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
15103 order to eliminate kidnapping.
15106 Type C content raises a different
<quote>problem.
</quote> This is content that was,
15107 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
15108 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
15109 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
15110 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
15111 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
15112 way that returns something to the artist.
15114 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
15115 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
15117 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
15118 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
15119 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
15120 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
15121 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
15122 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
15123 from the author's perspective, this
<quote>sharing
</quote> of his content without
15124 his being compensated is less than ideal.
15127 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
15128 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
15129 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
15130 providers would be free, under this rule, to
<quote>share
</quote> that content,
15131 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
15132 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
15133 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
15137 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
15138 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
15139 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
15140 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
15141 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
15142 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
15143 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
15144 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
15148 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
15149 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
15150 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
15151 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
15152 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
15153 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
15154 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
15155 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
15158 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
15159 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
15160 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
15161 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
15162 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
15163 delivering and accessing content.
15166 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
15167 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
15170 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
15171 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
15172 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
15173 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
15174 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
15175 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
15176 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
15177 harmed the interests of the content industry.
15180 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
15181 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
15182 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
15183 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
15184 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
15185 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
15186 way to compensate those who are harmed.
15188 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'
><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)
</primary></indexterm>
15190 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
15191 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.
<footnote>
15194 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
15195 William Fisher,
<citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities
</citetitle> (last
15196 revised:
10 October
2000), available at
15197 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
77</ulink>; William
15198 Fisher,
<citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
15199 Entertainment
</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
15200 2004), ch.
6, available at
15201 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
78</ulink>. Professor
15202 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
15203 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
15204 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel,
<quote>Impose a
15205 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,
</quote> available at
15206 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig,
<quote>Who's Holding Back
15207 Broadband?
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
8 January
2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
15208 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
15209 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee,
26 February
2002,
15211 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine,
<citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
15212 Use Fee (IPUF)
</citetitle>,
3 March
2002, available at
15213 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
15214 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,
</quote> <citetitle>USA Today
</citetitle>,
13 May
15216 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry,
<quote>Getting Copyright Right,
</quote>
15217 IEEE Spectrum Online,
1 July
2002, available at
15218 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
83</ulink>; Declan
15219 McCullagh,
<quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,
</quote> CNET News.com,
27 August
15221 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
84</ulink>.
15222 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
15223 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
15224 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
15225 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
15226 debate by about a decade. See
15227 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
85</ulink>.
15228 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William
</primary></indexterm>
15229 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
15230 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)
</primary></indexterm>
15231 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'
/>
15233 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
15234 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
15235 would (
1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
15236 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
15237 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
15238 develop (
2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
15239 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (
3) artists would be
15240 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (
4) an appropriate
15244 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
15245 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
15246 <citetitle>Promises to Keep
</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
15247 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
15248 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
15249 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
15250 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
15251 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
15252 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
15253 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
15254 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
15255 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
15256 controlling access.
15258 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'
/>
15259 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
15261 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
15262 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
15263 the system supports the widest range of
<quote>semiotic democracy
</quote>
15264 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
15265 other changes I described were accomplished
—in particular, the
15266 limits on derivative
15268 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
15269 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
15270 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
15271 allowed to do with the content itself.
15273 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation
</primary></indexterm>
15274 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore
</primary></indexterm>
15275 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks
</primary></indexterm>
15276 <indexterm><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>prices of
</secondary></indexterm>
15278 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
15279 <quote>harm
</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
15280 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
15281 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
15282 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
15283 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat
<quote>free
</quote> by being
15284 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
15285 of songs at even the very high price of
99 cents a song. (At
99 cents,
15286 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
15287 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
15288 Real Networks, offering music at just
79 cents a song. And no doubt
15289 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
15292 <indexterm><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
15293 <indexterm><primary>television
</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast
</secondary></indexterm>
15294 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
15295 <indexterm><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>in Asia
</secondary></indexterm>
15296 <indexterm><primary>film industry
</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in
</secondary></indexterm>
15298 This competition has already occurred against the background of
<quote>free
</quote>
15299 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
15300 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
15301 that, there is nothing impossible at all about
<quote>competing with free.
</quote>
15302 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
15303 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
15304 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
15305 theaters are often luxurious
—with
<quote>first class
</quote> seats, and meals
15306 served while you watch a movie
—as they struggle and succeed in
15307 finding ways to compete with
<quote>free.
</quote>
15310 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
15311 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
15312 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
15313 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
15314 innovators
—ones who would have a right to the content, and would
15315 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
15319 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
15323 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
15324 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
15325 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
15326 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
15327 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
15331 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
15334 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
15337 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
15341 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
15342 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
15347 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
15348 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
15352 But what if
<quote>piracy
</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
15353 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
15354 consumers continue to
<quote>take
</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
15358 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
15359 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
15360 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
15361 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
15362 technology that is
95 percent secure and produces a market of size
<citetitle>x
</citetitle>,
15363 or (b) to have a technology that is
50 percent secure but produces a
15364 market of five times
<citetitle>x
</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
15365 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
15366 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
15367 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
15368 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
15372 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
15373 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
15374 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
15376 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
15377 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
15378 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
15382 <section id=
"firelawyers">
15383 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers
</title>
15385 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
15386 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
15387 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
15388 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
15391 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
15392 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
15393 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
15394 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
15395 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
15396 strong view queers the law.
15398 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville
</primary></indexterm>
15399 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (
1998)
</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of
</secondary></indexterm>
15401 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
15402 <quote>radical
</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
15403 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
15404 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
15405 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
15406 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
15407 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
15408 Nimmer, thought it obvious.
<footnote><para>
15410 Lawrence Lessig,
<quote>Copyright's First Amendment
</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
15411 Memorial Lecture),
<citetitle>UCLA Law Review
</citetitle> 48 (
2001):
1057,
1069–70.
15416 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
15417 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
15418 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
15421 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
15422 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
15423 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
15424 the legal system are slight.
<footnote><para>
15426 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
15427 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
15428 leading him to question his own publicly stated
15429 position
—twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
15430 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
15431 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
15432 J. Liebowitz,
<citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
15433 Drive the Digital Marketplace
</citetitle> (New York: Amacom,
2002), (reviewing his
15434 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
15435 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?
</quote> working paper, June
2003,
15437 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
86</ulink>.
15438 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
15439 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
15440 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
15441 <citetitle>Rethinking
</citetitle>,
174–76.
15442 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
15444 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
15445 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
15449 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
15450 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
15451 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
15452 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
15453 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
15454 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
15455 practically never be done.
15458 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
15459 billed at the largest firms at more than $
400 per hour. How much time
15460 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
15461 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
15462 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
15463 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
15464 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
15465 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
15468 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
15469 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
15470 their duty to change the way the law works
—or better, to change the
15471 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
15472 top
1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
15473 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
15476 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
15477 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
15478 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
15481 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid
</primary></indexterm>
15483 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
15484 technology
—the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
15485 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
15486 technology
—a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
15487 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
15488 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
15489 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
15492 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture
—but it should
15493 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
15495 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311-->
15496 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
15497 simple pragmatic question:
<quote>Will it do good?
</quote> When challenged about
15498 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers,
<quote>Why not?
</quote>
15501 We should ask,
<quote>Why?
</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
15502 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
15503 keep your lawyers away.
15505 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
15509 <chapter label=
"17" id=
"c-notes">
15510 <title>NOTES
</title>
15512 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
15513 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
15514 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
15515 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
15516 this book. For each link below, you can go to
15517 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
15518 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
15519 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
15520 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
15524 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
15525 <?latex \theendnotes
?>
15527 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
15530 <chapter label=
"18" id=
"c-acknowledgments">
15531 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
</title>
15533 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
15534 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
15535 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
15536 to him that this book is dedicated.
15538 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark
</primary></indexterm>
15540 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
15541 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
15542 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
15543 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
15544 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
15545 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
15546 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
15547 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
15548 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
15549 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
15550 critical eye on much of this.
15553 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
15554 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
15555 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
15556 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
15557 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
15558 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
15559 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
15560 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
15561 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
15564 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
15565 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
15566 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
15567 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
15568 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
15569 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
15570 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
15571 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
15572 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
15573 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
15574 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
15575 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
15576 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
15577 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
15578 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams,
<quote>Wink,
</quote> Roger Wood,
<quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,
</quote>
15579 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
15580 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
15581 a bunch of great replies.)
15584 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
15585 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
15586 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
15587 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
15588 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
15589 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
15590 throughout this book.
15593 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
15594 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
15595 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
15596 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
15598 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->